Free Will: the Basics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Free Will: the Basics 1 Free Will: The Basics 1.1 Introduction Are we morally responsible for what we do? Ordinarily, we take it for granted that we are. You might feel guilty about forgetting your moth- er’s birthday, or declining a friend’s party invitation when you knew they really wanted you to go. If your mother forgets your birthday, or your friend declines your invitation, you might resent them for it, and you might (or might not) forgive them later; whereas, if a friend does something kind for you, you might be grateful to them. These emotional responses are central to our lives, and they are part and parcel of our conception of ourselves and others as bearers of moral responsibility. If we were to think that we are not really morally responsible for what we and others do, it would be inappropriate to feel guilty when we harm others, or resentful or grateful when other people do things that harm or benefit us. So, what are the conditions under which someone is truly morally responsible for what they do? That’s a big question, and this book focuses on just one aspect of it, namely freedom of the will . Our starting point is that one requirement that must be satisfied if someone is to be morally responsible for a given act, such as doing a favour for a friend, is that one perform the act freely . It’s easy to see why acting freely looks like a plausible requirement on moral responsibility. Imagine, for example, that it turns out that the reason your friend declined your invitation was that she was coerced into doing it: some deranged enemy of yours, hell-bent on ensuring that your party is a failure, had made it clear that if she were to accept, there would be terrible repercussions for her and all her family. In that case, it would certainly be inappropriate for you to resent her for declining 1 2 Free Will: An Introduction the invitation, and it would be inappropriate because she didn’t decline freely. We might put this in other words by saying that she didn’t really have a choice about whether to decline. Another kind of situation that seems to remove or diminish moral responsibility concerns one’s mental state at the time of the action. Consider ‘crimes of passion’, where the perpetrator is so overwhelmed by their emotional state – anger, say – that they lose their ability to control their actions. A woman who has been subjected to domestic abuse over a long period of time finally cracks and – without premedi- tation – stabs her husband to death. Or perhaps she discovers him in the throes of passion with another woman, and – again without premeditation – kills them both. Such cases are legal and moral mine- fields, but insofar as we take the perpetrators of such acts to lack or have a lower degree of responsibility for their action, we do so because we judge that they were not fully in control of what they were doing. And, again, we might put this by saying that they were not acting freely , or of their own free will . A third kind of case concerns the personal history of the person whose action we’re evaluating. Imagine that your car is stolen. You very much resent the perpetrator of this crime – let’s call her Carly. When Carly is apprehended, however, you discover a lot of facts about her life history. She was born into a family of car thieves, was taught to break into cars at a very young age and was expected to assist her parents in their nightly car-thieving rounds, and was generally lacking in any kind of moral education: she was praised for doing some things (stealing cars, for example) and punished for others, but was never taught or encouraged to think about the reasons why some acts are apparently praiseworthy and others merit punishment. Having learned all of this, you might take the view that Carly is not really morally responsible for stealing your car after all: it is really her parents who are to blame for having raised her in the way they did. Carly is disposed to steal cars without even considering whether doing so is right or wrong, but this aspect of her character is one that she was not responsible for forming: it is a result of her upbringing, and she had no control over how that went. This third kind of case might start to make you feel a little uncom- fortable, because, of course, we are all the product of a certain kind of upbringing. Most of us are not brought up to be car thieves – indeed, unlike Carly, we may have been brought up to think carefully about the difference between right and wrong. But that we have that kind of character is just as much a product of our upbringing as Carly’s character is a product of her upbringing; and – you might start to worry – we are Free Will: The Basics 3 therefore no more morally responsible for our behaviour than Carly is. After all, we had no more choice over who our parents are than she did. Moreover, we are at the mercy not only of the upbringing our parents subjected us to, but also the genes that they endowed us with; and it is entirely possible that many aspects of our character are also influenced by our genetic make-up. And, of course, the same point applies to our parents, too. We might be inclined to blame Carly’s parents, rather than Carly, for her car-stealing habit, but they, in turn, were the products of their