Responses to Critics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Responses to Critics Responses to Critics Miriam Solomon Temple University In this paper I respond to the criticisms of Helen Longino, Alan Richardson, Naomi Oreskes and Sharyn Clough. There is discussion of the character of social knowledge, the goals of scientiªc inquiry, the connections between Social Empiricism and other approaches in science studies, productive and unproductive dissent, and the distinction between empirical and non- empirical decision vectors. My critics have engaged with Social Empiricism from a variety of perspec- tives.1 Our views have much in common. Spending some time on our dif- ferences is valuable precisely because we share enough to make the differ- ences intelligible. We can pay attention to the working details of our views. Longino Longino and I agree that normative terms should be applied at the level of the community, rather than the individual. Where we disagree is on what we mean by “community knowledge.” By “community knowledge” I mean the aggregate of the knowledge of all scientists involved in a debate. That includes dissenting parties, both groups and individuals. I think Longino has something more epistemically processed in mind: something like “the considered reºective opinion of the experts,” or, as she says in her comments, “the accepted corpus.” For Longino, “community knowledge” is different from the aggregate of the knowledge of the individuals in the community: community knowledge has been through a normative process 1. Thanks to each of the authors for their thoughts on Social Empiricism. Special thanks to Alison Wylie for proposing this as a session at 4S 2006, and for editing our papers for Perspectives on Science. Perspectives on Science 2008, vol. 16, no. 3 ©2008 by The Massachusetts Institute of Technology 280 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc.2008.16.3.280 by guest on 28 September 2021 Perspectives on Science 281 of evaluation. (I think this is also what Alan Richardson means by “science with conscience.”) I’m not sure how Longino squares this with her empha- sis on pluralism, unless she allows the “accepted corpus” to include con- trary theories. Social Empiricism is not an account of the norms of scientists, unless those scientists are interested in broader questions of science policy. Normative judgments in social empiricism are applied by those social epistemologists interested in appraising what a community does. Longino wonders whether my normative prescriptions for decision vec- tors are really necessary. She notices that basically, what I recommend is consensus when all the available empirical success is in one theory and dis- sent when different theories have different empirical success. That is so. The decision vectors come into play when considering the distribution of cognitive labor. “Dissent” covers a wide range of distributions of cognitive labor—of which consensus is in fact an extreme. Distribution of cognitive labor can be normatively inappropriate when there is too much attention paid to one theory(ies) and not enough paid to another theory(ies). Several examples in my book show that a dissent can be normatively inappropri- ate when the non-empirical decision vectors are not equally distributed. Finally, I have an instrumental conception of rationality. So I am inter- ested in discussing both what counts as appropriate ends of inquiry (truth, empirical success or whatever) and in what is conducive to achieving those ends. Alan Richardson Richardson is right about my views. I think science should be done with- out “conscience” in the Hobbesian sense. I haven’t seen “conscience” to add much of value to scientiªc inquiry and I see it as often getting in the way. I’m ºattered that Richardson sees this as a revolutionary idea. I com- pletely agree that my views are 180 degrees away from those of Charles Sanders Peirce, the metaphysician of consensus, and would add that there is much that is similarly Hegeleian (and Habermasian) in Longino’s views. Richardson worries that without consensus as a telos of inquiry, inquiry will fall apart as a normative project and “epistemic irritation” will be un- addressed. I am completely unconcerned by this. For most epistemologists and scientists, anyway, consensus is just a proxy for truth, and not in itself valuable. I argue in Social Empiricism that “truth” can be a regulative goal in science without producing either temporary or ultimate consensus. “Whig Realism,” in Chapter 3, explains how there can be truth in a the- ory without a theory being literally true. It may be that, in the present or even in the limit of inquiry, truth content is maximized by having more Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc.2008.16.3.280 by guest on 28 September 2021 282 Responses to Critics than one theory. “Epistemic irritation” can be responded to in a number of different ways, or even ignored. It is true that what motivates some scientists is a desire to prove other scientists wrong. But usually that comes together with a desire to show that their theory does better than the theory of other scientists. I would say—it is not important for a scientist to get the opposition to convert or die. (Consensus is the result of such military methods.) What matters is that a scientist develop empirical successes—especially unique empirical successes—in their own theory. Do non-empirical decision vectors “wash out” or “cancel out” in good science? They balance, but they do not disappear. One way of putting it is that they cancel out logically, but not physically. Naomi Oreskes I love all the scholarship in science studies since Kuhn and I happily de- scribe its more recent insights in the introduction of my book. I see Social Empiricism as building on these ideas. I wanted to say something clearer than, for example, Latour’s “agonistic ªeld,” and, in particular, I