The Complete Works of Aristotle: Revised Oxford Translation V. 2 Free

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Complete Works of Aristotle: Revised Oxford Translation V. 2 Free FREE THE COMPLETE WORKS OF ARISTOTLE: REVISED OXFORD TRANSLATION V. 2 PDF Aristotle,Jonathan Barnes | 1248 pages | 21 Sep 1984 | Princeton University Press | 9780691016511 | English | New Jersey, United States Complete Works of Aristotle, Volume 2 | Princeton University Press With an OverDrive account, you can save your favorite libraries for at-a-glance information about availability. Find out more about OverDrive accounts. Bollingen General. Princeton The Complete Works of Aristotle: Revised Oxford Translation v. 2 Press. The Oxford Translation of Aristotle was originally published in 12 volumes between and It is universally recognized as the standard English version of Aristotle. This revised edition contains the substance of the original Translation, slightly emended in light of recent scholarship; three of the original versions have been replaced by new translations; and a new and enlarged selection of Fragments has been added. The aim of the translation remains the same: to make the surviving works of Aristotle readily accessible to English speaking readers. Media Complete Works of Aristotle, Volume 2. Add Book To Favorites. Format ebook. Series Bollingen General. Author Aristotle. Publisher Princeton University Press. Release 01 September Subjects Philosophy Nonfiction. Search for a digital library with this title Search by city, ZIP code, or library name Learn more about precise location detection. View more libraries Complete Works of Aristotle, Volume 2. Copy and paste the code into your website. OverDrive Borrow eBooks, audiobooks, and videos from thousands of public libraries worldwide. New here? Learn how to read digital books for free. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, Volume 2 by Aristotle The reference line of each paragraph of the database contains The Complete Works of Aristotle: Revised Oxford Translation v. 2 page number of the first line of the paragraph in the Barnes edition. Each reference line also contains the approximate Bekker number range of the paragraph if the work in question was included in the Bekker edition. Contents: V. Categories -- De interpretatione -- Prior analytics -- Posterior analytics -- Topics -- Sophistical refutations -- Physics -- On the heavens -- On generation and corruption -- Meteorology -- On the universe -- On the soul -- Sense and sensibilia -- On memory -- On sleep -- On dreams -- On divination in sleep -- On length and shortness of life -- On youth, old age, life and death, and respiration -- On breath -- History of animals -- Parts of animals -- Movement of animals -- Progression of animals -- Generation of animals -- On colours -- On things heard -- Physiognomonics -- V. Coverage: Varies - Updates vary. Vendor: Intelex Corporation. Producer: Intelex Corporation. Simultaneous User Limit: Unlimited simultaneous users. Other Campus Libraries. Popular Services Research Assistance. Help with Citing Sources. All Services. Expand search box Collapse search box. What would you like to find at the library today? Resource available to authorized IU Bloomington users on or off campus Scopus. Resource available without restriction HathiTrust Digital Library. Complete Works of Aristotle, Volume 2 - Aristotle, Jonathan Barnes - Bok () | Bokus Account Options Sign in. Top charts. New arrivals. Aristotle Sep Switch to the audiobook. The Oxford Translation of Aristotle was originally published in 12 volumes between and It is universally recognized as the standard English version of Aristotle. This revised The Complete Works of Aristotle: Revised Oxford Translation v. 2 contains the substance of the original Translation, slightly emended in light of recent scholarship; three of the original versions have been replaced by new translations; and a new and enlarged selection of Fragments has been added. The aim of the translation remains the same: to make the surviving works of Aristotle readily accessible to English speaking readers. More by Aristotle See more. Students of language, politics, religion, and philosophy have always turned to Aristotle, attributed with one of the greatest intellectual minds that ever lived, for answers and the dissection of seemingly natural phenomena. Aristotle and his contemporaries considered rhetorical skills-the ability to give speeches and make persuasive arguments-one of the most important a scholar could possess. In his famous essay Rhetoric, Aristotle outlines the three basic elements of the rhetorical arts: logos, pathos, and ethos; or logic, emotion, and ethics truth. This pyramid makes up the tenets of rhetoric which are still taught today, along with Aristotle's examinations on how to interpret and compose effective speeches and presentations. Student of Plato and teacher of Alexander the Great, Aristotle is considered the authority originator of many philosophical ideas and teachings. Famous today for works such as Politics, Poetics, Rhetoric, and Metaphysics, his many writings cover a wide range of subjects, ranging from literature, art, music, and politics to physics, zoology, biology, and the scientific method. Nicomachean Ethics. An excellent new translation and commentary. Reviews Review Policy. Published on. Original pages. Best for. Web, Tablet. Content protection. Learn more. Flag as inappropriate. It syncs automatically with your account and allows you to read online or offline wherever you are. Please follow the detailed Help center The Complete Works of Aristotle: Revised Oxford Translation v. 2 to transfer the files to supported eReaders. .
