Index of Biographies: Lives Recounted in the Lives

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Index of Biographies: Lives Recounted in the Lives Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-88335-1 — Diogenes Laertius: Lives of Eminent Philosophers Edited and translated by Stephen White Index More Information Index of Biographies: Lives Recounted in the Lives Philosopher Home Affiliation Lives Aeschines Athens Socratic 2.60–4 Alcmaeon Croton Pythagorean (?) 8.83 Alexinus Elis Socratic: Megaric 2.109–10 Anacharsis Scythia Sage 1.101–5 Anaxagoras Clazomenae early Ionian 2.6–15 Anaxarchus Abdera Democritean 9.58–60 Anaximander Miletus early Ionian 2.1–2 Anaximenes Miletus early Ionian 2.3–5 Antisthenes Athens Socratic: Cynic forerunner 6.1–19 Arcesilaus Pitane Academic: skeptic 4.28–45 Archelaus Athens? early Ionian 2.16–17 Archytas Tarentum Pythagorean 8.79–83 Aristippus Cyrene Socratic: Cyrenaic 2.65–85 Aristo Chios Stoic: dissenting 7.160–4 Aristotle Stagira Peripatetic 5.1–35 Bias Priene Sage 1.82–8 Bion Borysthenes Academic: sophist 4.46–58 Carneades Cyrene Academic: skeptic 4.62–6 Cebes Thebes Socratic 2.125 Chilon Sparta Sage 1.68–73 Chrysippus Soloi Stoic 7.179–202 Cleanthes Assos Stoic 7.168–76 Cleobulus Lindos Sage 1.89–93 Clitomachus Carthage Academic: skeptic 4.67 Crantor Soloi Academic 4.24–7 Crates Athens Academic 4.21–3 Crates Thebes Cynic 6.85–93 Crito Athens Socratic 2.121 Demetrius Phalerum Peripatetic 5.75–85 Democritus Abdera Atomist 9.34–49 Diodorus Iasos Socratic: Megaric 2.111–12 Diogenes Apollonia Democritean 9.57 Diogenes Sinope Cynic 6.20–81 Dionysius Heraclea Stoic: dissenting 7.166–7 Empedocles Acragas Pythagorean (?) 8.51–77 Epicharmus Syracuse Pythagorean (?) 8.78 Epicurus Athens Epicurean 10.1–154 (all) Epimenides Crete Sage 1.109–15 482 © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-88335-1 — Diogenes Laertius: Lives of Eminent Philosophers Edited and translated by Stephen White Index More Information Index of Biographies Philosopher Home Affiliation Lives Euboulides Miletus Socratic: Megaric 2.108–9 Euclides Megara Socratic: Megaric 2.106–8 Eudoxus Cnidos Pythagorean (?) 8.86–91 Euphantus Olynthus Socratic: Megaric 2.110 Glaucon Athens Socratic 2.124 Heraclides Heraclea (Pontus) Academic & Peripatetic 5.86–94 Heraclitus Ephesus “isolated” 9.1–17 Herillus Calchedon Stoic: dissenting 7.165–6 Hermarchus Mytilene Epicurean 10.24–5 Hipparchia Maroneia Cynic 6.96–8 Hippasus Metapontum Pythagorean 8.84 Lacydes Cyrene Academic: skeptic 4.59–61 Leucippus ? Atomist 9.30–3 Lycon Alexandria Troas Peripatetic 5.65–74 Melissus Samos Eleatic 9.24 Menedemus Eretria Socratic: Eretric 2.125–44 Menedemus ? Cynic 6.102 Menippus Gadara Cynic 6.99–101 Metrocles Maroneia Cynic 6.94–5 Metrodorus Lampsacus Epicurean 10.22–4 Monimus Syracuse Cynic 6.82–3 Myson Khên Sage 1.106–8 Onesicrates Aegina or Astypalaea Cynic 6.84 Parmenides Elea Eleatic 9.21–3 Periander Corinth Sage 1.94–100 Persaeus Citium Stoic 7.36 Phaedo Elis Socratic: Eliac 2.105 