wanted to develop a normative voice, which is largely absent in non-philosophy sci- ence studies. When historians and sociologists write about how the “ratio- nal” is socially constituted, they are working at a descriptive level, at most describing how a particular social group demarcates the “rational” from the “irrational”. I wanted to say something normative enough about scientiªc rationality that I would be willing to go out on a limb and com- ment usefully on current scientiªc controversies, with the ultimate goal of fostering scientiªc success. I couldn’t have written Social Empiricism with- out building on the creative social epistemologies of non-philosophers such as Peter Galison, Donna Haraway, Bruno Latour, Andy Pickering and Steven Shapin. But they do not propose a normative perspective—indeed, some of them are opposed, for various theoretical reasons, to the idea of producing one—and so I tried to create one. We agree about the basic character of the rejection of continental drift. I don’t accuse Oreskes of writing that the debate had “no signiªcant social dimensions.” We disagree a little about what some of the “social dimen- sions” are. Oreskes analyses in terms of “epistemological afªnities” and I ªnd factors such as empirical salience of some data, conservatism, anti- theoretic preferences and national alliances to be important. (Some of these factors may overlap.) It is here that we need to talk more about his- torical details. For example, I see American anti-theoretical preferences as quite different from the “method of multiple working hypotheses” that was explicitly adopted by the Canadian geologist Tuzo Wilson. Wilson Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc.2008.16.3.280 by guest on 28 September 2021 Perspectives on Science 283 was much more open to continental drift than the vast majority of Ameri- can geologists. It’s ªne with me if the normative conditions for consensus are an “im- possible standard.” Fine because, according to Social Empiricism, consensus is not a normative goal. However, I don’t think the normative conditions for consensus are in fact impossible, although they occur less often than consensus occurs (scientists, like many philosophers, are rather attached to the ideology of consensus). I require for consensus that one theory has all the available empirical successes. That does not mean that it explains everything; just that other theories do not do a better job of explaining/ predicting/controlling (in brief, “handling”) particular phenomena. It means that the other theories are dispensable, not that we are at the end of inquiry. In the case of the plate tectonics theory, as Oreskes says, there were lots of difªculties still to address, either with the plate tectonics the- ory or with some other theory. If the geosyncline theory really handled seismic data that the plate tectonics theory did not, then I am happy to re- vise my assessment and say that consensus on plate tectonics theory was inappropriate. (Was anything done with MacDonald’s measurements to repeat them or extend them? Explanatory success, as I argue in my book, is a weak form of empirical success, and theories should have more than explanatory success to be worthy of pursuit.) If it was just the case that there were a number of seismic anomalies not handled well by the plate tectonics theory OR by any other theory, then consensus on plate tectonics theory was appropriate. Social Empiricism offers a framework for distinguishing scientiªcally productive dissent from dissent that is not scientiªcally productive, but is, rather, in support of other enterprises. Scientiªcally productive dissent in- volves developing empirical successes that are not available in the other theory: making new predictions, doing new experiments, explaining un- explained phenomena, and developing new technologies. If that isn’t go- ing on, then the dissenting theory does not merit serious scientiªc atten- tion.
Recommended publications
  • Science, Technology, Policy Fellowship Program Step Into Our Community and Shape Science for Society!
    STeP Science, Technology, Policy Fellowship Program Step into our community and shape science for society! A LANDMARK PROGRAM OF THE INTER-AMERICAN INSTITUTE FOR GLOBAL CHANGE RESEARCH (IAI) 2021 IAI WHO WE ARE The Inter-American Institute for Global Change Research (IAI) is an intergovernmental organization supported by 19 countries in the Americas, dedicated to pursuing the principles of scientific excellence, international cooperation, capacity building, and the full and open exchange of scientific information to increase the understanding of global change phenomena and their social-economic implications. The IAI enables a well-informed, inclusive and sustainable America, which collaboratively meets the challenges posed by global change by supporting flexible science-based policies and actions. History of the IAI In 1992, 12 nations of the Americas came together in Montevideo, Uruguay to establish the IAI. The 12 governments, in the Declaration of Montevideo, called for the Institute to develop the best possible international coordination of scientific and economic research of global change in the Americas. Since then, 7 additional nations have acceded to the treaty, and the IAI has now 19 parties in the Americas. IAI INTER-AMERICAN INSTITUTE FOR GLOBAL CHANGE RESEARCH SCIENCE, TECHNOLOGY, POLICY FELLOWSHIP The Science, Technology, Policy (STeP) Fellowship Program is an innovative landmark program of the IAI to enhance human and institutional capacities in IAI member countries and to support the provision of expert scientific advice to policy makers for the development of public policy relevant to global change. Fellows in the STeP program are placed at host government or private organizations to engage first-hand with policy and decision-makers and facilitate the uptake of scientific knowledge into policy processes.