own upbringing and genetic make-up every bit as much as Carly was. And again, the same point applies to our own parents as well. The question all of this raises is: Where, if anywhere, does the buck stop – and, if it stops anywhere, why does it stop just there? Here’s one way you might try to answer that question. Thinking about Carly, you might say: Well, whether or not Carly is morally responsible for stealing my car depends on whether her upbringing and so on determined her to steal the car, or whether instead she still had a choice about whether to steal it or not. Perhaps her upbringing strongly disposed her towards a life of crime, but perhaps, nonetheless, she was able to do otherwise than steal the car. After all, presumably earlier that evening she was sitting down thinking about what she was going to do later on, and after thinking about it, she decided that she would go out car-stealing. But – we might suppose – she didn’t have to make that decision. She could have decided to stay at home instead, or go to the cinema, or do what- ever else she was considering doing. In that case, she really is morally responsible for stealing your car. If, on the other hand, her upbringing and so on really did determine that there was only one decision she could make in the circumstances – viz , to go out car- stealing – then she isn’t morally responsible for it. This brings us to what is sometimes known as ‘the problem of free will’ (although, as we shall see, there is more than one problem of free will), namely, the problem of the apparent incompatibility of free will with determinism . The basic idea here is that if someone is determined to behave in the way that they do – if Carly, for example, is determined to steal your car by her upbringing, current circumstances and other factors – then it would appear that they do not act freely , since there is nothing else they could have done. In other words, they could not have done otherwise than what they actually did (in Carly’s case, stealing your car). If being fully determined to behave in a certain way by one’s upbringing (or whatever) deprives one of the ability to do otherwise, and if being able to do otherwise is required for acting freely, then being so determined is incompatible with acting freely. And, finally, if acting 4 Free Will: An Introduction freely is required for being morally responsible for that act, then being determined to act is incompatible with moral responsibility. The argument just rehearsed is known as the ‘Consequence Argument’, and we’ll come back to it in §1.4. Philosophers tend to fall into two broad camps when it comes to the Consequence Argument. Some are in fundamental sympathy with it: they think that determinism and free will just can’t be compatible. Such philosophers are known, unsurpris- ingly, as incompatibilists . Other philosophers, on the other hand, think there is something fishy about the Consequence Argument. They think that determinism and free will don’t need to be at odds with one another. For obvious reasons, these philosophers are known as compatibilists . (Actually, this is oversimplifying the situation. Some incompatibilists are motivated not by the Consequence Argument but by other argu- ments for the incompatibility of free will and determinism. We’ll come back to these other arguments in §1.5.) The Consequence Argument gets its intuitive pull from the thought that acting freely requires, to use Daniel Dennett’s apt phrase, ‘elbow room’. If I freely decide whether to steal a car or go to my friend’s party, surely I could have made a different decision: the decision not to steal the car, say, or the decision to go to the party after all.
Recommended publications
  • Agency: Moral Identity and Free Will
    D Agency AVID Moral Identity and Free Will W DAVID WEISSMAN EISSMAN There is agency in all we do: thinking, doing, or making. We invent a tune, play, or use it to celebrate an occasion. Or we make a conceptual leap and ask more ab- stract ques� ons about the condi� ons for agency. They include autonomy and self- appraisal, each contested by arguments immersing us in circumstances we don’t control. But can it be true we that have no personal responsibility for all we think Agency and do? Agency: Moral Ident ty and Free Will proposes that delibera� on, choice, and free will emerged within the evolu� onary history of animals with a physical advantage: Moral Identity organisms having cell walls or exoskeletons had an internal space within which to protect themselves from external threats or encounters. This defense was both and Free Will structural and ac� ve: such organisms could ignore intrusions or inhibit risky behav- ior. Their capaci� es evolved with � me: inhibi� on became the power to deliberate and choose the manner of one’s responses. Hence the ability of humans and some other animals to determine their reac� ons to problema� c situa� ons or to informa- � on that alters values and choices. This is free will as a material power, not as the DAVID WEISSMAN conclusion to a conceptual argument. Having it makes us morally responsible for much we do. It prefi gures moral iden� ty. A GENCY Closely argued but plainly wri� en, Agency: Moral Ident ty and Free Will speaks for autonomy and responsibility when both are eclipsed by ideas that embed us in his- tory or tradi� on.