Recommended publications
  • Interpretation: a Journal of Political Philosophy
    Interpretation A JOURNAL A OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY Winter 1993-1994 Volume 21 Number 2 Thomas Lewis Identifying Rhetoric in the Apology: Does Socrates Use the Appeal for Pity? Joel Warren Lidz Reflections on and in Plato's Cave Bernard Jacob Aristotle's Dialectical Purposes Mary L. Bellhouse Rousseau Under Surveillance: Thoughts on a New Edition and Translation of Rousseau, Judge of Jean-Jacques: Dialogues Peter Augustine Lawler Tocqueville on Socialism and History Maurice Auerbach Carl Schmitt's Quest for the Political: Theology, Decisionism, and the Concept of the Enemy Discussion Victor Gourevich The End of History? Book Reviews Will Morrisey Self-Knowledge in Plato's Phaedrus, by Charles L. Griswold, Jr. Leslie G. Rubin Citizens and Statesmen: A Study of Aristotle's Politics, by Mary P. Nichols John S. Waggoner The Liberal Political Science of Raymond Aron: A Critical Introduction, by Daniel J. Mahoney Interpretation Editor-in-Chief Hilail Gildin, Dept. of Philosophy, Queens College Executive Editor Leonard Grey General Editors Seth G. Benardete Charles E. Butterworth Hilail Gildin Robert Horwitz (d. 1987) Howard B. White (d. 1974) Consulting Editors Christopher Bruell Joseph Cropsey Ernest L. Fortin John Hallowell (d. 1992) Harry V. Jaffa David Lowenthal Muhsin Mahdi Harvey C. Mansfield, Jr. Arnaldo Momigliano (d. 1987) Michael Oakeshott (d. 1990) Ellis Sandoz Leo Strauss (d. 1973) Kenneth W. Thompson European Editors Terence E. Marshall Heinrich Meier Editors Wayne Ambler Maurice Auerbach Fred Baumann Michael Blaustein - Patrick Coby Edward J. Erler Maureen Feder-Marcus Joseph E. Goldberg Stephen Harvey Pamela K. Jensen Ken Masugi Grant B. Mindle James W. Morris Will Morrisey Aryeh L.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy 303 the Practice of Philosophy: Modes of Philosophical Argument
    Philosophy 303 The Practice of Philosophy: Modes of Philosophical Argument TA: Carrie Swanson Email: [email protected] Office hours: After class, or by appointment (Mondays or Thursdays). Course description: This course is devoted to an examination of various modes of argumentation in the Western philosophical tradition. Our special topic this term is the art of refutation, with a special emphasis upon its origins and development in ancient Greek philosophy. Our starting point is the following remark of Aristotle (from chapter 11 of his treatise, On Sophistical Refutations): ‘Dialectic is at the same time a mode of examination as well. For neither is the art of examination an accomplishment of the same kind as geometry, but one which a man may possess, even though he has not knowledge. For it is possible even for someone who does not know the subject [scientifically] to hold an examination of one who does not know the subject, if also the latter grants him points taken not from thing that he knows or from the special principles of the subject under discussion but from all that range of consequences attaching to [the special principles of a subject] which a man may indeed know without knowing the theory of the subject, but which if he does not know, he is bound to be ignorant of the theory. So then clearly the art of examining does not consist in knowledge of any definite subject. For this reason, too, it deals with everything: for every 'theory' of anything employs also certain common principles. Hence everybody, including even amateurs, makes use in a way of dialectic and the practice of examining: for all undertake to some extent a rough trial of those who profess to know things.