Pherecydes Syros Sage; cf. Pythagoras 1.116–22 Philo Athens Pyrrhonian 9.67–9 Philolaos Croton Pythagorean 8.84–5 Pittacus Mytilene Sage 1.74–81 Plato Athens Academic 3.1–109 (all) Polemo Athens Academic 4.16–20 Protagoras Abdera Democritean 9.50–6 Pyrrho Elis Pyrrhonian 9.61–9 Pythagoras Samos Pythagorean 8.1–50 Simmias Thebes Socratic 2.124 Simon Athens Socratic 2.122–3 Socrates Athens Socratic 2.18–47 Solon Athens Sage 1.45–67 Speusippus Athens Academic 4.1–5 Sphaerus Bosporus Stoic 7.177–8 Stilpo Megara Socratic: Megaric 2.113–20 Strato Lampsacus Peripatetic 5.58–64 Thales Miletus Sage: Ionian 1.22–44 Theano Croton Pythagorean 8.42–3 Theodorus Cyrene Socratic: Cyrenaic 2.97–104 483 © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-88335-1 — Diogenes Laertius: Lives of Eminent Philosophers Edited and translated by Stephen White Index More Information Index of Biographies Philosopher Home Affiliation Lives Theophrastus Eresos Peripatetic 5.36–57 Timon Phlius Pyrrhonian 9.109–16 Xenocrates Calchedon Academic 4.6–15 Xenophanes Colophon > Elea “isolated” 9.18–20 Xenophon Athens Socratic 2.48–59 Zeno Citium Stoic 7.1–35 Zeno Elea Eleatic 9.25–9 484 © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-88335-1 — Diogenes Laertius: Lives of Eminent Philosophers Edited and translated by Stephen White Index More Information Index of Citations: Authors Cited in the Lives All ancient writings cited in the Translation are listed here by author, including some who remain “Anonymous.” Only material ostensibly from an author’s writings is included; strictly oral remarks, even verbatim quotations, appear only when cited from a written work, and under the author’s name, not the speaker’s. Citations are normally flagged in the Translation by abbreviated references in square brackets, often by “F” for “frag- ments” or paraphrases. The collections and editions from which those references derive are indicated here following each author’s name. Citations from an author’s extant works appear first, then fragmentary material; citations found in different collections are listed on separate lines; and citations not found in the specified collections are listed last, sepa- rated by a semi-colon. The Index also lists the sources of fragmentary material for ancient authors cited only in the notes, but not citations found only there. Abbreviations CA Collectanea Alexandrina, ed. J. U. Powell (Oxford 1925) DK Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, ed. H. Diels and W. Kranz (Berlin 1951) FGE Further Greek Epigrams, ed. D. L. Page (Cambridge 1982) FGrH Die Fragmente der griechischen Historiker, ed. F. Jacoby (Berlin 1923–1930; Leiden 1940–1958) FGrHC Die Fragmente der griechischen Historiker, Continued, ed. G. Schepens et al. (Leiden 1998–) FHG Fragmenta Historicorum Graecorum, ed. C. and T. Müller (Paris 1841–1870) HE The Greek Anthology: Hellenistic Epigrams, ed. A. S. F. Gow and D. L. Page (Cambridge 1965) LS The Hellenistic Philosophers, ed. A. A. Long and D. N. Sedley (Cambridge 1987) M Sextus Empiricus, Adversus Mathematicos: M 1–6 = Against Those in the Disciplines 1–6, M 7–8 = Against the Logicians 1–2, M 9–10 = Against the Physicists 1–2, M 11 = Against the Ethicists Pal. Palatine Anthology, commonly called “Greek Anthology”: H. Beckby (1965–1966) PCG Poetae Comici Graeci, ed. R. Kassel and C. Austin (Berlin 1983–2001) PEG Poetarum Epicorum Graecorum, ed. A. Bernabé (Stuttgart 1996–2007) PMG Poetae Melici Graeci, ed. D. L. Page (Oxford 1962) PPF Poetarum Philosophorum Fragmenta, ed. H. Diels (Berlin 1901) SA Die Schule des Aristoteles, ed. F. Wehrli (Basel and Stuttgart 1967–1978) SH Supplementum Hellenisticum, ed. H. Lloyd-Jones and P. Parsons (Berlin 1983) SSR Socratis et Socraticorum reliquiae, ed. G. Giannantoni (Naples 1990) SVF Stoicorum veterum fragmenta, ed. J. von Arnim (Leipzig 1903–1905) TrGF Tragicorum Graecorum Fragmenta, ed. B. Snell, R. Kannicht, S. Radt (Göt- tingen 1981–2004) 485 © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-88335-1 — Diogenes Laertius: Lives of Eminent Philosophers Edited and translated by Stephen White Index More Information Index of Citations Achaeus of Eretria: TrGF 1 Anonymous comic verse: PCG 8 F34 2.133 F149 2.108, F155 7.67 Achaïcus Anonymous epigrams: FGE 6.99 Anon. 93 8.49 Aenesidemus of Knossos: Polito (2014) Anonymous hexameters: Davies (1988) F5 9.106, F6 9.62, F17 9.87 F5 2.117 Aeschines of Sphettos (Athens): SSR VI A 7.27 F91 2.65 Anonymous tragic verse: TrGF 2 Agrippa F177 7.67, F 281 4.25, F282 4.35, F283 9.88–9 4.35, F285 6.95, F286 7.67 Alcaeus of Mytilene: Voigt (1971) Antagoras of Rhodes: CA; HE F360 1.31, F429 1.81 F1 4.26–7, F2 (Epigram 1) 4.21 Alcidamas of Elaea: Avezzù (1982) Anticlides of Athens: FGrH 140 F8 8.56, F12 9.54 F1 8.11 Alcimus of Sicily: FGrH 560 Antigonus of Carystus: Dorandi (1999a) F6 3.9–17 F2A 9.62–4, F3 9.62, F4B 9.66 n., F5 Alcmaeon of Croton: DK 24 9.110–11, F6 9.112, F7 9.112, F9B F1 8.83 4.17, F11B 4.24 n., F12 4.26 n., F14 Alexander of Myndus: FGrH 25 4.22, F15 4.21 n., F24 5.67, F25 F1 1.29 2.136, F26B 2.139–40 n., F27 2.143, Alexander Polyhistor: FGrH 273; cf. F32 7.12, F34B 7.13 n., F35B 7.13 Giannattasio Andria (1989) n., F36 7.14, F38B 7.19 n., F39 3.66, F85 1.116, F86 2.19, F87 2.106, F88 F46 7.188, F48 2.15, F49 9.49 3.4, F89 3.5, F90 4.62, F91 7.179, Antileon: FGrH 247 F92 9.61, F93 8.24–36 F1 3.3 Alexis of Thurii: PCG 2 Antipater of Sidon: HE F1 3.27, F151 3.27, F163 3.28, F185 Epigrams 35 7.29 3.28 Antipater of Tarsus: SVF 3.244–58 Ambryon F16 7.55, F18 7.54, F22 7.57, F23 7.60, 5.11 F32 7.150, F51 7.84, F49 7.159, F60 Ameipsias of Athens: CPG 2 7.92; 7.68 F9 2.28 Antipater of Tyre: cf. SVF 3.250 F43–5 Amphicrates of Athens: FHG 4 F43 7.140, F44 7.148, F45 7.142; 7.139 F2 2.101 Antiphon: FGrHC 1096 Amphis (of Andros?): PCG 2 F1 8.3 F6 3.27, F13 3.28 Antisthenes of Athens: SSR V A; cf. Anaxagoras of Clazomenae: DK 59 Prince (2015) F1 2.6 F98 6.104, F99 6.105, F148 3.35 Anaxandrides of Rhodes: PCG 2 Antisthenes of Rhodes: FGrH 508; cf.
