<<

Know!. Org. 26(1999)No.2 65 H.A. Olson: Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: Our Aristotelean Legacy

Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: Our Aristotelean Legacy

Hope A. Olson

School of Library & Information Studies, University of Alberta

Hope A. Olson is an Associate Professor and Graduate Coordinator in the School of Library and Information Studies at the University of Alberta in Edmonton, Alberta, Canada. She holds a PhD from the University of Wisconsin-Madison and MLS from the University of Toronto. Her re­ search is generally in the area of subject access to information with a focus on classification. She approaches this using feminist, poststructural and postcolonial theory. Dr. Olson teaches of knowledge, cataloguing and classification, and courses examining issues in femi­ nism and in globalization and diversity as they relate to library and information studies.

Olson, H.A. (1999). Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: Our Aristotelean Legacy. Knowl· edge Organization, 26(2). 65-73. 16 refs.

ABSTRACT: This paper examines Parmenides's Fragments, Plato's The , and 's Prior AnalyticsJ Parts ofAnimals and Generation ofAnimals to identify three underlying presumptions of classical using the method of Foucauldian discourse analysis. These three presumptions are the notion of mutually exclusive , teleology in the sense of linear progression toward a goal, and hierarchy both through logical division and through the dominance of some classes over others. These three presumptions are linked to classificatory thought in the western . The purpose of making these connections is to investi­ gate the cultural specificity to western culture of widespread classificatory practice. It is a step in a larger study to examine classi­ fication as a cultural construction that may be systemically incompatible with cultures and with marginalized elements of western culture.

1. of the Problem time and those of its author." Foskett implies, and I will explore further, the notion that classification is a The problem addressed in this article is to identify cultural construction. It is efficient in representing the the underlying presumptions of classification as it is mainstream of its originating culture. However, if the generally practiced. In particular, I will trace these fundamental presumptions underlying classificatory presumptions to the development of logic in fourth practice are culturally constructed, then what is mar­ century BeEt Greece. This study is not only of aca­ ginalized in the originating culture and what is differ­ demic interest. It can also help to explain the systemic ent in other cultures may well be poorly or even dele­ of classifications and how in clas­ teriously represented. sification may be related to that systemic structure. A This is part of a larger project exploring large body of research and descriptive literature has the idea that classification is a cultural construction. been built up over several decades documenting the The way we do classification is not only a reflection failure of library classifications to accommodate effec­ of our mainstream culture, it is a tool of that culture, tively outside of a conventional mainstream.2 both reflecting and reinforcing it. If a particular classi­ Biases in terms of race, gender, ability, nationality, fication represents the mainstream in its originating sexuality, religion and other factors have been well­ culture is it simply a of adding more established. However, library classifications have and reallocating space to stretch a classification into done reasonably well in representing mainstream representing other cultures? My suggestion in this pa­ conceptions of . But whose mainstream? per is that its foundational elements - its underlying Whose reality? A.C. Foskett (1971, p.1l7) observes presumptions - may well be specific to the originat­ that "when one begins to examine almost any scheme ing culture rather than universal. Classifications are it quickly becomes clear that, far from being objec­ being used increasingly across cultures, so if there is a tive, it is likely to reflect both the prejudices of its systemic basis for bias we have an ethical responsibil- 66 Know!. Org. 26(1999)No.2 H.A. Olson: Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: Our Aristotelean Legacy

