PACLIC-27

Reduplication across Categories in

Charles Lam Linguistics Program, Purdue University Beering Hall, Room 1289 West Lafayette, IN 47907 [email protected]

Abstract ity and quantization, the interpretations of redupli- cation are predictable. This paper investigates the formal seman- In what follows, section 2 lists out the distri- tics of reduplication in Cantonese, i.e. how bution and characteristics of reduplication in Can- the meaning of reduplicated forms are en- tonese. Section 3 reviews previous studies and coded and computed with the given mean- ing from the base forms. In particular, points out that they cannot account for the be- this paper argues that reduplication denotes haviour of reduplication across categories. Sec- a summation function that adds up argu- tion 4 discusses the formal property of cumula- ments (be they object-, event- or degree- tivity (Krifka, 1998; Rothstein, 2004), which pro- arguments) and return a collection of the el- vides a basis to account for the surface differences ements. The surface difference across - across categories. To test the hypothesis, section egories is accounted for in terms of cu- 5 provides the details of the proposal and shows mulativity and quantization (Krifka, 1998; how various interpretations can be handled by the Krifka, 2001; Rothstein, 2004). The present approach makes use of scalar structure and present cumulativity analysis. Section 6 discusses summation as formal tools to model the the advantage of this approach and also the theo- cross-categorial behaviour of reduplication. retical implications. It provides the advantage of a unified theory for lexical composition across categories 2 Data nouns, verbs and adjectives. This section makes a few observations on redupli- Keywords: reduplication, formal semantics, cation in Cantonese. We will first focus on adjec- cumulativity, cross-categorial behaviour tives, then include nouns and verbs, which share a similar surface pattern. Consider the sentence (1), 1 Introduction which provides a reduplicated adjectives denote a sense of hedging or diminution. Reduplication is found across syntactic categories noun, verb and adjective in Cantonese. They all (1) keoi5 gou1 gou1 dei2 share a similar surface order, but the interpreta- 3sg tall tall Prt tion can be quite differently. Nominal reduplica- ‘S/he is fairly tall.’ tion denotes an exhaustive list such as ‘everybody, every apple’. Verbal reduplication displays ei- Uttering (1) means that the person is considered ther durative or iterative reading, depending on the tall, but probably not the tallest person or not even telicity of the verbal predicate. Adjectival redupli- ‘very tall’. This can be seen in (2), which is in- cation shows a hedging and diminutive reading, as felicitous unless it is otherwise specified that all in ‘a little fat’ or ‘reddish’ other members of the group are simply short. The goal of this paper is to establish a unified (2) keoi5 gou1 gou1 dei2, so2ji5 keoi5 account for the cross-categorial reduplication that 3sg tall tall Prt, therefore 3sg can interpret the various meanings. We argue that zeoi3 gou1 the common thread behind these interpretations is SUPERLATIVE tall summation. Building on the notions of cumulativ- ‘#S/he is fairly tall, so s/he is the tallest.’

277 Copyright 2013 by Charles Lam 27th Pacific Asia Conference on Language, Information, and Computation pages 277-286 PACLIC-27