Recommended publications
  • Copyrighted Material
    Index Note: page numbers in italics denote tables, maps, or illustrations Abdera 74 Cleomenes 237 ; coins 159, 276 , Abu Simbel 297 277, 279 ; food production 121, 268, Abydos 286 272 ; imports 268 ; Kleoitas 109 ; Achaea/Achaeans: Aigialos 213 ; Naucratis 269–271 ; pottery 191 ; basileus 128, 129, 134 ; Sparta 285 ; trade 268, 272 colonization 100, 104, 105, 107–108, Aegium 88, 91, 108 115, 121 ; democracy 204 ; Aelian 4, 186, 188 dialect 44 ; ethnos 91 ; Aeneas 109, 129 Herodotus 91 ; heroes 73, 108 ; Aeolians 45 , 96–97, 122, 292, 307 ; Homer 52, 172, 197, 215 ; dialect group 44, 45, 46 Ionians 50 ; migration 44, 45 , 50, Aeschines 86, 91, 313, 314–315 96 ; pottery 119 ; as province 68 ; Aeschylus: Persians 287, 308 ; Seven relocation 48 ; warrior tombs 49 Against Thebes 162 ; Suppliant Achilles 128, 129, 132, 137, 172, 181, Maidens 204 216 ; shield of 24, 73, 76, 138–139 Aetolia/Aetolians 20 ; dialect 299 ; Acrae 38 , 103, 110 Erxadieis 285 ; ethnos 91, 92 ; Acraephnium 279 poleis 93 ; pottery 50 ; West Acragas 38 , 47 ; democracy 204 ; Locris 20 foundation COPYRIGHTED 104, 197 ; Phalaris 144 ; Aëtos MATERIAL 62 Theron 149, 289 ; tyranny 150 Africanus, Sextus Julius 31 Adrastus 162 Agamemnon: Aeolians 97 ; anax 129 ; Aegimius 50, 51 Argos 182 ; armor 173 ; Aegina 3 ; Argos 3, 5 ; Athens 183, basileus 128, 129 ; scepter 133 ; 286, 287 ; captured 155 ; Schliemann 41 ; Thersites 206 A History of the Archaic Greek World: ca. 1200–479 BCE, Second Edition. Jonathan M. Hall. © 2014 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Published 2014 by John Wiley & Sons,
    [Show full text]
  • ARISTOXENUS of TARENTUM Rutgers University Studies in Classical Humanities
    ARISTOXENUS OF TARENTUM Rutgers University Studies in Classical Humanities Series Editor: David C. Mirhady Advisory Board: William W. Fortenbaugh Dimitri Gutas Pamela M. Huby Timothy C. Powers Eckart Schütrumpf On Stoic and Peripatetic Ethics: The Work of Arius Didymus I Theophrastus of Eresus: On His Life and Work II Theophrastean Studies: On Natural Science, Physics and Metaphysics, Ethics, Religion and Rhetoric III Cicero’s Knowledge of the Peripatos IV 7KHRSKUDVWXV+LV3V\FKRORJLFDO'R[RJUDSKLFDODQG6FLHQWLÀF Writings V Peripatetic Rhetoric after Aristotle VI The Passionate Intellect: Essays on the Transformation of Classical Traditions presented to Professor I.G. Kidd VII Theophrastus: Reappraising the Sources VIII Demetrius of Phalerum: Text, Translation and Discussion IX Dicaearchus of Messana: Text, Translation and Discussion X Eudemus of Rhodes XI Lyco of Troas and Hieronymus of Rhodes XII Aristo of Ceos: Text, Translation and Discussion XIII Heraclides of Pontus: Text and Translation XIV Heraclides of Pontus: Discussion XV Strato of Lampsacus: Text, Translation and Discussion XVI ARISTO XENUS OF TARENTUM DISCUSSION RUTGERS UNIVERSITY STUDIES IN CLASSICAL HUMANITIES VOLUMEXVU EDITED BY eARL A. HUFFMAN First published 2012 by Transaction Publishers Published 2017 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017, USA Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business Copyright © 2012 by Taylor & Francis. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
    [Show full text]
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Categories in the Early Roman Empire, Oxford: Oxford University Press 2015, in Sehepunkte 15 (2015), Nr