ity to recognize it. It is only through such recognition For this analysis I have chosen the wrItings of that it might be addressed. Just as the ubiquity of Parmenides, Plato and Aristotle. Aristotle built on North American and European consumer products concepts established by Parmenides and Plato to cre­ has shifted material practices and values within other ate the pattern of reasoning we call logic and a classi­ cultures, so library classification promulgates a west­ ficatory mode that is still with us. Each of these three ern view of how information is structured to form philosophers contributed a fundamental presumption knowledge. Library classification, as a mapping of in­ and each of these presumptions now goes unques­ formation, is one among many social classifications tioned. These presumptions - which I am calling ex­ that construct people's everyday . clusivity, teleology and hierarchy - have become so In this article I address the first in examin­ ingrained as to go unrecognized. They are transparent ing the cultural specificity of our classifications: iden­ in the sense that we do not see them even while they tifying the underlying presumptions of classification are controlling our classificatory practice. It is for this that are culturally linked to a European-derived cul­ reason that I refer to them as presumptions. Were ture (although it has become common in many other they articulated as reasonable guesses on which we parts of the world) as developed from Classical could build a classificatory structure they would be Greece. assumptions. However, as they are hidden (in plain sight) rather than recognized and articulated, they are 2. Methodology presumptuous, taken for granted as acceptable. In analyzing these texts I am also using works by This research is a Foucauldian discourse analysis feminist philosopher, Andrea Nye, and empiricist examllllllg texts in Classical Greek logic to identify philosopher, John Dupre. Nye's chapter on classical the discourses underlying classificatory thought and logic in her Words ofPower: A Feminist Reading of the practice in western culture. History ofLogic (1990) introduced to me the presump­ Discourse analysis is a poststructural methodology tions contributed by Parmenides, Plato and Aristotle and is especially useful for identifying and questioning that I relate to classification. My choice of these three underlying presumptions that operate to construct philosophers follows her critique. Nye's interpreta­ our realities. Poststructuralism, as a critical philoso­ tion is much like a discourse analysis, rereading the phy, questions the of universal principles. texts to discover the discourses of power behind the Therefore, it is appropriate for identifying culturally development and practice of logic. Exclusivity, tele­ specific principles as such. As a specific poststructural ology and hierarchy were not presumptions at the methodology, Foucauldian discourse analysis exam­ time that Greek philosophers were creating the ines texts for their indications of power as embodied branch of we know as logic. They have in discourses. Discourse is used here: become presumptions because of. their permeation of ... in the Foucauldian sense of a conceptual grid our culture. In ancient Greece, logic was developed with its own exclusions and erasures, its own within a social and cultural context and it is the pres­ rules and decisions, limits, inner logic, parame­ ervation of certain aspects of that context that is the ters and blind alleys. A discourse is that which is result of these discourses' continued influence. One beneath the writer's awareness in terms of rules aspect of the context was, of course, male control of governing the fo rmation and transformation of . To identify the mechanisms of male domina­ ideas into a dispersal of the historical agent, the tion, a feminist critique must make the transparent knowing subject. (Lather 1991 - emphasis visible. It is, therefore, also useful in revealing pre­ added) sumptions that have a broader influence. Dupre's critique of the unity of science, The Disor­ Classification is, indeed, a "conceptual grid" con­ der of Things: Metapbysical Foundations of the Disunity structed by "rules governing the formation and trans­ of Science (1993), is one of the few recent works to formation of ideas." As classificationists and classifiers address issues of classification in philosophy. In it we shape the ideas that transform knowledge by or­ Dupre questions the presumption of modern western ganizing it into a particular structure. We think of science that the universe is orderly, and, because it is that structure as a logical arrangement and, as I will orderly, a unified science is possible. Dupre posits es­ explore, the link between logic and classification sentialism, and as the three seems a very strong one. Our purpose may not be to presumptions required to establish the notion of an exert power, except the power of retrieval, but we are orderly universe. These three presumptions roughly part of a powerful cultural discourse, not simply af­ parallel exclusivity, teleology and hierarchy making fected by it. This analysis will identify the characteris­ Dupre's discussion illuminating for this research. tics of that discourse. Know!. Org. 26(1999)No.2 67 H.A. Olson: Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: OUf Aristotelean Legacy