The reduplicated adjective form with the parti- reduplicated verbs denote a collection of homo- cle gou1 gou1 dei2 is in complementary distribu- geneous subevents, following the assumption that tion with (3), where an overt marker shows the atelic events have ‘subevental properties’ (Bennett magnitude of tallness. This requirement of de- and Partee, 1972; Krifka, 2001). This paper ap- gree marker in (3) is well-documented, see Grano plies the existing analysis of cumulativity to redu- (2011) for a recent discussion of its syntax and se- plication in the nominal and verbal domain and mantics. further extends the analysis to adjectival redupli- cation. We thus hypothesize the following: (3) keoi5 *(hou2 / gei2) gou1 3sg very / fairly tall (6) Reduplication in Cantonese denotes a ‘S/he is very / fairly tall.’ summation function. Third, adjective reduplication shows an inter- The hypothesis in (6) predicts that the result of esting parallelism on the surface with nominal (4) the function is always a sum of the input. If the and verbal (5) reduplication in Cantonese. result of the reduplication does not denote a sum or total of the given input, one may claim that hy- (4) go2 go2 sai3lo6 *(dou1) hou2 lek1 pothesis (6) is falsified. CL CL child DISTR very smart ‘Every child is very smart.’ 1 3 Previous studies 3.1 The complex nature of adjectives (5) ngo5 tai2 tai2 ha5 syu1 fan3 zo2 1sg read read Dur book sleep Perf In general, the denotation of adjectives or prop- ‘I fell asleep while reading.’ erties can be decomposed into semantic functions of dimension, scale and degree. A dimension is a The data above show that reduplication can ap- choice of measurement, such as height or weight. ply to lexical categories (i.e. nouns, verbs and ad- Scale is an linear ordered set within the same di- jectives). This parallelism is not unique to Can- mension, such as tall or short for the same dimen- tonese: Chakraborty and Bandyopadhyay (2009) sion of height and heavy or light for weight. A also report that reduplication in Bengali can de- degree specifies a point along the scale. The de- note repetition (e.g. ‘every year’), plurality (e.g. gree can bear specific value, as in full or empty ‘the houses’), emphasis (e.g. ‘deep red rose’) and in English. For example, whenever a speaker per- imperfective verbs (e.g. ‘Talking about something, ceives the level in a cup to reach the max- suddenly he stopped.’), together with a few other imum value (i.e. 100%), then it would be felici- meanings. It is therefore plausible that reduplica- tous to say The cup is full. However, a degree can tion denotes some function that is more generic also bear a fuzzy value, which may vary depend- and applicable to different elements. This paper ing on the context. For instance, one would have does not attempt to account for cross-linguistic very different standard of ‘being tall’ for John is data, but instead focuses on Cantonese. The work- tall and The Willis tower is tall. This decom- ing hypothesis is that reduplicated forms have a posed adjective phrase analysis is also known as common semantic thread between them, and that the DegP-shell analysis. Based on this analysis that common thread is summation. What the sum- (Xiang, 2005; Grano and Kennedy, 2012), this pa- mation function does is ‘add up’ atomic elements per assumes that adjective phrases are internally into a collection. Reduplicated nouns denote an complex. In terms of syntax, there are multiple exhaustive group. For example, (4) refers to a heads within the traditional AdjP. group of children, which is equivalent to ‘every single child’ in English. Reduplicated verbs de- 3.2 Cross-categorial reduplication in various note a durative event, as in tai2 tai2 ha5 syu1 languages ‘reading (books)’ in (5). An interesting feature is There is little discussion specifically on adjectival that the predicates denoted by reduplicated verbs reduplication in the literature. Although adjectival must be an atelic event, which in turn suggests that reduplication is attested in many other languages, e.g. Basque (De Rijk and De Coene, 2008), Ben- 1Abbreviations: CL- classifier, DISTR- distributive marker, Dur- durative aspect, Perf- perfect aspect, 3sg- third gali (Chakraborty and Bandyopadhyay, 2009) and person singular pronoun, Prt- particle a handful of others (Rubino, 2011), little attention

278 PACLIC-27

is put on its formal semantic properties. Regier for size and shape adjectives bearing diminutive (1994) does provide a good summary of what reading, because the dispersive reading is impossi- reduplication can mean in various languages, but ble for size and shape adjectives. This paper takes does not include Cantonese. the intuition that reduplication denotes a sense of A recent study on adjective reduplication in multiplicity of elements, but does not assert that Mandarin (Liu, 2012) provides an informal prag- diminution comes from dispersion. Instead, this matic account of some restrictions on adjectives paper suggests that both diminutive and dispersive that can undergo reduplication. Liu’s account, like readings are the result of summation, as will be other works cited in this section, adopts an in- further discussed in section 5.3. formal cognitive grammar approach to the issue. The theory in Abraham (2005) and Kouwenberg Also, Liu did not attempt to handle reduplication and LaCharite´ (2005) treats iconicity as a central in nouns and verbs, thus the present analysis dif- property in reduplication. This paper takes the fers from Liu’s analysis both in terms of the formal multiplication as an intuition that there is a sum- approach and scope of study. mation process. In sections 4 and 5, we show that Based on crosslinguistic data, Abraham (2005) the formal properties of cumulativity and quanti- suggests ‘divisibility’ as a criterion for base forms zation can resolve the apparent contradiction that that undergo reduplication. He generalizes that the same predicate can denote the sum of a collec- reduplicated forms always denote predicates that tion and a subpart of the same collection. are divisible, so these divisible predicates must al- ways be a collection of some elements. Abraham 4 Cumulativity and Quantization (2005) also notes that this generalization would The central claim of this paper is that summation contradict the empirical data that some reduplica- is the underlying common thread in reduplication. tion forms actually denote diminutive adjectives. Before we move on to the implementation, it is Kouwenberg and LaCharite´ (2005) address the crucial to understand that cumulativity and quan- apparent contradiction of diminutive or ‘approxi- tization have a direct impact on the result of the el- mative’ interpretation of reduplication and suggest ements undergoing summation. This section sets that the diminutive reading is an extension from up the background of cumulativity in the literature a dispersive interpretation. That means a diminu- on nouns and verbs. tive reading of ‘yellowish’ would come from a dis- Krifka (2001) defines cumulativity as the fol- persive ‘yellow-spotted’. ‘Dispersive’ means that lowing: multiple instances of yellow-ness, such as spots or stains, are spread over or dispersed. This reading (7) A predicate P is cumulative iff can therefore be construed as multiple instances of (i) ∀x, y[P (x) ∧ P (y) → P (x ⊕ y)] ‘yellow’. For Kouwenberg and LaCharite´ (2005), (ii) ∃x, y[P (x) ∧ P (y) ∧ ¬x = y]] this is a connecting context where reduplication first bears plurality. This reading can be ex- Condition (i) means when two entities x and y are tended to diminution, in the sense that yellow- added together, they can still be described with the ness is spread over the entity in a diluted way, in- same denotation. Condition (ii) ensures x and y stead of being individual spots or patches. How- are distinct elements. For example, in a situation ever, such an account does not constrain when a when Mary said she saw that John left, and Jane language or an expression can perform semantic also said she saw that John left, we cannot infer extension from dispersive to diminutive. It does that John left twice or conclude that ‘leaving’ is work well for reduplication of colour adjectives cumulative. The reason is that ‘John’ in the two in Cantonese, but not with adjectives of size and utterances is the same person. shape. For example, reduplication of predicates Cumulative predicates include ‘wine’ or ‘ap- 2 such as ‘big’ or ‘tall’ can never bear any disper- ples’ . If an object x called ‘wine’ is added to an- sive reading, because the property of ‘big’ or ‘tall’ other object, which is distinct from x, let’s call it y, always predicates over the whole entity, not part of which is also wine, we have a new object contain- it. Kouwenberg and LaCharite´ (2005)’s theory of ing x and y. Since we can reasonably describe this extension relies on the dispersive reading extend- 2Here the term predicate is used in a logical sense, not a ing to diminution. Therefore, it cannot account linguistic sense. It bears no specification of category such as noun or verb, nor is it restricted to events or properties.