    Citation style Andrea Falcon: Rezension von: Michael J. Griffin: Aristotle's Categories in the Early Roman Empire, Oxford: Oxford University Press 2015, in sehepunkte 15 (2015), Nr. 7 [15.07.2015], URL:http://www.sehepunkte.de/2015/07/27098.html First published: http://www.sehepunkte.de/2015/07/27098.html copyright This article may be downloaded and/or used within the private copying exemption. Any further use without permission of the rights owner shall be subject to legal licences (§§ 44a-63a UrhG / German Copyright Act). sehepunkte 15 (2015), Nr. 7 Michael J. Griffin: Aristotle's Categories in the Early Roman Empire This is a book about the reception of Aristotle's Categories from the first century BC to the second century AD. The Categories does not appear to have circulated in the Hellenistic era. By contrast, this short but enigmatic treatise was at the center of the so-called return to Aristotle in the first century BC. The book under review tells us the story of this remarkable reversal of fortune. The main characters in this story are philosophers working in the three main philosophical traditions of post- Hellenistic philosophy. For the Peripatetic tradition, these are Andronicus of Rhodes and Boethus of Sidon. For the Academic and Platonic tradition, Eudorus of Alexandria and Lucius. For the Stoic tradition, Athenodorus and Cornutus. A supporting role is reserved to the following interpreters of the Categories : Aristo of Alexandria, Ps-Archytas, Nicostratus, Aspasius, Herminus, and Adrastus. In broad outline, the story told in the book goes as follows: Andronicus of Rhodes rescued the Categories from obscurity by deciding to place it at the beginning of his catalogue of Aristotle's writings (chapter 2).
    [Show full text]
  • The Influence of Achaemenid Persia on Fourth-Century and Early Hellenistic Greek Tyranny
    THE INFLUENCE OF ACHAEMENID PERSIA ON FOURTH-CENTURY AND EARLY HELLENISTIC GREEK TYRANNY Miles Lester-Pearson A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of PhD at the University of St Andrews 2015 Full metadata for this item is available in St Andrews Research Repository at: http://research-repository.st-andrews.ac.uk/ Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://hdl.handle.net/10023/11826 This item is protected by original copyright The influence of Achaemenid Persia on fourth-century and early Hellenistic Greek tyranny Miles Lester-Pearson This thesis is submitted in partial fulfilment for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy at the University of St Andrews Submitted February 2015 1. Candidate’s declarations: I, Miles Lester-Pearson, hereby certify that this thesis, which is approximately 88,000 words in length, has been written by me, and that it is the record of work carried out by me, or principally by myself in collaboration with others as acknowledged, and that it has not been submitted in any previous application for a higher degree. I was admitted as a research student in September 2010 and as a candidate for the degree of PhD in September 2011; the higher study for which this is a record was carried out in the University of St Andrews between 2010 and 2015. Date: Signature of Candidate: 2. Supervisor’s declaration: I hereby certify that the candidate has fulfilled the conditions of the Resolution and Regulations appropriate for the degree of PhD in the University of St Andrews and that the candidate is qualified to submit this thesis in application for that degree.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae Voula Tsouna
    1 Curriculum Vitae Voula Tsouna Department of Philosophy, University of California Santa Barbara, CA 93106-3090 [email protected] Place of Birth: Athens, Greece Nationality: Greek (EU) & USA Languages: Ancient Greek, Latin, French (fluent), English (fluent), Modern Greek (fluent), Italian (competent), German (reading) AREA OF SPECIALIZATION Ancient Philosophy AREAS OF COMPETENCE Siècle des Lumières (French Enlightment), Early Modern Philosophy, topics in Epistemology, Moral Psychology, and Ethics. EDUCATION 1988 PhD (Thèse de doctorat), Ancient Philosophy, University of Paris X 1984-86 Doctoral Research, fully enrolled graduate student at the University of Cambridge, King’s College 1984 Diplôme d’Études