What, then, are the underlying presumptions of ­ to A-ness. Dupre (1993) identifies the problem of this brary classification that follows a western model? I kind of essentialism as being its inability to explain propose that Aristotle brought together three pre­ and predict. Knowing the defining characteristics of sumptions that form the basis of classification in the women or men (for example, the absence or presence western tradition as he built on the work of his of a penis) does not explain why our culture con­ predecessors, Parmenides and Plato. I will treat each structs social roles as it does. Further, since there is of them, working in chronological order to follow considerable diversity within a given kind, it is not that development. possible to say that all men will take on the same masculine roles. Nye (1990) notes that Parmenides's 3. Parmenides and Mutual Exclusivity concern over gender roles suggests that he does see an immutable essence for each. According to Par­ Parmenides was a Greek philosopher of Elea (a men ides, men and women are forced by a goddess Greek city on the Italian peninsula) active during the who "initiates hateful birth and union" (fragment 12) fifth century BeE. Parmenides's surviving texts now and as the potencies, the essences, of male and female include only fragments of a heroic poem. In it, Par­ mingle they risk the result that neither will emerge as menides discusses , the philosophy of being the single dominant potency in which case "furies will or existence. The hero of the poem is told by a ­ vex the nascent child with double seed" (fragment 19). dess: Thus, Parmenides bemoans the necessity of sexual un­ Come now, I will tell you ... about those ways of ion and highlights the risks it involves in bringing enquiry which are alone conceivable. The one, that opposites together. a thing is, and that it is not for not being, is the Dupre (1993, p.2S3) carries the example of sex dif­ journey of persuasion, for persuasion attends on ferences further when he explains the potential for realitYi the other, that a thing is not, and that it abuse in relation to essentialist presumptions. Essen­ must needs not be, this I tell you is a path wholly tialism has gotten a very bad name in contemporary without report, for you can neither know what is thought because it verges on stereotyping. Systemic not (for it is impossible) nor tell of it ... (par­ differences between the sexes in a given cultural con­ menides, fragment 3) text (such as the relation of men to reason and women to emotion) are often linked to their biologi­ This passage might be summarized as what is is, be­ cal differences. If such differences are seen as essential cause it is not not and the relationship cannot be ap­ then they are not subject to change, no matter how proached from the other direction of what is not - "a outdated and unjust they are. path wholly without report" - because there is no Mutual exclusivity, then, is a long-standing funda­ way to determine what does not exist. Parmenides di­ mental, but it is also one that has an identifiable ori­ vides "is" from "is not" and then, since "is not" does gin as it is defined in western culture and classifica­ not exist, affirms his monist philosophy that Being is tion. The idea of creating categories defined by es­ a unity, a whole. The irony is that Parmenides, the sences is, fortunately, something largely eschewed by monist, contributed the idea of mutually exclusive bibliothecal classificationists. We typically claim only categories to logic and introduced the idea that a con­ that we are constructing practical schemes for the ac­ cept is defined by what it is not. commodation of knowledge and information. How­ This idea that Being and non-being are mutually ever, the derogatory connotations of the word "pi­ exclusive categories was the inception of the Law of geon-holing" as oversimplified and limiting should Non- in logic which can be stated III warn us that the presumption of mutually exclusive two ways: categories is as dangerous for us as for the broader so­ no statement can be both true and false; and cial fabric of which we are an integral part. nothing can be both A and non-A. Classificatory practice �ike Plato and Aristotle as In classification we presume mutually exclusive described below) has taken the idea of mutually ex­ categories. We define things as being either A or non­ clusive categories beyond Parmenides's law of non­ A, but not both. This division presumes that we can contradiction to suggest that not only is A not non­ define limits for any given concepti that we can de­ A, A is also not B and vice versa. We separate science cide where one ends and another begins. from , literature from folklore, and poli­ To make the division between A and non-A, one tics from as though there are no overlap has to identify what characteristics define something areas even though we know there are. There is no in­ belonging to the or kind, A. If these are the defin­ nate reason to think that concepts or topics are actu­ ing and immutable characteristics of A, then collec­ ally mutually exclusive or even that there is a dividing tively they form the essence of A. They are essential line between A and non-A. One development that has 68 Know!. Org. 26(1999)No.2 H.A. Olson: Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: Our Aristotelean Legacy

shown the problems of mutual exclusivity by trying each question leads to another dualistic question in a to solve them is fuzzy logic in which something can progression toward the goal of logical victory over his be A to a varying . However, classifications still opponent. So, for example, the first set of divisions seek to build fences between concepts, even recogniz­ explores the art of the Sophist which is: ing their artificiality by filling our schedules with acquisitive, not productive notes about how to differentiate between concepts. by conquest, not by voluntary exchange