    [Show full text]
  • Answering the New Atheists: How Science Points to God and to the Benefits of Christianity
    Answering the New Atheists: How Science Points to God and to the Benefits of Christianity Anthony Walsh Boise State University Series in Philosophy of Religion Copyright © 2018 Vernon Press, an imprint of Vernon Art and Science Inc, on behalf of the author. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Vernon Art and Science Inc. www.vernonpress.com In the Americas: In the rest of the world: Vernon Press Vernon Press 1000 N West Street, C/Sancti Espiritu 17, Suite 1200, Wilmington, Malaga, 29006 Delaware 19801 Spain United States Series in Philosophy of Religion Library of Congress Control Number: 2018904925 ISBN: 978-1-62273-390-3 Cover design by Vernon Press using elements by Kjpargeter - Kotkoa - Freepik.com, geralt – pixabay.com Product and company names mentioned in this work are the trademarks of their re- spective owners. While every care has been taken in preparing this work, neither the authors nor Vernon Art and Science Inc. may be held responsible for any loss or dam- age caused or alleged to be caused directly or indirectly by the information contained in it. Table of Contents Acknowledgements v Preface vii Chapter 1 Science Points the Way to God 1 Chapter 2 Christianity, Rationality, and Militant New Atheism 15 Chapter 3 Christianity, Atheism, and Morality 29 Chapter 4 Christianity, Western Democracy, and Cultural Marxism 43 Chapter 5 The Big Bang and Fine Tuning of the Universe 59 Chapter 6 Earth: The Privileged Planet 75 Chapter 7 Cosmological Fine-Tuning and the Multiverse 91 Chapter 8 Abiogenesis: The Search for the Origin of Life 107 Chapter 9 Cracks in Neo-Darwinism: Micro is not Macro 125 Chapter 10 Answering the Tough Questions: God of the Gaps, Free Will, and the Problem of Evil 141 Chapter Footnotes 157 References 171 Index 187 Acknowledgements I would first of all like to thank commissioning editor, Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • New Atheism and the Scientistic Turn in the Atheism Movement MASSIMO PIGLIUCCI
    bs_bs_banner MIDWEST STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY Midwest Studies In Philosophy, XXXVII (2013) New Atheism and the Scientistic Turn in the Atheism Movement MASSIMO PIGLIUCCI I The so-called “New Atheism” is a relatively well-defined, very recent, still unfold- ing cultural phenomenon with import for public understanding of both science and philosophy.Arguably, the opening salvo of the New Atheists was The End of Faith by Sam Harris, published in 2004, followed in rapid succession by a number of other titles penned by Harris himself, Richard Dawkins, Daniel Dennett, Victor Stenger, and Christopher Hitchens.1 After this initial burst, which was triggered (according to Harris himself) by the terrorist attacks on September 11, 2001, a number of other authors have been associated with the New Atheism, even though their contributions sometimes were in the form of newspapers and magazine articles or blog posts, perhaps most prominent among them evolutionary biologists and bloggers Jerry Coyne and P.Z. Myers. Still others have published and continue to publish books on atheism, some of which have had reasonable success, probably because of the interest generated by the first wave. This second wave, however, often includes authors that explicitly 1. Sam Harris, The End of Faith: Religion, Terror, and the Future of Reason (New York: W.W. Norton, 2004); Sam Harris, Letter to a Christian Nation (New York: Vintage, 2006); Richard Dawkins, The God Delusion (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2006); Daniel C. Dennett, Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon (New York: Viking Press, 2006); Victor J. Stenger, God:The Failed Hypothesis: How Science Shows That God Does Not Exist (Amherst, NY: Prometheus, 2007); Christopher Hitchens, God Is Not Great: How Religion Poisons Everything (New York: Twelve Books, 2007).
    [Show full text]
  • PDF Download the Moral Landscape Kindle
    THE MORAL LANDSCAPE PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Sam Harris | 384 pages | 04 Dec 2012 | Transworld Publishers Ltd | 9780552776387 | English | London, United Kingdom The Moral Landscape PDF Book By Marilynne Robinson. Some morals may be consistent in some form across times and cultures. Since it's possible that human well-being and moral goodness are not identical, it follows necessarily that human well-being and moral goodness are not the same, as Harris has asserted. Horgan, "Be wary of the righteous rationalist: We should reject Sam Harris's claim that science can be a moral guidepost" , Scientific American blog, Oct. I don't think, though, that the failure of this claim is fatal to the rest of Sam's claims. Immorality is knowing what is right and wrong but acting wrongly anyway. But would a life spent popping MDMA, although presumably full of "good feelings", be a peak in his moral landscape? For example, he says that there are objectively good and bad moves in chess Moral Landscape , 8. A rustic-style deck, for example, will look much better attached to a log cabin than to an ultra-modern contemporary. Morals in the US. It seems to me that morality, particularly when it is promoted for the good of the general public, ought to emphasise concern with the latter harms committed against others , if it even concerns the former "harms" committed against oneself at all. Nuzzolilli wrote a generally favorable review in a journal of the Association for Behavior Analysis International :. Now, Sam's notion that a society of equally-matched sadists and masochists would could be morally equivalent to a world of conventionally wired people is harder to defuse given his premises, but let's look at it a little critically: in fact, it doesn't take much to immediately question whether the experience of a masochist is genuinely one of equal well-being with that of a normally-adjusted individual.