Approfondies (DEA, equivalent to the MA), Ancient Philosophy, University of Paris X 1983 Bachelor of Arts in Philosophy summa cum laude (Πτυχεῖον summa cum laude), Philosophy, University of Athens ACADEMIC APPOINTMENTS 2006–present University of California at Santa Barbara, Full Professor 2000–2006 University of California at Santa Barbara, Associate Professor 1997–2000 University of California at Santa Barbara, Assistant Professor 1997 (Winter) University of California at Santa Barbara, Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy 2010 (Spring) University of Crete, Holder of the Michelis Chair in Aesthetics at the Department of Philosophy and Social Studies 1994–1996 Pomona College, Visiting Assistant Professor 1992–1993 University of Glasgow, Scotland, Research Fellow 1991–1992 California State University at San Bernardino, Lecturer
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelianism in the First Century BC
    CHAPTER 5 Aristotelianism in the First Century BC Andrea Falcon 1 A New Generation of Peripatetic Philosophers The division of the Peripatetic tradition into a Hellenistic and a post- Hellenistic period is not a modern invention. It is already accepted in antiquity. Aspasius speaks of an old and a new generation of Peripatetic philosophers. Among the philosophers who belong to the new generation, he singles out Andronicus of Rhodes and Boethus of Sidon.1 Strabo adopts a similar division. He too distinguishes between the older Peripatetics, who came immediately after Theophrastus, and their successors.2 He collectively describes the latter as better able to do philosophy in the manner of Aristotle (φιλοσοφεῖν καὶ ἀριστοτελίζειν). It remains unclear what Strabo means by doing philosophy in the manner of Aristotle.3 But he certainly thinks that the philosophers who belong to the new generation, and not those who belong to the old one, deserve the title of true Aristotelians. For Strabo, the event separating the old from the new Peripatos is the rediscovery and publication of Aristotle’s writings. We may want to resist Strabo’s negative characterization of the earlier Peripatetics. For Strabo, they were not able to engage in philosophy in any seri- ous way but were content to declaim general theses.4 This may be an unfair judgment, ultimately based on the anachronistic assumption that any serious philosophy requires engagement with an authoritative text.5 Still, the empha- sis that Strabo places on the rediscovery of Aristotle’s writings suggests that the latter were at the center of the critical engagement with Aristotle in the 1 Aspasius, On Aristotle’s Ethics 44.20–45.16.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato Apology of Socrates and Crito
    COLLEGE SERIES OF GREEK AUTHORS EDITED UNDER THE SUPERVISION OF JOHN WILLIAMS WHITE, LEWIS R. PACKARD, a n d THOMAS D. SEYMOUR. PLATO A p o l o g y o f S o c r a t e s AND C r i t o EDITED ON THE BASIS OF CRON’S EDITION BY LOUIS DYER A s s i s t a n t ·Ρι;Οχ'ε&^ο^ ι ν ^University. BOSTON: PUBLISHED BY GINN & COMPANY. 1902. I P ■ C o p · 3 Entered, according to Act of Congress, in the year 1885, by J o h n W il l ia m s W h i t e a n d T h o m a s D. S e y m o u r , In the Office of the Librarian of Congress, at Washington. J . S. C u s h in g & Co., P r i n t e r s , B o s t o n . PREFACE. T his edition of the Apology of Socrates and the Crito is based upon Dr. Christian Cron’s eighth edition, Leipzig, 1882. The Notes and Introduction here given have in the main been con­ fined within the limits intelligently drawn by Dr. Cron, whose commentaries upon various dialogues of Plato have done and still do so much in Germany to make the study of our author more profitable as well as pleasanter. No scruple has been felt, how­ ever, in making changes. I trust there are few if any of these which Dr. Cron might not himself make if he were preparing his work for an English-thinking and English-speaking public.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Rhetorical Use of Torture in Attic Forensic Oratory VASILEIOS