4. ato by hunting, not by competition Pl and Teleology etc. Plato criticized Parmenides for this notion of the And the hunter hunts: wholeness of being, his , but still accepted the idea of mutually exclusive defining opposites as the things on land, not swimming basis for his major contribution to logic, the dialectic. tame, not wild Parmenides' rejection of the way of "non-being" - his , not nonhuman notion that "is not" does not exist - meant that he by persuasion, not by force and his followers made it impossible to determine in private, not in public whether or not something is true or not true, being for wages, not as a gift or not being, because everything was included in one etc. unified structure. There was no way to discriminate Several series of such dialectical strings of dualistic between things or between thoughts: questions back the Sophist into a corner where he ". it will be necessary to put a statement of our must admit to being a seeker of profit obtained by in­ father Parmenides to the test and overwhelm it sinuating himself into private instruction on the topic with the claim that what is not in some sense is of based on imitation and ignorance. and in turn again that what is in some sense is In this way Plato makes the next step in the mu­ not. ". For unless these things are either cross­ tual exclusivity of categories at the same time that he examined or agreed to, then anyone whatsoever introduces the linear and teleological dialectic. The will hardly fail to be ridiculous when he is definition of teleology I am using here is: a linear forced to contradict himself in speaking about progress toward a goal (telos in its sense of "goal," false statements or opinion ... (Plato, The Soph­ "purpose," or "end"). Plato's dialectic uses mutually ist, 24m-E). exclusive answers to a series of questions to progress inexorably toward the goal of winning the argument. Here Plato is rejecting Parmenides' monism in no Dupre (1993) examines order in light of the goal it uncertain terms. Plato nevertheless took on Par­ is intended to achieve. Different goals will demand menides' concept of non-contradiction. That some­ classification into different categories with different thing could be A or non-A requires that "what is not" characteristics. That is, which characteristics are cho­ be accepted as existing. The law of non-contradiction sen for differentiation will depend on the goal sought. is played out in the dualisms that Plato introduced to Obviously, Plato followed this pattern in 17,eSopbist. western culture: reason as opposed to emotion, mind However, if there are different purposes then the or­ as opposed to body, and so forth. What is interesting der of the universe is disorder. The variant character­ is that Plato (well ahead of Jacques Derrida) shows us istics considered to constitute essences will make the how to deconstruct his own concept of dualism when essential qualities of any category mutable, not immu­ he suggests that "what is not in some sense is and in . What a universal order requires is, according to turn again that what is in some sense is not." Ironi­ Dupre, a type of determinism: a world "in which eve­ cally, he must contradict the law of non-contradiction rything that happens is fully necessitated by antece­ before he can claim "what is not" exists and set the dent circumstances" (1993, p.I71). With such deter­ stage for using the law of non-contradiction in his dia­ minism, the goal will never vary. Further, if every­ lectic. thing that happens has an antecedent, there must also The key that Plato introduces is logical division on be a first cause - what "happens was necessitated by the basis of difference. Being able to divide A from the manner in which the world began ..." (1993, non-A is the prerequisite for his dialectical form of p.I71). Each essence would be predetermined and, argument. Plato's dialectic uses opposites through di­ therefore, each category would be predetermined. If vision rather than wholeness. In The Sophist, Plato the essences/categories are not predetermined then sets out to entrap his philosophical opponent, Theae­ there can be no universal order. Dupre, as one can tetus representing the Sophist school of philosophy, imagine, argues that such determinism is flawed and, through a series of dualistic questions. The answer to therefore, so is the concept of an ordered universe. Know!. Org. 26(1999)No.2 69 H.A. Olson: Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: Our Aristotelean Legacy