    [Show full text]
  • Experimental Philosophy and Free Will Tamler Sommers* University of Houston
    Philosophy Compass 5/2 (2010): 199–212, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2009.00273.x Experimental Philosophy and Free Will Tamler Sommers* University of Houston Abstract This paper develops a sympathetic critique of recent experimental work on free will and moral responsibility. Section 1 offers a brief defense of the relevance of experimental philosophy to the free will debate. Section 2 reviews a series of articles in the experimental literature that probe intuitions about the ‘‘compatibility question’’—whether we can be free and morally responsible if determinism is true. Section 3 argues that these studies have produced valuable insights on the fac- tors that influence our judgments on the compatibility question, but that their general approach suffers from significant practical and philosophical difficulties. Section 4 reviews experimental work addressing other aspects of the free will ⁄ moral responsibility debate, and section 5 concludes with a discussion of avenues for further research. 1. Introduction The precise meaning of ‘experimental philosophy’ is a matter of controversy even among its practitioners, but all agree that it refers to a movement which employs the methods of empirical science to shed light on philosophical debates. Most commonly, experimental philosophers attempt to probe ordinary intuitions about a particular case or question in hopes of learning about the psychological processes that underlie these intuitions (Knobe 2007).1 The unifying conviction behind the movement is that many deep philosophical problems ‘can only be properly addressed by immersing oneself in the messy, contingent, highly variable truths about how human beings really are’.2 And the problem that has received the most attention from experimental philosophers thus far is the problem of free will.
    [Show full text]
  • Free Will: Hail and Farewell
    Essays in the Philosophy of Humanism © 2019 The American Humanist Association volume 27 (2019), article 6, 98-124. ISSN 1522-7340 (print), 2052-8388 (online) Free Will: Hail and Farewell James A. Montanye Independent scholar, Falls Church, VA [email protected] This essay traces the evolution of the free will concept, from Plato to the present. It examines interpretations offered by theologians, political philosophers, philosophers of mind and consciousness, neuroscientists, evolutionists, legal scholars, and economists. The essay illuminates the concept’s instrumental use as an artifice for manipulating behavioral adaptations to the scarcity of economic resources. Macroeconomic and ngram data reveal these manipulations as having locked Western civilization into centuries of social and economic stagnation. Keywords: free will, consciousness, economics, prosperity, scarcity, competition, neuroscience, compatibilism, incompatibilism, ngrams “The persistence of the traditional free will problem in philosophy seems to me something of a scandal. After all these centuries of writing about free will, it does not seem to me that we have made very much progress.” John Searle (2007, 37) “A flood of ink has been spilled, especially in the modern era, on how to understand the concept of being able to do otherwise.” Timothy O’Connor (2016) “...the whole arcane issue about free will is a miscast concept, based on social and psychological beliefs held at particular times in human history that have not been borne out and/or are at odds with modern scientific knowledge about the nature of our universe.” Michael Gazzaniga (2011, 219) “...if we no longer entertain the luxury of a belief in the ‘magic of the soul,’ then there is little else to offer in support of the concept of free will.” Anthony Cashmore (2010, 1) [98] 1.