    The Rhetorical Use of Torture in Attic Forensic Oratory VASILEIOS ADAMIDIS Mailing Address: Flat 2, 43 Burns street, NG7 4DS Nottingham United Kingdom Email address: [email protected] Tel: +44(0)7930520275 1 The Rhetorical Use of Torture in Attic Forensic Oratory ABSTRACT: Come 'regola', la tortura di schiavi innocenti che è stata concordata dai querelantia fini probatori (βάσανος probatori) fu ritenuto dagli oratori lo strumento più efficace per giungere alla verità. Questo paper, con riferimento alla psicologia dell'antica Grecia, spiega perché la menzionata regola fu di cruciale importanza per la retorica. Gli oratori, sulla base della presunta attendibilità dell'istituzione dei βάσανος, furono in grado di sviluppare argomenti basati sulle sfide (πρόκλησις), che possono essere comprese al meglio alla luce della concezione greca, piuttosto che moderna, di razionalità ed azione umana. Di conseguenza, a dispetto dell'incertezza che circonda l'attualità della tortura a fini probatori nell'età degli oratori, l'importanza retorica dei πρόκλησις εἰς βάσανον è innegabile e va esaminata attentamente. KEYWORDS: Basanos (βάσανος), Greek psychology, human motivation, practical reasoning. *** The institution of torture is highly controversial; its morality is extremely dubious and its expediency is, at minimum, questionable. A particular form of torture that seems completely indefensible from a modern perspective is the torture (βάσανος) of innocent slaves for evidentiary purposes in Athenian law. This has been characterised as ‘wanton and purposeless barbarity’1, yet has been explained as a way classical Athenian citizens reinforced their dominant political status and ‘confirm[ed] their own social hierarchy and cohesion’2. The barbarity and putative irrationality of evidentiary βάσανος3, in addition to the lack of evidence proving the actuality of this practice, make its existence, at least in the period of the Attic orators, doubtful4.
    [Show full text]
  • The Appeal to Easiness in Aristotle's Protrepticus
    THE APPEAL TO EASINESS IN ARISTOTLE’S PROTREPTICUS Matthew D. Walker [Uncorrected draft. To be published in Ancient Philosophy 39 (2019). Please cite only the final published version.] Aristotle’s Protrepticus sought to exhort its audience to engage in philosophy (filosofi&a), i.e., the “acquisition and use of wisdom” (kth~si&v te kai_ xrh~siv sofi&av: 6, 40.2-3/B53; cf. 6, 37.7-9/B8).1 The Protrepticus is now lost. But work by D.S. Hutchinson and Monte Ransome Johnson (2005) has confirmed earlier speculation – initiated by Ingram Bywater (1869) – that Iamblichus preserves large passages of the work in his own Protrepticus. Hutchinson and Johnson 2018 argue that significant portions of the Protrepticus also appear in Iamblichus’ De Communi Mathematica Scientia (DCMS), and that the Protrepticus was originally a dialogue. In passages preserved in Chapter 6 of Iamblichus’ Protrepticus (at 40.15-41.2/B55- 56), Aristotle offers three linked arguments for the claim that philosophy is easy. (I number the arguments in the translation that follows.) [1] For, with no pay coming from people to those who philosophize, on account of which [the latter] would have labored strenuously in this way, and with a great lead extended to the other arts, nevertheless their passing [the other arts] in exactness despite running a short time seems to me to be a sign of the easiness about philosophy. [2] And further, everybody’s feeling at home in it and wishing to occupy leisure with it, leaving aside all else, is no small sign that the close attention comes with pleasure; for no one is willing to labor for a long time.