    [Show full text]
  • Contemplation and the Human Animal in the Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 2011 Contemplation and the Human Animal in the Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas Edyta M. Imai Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Imai, Edyta M., "Contemplation and the Human Animal in the Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas" (2011). Dissertations. 205. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/205 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 2011 Edyta M. Imai LOYOLA UNIVERSITY CHICAGO CONTEMPLATION AND THE HUMAN ANIMAL IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF ST. THOMAS AQUINAS A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY PROGRAM IN PHILOSOPHY BY EDYTA M. IMAI CHICAGO IL DECEMBER 2011 Copyright by Edyta M. Imai, 2011 All rights reserved TABLE OF CONTENTS LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS iv INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER ONE: CONTEMPLATION AND NATURAL APPETITES 30 CHAPTER TWO: SENSATION AND CONTEMPLATION 104 CHAPTER THREE: DESIRE AND CONTEMPLATION 166 CHAPTER FOUR: DELIGHT AND CONTEMPLATION 230 BIBLIOGRAPHY 291 VITA 303 iii LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS ST Summa theologiae SCG Summa contra gentiles QDV Quaestiones disputatae de veritate QDA Quaestiones disputatae de anima In Boetii de Trin. In Librum Boetii de Trinitate Expositio In DA Sententia libri De anima In NE Sententia libri Ethicorum In Met Commentarium in XII libros Metaphysicorum In Ph Commentarium in VIII libros Physicorum SENT Commentarium in quatuor libros Sententiarum iv INTRODUCTION In this dissertation I examine the manner in which – according to Thomas Aquinas - the operations of the sensitive soul contribute to contemplation.
    [Show full text]
  • CCAC Guidelines On: Laboratory Animal Facilities — Characteristics
    Canadian Council on Animal Care guidelines on: laboratory animal facilities — characteristics, design and development This document, the CCAC guidelines on: laboratory animal facilities — characteristics, design and development, has been developed by Drs David Neil and Donald McKay with the collaboration of the CCAC Facilities Standards Subcommittee: Dr Laurence Schofield, Department of National Defence (Chair) Dr Michèle Bailey, Cornell University Mr Richard Bélanger, Ottawa Health Research Institute Dr Sandra Fry, Canadian Food Inspection Agency Dr Martin Kirk, University of Calgary Dr Donald McKay, University of Alberta Dr David Neil, University of Alberta Dr Elizabeth Rohonczy, Canadian Food Inspection Agency Dr Gilles Demers, Canadian Council on Animal Care Dr Gilly Griffin, Canadian Council on Animal Care In addition, the CCAC is grateful to those individuals and organizations that provided comments on earlier drafts of this guidelines document. © Canadian Council on Animal Care, 2003 REVISION DATE: May 2020 ISBN: 0–919087–41–8 Canadian Council on Animal Care 1510–130 Albert Street Ottawa ON CANADA K1P 5G4 http://www.ccac.ca CCAC guidelines on: laboratory animal facilities — characteristics, design and development, 2003 TABLE OF CONTENTS A. PREFACE . .1 3.16 Laundry facilities . .31 3.17 Toilets . .31 SUMMARY OF THE GUIDELINES 3.18 Staff break and meeting room(s) . .31 LISTED IN THIS DOCUMENT . .3 3.19 Mechanical and electrical space and distribution of services . .31 B. INTRODUCTION . .13 3.20 Corridors . .32 3.21 Barriers . .33 C. THE CHARACTERISTICS OF A 3.22 Radiation shielded suites . .37 LABORATORY ANIMAL 4. Functional Adjacencies . .38 FACILITY . .15 4.1 Personnel facilities . .38 1. Functional Imperatives of the 4.2 Animal holding rooms .