What his argument contributed to my discussion is ... statement of something about some subject. the notion that the order we create is, indeed, con­ This statement may be universal or particular or structed with a goal in mind, even if that goal is not indefinite. By universal, I mean a statement always immediately apparent. In fact, the goal may which applies to all, or to none, of the subject; well be as transparent as the fundamental presump­ by particular a statement which applies to some, tions. or does not apply to all; by indefinite, a state­ Plato sets up a parallel to such determinism in his ment which applies or does not apply without dialectic. The essences of Plato's dualisms are prede­ reference to universality or particularity termined by Plato to result in a specific end. In The (PriorAnalytics 1.1.24a) Sophist he sets up a linear argument that has certain An example of such a syllogism is: advantages in its seeming to be open to variance. As Nye points out: All are mortal Socrates is human Logical division offers an alternative to a lecture Therefore, Socrates is mortal. which can be ignored or disbelieved, at the same time as it prevents discussion from being inter­ The first two statements are premisses from which rupted by contrary views or responses. the third statement is deduced. This syllogism is in Logical division makes possible a conversation the form of what Aristotle called the first figure: in which one party is in complete control of the "When three terms are so related to one another that discussion. The Stranger leaves Theaetetus no the last is wholly contained in the middle and the opening for any substantive contributions to the middle is wholly contained in or excluded from the discussion. At the same time the illusion is cre­ first, the extremes must admit of a perfect syllogism" ated of an exchange of views. At each level of ( I.IV.2Sb). Another way of thinking division, the Stranger elicits either a positive re­ about this relationship is in terms of : the sponse or a question asking for further clarifica­ set of mortal beings contains the set of humans (a tion from Theaetetus. The either! or questions universal premiss); and the set of humans contains he asks, however, strictly limit the kind of an­ Socrates (a particular premiss). Aristotle suggests that swer Theaetetus can give. (1990, p.33) only by having this type of relationship between the elements of the syllogism is it possible to have a to­ Plato's is a constructed determinism in its orienta­ tally self-contained "perfect" syllogism. It requires no tion toward a goal. other information to reach its conclusion that Socra­ Teleology within classification is illustrated by two tes is mortal. Other types of syllogisms (Aristotle's factors: 1) the progression of main classes from basic second and third figures) have the potential to reach to more developed (the development of Dewey's true conclusions with the addition of other premisses. main classes from William T. Harris's inverted Baco­ However, ultimately, they will be validated only if nian progression is a case in point); and 2) the devel­ they can reach the form of the first figure (Prior Ana­ opment of a hierarchy with the level of specificity in­ lytics 1.VII.29a). The progression of a logical argument dicating its degree of sophistication and with generali­ between the particular and the universal in Aristotle's zation (the top level of the hierarchy) being the goal. syllogisms clearly implies hierarchical relationships if This integral relationship between teleology and hier­ the syllogism is to be perfect. The of mortal be­ archy follows from Aristotle's development of syllo­ ings contains the exclusive subclass of humans, but gistic argument and hierarchy. also other exclusive subclasses. The subclass of hu­ mans contains Socrates, but also Lao Tzu, Sophia 5. Aristotle and Hierarchy Loren, Martin Luther King, Jr., Catherine the Great, Aristotle took the step-by-step approach of Plato's Ibn Bhattuta and me - among others. dialectic and turned it into a hierarchical form of ar­ Aristotle uses this process of logical division to in­ gument, the syllogism, and into classification. The vent "natural" classification in the form of a taxon­ syllogism "is a form of words in which, when certain omy. He explains the process in his Parts ofAnimals. assumptions are made, something other than what has He does not accept Plato's concept of division as A or been assumed necessarily follows from the fact that non-A. Aristotle, developing much more fully the the assumptions are such" (Aristotle, Prior Analytics notion of categories and essences, does not recognize 1.1.24b). That is, a syllogism is a means of pursuing "non-A" as a valid essence: new knowledge based on existing assumptions of ... this method of twofold division makes it nec­ knowledge. Each assumption in the syllogism is a essary to introduce privative terms, and those premISS or who adopt it actually do this. But a privation, as 70 Know!. Org. 26(1999)No.2 H.A. Olson: Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: Our Aristotelean Legacy

privation, can admit no differentiationj there closer to the goal. This appears natural cannot be of what is not there at all, e.g. since it is based on characteristics of the of "footless" or "featherless", as there can be of themselves. However, it is actually a very stylized "footed" and "feathered"; and a generic differen­ and not simply a natural reflection of what is. tia must contain species, else it is specific not Other criteria for division (or facets) such as function, generic. (Aristotle, Parts a/Animals LIl1.642b) form and characteristics of various body parts would have been equally natural. The differentiae, the characteristics by which dif­ In addition to the criterion Aristotle chose, the or­ ferentiation of genera and species are made, cannot be der in which he placed animals was determined by his the equivalent of non-A as non-A does not positively judgment of what type of reproduction was most ad­ identify a genus or species. Therefore, at each level of vanced, choosing, of course, the one characteristic of a hierarchy the division is into however many genera, humans. He suggests, according to the understanding species, etc. are necessary to account for the whole. of reproduction of his time, that animals have sepa­ "The number of differentiae will be equal to the rate male and female so that the semen of the male number of species" (Aristotle, Parts 0/ Animals can produce a foetus from the matter found in the LIII.643a.). Further, female. The need to have the female as a separate be· ... if the differentiae under which the indivisible ing is so that animals can, in addition to simply re­ and ultimate species fall are to be proper and producing, perform at some level: private to each one, it is necessary that no differ­ All animals have, in addition [to reproduction as entiae be common; otherwise, species which are a purpose], some measure of knowledge of some actually different will come under one and the sort (some have more, some less, some very lit­ selfsame differentiae. ... And we may not place tle indeed), because they have sense-perception, one and the same indivisible species under two and sense-perception is, of course, a sort of or three of the lines of differentiation given by knowledge . ... Compared with the intelligence the divisions; nor may we include different spe­ possessed by man, it seems as nothing to possess cies under one and the same line of differentia­ the two senses of touch and taste only; but tion. Yet each species must be placed under the compared with entire absence of sensibility it lines of differentiation available. (Aristotle, Parts seems a very fine thing indeed. (Generation 0/ a/Animals LIII.643a.) Animals LXXIII.731a-731b)