    [Show full text]
  • Roles for Socially-Engaged Philosophy of Science in Environmental Policy
    Roles for Socially-Engaged Philosophy of Science in Environmental Policy Kevin C. Elliott Lyman Briggs College, Department of Fisheries and Wildlife, and Department of Philosophy, Michigan State University Introduction The philosophy of science has much to contribute to the formulation of public policy. Contemporary policy making draws heavily on scientific information, whether it be about the safety and effectiveness of medical treatments, the pros and cons of different economic policies, the severity of environmental problems, or the best strategies for alleviating inequality and other social problems. When science becomes relevant to public policy, however, it often becomes highly politicized, and figures on opposing sides of the political spectrum draw on opposing bodies of scientific information to support their preferred conclusions.1 One has only to look at contemporary debates over climate change, vaccines, and genetically modified foods to see how these debates over science can complicate policy making.2 When science becomes embroiled in policy debates, questions arise about who to trust and how to evaluate the quality of the available scientific evidence. For example, historians have identified a number of cases where special interest groups sought to influence policy by amplifying highly questionable scientific claims about public-health and environmental issues like tobacco smoking, climate change, and industrial pollution.3 Determining how best to respond to these efforts is a very important question that cuts across multiple
    [Show full text]
  • Breaking the Siege: Guidelines for Struggle in Science Brian Martin Faculty of Arts, University of Wollongong, NSW 2522 [email protected]
    Breaking the siege: guidelines for struggle in science Brian Martin Faculty of Arts, University of Wollongong, NSW 2522 http://www.bmartin.cc/ [email protected] When scientists come under attack, it is predictable that the attackers will use methods to minimise public outrage over the attack, including covering up the action, devaluing the target, reinterpreting what is happening, using official processes to give an appearance of justice, and intimidating people involved. To be effective in countering attacks, it is valuable to challenge each of these methods, namely by exposing actions, validating targets, interpreting actions as unfair, mobilising support and not relying on official channels, and standing up to intimidation. On a wider scale, science is constantly under siege from vested interests, especially governments and corporations wanting to use scientists and their findings to serve their agendas at the expense of the public interest. To challenge this system of institutionalised bias, the same sorts of methods can be used. ABSTRACT Key words: science; dissent; methods of attack; methods of resistance; vested interests Scientists and science under siege In 1969, Clyde Manwell was appointed to the second chair environmental issues?” (Wilson and Barnes 1995) — and of zoology at the University of Adelaide. By present-day less than one in five said no. Numerous environmental terminology he was an environmentalist, but at the time scientists have come under attack because of their this term was little known and taking an environmental research or speaking out about it (Kuehn 2004). On stand was uncommon for a scientist. Many senior figures some topics, such as nuclear power and fluoridation, it in government, business and universities saw such stands can be very risky for scientists to take a view contrary as highly threatening.
    [Show full text]
  • The Controversy Over Climate Change in the Public Sphere
    THE CONTROVERSY OVER CLIMATE CHANGE IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE by WILLIAM MOSLEY-JENSEN (Under the Direction of Edward Panetta) ABSTRACT The scientific consensus on climate change is not recognized by the public. This is due to many related factors, including the Bush administration’s science policy, the reporting of the controversy by the media, the public’s understanding of science as dissent, and the differing standards of argumentation in science and the public sphere. Al Gore’s An Inconvenient Truth was produced in part as a response to the acceptance of climate dissent by the Bush administration and achieved a rupture of the public sphere by bringing the technical issue forward for public deliberation. The rupture has been sustained by dissenters through the use of argument strategies designed to foster controversy at the expense of deliberation. This makes it incumbent upon rhetorical scholars to theorize the closure of controversy and policymakers to recognize that science will not always have the answers. INDEX WORDS: Al Gore, Argument fields, Argumentation, An Inconvenient Truth, Climate change, Climategate, Controversy, Public sphere, Technical sphere THE CONTROVERSY OVER CLIMATE CHANGE IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE by WILLIAM MOSLEY-JENSEN B.A., The University of Wyoming, 2008 A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of The University of Georgia in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree MASTER OF ARTS ATHENS, GEORGIA 2010 © 2010 William Mosley-Jensen All Rights Reserved THE CONTROVERSY OVER CLIMATE CHANGE IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE by WILLIAM MOSLEY-JENSEN Major Professor: Edward Panetta Committee: Thomas Lessl Roger Stahl Electronic Version Approved: Maureen Grasso Dean of the Graduate School The University of Georgia May 2010 iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS There are many people that made this project possible through their unwavering support and love.