279 PACLIC-27

new object as ‘wine’ (as opposed to ‘two wines’, 5 Summation as a common thread which is possible in a different context), we can The previous section shows that the behaviour or conclude that ‘wine’ denotes a cumulative pred- the interpretation of the sum (i.e. the returned icate. Typically, but not necessarily, cumulative value as a result of summation) can be used to predicates include mass nouns and count plural indicate cumulativity and quantization. The de- nouns. As noted in Rothstein (2004), there are notation of ‘SUM’ in (9) is essentially ‘every’ in several ‘exceptions’ like line, sequence or fence in English (Heim and Kratzer, 1998). English, which we will not discuss in detail here. The same characteristic can be applied to verbal (9) SUM = λf ∈ D . ∀x ∈ D → f(x) = 1 predicates. Atelic predicates are typically cumula- J K This ensures all the individuals x are included in tive. Take run in English as an example. Two dis- the sum D. From this formalization, we can see tinct instances of run, when put together, can also that whenever the sum shares the same denotation be described as ‘run’. Likewise, putting John built as its atomic elements, then we can see that the houses last year and John builds houses this year atomic elements must be cumulative. (e.g. ‘some together, one can still describe the whole event as water’ can be a collection of ‘some water’). On the ‘building houses’. contrary, if a collection does not share the same In contrast, count nouns with number marking denotation as its atoms (e.g. ‘a chair’ cannot have are characterized by the property of quantization. ‘a chair’ as its proper subset), the elements are Krifka (2001) defines quantized predicates as: quantized. (8) A predicate P is quantized iff This section shows the implementation of sum- ∀x, y[P (x) ∧ P (y) → ¬y < x]] mation in reduplication across the categories noun, verb and adjective in Cantonese. Using the example in Krifka (1998), if an ele- 5.1 Nouns ment x can be called ‘3 apples’, then it is impos- sible for any proper subset of x to be described Cantonese nominals in general require classifiers as ‘3 apples’. This captures our intuition that part on top of the noun. Nominal reduplication always of ‘3 apples’ can be an apple, or two apples, but applies to the classifier, as in (10). In (10) and not three apples. Similarly, a proper part of quan- (11), both the classifier and noun are present. The tized events cannot be identical to its superset. If crucial difference between (10) and (11) is that the we say ‘John made four cakes.’, the part of the former reduplicates its classifier, which is accept- event, for example John making one cake, can- able, and the latter reduplicates its noun, which is not be described as ‘John made four cakes.’ It unacceptable. Sentence (12) shows reduplication shows that the verbal predicate ‘make four cakes’ of the noun without a classifier, which is also un- is quantized. acceptable. The notions of cumulativity and quantization (10) go2 go2 sai3lo6 dou1 hou2 lek1 capture the human understanding of collective en- CL CL child DISTR very smart tities. There are two important messages. Firstly, ‘Every child is very smart.’ summation of two elements (more precisely, two predicates) can often result in an element with (11) *go2 sai3lo6 sai3lo6 dou1 hou2 same denotation, as seen in cumulative predicates CL child child DISTR very ‘apples’ or ‘run’. Note that the count-mass dis- lek1 tinction is linguistic, which means that the encod- smart ing of whether a noun is count or mass is indepen- Intended: ‘Every child is very smart.’ dent from ontology. For example, nouns like ‘fur- (12) *sai3(lo6) sai3lo6 dou1 hou2 lek1 niture’ or ‘footwear’ are considered mass because child child DISTR very smart they do not co-occur with numerals or the singu- lar indefinite article, as in ‘*four furniture’ or ‘*a Intended: ‘Every child is very smart.’ footwear’. Second, the count-mass distinction is The data show that Cantonese reduplication ap- language-specific, meaning that an entity denoted plies only to classifiers, but not nouns 3 . Both by a mass noun in one language can be count in 3For detailed discussion syntax of classifier and noun in another language. Cantonese, see Cheng, 2012), which points out two puzzles