So each species falls in its own place in the hierar­ Aristotle's implication is that the male is free to be chy and only in that place. Thus, at each level the sentient because of the female's responsibility for re­ logical division creates mutually exclusive categories. production once the generative semen has been con­ This structure is the same as that of the elements in a tributed to the process. However, plants, which Aris­ perfect syllogism - hierarchical relationships differen· totle takes to have reproduction as their sole purpose, tiated on the grounds of unique characteristics. can have the male and female combined in one being. The applied taxonomy generally drawn from Aris­ The logic of this is transparent according to Aristotle: totle is based on his Generation ofAnimals in which " ... Nature acts in every particular as reason would he uses type of reproduction for the highest level of expect" (Generation a/Animals LxxIII.731a). differentiation. This criterion is teleological in that This classification is then clearly a constructed one Aristotle suggests that the higher degree of develop­ exhibiting hierarchy and mutual exclusivity through ment reached before "birth," the more advanced the Aristotle's development of division. He constructs a : hierarchical order in the teleological progression to­ ... those animals are viviparous which are more ward humans (males) as the pinnacle of what we perfect in their nature, which partake of a purer would now call evolution. This sequence of develop­ "principle"; ... And since an actual animal is ment of various parts of a domain from primitive to something perfect whereas larvae and eggs are sophisticated (e.g. plants to humans) implies the something imperfect, Nature's rule is that the placed on different entities in the progression. For ex­ perfect offspring shall be produced by the more ample, Juliet Clutton-Brock (1995) develops a parallel perfect sort of . (Generation 0/ Animals between Aristotle's ordering of animals and our value 1I.I.732b-733a) and treatment of animals. The values reflected in the classification are also reinforced by it. Therefore, animals that give birth to fully devel­ Hierarchy, as the division of a domain (e.g. nature) oped offspring (vivipara), rather than to eggs (ovipara) into ever smaller parts that are subsumed under the or larvae Oarvipara) that still require development are next larger, the parts becoming ever tinier and less Know!. Org. 26(1999)No.2 71 H.A. Olson: Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: OUf Aristotelean Legacy