    [Show full text]
  • The Epistemic Value of 'Κατά Τόν Λόγον': Meteorology
    The epistemic value of ‘κατά τόν λόγον’: Meteorology 1.7 By Eleftheria Rotsia Dimou Submitted to Central European University Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the one year MA degree of Philosophy Supervisor: Associate Professor István Bodnár Budapest, Hungary 2018 CEU eTD Collection © Copyright by Eleftheria Rotsia Dimou, 2018 1 Τὸν μὲν οὖν Ἀναξαγόραν φασὶν ἀποκρίνασθαι πρός τινα διαποροῦντα τοιαῦτ ̓ ἄττα καὶ διερωτῶντα τίνος ἕνεκ ̓ ἄν τις ἕλοιτο γενέσθαι μᾶλλον ἢ μὴ γενέσθαι ‘τοῦ’ φάναι “θεωρῆσαι τὸν οὐρανὸν καὶ τὴν περὶ τὸν ὅλον κόσμον τάξιν”. (Aristotle, E.E Ι, 1216a12–14). CEU eTD Collection 2 Contents 1. Abstract ……………………………………………………….……4 2. Acknowledgments……………………………………..……………5 3. Introduction……………………………………………..…………..6 4. Part I: An Ontological Question…………………………...……….9 5. Part II: An Epistemological Question……………………………..14 6. Concluding Remarks…………………………………………..…..38 7. Bibliography………………………………………………………40 CEU eTD Collection 3 Abstract Ι will attempt to shed some light on the troubling matter of the obscure particulars ― treated by Aristotle in Meteorology ― (τῶν ἀφανῶν τῇ αἰσθήσει), that is, phenomena which are not apparent to the senses in their full extent (Meteorology 344a5). In the framework of the present paper, the aim is to highlight the use of κατά τόν λόγον which appears in the first lines of chapter I.7 of Aristotle’s Meteorology, by focusing on two philosophical questions: one ontological (what is the ontological status of obscure phenomena?) and one epistemological (can we come to the knowledge of such phenomena, and if so, in which way?). Aristotle proposes two answers to these questions in the text, respectively: The meteora (and therefore the comets discussed in chapter I.7 of Meteorology) are natural entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Marko Malink (NYU)
    Demonstration by reductio ad impossibile in Posterior Analytics 1.26 Marko Malink (New York University) Contents 1. Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 ................................................................................. 1 2. Direct negative demonstration vs. demonstration by reductio ................................................. 14 3. Aristotle’s argument from priority in nature .............................................................................. 25 4. Priority in nature for a-propositions ............................................................................................ 38 5. Priority in nature for e-, i-, and o-propositions .......................................................................... 55 6. Accounting for Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 ................................................... 65 7. Parts and wholes ............................................................................................................................. 77 References ............................................................................................................................................ 89 1. Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 At the beginning of the Analytics, Aristotle states that the subject of the treatise is demonstration (ἀπόδειξις). A demonstration, for Aristotle, is a kind of deductive argument. It is a deduction through which, when we possess it, we have scientific knowledge (ἐπιστήμη). While the Prior Analytics deals with deduction in
    [Show full text]
  • The INPR Journal. Volume I, Fall 2020
    Crossing: The INPR Journal. Volume I, Fall 2020. Editor in chief Emmanuel Falque Editorial coordinators William L. Connelly Domenico Cambria Editorial committee Tamsin Jones Adam Graves Martin Koci William Woody S.J. Crossing: The INPR Journal. Volume I. November 2020. 26 Rue d’Assas 75006 Paris, France. ISSN (online): 2644-9242 DOI: 10.21428/8766eb43.b95a977c Web: https://inprjournal.pubpub.org/ http://www.network-inpr.org/ Email: [email protected] Crossing : une étape fondatrice de l’INPR (English Translation on Page III) L’international Network of Philosophy of Religion (INPR) est un réseau international de jeunes philosophes et théologiens (doctorants, post-doctorants, jeunes professeurs) réunis pour travailler ensemble autour de la question de Dieu et de sa pertinence dans un monde contemporain sécularisé. Essentiellement appuyé sur la philosophie continentale, mais pas exclusivement, il s’efforce d’être au service d’un renouveau de la philosophie et de la théologie chez les jeunes générations pour aujourd’hui. Loin de rester chacune sur leur pré-carré, philosophie et théologie sont appelées aujourd’hui à se croiser et à davantage se féconder mutuellement, dans le respect de la distinction des disciplines. Et les chercheurs de différents pays, en particulier ceux qui feront la pensée de demain, doivent eux aussi mieux dialoguer, sûrs que dans la confrontation des idées se fomente le terreau d’où naissent de nouvelles pensées. Inauguré en 2015, ce réseau international compte aujourd’hui plus d’une centaine de membres personnellement engagés, de plus de dix nationalités différentes, et venus en particulier d’Europe et des États-Unis. Les membres qui constituent ce réseau ont déjà fait la preuve par plusieurs séminaires (grands colloques ou séminaires doctoraux et post-doctoraux) du bien-fondé de leur démarche commune.