280 PACLIC-27

the classifier and the noun must be present and child’ is quantized, we predict that a summation whenever there is reduplication, it must apply to of such elements would result in a quantized en- the classifier4. tity. This prediction is borne out in the data. To There are a few apparent exceptions to the gen- see this, let us focus on the individual member eralization that reduplication always applies to the first. Since the utterance (10) denotes an exhaus- classifier, such as jat6 jat6 ‘day-day – every day’, tive group of ‘every child’, it means that the pred- jan4 jan4 ‘person-person – everybody’, dou6 dou6 icate ‘very smart’ would apply to each of the in- ‘place-place – everywhere’, where there is no clas- dividual members. The interpretation is also sup- sifier present. However, one can also observe that ported by the self-contradiction in the utterance in these nouns behave differently from other com- (15). Since (15) is not acceptable, we can infer mon nouns in other contexts. For example, these that the reduplicated noun must denote every sin- nouns can cooccur with numerals without any gle member of ‘the children’. classifiers, as shown in (13). Also, exceptions like jat6 ‘day’ or nin4 ‘year’ are measurement units (15) #go2 go2 sai3lo6 dou1 hou2 lek1, of time, which can never occur with classifiers CL CL child DISTR very smart (*saam1 go3 jat6 ‘three-classifier-day’ would be dan6hai6 jau1 jat1 go3 m4 lek1 unacceptable for ‘3 days’). We can therefore treat but EXIST one CL Neg smart these nouns as if they already carry the functional ‘#Every child is very smart, but one of them feature that classifiers add to common nouns. This is not.’ observation conforms with (Zhang, 2013)’s view that individuation is not exclusively expressed by As predicted for the reduplicated form denoting classifiers and bare nouns in classifier-languages ‘every child’, we can also observe the predicted can denote countable objects. result of a quantized entity. A proper subset of ‘every child’ cannot be also described as ‘every (13) keoi5 heoi5 zo2 hon4gwok3 sap6 child’, for the reason that if a set y is the proper 3sg go Perf Korea ten subset of a larger set x, y is necessarily smaller and (*go3) jat1 thus does not include at least one of the members CL day in x. Thus it is impossible to describe set y with ‘S/he went to Korea for ten days.’ the same denotation of x and we can conclude that the reduplicated noun phrase denotes a quantized Now with well-formed reduplication like (10), predicate as well. we can see that each single member ‘child’ in the group ‘every child’ is quantized, but not cumula- 5.2 Verbs tive, because a proper subpart of a child would not Verbal reduplication in Cantonese shows a differ- qualify as a child, i.e. one cannot reasonably call ent pattern than nominals. Example (5) is repeated a subpart, say the shoulder of a child, ‘a child’. below as (16). The reading event must be inter- Formally: preted as a prolonged, durative event, as its En- glish translation suggests. (14) SUM (child) = λf ∈ D . ∀x ∈ D → f(x)=1 J K = ∀x ∈ D → child(x)=1 (16) ngo5 tai2 tai2 ha5 syu1 fan3 zo2 1sg read read Dur book sleep Perf The phrase ‘every child’ is true (truth value=1), iff each of the members in the domain D is a child. ‘I fell asleep while reading.’ go3 sai6lo6 The Cantonese phrase ‘a child’ (be- As first suggested by Bennett and Partee (1972), fore reduplication) works the same way as its En- all the subparts within an atelic event are homo- go3 sai6lo6 glish counterpart. Since the phrase ‘a geneous. It provides a basis to compare an atom about Cantonese classifier reduplication. While both Can- of a durative event to a singular member in plu- tonese and Mandarin use classifiers in their nominals, only ral count nouns. That means, the durative reading Cantonese allows classifier reduplication. 4For independent reason, presumably phonological, Can- event in (16) can be seen as a collection of atomic tonese reduplication often takes one syllable. The unaccept- reading subevents. Since these subevents are ho- ability of (12) shows that a partial reduplication (i.e. redupli- mogeneous, the whole reading event is considered cating only the first syllable) would not make the utterance atelic. acceptable.