    [Show full text]
  • How the New Atheists Are Reminding the Humanities of Their Place and Purpose in Society
    University of Louisville ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository Electronic Theses and Dissertations 12-2018 The emperor's new clothes: how the new atheists are reminding the humanities of their place and purpose in society. David Ira Buckner University of Louisville Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.library.louisville.edu/etd Part of the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Buckner, David Ira, "The emperor's new clothes: how the new atheists are reminding the humanities of their place and purpose in society." (2018). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. Paper 3112. https://doi.org/10.18297/etd/3112 This Doctoral Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository. This title appears here courtesy of the author, who has retained all other copyrights. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE EMPEROR’S NEW CLOTHES: HOW THE NEW ATHEISTS ARE REMINDING THE HUMANITIES OF THEIR PLACE AND PURPOSE IN SOCIETY By David Ira Buckner B.S., East Tennessee State University, 2006 M.A., East Tennessee State University, 2008 A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the College of Arts and Sciences of the University of Louisville In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy
    [Show full text]
  • Responding to the New Atheism: Scientific and Religious Perspectives
    THE WHEATLEY INSTITUTION Responding to the New Atheism: Scientific and Religious Perspectives Richard N. Williams and Edwin E. Gantt, Editors Wheatley Publications Responding to the New Atheism: Scientific and Religious Perspectives Richard N. Williams and Edwin E. Gantt, Editors Wheatley Publications The Wheatley Institution Brigham Young University 392 Hinckley Center Provo, UT 84602 Main: 801-422-5883 Fax: 801-422-0017 Email: [email protected] http://wheatleyinstitution.byu.edu Donor Liaison: Tom Mullen Phone: 801-422-4476 Email: [email protected] CONTENTS Responding to the New Atheism . 1 Richard N. Williams and Edwin E. Gantt Defending Against the Threat of the New Atheism . 7 Dinesh D’Souza, King’s College The Possibility of Atheism; the Place of Faith . .15 James E. Faulconer, Richard L. Evans Professor of Religious Understanding; Professor of Philosophy, Brigham Young University Scientific Fundamentalism and Its Cultural Impact . 23 Karl W. Giberson, Eastern Nazarene College Physics and Faith . 31 Stephen M. Barr, University of Delaware The Argument for Intelligent Design in Biology . 37 Michael J. Behe, Lehigh University Outlines of an LDS Response to the New Atheism. 45 Edwin E. Gantt and Richard N. Williams, Brigham Young University RESPONDING TO THE NEW ATHEISM Richard N. Williams and Edwin E. Gantt t may be lamentable, but is nonetheless true, that many trustworthy, and just plain worthy in the intellectual life of I people speak and write English without ever consult- our culture, as well as what is incoherent, erroneous, and ing a dictionary of the English language or a grammar text. unworthy. Many, if not most Americans will defend our constitutional This is most often not an easy thing to do.
    [Show full text]
  • Reflections on Sam Harris' “Free Will”
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia (Università degli Studi di Bari) RIVISTA INTERNAZIONALE DI FILOSOFIA E PSICOLOGIA ISSN 2039-4667; E-ISSN 2239-2629 DOI: 10.4453/rifp.2017.0018 Vol. 8 (2017), n. 3, pp. 214-230 STUDI Reflections on Sam Harris’ “Free Will” Daniel C. Dennett(α) Ricevuto: 11 aprile 2016; accettato: 10 gennaio 2017 █ Abstract In his book Free Will Sam Harris tries to persuade us to abandon the morally pernicious idea of free will. The following contribution articulates and defends a more sophisticated model of free will that is not only consistent with neuroscience and introspection but also grounds a variety of responsibility that justifies both praise and blame, reward and punishment. This begins with the long lasting parting of opinion between compatibilists (who argue that free will can live comfortably with determinism) and in- compatibilists (who deny this). While Harris dismisses compatibilism as a form of theology, this article aims at showing that Harris has underestimated and misinterpreted compatibilism and at defending a more sophisticated version of compatibilism that is impervious to Harris’ criticism. KEYWORDS: Sam Harris; Free Will; Compatibilism; Incompatibilism; Neuroscience █ Riassunto Riflessioni su “Free Will” di Sam Harris – Nel suo volume Free Will Sam Harris cerca di persua- derci ad abbandonare l’idea, a suo avviso moralmente perniciosa, del libero arbitrio. Il contributo seguente articola e difende un modello di libero arbitrio che non solo è coerente con le neuroscienze e con l’introspezione, ma che dà anche fondamento a varie forme di responsabilità, giustificando encomio, biasi- mo, premi e punizioni.