meaningful to the whole as it progresses, combines An additional group that was the target of logic mutual exclusivity and teleology into a constructed were non-Greeks or "barbarians." Both Plato and Ar­ order. Dupre (1993) defines this kind of division as istotle were known to consider foreigners inferior, reductionism: breaking down the complex into the which is one of the reasons both criticized Par­ simple in order to understand it. Dupre suggests that menides {who was Greek, but not Athenian} even the type of reductionism involving division is, in fact, though they also drew from his work (Nye 1990, oversimplification. By creating a hierarchical ar­ p.37). At the time, many non-Greeks were drawn to rangement, it narrows the relationships between enti­ Athens for commercial purposes and the ties to purely hierarchical ones, failing to reflect other were among them, accounting for the money­ types of relationships. The example he gives is the grubbing imprecations of Plato's dialectic in TheSoph­ problem of understanding ecology as a knowledge ist. Other "barbarians" were slaves brought to Athens domain if we try to examine it hierarchically rather as the spoils of imperialistic conquest. For a moral than in some other structure that allows for the mul­ justification of slavery, Aristotle argued that "barbari­ tiple interactivity of its elements. A second criticism ans" were natural slaves and inferior just as animals of this kind of reduction is that each level is limited are inferior to humans and women to men (Aristotle by the one above it. In classification we refer to this I.1V.1254b). They may have had different val­ concept as hierarchical force. It is the hierarchy of Ar­ ues in terms of the role of women and other salient istotle's perfect syllogism. Whatever is true of the points. Such benighted views showed their lack of universal is true of the particular. Since the criteria reason and, therefore, their inferiority in the eyes of for constructing hierarchy are chosen, not innate, Athenians like Aristotle (Nye 1990, p.4S). Further, then the essences of the higher levels are made the one of the dualities that Plato sets up in TheSophist is characteristics of the lower. The order of levels {or ci­ that of public versus private, suggesting not only the tation order of facets} determines the groupings and, Sophists, who typically worked in private homes, but therefore, which characteristics are dominant. The also women whose domain was the private while men fixity of these relationships in any given classification controlled the public. The groups of the excluded limits what can be represented and in what context. were knit together in their exclusion. The use of division to separate terms in a logical 6. Cultural Context argument reflects its purpose of division between Athenian and non-Greek, men anel women, free and In the above discussion I have established the fun­ slaves, public and private, reason and emotion as mu­ damental logical concepts of exclusivity, teleology tually exclusive categories with each pair having one and hierarchy as derived from Parmenides, Plato and element hierarchically to the other. These Aristotle and have related them to classification. values of the cultural elite that developed classical Along the way I have noted some instances of the so­ logic are paralleled in the sexism, homophobia, cial and political ramifications of these presumptions. and xenophobia of our contemporary world. It is vi­ These ramifications may well grow from the cultural tal that we not allow our classifications to be tools of context in which these presumptions were developed. such values, especially if these values are linked to the Plato's dialectic and Aristotle's syllogistic forms of structure and not just the content of our classifica­ argument were applied by those who were of the tions. educated elite in fourth century BCE Athens. There­ Hierarchy follows logically from teleology since fore, women, artisans, laborers and slaves were un­ the progression both up and down a hierarchy is ori­ likely to be adept at logic. As a result, the men who ented toward a goal. Most of us find it difficult to controlled Athens had logic as their own device for imagine a classification without hierarchy, but there enforcing their control since they could exercise what is no innate reason that some other structure is not has become known as reason (Nye 1990, p.4S). Rea­ feasible. Many kinds of relationships can occur be­ son, in the form of logic, has the same power of con­ tween concepts such as process and product, cause trol in classification. A classification like Aristotle's, is and effect, but we privilege hierarchical relationships an ontological device. The etymology of the word over all other kinds of relationships - just as Aristotle "ontology" is a useful tool for understanding this did. power: "onto" derived from the Greek word for be­ ing and "logo" meaning "reason" or "speech." Thus, it 7. Conclusion is possible to define what is recognized as existing based on reason in the form of logical argument and To uncover exclusivity, teleology and hierarchy as classification as developed in Plato's dialectic and Ar­ underlying presumptions of classification drawn from istotle's syllogism. the philosophical study of logic is only a beginning to 72 Know!. Org. 26(1999)No.2 H.A. Olson: Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: Our Aristotelean Legacy

understanding the cultural construction of classifica� References tion and its ramifications. While it is of academic in� Aristotle. (1943). , A.L. Peck terest in and of itself, its cultural ramifications require (trans.). (). London: William further research. First, the examination of classificaw Heinemann. tory texts and practices in the intervening centuries is Aristotle. (1937). , A.L. Peck (trans.). necessary to determine how pervasive these three prew With , Progression of Animals. sumptions have been. Second, the views of western (Loeb Classical Library). London: William Heine­ culture toward other cultures in relation to classifica� mann. tion would give an idea of the manner in which classi� Aristotle. (1987). Politics. In J.L. Ackrill (ed.), A New fica tory presumptions may or may not have been im� Aristotle Reader. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univer� posed. Finally, an attempt must be made to see sity Press. whether or not these presumptions are incompatible Aristotle. (1938). Prior Analytics. Hugh Tredennick with other cultures (see Olson, in press). (trans.). In The I, pp.182-531. (Loeb Clas­ A knowledge of the of our classifica� sical Library). London: William Heinemann. tory practice and its potential ramifications will allow Clutton-Brock, Juliet. (1995). Aristotle, the scale of us to approach an ethical relationship to others both nature, and modern attitudes to animals. Social Re­ within and across cultures. This article offers one in� search,62(3),421-440. terpretation from which to proceed. Dupre, John. (1993). The Disorder of Things: Meta­