281 PACLIC-27

Atelic events can be independently tested with the reduplicated verb still denotes one prolonged duration modification, which is equivalent to the event, we must account for this difference from for / in a period of time test in English. If a predi- nominal reduplication (which denotes a collection cate can be modified by ‘for an hour’ (or any other of distinct, individuated members) in terms of cu- context-appropriate time interval), then the predi- mulativity. cate is atelic. For example, John read for an hour However, it is also possible for verb redupli- is acceptable, whereas *John read in an hour is cation to contain non-cumulative and quantized not. It shows that ‘read’ is atelic. Cantonese does subevents. Semelfactive verbs, such as jump and not use a prepositional phrase to show duration, knock in English are always punctual, i.e. they but uses the verb copying construction like (17) cannot be durative. This is shown by the observa- instead5. Example (18) is equivalent to in 3 min- tion that John jumps for an hour would only give utes in English. Since only (17) but not (18) is the iterative reading that there are more than one compatible with tai2 syu1 ‘read’, we can conclude jumps in that hour, rather than the reading that one that tai2 syu1 is atelic. single jump lasts for an hour. The verb tiu3 ‘jump’ in Cantonese works the same way as its English (17) ngo5 tai2 syu1 tai2 zo2 counterpart. Only (20), but not (21), is accept- 1sg read book read Perf able6. saam1-fen1-zong1 3-minute (20) ngo5 tiu3 zo2 saam1-fen1-zong1 ‘I read for 3 minutes.’ 1sg jump Perf 3-minute ‘I jumped for 3 minutes.’ (iterative only) (18) *ngo5 hai2 saam1-fen1-zong1 zi1noi6 1sg in 3-minute within (21) *ngo5 hai2 saam1-fen1-zong1 zi1noi6 tai2 syu1 1sg in 3-minute within read book tiu3 (zo2) ‘*I read (with)in 3 minutes.’ jump Perf ‘*I jumped (with)in 3 minutes.’ Because tai2 syu1 ‘read’ is atelic, we can say that each instance of reading is identical to other in- When the verb tiu3 ‘jump’ is reduplicated, as in stances within the same event. (22), the only reading allowed is that jumping is What makes verbal reduplication such as (17) iterative, i.e. there must be more than one instance different from nominal reduplication is that the of repeated jumping. members of the reading events are non-quantized ngo5 tiu3 tiu3 ha5 gok3dak1 and cumulative. Conceptually, an instance of read- (22) ing counts as reading, no matter how long it lasts. 1sg jump jump Dur feel Also, adding up two instances of reading would tou5ngo6 also be interpreted reading. In other words, atelic hungry predicates such as tai2 syu1 ‘read book’ in Can- ‘I (begin to) feel hungry while jumping.’ tonese are cumulative. Let x and y be distinct (iterative reading only) atomic events, and tai2 syu1 read be predicate The fact that (22) cannot be durative can naturally over each of them. The interpretationsJ K above are be explained by the cumulativity and quantization formalized in (19) below: contrast. (19) read (x) ∧ read (y) = 1 J K J K (23) jump (x) ∧ jump (y) = 1 read (x ⊕ y) = 1 J K J K J K (24) jump (y) → ¬y < x = 1 What the durative interpretation of verbal redupli- J K cation tells us is that it must denote a sum of mul- If (23) is true, then (24) is necessarily true, i.e. tiple subevents as members, otherwise one should the atomic event y must not be a proper subpart be able to find verbal reduplication examples that of the atomic event x (cf. definition (8)). Since are punctual (i.e. not durative). However, since 6Similar to English, one would judge (21) as acceptable if 5Note that the two occurrences in (17) are not contiguous, there was an implicit object that gives some other meaning. thus it is distinct from verb reduplication. (21) intends only the literal meaning of ‘jump’.