    [Show full text]
  • Free Will, Determinism, and Moral Responsibility: an Analysis of Event-Causal Incompatibilism Gunnar Footh Macalester College, [email protected]
    Macalester College DigitalCommons@Macalester College Philosophy Honors Projects Philosophy Department July 2017 Free Will, Determinism, and Moral Responsibility: An Analysis of Event-Causal Incompatibilism Gunnar Footh Macalester College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.macalester.edu/phil_honors Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Footh, Gunnar, "Free Will, Determinism, and Moral Responsibility: An Analysis of Event-Causal Incompatibilism" (2017). Philosophy Honors Projects. 10. http://digitalcommons.macalester.edu/phil_honors/10 This Honors Project is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at DigitalCommons@Macalester College. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Honors Projects by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Macalester College. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Free Will, Determinism, and Moral Responsibility: An Analysis of Event-Causal Incompatibilism By Gunnar John Footh Professor Geoffrey Gorham Department of Philosophy 4/26/17 Chapter 1: Introduction The question of moral responsibility has been around for millenia. What is moral responsibility? How do we define it? What does it mean to be a moral person? This philosophical topic alone has been analyzed and debated among philosophers for centuries. The very existence of the debates over moral responsibility and value theory as a whole evidences the importance humanity puts on answering these moral questions. It is no surprise that these topics are still being discussed and debated today. The moral responsibility-determinism debate is ongoing in contemporary philosophy, and it asks the following question: is moral responsibility reconcilable or compatible with a deterministic universe? Here I will define determinism as causal ​ determinism, the idea that every event is necessitated by antecedent events in conjunction ​ with the laws of nature.
    [Show full text]
  • Free Will: Real Or Illusion a Debate with Contributions by Christian List
    Free Will: Real or Illusion A Debate With contributions by Christian List, Gregg Caruso, and Cory Clark This is a preprint of an exchange published in The Philosopher, Vol. 108, No. 1 The published version can be found at: thephilosopher1923.org/product-page/winter-2020-the-other-animals © C. List, G. Caruso, and C. Clark Free Will: Real or Illusion? Christian List If you are a regular reader of popular science writings, the chances are that you have come across articles or books arguing that free will is an illusion. Writers such as Sam Harris, Michael Gazzaniga, and Jerry Coyne, among others, have influentially claimed that the notion of free will – a person’s capacity to choose and control his or her own actions – is refuted by modern science. They argue that human actions are caused not by people’s conscious mental states, but by physical processes in their brains and bodies and the world at large, processes over which people have no control. If this is right, the idea of free will is a remnant of a superseded, unscientific worldview. Although such free-will skepticism is not yet the established view in society, nor dominant in academic philosophy, it is gaining prominence, and if it became accepted as the truth, it would raise significant questions about the picture of humans as choice-making agents, and it would cast into doubt society’s practices of assigning responsibility to people for their actions. It seems problematic to hold a person responsible for something he or she did not freely do. Some skeptics are untroubled by these implications or even find them congenial.
    [Show full text]
  • A Libertarian Response to Dennett and Harris on Free Will John Lemos(Α)
    RIVISTA INTERNAZIONALE DI FILOSOFIA E PSICOLOGIA ISSN 2039-4667; E-ISSN 2239-2629 DOI: 10.4453/rifp.2017.0019 Vol. 8 (2017), n. 3, pp. 231-246 STUDI A Libertarian Response to Dennett and Harris on Free Will John Lemos(α) Ricevuto: 01 febbraio 2017; accettato: 24 agosto 2017 █ Abstract This article critically examines central arguments made in Sam Harris’ “Free Will” as well as key aspects of Daniel Dennett’s compatibilist conception of free will. I argue that while Dennett makes thoughtful replies to Harris’ critique of compatibilism, his compatibilism continues to be plagued by criti- cal points raised by Bruce Waller. Additionally, I argue that Harris’ rejection of the libertarian view of free will is ill-informed and I explain the basics of Robert Kane’s libertarian view, arguing that it can be de- fended against points raised by both Dennett and Harris. KEYWORDS: Free Will; Libertarianism; Compatibilism; Daniel Dennett; Sam Harris █ Riassunto Una risposta libertaria a Dennett e Harris sul libero arbitrio – Questo articolo prende critica- mente in esame gli argomenti principali presentati nel volume di Sam Harris “Free Will” e gli aspetti princi- pali della concezione compatibilista proposta da Daniel Dennett sul libero arbitrio. Intendo sostenere che Dennett, pur rispondendo accuratamente alla critica del compatibilismo proposta da Harris, sostiene un compatibilismo che resta sotto il giogo delle critiche sollevate da Bruce Waller. Inoltre, cercherò di sostenere che il rifiuto della prospettiva libertaria proposto da Harris è una posizione male informata e illustrerò i principi di fondo della prospettiva libertaria di Robert Kane, affermando che la si può difendere dalle criti- che sollevate sia da Dennett che da Harris.
    [Show full text]