    [Show full text]
  • 19 Another Interpretation of Aristotle's De Interpretatione IX a Support for the So-Called Second Oldest Or 'Mediaeval' Interpre
    Another Interpretation of Aristotle's De Interpretatione IX A support for the so-called second oldest or 'mediaeval' interpretation JOB VAN ECK Controversies regarding propositions about the future, occasioned by Aristotle's De Interpretatione IX have occurred throughout the history of logic from Antiquity to the 20th century, especially in the Middle Ages. The question under discussion is: must some such propositions be denied a truth value in order to escape determinism? Or does the law of bivalence also hold for future contingency propositions? And what is Aristotle's position in De Interpretatione IX? Does he say that bivalence implies determinism and thus abandons universal bivalence (this is called the oldest, or traditional, interpretation), or does he reconcile bivalence with indeterminism (the so-called second oldest in- terpretation). Boethius, in his two commentaries on De Interpretatione, shows himself a representantive of the second oldest interpretation. His main thesis is that according to Aristotle it is necessary for a future con- tingency proposition and its negation that one is true and the other false, but not definitely true, nor definitely false. In a recent article Pro- fessor Norman Kretzmann stressed the influence this point of view of Boethius has had on the subsequent discussion' . The second oldest interpretation became so prominent among mediaeval philosophers that some call it the mediaeval interpretation. In modern times most authors reject this interpretation, partly because the phrase "definitely true", which is at the heart of it, is rather obscure and its Greek analogue alêthes aphorismends does not oc- cur in De Interpretatione IX at all.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Verbal Communication: the First Chapters of De Interpretatione
    EJPC 7 (2) pp. 239–253 Intellect Limited 2016 Empedocles: European Journal for the Philosophy of Communication Volume 7 Number 2 © 2016 Intellect Ltd Critical Review. English language. doi: 10.1386/ejpc.7.2.239_3 CRITICAL REVIEW ANITA KASABOVA Sofia University VLADIMIR MARINOV New Bulgarian University Aristotle on verbal communication: The first chapters of De Interpretatione ABSTRACT KEYWORDS This article deals with the communicational aspects of Aristotle’s theory of significa- Aristotle tion as laid out in the initial chapters of the De Interpretatione (Int.).1 We begin De Interpretatione by outlining the reception and main interpretations of the chapters under discussion, verbal communication rather siding with the linguistic strand. We then argue that the first four chap- signification ters present an account of verbal communication, in which words signify things via linguistic expressions thoughts. We show how Aristotle determines voice as a conventional and hence acci- convention dental medium of signification: words as ‘spoken sounds’ are tokens of thoughts, language use which in turn are signs or natural likenesses of things. We argue that, in this way, 1. We follow the standard linguistic expressions may both signify thoughts and refer to things. This double edition of the Greek account of signification also explains the variety of ontological, logical and psycho- text of Int. by Minio- logical interpretations of the initial chapters of Int. Paluello (1949: 47–72), unless otherwise stated. All references to Aristotle’s works 239 11_EJPC 7.2_Critical review article_239-253.indd 239 11/22/16 1:55 PM Anita Kasabova and Vladimir Marinov follow the citation 1.
    [Show full text]
  • From Aristotle to Contemporary Biological Classification: What Kind of Category Is “Sex”? Stella Sandford Kingston University London, UK [email protected]
    REDESCRIPTIONS Sandford, Stella. 2019. “From Aristotle to Contemporary Biological Political Thought, Conceptual History and Feminist Theory Classification: What Kind of Category is “Sex”?” Redescriptions: Political Thought, Conceptual History and Feminist Theory 22(1): 4–17. DOI: https://doi.org/10.33134/rds.314 RESEARCH From Aristotle to Contemporary Biological Classification: What Kind of Category is “Sex”? Stella Sandford Kingston University London, UK [email protected] This paper examines the nature of the categories of ‘male’ and ‘female’ as ­classificatory­groupings,­via­an­examination­of­this­question­in­Aristotle’s­zoology­ and­metaphysics.­Tracing­the­use­of­Aristotle’s­logical­categories­of­‘genus’­and­ ‘species’­in­his­zoological­works­and­contrasting­this­with­the­use­of­the­terms­ in­contemporary­taxonomy,­the­paper­demonstrates­that­‘male’­and­‘female’­are,­ in­a­significant­sense,­unclassifiable.­Although­Aristotle­has­no­generic­concept­of­ ‘sex’­at­his­disposal,­the­paper­shows­how­many­English­translations­of­his­works­ introduce­‘sex’­as­if­in­answer­to­the­question­of­the­nature­of­the­categories­of­ male­and­female.­The­paper­then­argues­that­the­generic­concept­of­sex­covers­ over­the­problem­of­the­classification­of­male­and­female­in­both­Aristotle­and­ contemporary­biology­(including­botany,­mycology­and­bacteriology),­by­introduc- ing­a­classificatory­genus­(‘sex’)­that­does­not­in­fact­explain­anything­but­rather­ (in­its­trans-species­generality)­needs­explaining. Keywords:­Sex;­male/female;­Aristotle;­biology;­taxonomy;­classification All living organisms that have been scientifically recorded or studied are named according to the relevant international code for nomenclature. Naming and denoting a taxonomical clas- sification are two sides of the same coin.