282 PACLIC-27

tiu3 ‘jump’ is punctual and quantized, the sum of Since reduplication and degree markers like hou2 multiple instances of it must be a proper superset ‘very’ cannot cooccur and one of them must ap- of each individual instance, therefore the redupli- pear in the utterance, they are in complementary cation is interpreted as an iterative event, but not a distribution and must denote similar function. durative one. Section 3 showed that adjective predicates are This section has shown that the summation for- internally complex, based on previous studies on mulation naturally handles the two kinds of verb scale and degrees. Following Grano (2011) and reduplication without stipulating summation it- Grano and Kennedy (2012)’s analysis of Man- self. The choice between durative reading of one darin, elements like ‘very’ in Chinese denote instance of the same event and the iterative read- a morpheme that turns a bare adjective into a ing that represents multiple instances can be pre- degree-marked element7. More specifically, the dicted solely by the nature of the event denoted by assertion of the degree-marked adjective would in- the base verb. If the base form is cumulative, the volve a morpheme pos , which provides the con- summation function returns a durative event; if the textual standard to determineJ K whether the object in base form is quantized, summation returns an iter- question meets the standard for the given property. ative reading. Since reduplication also denotes the assertion that an entity meets a certain standard, one can say that 5.3 Adjectives reduplication shares the same position as pos , by There are two independent issues in the interpre- the distribution shown above. J K tation of adjectives. The first one concerns the sta- The second issue is the diminutive interpreta- tus of reduplication as a semantic function and a tion as a counterexample of to the present sum- syntactic head in the domain of adjectives. The mation theory. Abraham (2005) investigates how second issue is the apparent contradiction between reduplication can provide diminutive interpreta- summation and the hedging and diminutive read- tion, assuming reduplication was a iconic manifes- ing. This section will show that reduplication is tation of multiplicity. The data for diminitive redu- indeed one of the variants that denotes degree, plication cited in Abraham (2005) and Kouwen- alongside hou2 ‘very’ and other degree markers, berg and LaCharite´ (2005) include verbs and ad- such as gei2 ‘fairly’. It will also be shown that jectives, but the adjective examples are colour the diminutive reading does not contradict summa- terms and other adjectives that can describe part tion or plurality in general, echoing previous stud- of an entity, as in (28) and (29). ies on diminutive reduplication (Abraham, 2005; Kouwenberg and LaCharite,´ 2005). (28) a. Base form: red ‘red’ Regarding the first issue, the distribution of b. redi-redi ‘reddish, red-spotted’ reduplication shows that the reduplication mor- Caribbean Creoles (Abraham, 2005, p.552) pheme should be a functional head asserting some sort of degree. By comparing (25) and (26) against (29) a. Base form: brok ‘to break’ the ungrammatical (27), we can see that adjectival b. brokii-brokii ‘as if broken all over’ predicates must either have hou2 ‘very’ or redu- Caribbean Creoles (Kouwenberg and plication to be acceptable. LaCharite,´ 2005, p.538) (25) go2 zek3 maau1 hou2 fei4 The explanation given in Kouwenberg and that CL cat very fat LaCharite´ (2005) is that there is an intermediate ‘That cat is very fat.’ meaning of ‘red-spotted’ or ‘as if broken all over’ (26) go2 zek3 maau1 fei4 fei4 dei2 which denotes multiple instances of redness (or that CL cat fat fat Prt for (29), breaks). The dispersive reading (‘red- spotted’ or ‘as if broken all over’) is then ex- ‘That cat is fairly fat.’ tended to diminutive reading (‘reddish’ or ‘fairly/

(27) *go2 zek3 maau1 fei4 7Cantonese is similar to Mandarin in all the related as- that CL cat fat pects here. Grano (2011) also notes that (27) can provide ‘Intended: That cat is fat.’ implicit comparative reading in a contrastive context, but this is outside the focus of this paper.

283 PACLIC-27

slightly broken’). In such a theory, both Kouwen- denotes a cumulative and non-quantized predicate. berg and LaCharite´ (2005) and Abraham (2005) Cumulativity succeeds in preventing the wrong in- claim that reduplication in form does denote a terpretation for reduplication to denote intensifica- sense of multiplicity, only that the multiplicity is tion in Cantonese. By extending the cumulativity distributed to the same entity. (Kouwenberg and analysis to adjectives, it can be seen that redupli- LaCharite,´ 2005) claim that ‘(t)he real-world ef- cation does not necessarily denote ‘more’ in the fect of such scattered distribution of colour is to quantized sense, even though it denotes a summa- tone down rather than intensify the colour’. There- tion function. fore the multiple spots of the colour would re- The apparent contradiction between summation sult in a diminutive reading, through the dispersive and diminution comes from the wrong compari- reading. son. Since atomic bare adjectives do not denote However, the iconicity theory cannot explain any degree, it would be wrong to compare the de- the Cantonese examples like (26), where there gree denoted by reduplication and the non-existing cannot be a dispersive reading. Since the predicate degree denoted by the bare form. Instead, the fei4 ‘fat’ applies to the whole entity ‘cat’, but not reduplicated form should be compared to the de- part of it, it is impossible to interpret fei4 fei4 dei2 fault degree-marker hou2 ‘very’, as in (25), when as ‘being fat everywhere / all over’ in (26). The one is measuring the intensity or extent of the cumulative analysis pursued in this paper avoids assertion. Recall that Cantonese requires overt the problem with dispersive reading. Based on degree-marking, as shown by the unacceptability the discussion of distribution above, we can see of (27). Comparing the two options (25) and (26) that bare adjectives (27) are not allowed in the lan- to assert a positive degree, (25) with hou2 would guage. If we further assume that adjectival predi- denote a neutral assertion of positive degree, but cates should include the positive morpheme pos it can also be interpreted as emphasis or intensi- for any assertion, the Cantonese data wouldJ meanK fication, whereas (26) gives the diminutive, hedg- that bare adjectives do not denote the positive de- ing reading (‘slightly, fairly Adj’). Despite being gree, since they cannot assert the positive degree. a result of summation from the bare adjective, the The cumulativity analysis, on the other hand, degree denoted by reduplication should be com- explains the correct diminutive interpretation and pared to the canonical positive assertion, but not why no intensification arises. Given the formula- the atomic bare adjective. In other words, there is tion of cumulativity in (7), a predicate is consid- no contradiction between the summation formula- ered cumulative if the sum of the predicate has the tion and the diminutive interpretation. same denotation of its atomic elements. Let x and The present account is more powerful than the y be two property-denoting variables, each predi- iconicity-based theory for two reasons. First, cu- cated by fat as in (30a): mulativity is a property more widely observed J K across categories and languages, whereas iconic- (30) a. fat(x) ∧ fat(y) = 1 ity is not as prominent in explaining behaviours of b. ∀x,y [fat(x⊕y)] = 1 various constructions. The present account does c. ∀x,y [fat(x) ∧ fat(y) → ¬ y