    [Show full text]
  • Lessons from the History of UK Science Policy
    Lessons from the History of UK Science Policy August 2019 2 Science Policy History Foreword The British Academy is the UK’s national body for the humanities and social sciences. Our purpose is to deepen understanding of people, societies and cultures, enabling everyone to learn, progress and prosper. The Academy inspires, supports and promotes outstanding achievement and global advances in the humanities and social sciences. We are a fellowship of over 1000 of the most outstanding academics, an international community of leading experts focused on people, culture and societies, and are the voice for the humanities and social sciences.1 The British Academy aims to use insights from the past and the present to help shape the future, by influencing policy and affecting change in the UK and overseas. Given this, the Academy is well-placed to bring humanities and social science insight from the past into policymaking for the present and the future. One way to do this is in using historical insights to inform policymaking – ‘looking back to look forward’. To support these efforts, the Academy’s public policy team in collaboration with the Department for Business, Energy and Industrial Strategy, has undertaken a new programme of work on policy histories. The policy histories series develop historical analyses for individual policy areas. These analyses are used to provide: • a structured, rigorous and objective account of the history of a given policy area and the significance of key milestones in context, • an informed basis for analysis and insights from the timelines as well as dialogue and discussion about what history can tell us about the future.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is a Science Diplomat?
    The Hague Journal of Diplomacy 15 (2020) 409-423 brill.com/hjd What Is a Science Diplomat? Lorenzo Melchor Spanish Foundation for Science and Technology (FECYT), Madrid, Spain; former FECYT Science Adviser in the Spanish Embassy in London, United Kingdom [email protected] Received: 22 May 2020; revised: 4 July 2020; accepted: 21 July 2020 Summary The COVID-19 crisis has shown how countries initially responded to a global chal- lenge on their own, instead of relying on a multilateral science diplomacy — based response. Although, science diplomacy has received great attention for the past de- cade, its meaning and the nature of the diverse practitioners involved remain elusive. Science diplomacy is a transboundary field sitting across national borders, policy frameworks and stakeholders of all natures and professional backgrounds. But what is a science diplomat? What science diplomacy roles formally exist? Who can become a science diplomat? What knowledge and skills are required? This practitioner’s essay proposes a typology of science diplomacy practitioners who bring science, technology, innovation, foreign policy and the international political system altogether closer in either institutionalised or non-institutionalised roles, and it also provides guidance for pursuing a career in science diplomacy. These science diplomats may promote na- tional competitiveness but also facilitate multilateral responses to global challenges. Keywords science diplomacy – science diplomat – science counsellor – science attaché – science adviser – science advice – science-policy interface – knowledge diplomacy – COVID-19 © Lorenzo Melchor, 2020 | doi:10.1163/1871191X-bja10026 This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the CC BY 4.0Downloaded license. from Brill.com10/01/2021 11:43:18AM via free access 410 Melchor 1 Introduction1 The COVID-19 outbreak has caused a profound global public health and socio- economic crisis.
    [Show full text]
  • Advancing Science Communication.Pdf
    SCIENCETreise, Weigold COMMUNICATION / SCIENCE COMMUNICATORS Scholars of science communication have identified many issues that may help to explain why sci- ence communication is not as “effective” as it could be. This article presents results from an exploratory study that consisted of an open-ended survey of science writers, editors, and science communication researchers. Results suggest that practitioners share many issues of concern to scholars. Implications are that a clear agenda for science communication research now exists and that empirical research is needed to improve the practice of communicating science. Advancing Science Communication A Survey of Science Communicators DEBBIE TREISE MICHAEL F. WEIGOLD University of Florida The writings of science communication scholars suggest twodominant themes about science communication: it is important and it is not done well (Hartz and Chappell 1997; Nelkin 1995; Ziman 1992). This article explores the opinions of science communication practitioners with respect to the sec- ond of these themes, specifically, why science communication is often done poorly and how it can be improved. The opinions of these practitioners are important because science communicators serve as a crucial link between the activities of scientists and the public that supports such activities. To intro- duce our study, we first review opinions as to why science communication is important. We then examine the literature dealing with how well science communication is practiced. Authors’Note: We would like to acknowledge NASA’s Marshall Space Flight Center for provid- ing the funds todothis research. We alsowant tothank Rick Borcheltforhis help with the collec - tion of data. Address correspondence to Debbie Treise, University of Florida, College of Journalism and Communications, P.O.