Acknowledgment physical Foundations of the Disunity of Science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. The author acknowledges suggestions from Birger Foskett, A.C. (1971). Misogynists all; A study in Hj"rland and Jens-Erik Mai and members of the critical classification. LibralY Resources & Technical Royal School of Librarianship, Copenhagen in gen­ Services, 15(2), 117-121. eral and of the Swedish School for Library and In­ Frohmann, Bernd. (1994). Discourse analysis as a re� formation Studies, Bod,s to whom preliminary ver� search method in library and information science. sions of this work were presented. Library& Information Science Researcb, 16, 119-138. Fuss, Diana. (1989). Essentially Speaking: , Notes Nature & Difference. New York: Routledge. 1 I use the abbreviation "BCE" meaning "before the Lather, Patti. (1991). Getting Smart: Feminist Researcb Christian era" rather than the conventional "BC", and Pedagogy with/in the Postmodern. New York: "before Christ", as a reminder that the world in Routledge. which we classify is heterogeneous in its religions Nye, Andrea. (1990). Words of Power: A Feminist and cultures as is pertinent to this research. Reading of tbe History of Logic. New York: Rout­ 2 For a content analysis of the literature of bias in ledge. subject access see Olson and SchIegl (1999). The lit­ Olson, Hope A. (1998). Mapping beyond Dewey's erature reviewed in this content analysis is listed at: boundaries: Constructing classificatory space for http://www.ualberta.cal-holson/margins.htm!. marginalized knowledge domains. Library Trends For a conceptual overview see Olson (1998). 47(2), 233-254. 3 For a fuller description of discourse analysis see Olson, Hope A. (In press). Cultural discourses of Frohmann (1994). classification: Indigenous alternatives to the tradi� 4 References to Parmenides' fragments use the num� tion of Aristotle, Durkheim and Foucault. In Pro­ bers in the Coxon translation (1986) which are in a ceedings of the Classification Research Special Interest different order from those in the other commonly Group of the American Society for Information Sci­ used version: H.Diels. Die Fragmente der Vorsok­ ence Workshop 1999. ratiker. Olson, Hope A., & SchIegl, Rose. (1999). Bias in sub­ 5 For a fuller discussion of essentialism see Diana ject access standards: A content analysis of the Fuss (1989) Essentially Speaking: Feminism, Nature critical literature. In James Turner (ed')J In/orma­ & Difference. tion Science: Where Has It Been, Wbere Is It Going? 6 References to The Sophist follow the traditional use Proceedings of tbe 27'1, Annual Conference of tbe Ca­ of paging in the Stephanus edition of the Greek nadian Association for In/ormation Science Les sci· text. ence de l'information: D 'oji viennent-elles et oil s 'en 7 References to Aristotle's works use the book and vont-elles?Actes du 27e Cong,.es annuel de l'Associa· chapter plus the standard citation of the page and tion canadienne pour les scienes de l'information) column in Becker's 1831 edition. pp.236-247. [Montreal: CAIS!ACSI]. Know!. Org. 26(1999)No.2 73 H.A. Olson: Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: OUf Aristotelean Legacy

Parmenides. (1986). The Fragments 0/ Parmenides: A Critical Text with Introduction, Translation, the An­ cient Testimonia and a Commentary, by A.H. Coxon. Assen/Maastricht: Van Gorcum. Plato. (1990). Plato's Sophist, William S. Cobb (trans.). Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

Prof. Hope Olson, University of Alberga, Canada [email protected] http://www.ualberta.ca/-holson/

CALL FOR PAPERS

Knowledge Organization (KO)

Official Quarterly Journal of the International Society for Knowledge Organization (ISKO)

Knowledge Organization is currently evaluating papers for publication.

Specific instructions appear in each issue of the journal.

To submit a manuscript,

please send two double�spaced copies with an indicative abstract to:

BeforeMay 31, 2000: AfterTllne 1, 2000:

Clare Beghtol (Acting Editor) Hope A. Olson (Editor) Faculty of Information Studies School of Library and University of Toronto Information Studies 140 St. George St. 3-20 Rutherford South Toronto, Ontario MTS 3G6 University of Alberta Canada Edmonton, Alberta T6G 2J4 Canada Email: Email: [email protected] [email protected]