284 PACLIC-27

(ii) in languages where reduplicated adjectives de- would then predict that the reduplicated elements note diminution, the adjectives are not marked are quantized, since the sum would have a distinct with degree and thus cumulative. Cantonese ad- denotation. jectives would belong to type (ii). On the one The advantage of the present proposal is that the hand, Cantonese adjective reduplication denotes notions of cumulativity and quantization are inde- diminution. On the other hand, Cantonese adjec- pendently testable without reduplication. For lan- tives alone do not carry degree, as revealed by the guages that show reduplication, knowing the cu- observation that it requires degree marking. mulativity and quantization properties can predict This analysis does not exclude the possibility the reading of reduplication. For unreduplicated that the two options can co-exist in the same lan- base forms that are cumulative, such as paau2 guage, as we have already observed such cases bou6 ‘lit: run step, i.e. to jog’ in (31), the present in Cantonese verbs, where both cumulative and proposal predicts that its reduplicated form would quantized predicates are possible within the same denote the same predicate, i.e. a durative, atelic category. Our Cantonese adjectives are exclu- event. On the other hand, in a base form that is sively cumulative, but it does not mean that it is punctual, such as tiu3 sing2 ‘jump rope’ in (32), impossible for other languages to show category- each instance of jump must be quantized because internal variations in terms of cumulativity and the sum of two jumps cannot be described as a quantization. What the present analysis predicts is jump. In this case, it correctly predicts that the fe- that the two subtypes of adjectives would each dis- licitous reading in sentence (32) must be iterative, play a different meaning in their respective redu- but not a reading of a single prolonged jumping- plication forms, if they exist at all in such a lan- action. guage. This section has explained that adjective redu- (31) keoi5 paau2 paau2 ha5 bou6 plication in Cantonese should be treated as 3sg run run Asp step diminutive because the atomic bare adjective is cu- gok3dak3 tou5ngo6 mulative. By showing that we should be compar- feel hungry ing reduplication forms only to degree-marked ad- ‘S/he feels hungry while jogging.’ jectives, instead of the base form, we conclude that there is indeed no contradiction between the sum- (32) keoi5 tiu3 tiu3 ha5 sing2 gok3dak3 mation treatment to reduplication and its diminu- 3sg jump jump Asp rope feel tive interpretation. By analogy, adjectives with- tou5ngo6 out degree-marking are similar to verbs without hungry aspect-marking or nouns without classifiers or de- ‘S/he feels hungry while jumping rope.’ terminers, in the sense that bare verbs and bare nouns do not denote instantiated arguments, but The present analysis shows that reduplication 8 only kinds of object or events in an abstract sense. can be formalized as a summation process , while the difference across categories in their respective 6 Implications interpretations can be resolved with the notions of cumulativity and quantization. This step allows The present hypothesis that reduplication denotes us to apply semantic functions independently of summation is confirmed only with Cantonese data. syntactic categories. Since there can be variance However, it can also be tested by cross-linguistic of cumulativity and quantization within the same data. Various pragmatic interpretation are dis- category, as observed in mass nouns and bare plu- cussed in the literature (Regier, 1994). Regier sug- ral count nouns being cumulative and quantified gests notions like ‘lack of specificity’ and ‘non- count nouns being quantized, the cumulativity and uniformity’ as subtypes of meanings that can be quantization contrast in different cases of redupli- denoted by reduplication. These can potentially cation should not be solely attributed to a differ- be formalized as elements with fuzzy boundaries ence in category. This also raises the question or multiple degrees along a scale. In languages 8 where reduplication denotes intensification, the A natural next step is to extend the current analysis to present analysis can also be extended to account the bisyllabic full reduplications, commonly known as the AABB and ABAB patterns. This is, however, beyond the for the increased degree through summation. This scope of this study.