    [Show full text]
  • Dissent and Heresy in Medicine: Models, Methods, and Strategies Brian Martin*
    ARTICLE IN PRESS Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 713–725 Dissent and heresy in medicine: models, methods, and strategies Brian Martin* Science, Technology and Society, University of Wollongong, Wollongong NSW 2522, Australia Abstract Understandingthe dynamics of dissent and heresy in medicine can be aided by the use of suitable frameworks. The dynamics of the search for truth vary considerably dependingon whether the search is competitive or cooperative and on whether truth is assumed to be unitary or plural. Insights about dissent and heresy in medicine can be gained by making comparisons to politics and religion. To explain adherence to either orthodoxy or a challenging view, partisans use a standard set of explanations; social scientists use these plus others, especially symmetrical analyses. There is a wide array of methods by which orthodoxy maintains its domination and marginalises challengers. Finally, challengers can adopt various strategies in order to gain a hearing. r 2003 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved. Keywords: Dissent; Heresy; Orthodoxy; Medical knowledge; Medical research; Strategies Introduction challenges to it, there is a tremendous variation in ideas, support, visibility and outcome. The conventional view is that the human immunode- What is the best term for referringto a challengeto ficiency virus, HIV, is responsible for AIDS. But for orthodoxy? Wolpe (1994) offers an illuminating many years, a few scientists have espoused the incom- typology of internal challenges. One type of challenge patible view that HIV is harmless and is not responsible is to ‘‘knowledge products’’ such as disease for AIDS (Duesberg, 1996; Maggiore, 1999). The issue prognoses that question current knowledge—namely, came to world attention in 2001 when South African what are considered to be facts—while operating President Thabo Mbeki invited a number of the so- within conventional assumptions about scientific meth- called HIV/AIDS dissidents to join an advisory panel.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientists Dissent List
    A SCIENTIFIC DISSENT FROM DARWINISM “We are skeptical of claims for the ability of random mutation and natural selection to account for the complexity of life. Careful examination of the evidence for Darwinian theory should be encouraged.” This was last publicly updated April 2020. Scientists listed by doctoral degree or current position. Philip Skell* Emeritus, Evan Pugh Prof. of Chemistry, Pennsylvania State University Member of the National Academy of Sciences Lyle H. Jensen* Professor Emeritus, Dept. of Biological Structure & Dept. of Biochemistry University of Washington, Fellow AAAS Maciej Giertych Full Professor, Institute of Dendrology Polish Academy of Sciences Lev Beloussov Prof. of Embryology, Honorary Prof., Moscow State University Member, Russian Academy of Natural Sciences Eugene Buff Ph.D. Genetics Institute of Developmental Biology, Russian Academy of Sciences Emil Palecek Prof. of Molecular Biology, Masaryk University; Leading Scientist Inst. of Biophysics, Academy of Sci., Czech Republic K. Mosto Onuoha Shell Professor of Geology & Deputy Vice-Chancellor, Univ. of Nigeria Fellow, Nigerian Academy of Science Ferenc Jeszenszky Former Head of the Center of Research Groups Hungarian Academy of Sciences M.M. Ninan Former President Hindustan Academy of Science, Bangalore University (India) Denis Fesenko Junior Research Fellow, Engelhardt Institute of Molecular Biology Russian Academy of Sciences (Russia) Sergey I. Vdovenko Senior Research Assistant, Department of Fine Organic Synthesis Institute of Bioorganic Chemistry and Petrochemistry Ukrainian National Academy of Sciences (Ukraine) Henry Schaefer Director, Center for Computational Quantum Chemistry University of Georgia Paul Ashby Ph.D. Chemistry Harvard University Israel Hanukoglu Professor of Biochemistry and Molecular Biology Chairman The College of Judea and Samaria (Israel) Alan Linton Emeritus Professor of Bacteriology University of Bristol (UK) Dean Kenyon Emeritus Professor of Biology San Francisco State University David W.