    [Show full text]
  • Macedonische Koningen in Beeld De Representatie Van De Macedonische Koningen Amyntas III, Philippus II, Alexander III En Demetrios I in Kunst, Architectuur En Munten
    Macedonische Koningen in Beeld De representatie van de Macedonische koningen Amyntas III, Philippus II, Alexander III en Demetrios I in kunst, architectuur en munten Student: Marinde Hiemstra Studentnummer: 3666581 Docent: F. van den Eijnde Cursus: Onderzoeksseminar III Universiteit Utrecht Maart 2013 Inhoudsopgave Inleiding......................................................................................................................................2 Amyntas III.................................................................................................................................5 Philippus II.................................................................................................................................8 Alexander III 'de Grote'............................................................................................................12 Demetrios I 'Poliorketes'...........................................................................................................16 Conclusie..................................................................................................................................20 Literatuurlijst............................................................................................................................23 1 Art and architecture are mirrors of a society. They reflect the state of its values, especially in times of crisis or transition. ~ P. Zanker1. Inleiding In 338 voor Christus gaf Philippus II van Macedonië opdracht om een rond gebouw neer te zetten naast de
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Synopsis of the Aristotelian Commentary Tradition (In Less Than Sixty Minutes)
    HISTORICAL SYNOPSIS OF THE ARISTOTELIAN COMMENTARY TRADITION (IN LESS THAN SIXTY MINUTES) Fred D. Miller, Jr. CHAPTER 1 PERIPATETIC SCHOLARS Aristotle of Stagira (384–322 BCE) Exoteric works: Protrepticus, On Philosophy, Eudemus, etc. Esoteric works: Categories, Physics, De Caelo, Metaphysics, De Anima, etc. The legend of Aristotle’s misappropriated works Andronicus of Rhodes: first edition of Aristotle’s works (40 BCE) Early Peripatetic commentators Boethus of Sidon (c. 75—c. 10 BCE) comm. on Categories Alexander of Aegae (1st century CE)comm. on Categories and De Caelo Adrastus of Aphrodisias (early 1st century) comm. on Categories Aspasius (c. 131) comm. on Nicomachean Ethics Emperor Marcus Aurelius establishes four chairs of philosophy in Athens: Platonic, Peripatetic, Stoic, Epicurean (c. 170) Alexander of Aphrodisias (late 2nd —early 3rd century) Extant commentaries on Prior Analytics, De Sensu, etc. Lost comm. on Physics, De Caelo, etc. Exemplar for all subsequent commentators. Comm. on Aristotle’s Metaphysics Only books 1—5 of Alexander’s comm. are genuine; books 6—14 are by ps.-Alexander . whodunit? Themistius (c. 317—c. 388) Paraphrases of Physics, De Anima, etc. Paraphrase of Metaphysics Λ (Hebrew translation) Last of the Peripatetics CHAPTER 2 NEOPLATONIC SCHOLARS Origins of Neoplatonism Ammonius Saccas (c. 175—242) forefather of Neoplatonism Plotinus (c. 205—260) the Enneads Reality explained in terms of hypostases: THE ONE—> THE INTELLECT—>WORLD SOUL—>PERCEPTIBLE WORLD Porphyry of Tyre (232–309) Life of Plotinus On the School of Plato and Aristotle Being One On the Difference Between Plato and Aristotle Isagoge (Introduction to Aristotle’s Categories) What is Neoplatonism? A broad intellectual movement based on the philosophy of Plotinus that sought to incorporate and reconcile the doctrines of Plato, Pythagoras, and Aristotle with each other and with the universal beliefs and practices of popular religion (e.g.
    [Show full text]