    [Show full text]
  • Catalogue of Titles of Works Attributed to Aristotle
    Catalogue of Titles of works attributed by Aristotle 1 To enhance readability of the translations and usability of the catalogues, I have inserted the following bold headings into the lists. These have no authority in any manuscript, but are based on a theory about the composition of the lists described in chapter 3. The text and numbering follows that of O. Gigon, Librorum deperditorum fragmenta. PART ONE: Titles in Diogenes Laertius (D) I. Universal works (ta kathalou) A. The treatises (ta syntagmatika) 1. The dialogues or exoterica (ta dialogika ex terika) 2. The works in propria persona or lectures (ta autopros pa akroamatika) a. Instrumental works (ta organika) b. Practical works (ta praktika) c. Productive Works (ta poi tika) d. Theoretical works (ta the r tika) . Natural philosophy (ta physiologia) . Mathematics (ta math matika) B. Notebooks (ta hypomn matika) II. Intermediate works (ta metaxu) III. Particular works (ta merika) PART TWO: Titles in the Vita Hesychii (H) This list is organized in the same way as D, with two exceptions. First, IA2c “productive works” has dropped out. Second, there is an appendix, organized as follows: IV. Appendix A. Intermediate or Particular works B. Treatises C. Notebooks D. Falsely ascribed works PART THREE: Titles in Ptolemy al-Garib (A) This list is organized in the same way as D, except it contains none of the Intermediate or Particular works. It was written in Arabic, and later translated into Latin, and then reconstructed into Greek, which I here translate. PART FOUR: Titles in the order of Bekker (B) The modern edition contains works only in IA2 (“the works in propria persona”), and replaces the theoretical works before the practical and productive, as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Radical Psychoanalysis
    RADICAL PSYCHOANALYSIS Only by the method of free-association could Sigmund Freud have demonstrated how human consciousness is formed by the repression of thoughts and feelings that we consider dangerous. Yet today most therapists ignore this truth about our psychic life. This book offers a critique of the many brands of contemporary psychoanalysis and psychotherapy that have forgotten Freud’s revolutionary discovery. Barnaby B. Barratt offers a fresh and compelling vision of the structure and function of the human psyche, building on the pioneering work of theorists such as André Green and Jean Laplanche, as well as contemporary deconstruction, feminism, and liberation philosophy. He explores how “drive” or desire operates dynamically between our biological body and our mental representations of ourselves, of others, and of the world we inhabit. This dynamic vision not only demonstrates how the only authentic freedom from our internal imprisonments comes through free-associative praxis, it also shows the extent to which other models of psychoanalysis (such as ego-psychology, object-relations, self-psychology, and interpersonal-relations) tend to stray disastrously from Freud’s original and revolutionary insights. This is a vision that understands the central issues that imprison our psychic lives—the way in which the reflections of consciousness are based on the repression of our innermost desires, the way in which our erotic vitality is so often repudiated, and the way in which our socialization oppressively stifles our human spirit. Radical Psychoanalysis restores to the discipline of psychoanalysis the revolutionary impetus that has so often been lost. It will be essential reading for psychoanalysts, psychoanalytic psychotherapists, mental health practitioners, as well as students and academics with an interest in the history of psychoanalysis.
    [Show full text]