285 PACLIC-27

of the traditional notion of ’category’. More pre- iconicity, pages 547–568. cisely, if the semantic functions are shared across Beavers, J. (2008). Scalar complexity and the struc- categories, then what is the role of categories ture of events, pages 245–265. Berlin: Mouton de in grammar? Independently, there are decompo- Gruyter. sitional proposals in syntax that explicitly sug- Bennett, M. and Partee, B. (1972). Towards the logic of tense and aspect in English. Report for the Sys- gest parallel structure between the nominal and tem Development Corporation. Compositionality in the verbal domains (Borer, 2005a; Borer, 2005b; Formal Semantics, pages 59–109. Megerdoomian, 2008) and between the verbal and Borer, H. (2005a). Structuring Sense: Volume 1: In adjectival domains (Kennedy and McNally, 2005; Name Only. Oxford University Press. Beavers, 2008; Ramchand, 2012). Wouldn’t it be Borer, H. (2005b). Structuring Sense: Volume II: The desirable to have a unified theory across lexical Normal Course of Events, volume 2. Oxford Uni- categories? Due to the limited scope of this study, versity Press, USA. we will leave the issue here for future research. Chakraborty, T. and Bandyopadhyay, S. (2009). Iden- tification of reduplication in Bengali corpus and 7 Conclusion their semantic analysis: A rule-based approach. In 23rd International Conference on Computational The main goal of this paper is to explain the cross- Linguistics, page 73. categorial behaviour of reduplication in Can- Cheng, L. L. S. (2012). Counting and classifiers. Ox- tonese. ford University Press. De Rijk, R. P. and De Coene, A. (2008). Standard This paper has shown that it is possible to inter- Basque: A progressive grammar. MIT Press. pret reduplicated forms in lexical categories (i.e. Grano, T. and Kennedy, C. (2012). Mandarin transi- nouns, verbs and adjectives) under the same func- tive comparatives and the grammar of measurement. tion, summation. Whenever reduplication occurs, Journal of East Asian Linguistics, 21:219–266. the atomic elements are added up and put into a Heim, I. and Kratzer, A. (1998). Semantics in genera- collection. We argue that the difference in inter- tive grammar, volume 13. Wiley-Blackwell. pretations depends solely on the cumulativity and Kennedy, C. and McNally, L. (2005). Scale structure, quantization of the element, but not its category. degree modification, and the semantics of gradable Nominal reduplication returns a superset of its el- predicates. Language, pages 345–381. Kouwenberg, S. and LaCharite,´ D. (2005). Less is ements, which conforms with the fact that classi- more: Evidence from diminutive reduplication in fier phrases in Cantonese denote individuated el- Carribbean Creole languages. pages 533–545. ements and is thus quantized. Verbal reduplica- Krifka, M. (1998). The origins of telicity. Events and tion can be either cumulative or quantized, de- grammar, 197:235. pending on the aktionsart of the individual verbal Krifka, M. (2001). The mereological approach to as- predicate. Adjectival reduplication is cumulative, pectual composition. Conference Perspectives on due to its divisibility into subparts. The present Aspect. University of Utrecht, OTS. analysis bears two implications. It captures the Liu, C.-S. L. (2012). Reduplication of adjectives in Chinese: a default state. Journal of East Asian Lin- cross-categorial behaviour in semantic terms and guistics. provides a basis for future research on the formal Megerdoomian, K. (2008). Parallel nominal and ver- semantic properties of reduplication across lan- bal projections. Current studies in linguistics series, guages. 45:73. Ramchand, G. (2012). Scalar structure across cate- Acknowledgments gories: V, P vs. A*. CASTL, Univeristy of Tromsø. Regier, T. (1994). A preliminary study of the semantics I thank Ronnie Wilbur and Chuck Bradley for of reduplication. sharing their insights and critical comments at ear- Rothstein, S. (2004). Structuring Events. Blackwell. lier stages of this project. I am grateful to the Rubino, C. (2011). Reduplication. In Dryer, M. S. three anonymous reviewers for constructive sug- and Haspelmath, M., editors, The World Atlas of gestions. Language Structures Online. Max Planck Digital Li- brary, Munich. Xiang, M. (2005). Some topics in comparative con- References structions. PhD thesis, Michigan State University. Classifier Structures in Mandarin Abraham, W. (2005). Intensity and diminution trig- Zhang, N. N. (2013). gered by reduplicating morphology: Janus-faced Chinese. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

286