    [Show full text]
  • Sbchinn 1.Pdf
    The Prevalence and Effects of Scientific Agreement and Disagreement in Media by Sedona Chinn A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Communication) in The University of Michigan 2020 Doctoral Committee: Associate Professor P. Sol Hart, Chair Professor Stuart Soroka Professor Nicholas Valentino Professor Jan Van den Bulck Sedona Chinn [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0002-6135-6743 DEDICATION This dissertation is dedicated to the memory of my grandma, Pamela Boult. Thank you for your unending confidence in my every ambition and unconditional love. ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I am grateful for the support of the Dow Sustainability Fellows Program, which provided much appreciated spaces for creative research and interdisciplinary connections. In particular, I would like to thank the 2017 cohort of doctoral fellows for their support, feedback, and friendship. I would also like to thank the Department of Communication and Media, the Center for Political Studies at the Institute for Social Research, and Rackham Graduate School for supporting this work. I truly appreciate the guidance and support of excellent advisors throughout this endeavor. Thanks to my advisors, Sol Hart and Stuart Soroka, for all of their long hours of teaching, critique, and encouragement. Know that your mentorship has shaped both how I think and has served as a model for how I Would like to act going forward in my professional life. Thanks to Nick Valentino and Jan Van den Bulck for your invaluable comments, insistence that I simplify experimental designs, and for your confidence in my Work. I truly appreciate all the ways in which your support and guidance have both improved the work presented here and my thinking as a researcher.
    [Show full text]
  • Science Metrics Initiative
    Social, Behavioral and Economic Sciences Science of Science and Innovation Policy: A Prospectus September, 2006 Introduction The Directorate for Social, Behavioral and Economic Sciences (SBE) at the National Science Foundation (NSF) aims to develop the knowledge, theories, data, tools, and human capital needed to cultivate a new Science of Science and Innovation Policy (SciSIP). Science and innovation policy discussions are frequently based upon past practice or data trends that may be out of date or have limited relevance to the current situation. Traditional models available for informing investment policies are often static, unidirectional and not developed for domain-specific applications. Past investments in basic scientific research have had an enormous impact on innovation, economic growth and societal well-being. However, there is modest capability of predicting how future investments will yield the most promising and important opportunities. SBE’s SciSIP activities will develop the foundations of an evidence-based platform from which policymakers and researchers may assess the impacts of the nation’s scientific and engineering enterprise, and improve their understanding of its dynamics and predict outcomes. Parallel research and data development will help answer pressing questions, such as: What are the critical elements of creativity and innovation? What are the likely futures of the technical workforce and what is its response to different forces of change? What is the impact of globalization on creativity and productivity in the science and engineering fields? Are there significantly different outcomes from federal and private investments in R&D and innovative activities? How does state support for public universities influence the national innovation system? Economic models offer guidance to Federal Reserve Board officials as they set interest rates, even when they encounter conflicting policy goals.
    [Show full text]
  • Oreskes Testimony 29April2015
    Excerpt from Chapter 4 of Oreskes, Naomi and Erik M. Conway, 2010. Merchants of Doubt: How a Handful of Scientists Obscured the Truth on Issues from Tobacco Smoke to Global Warming. (New York: Bloomsbury Press.), reproduced with permission. Constructing a Counter-narrative It took time to work out the complex science of ozone depletion, but scientists, with support from the U.S. government and international scientific organizations, did it. Regulations were put in place based on science, and adjusted in response to advances in it. But running in parallel to this were persistent efforts to challenge the science. Industry representatives and other skeptics doubted that ozone depletion was real, or argued that if it was real, it was inconsequential, or caused by volcanoes. During the early 1980s, anti-environmentalism had taken root in a network of conservative and libertarian “think tanks” in Washington. These think tanks—which included the Cato Institute, the American Enterprise Institute, Heritage Foundation, the Competitive Enterprise Institute, and, of course, the Marshall Institute, variously promoted business interests and “free market” economic policies, the rollback of environmental, health, safety, and labor protections. They were supported by donations from businessmen, corporations, and conservative foundations.i One aspect of the effort to cast doubt on ozone depletion was the construction of a counter-narrative that depicted ozone depletion as natural variation that was being cynically exploited by a corrupt, self-interested, and extremist scientific community to get more money for their research. One of the first people to make this argument was a man who had been a Fellow at the Heritage Foundation in the early 1980s, and whom we have already met: S.
    [Show full text]