The INPR Journal. Volume I, Fall 2020

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The INPR Journal. Volume I, Fall 2020 Crossing: The INPR Journal. Volume I, Fall 2020. Editor in chief Emmanuel Falque Editorial coordinators William L. Connelly Domenico Cambria Editorial committee Tamsin Jones Adam Graves Martin Koci William Woody S.J. Crossing: The INPR Journal. Volume I. November 2020. 26 Rue d’Assas 75006 Paris, France. ISSN (online): 2644-9242 DOI: 10.21428/8766eb43.b95a977c Web: https://inprjournal.pubpub.org/ http://www.network-inpr.org/ Email: [email protected] Crossing : une étape fondatrice de l’INPR (English Translation on Page III) L’international Network of Philosophy of Religion (INPR) est un réseau international de jeunes philosophes et théologiens (doctorants, post-doctorants, jeunes professeurs) réunis pour travailler ensemble autour de la question de Dieu et de sa pertinence dans un monde contemporain sécularisé. Essentiellement appuyé sur la philosophie continentale, mais pas exclusivement, il s’efforce d’être au service d’un renouveau de la philosophie et de la théologie chez les jeunes générations pour aujourd’hui. Loin de rester chacune sur leur pré-carré, philosophie et théologie sont appelées aujourd’hui à se croiser et à davantage se féconder mutuellement, dans le respect de la distinction des disciplines. Et les chercheurs de différents pays, en particulier ceux qui feront la pensée de demain, doivent eux aussi mieux dialoguer, sûrs que dans la confrontation des idées se fomente le terreau d’où naissent de nouvelles pensées. Inauguré en 2015, ce réseau international compte aujourd’hui plus d’une centaine de membres personnellement engagés, de plus de dix nationalités différentes, et venus en particulier d’Europe et des États-Unis. Les membres qui constituent ce réseau ont déjà fait la preuve par plusieurs séminaires (grands colloques ou séminaires doctoraux et post-doctoraux) du bien-fondé de leur démarche commune. Le sérieux dans la pensée et les liens d’amitié sont la condition de la confrontation des idées. Les nombreux exposés et débats qui se sont déjà déroulés au cœur de ce réseau ont permis à plus d’un d’orienter sa propre pensée. Aujourd’hui l’INPR passe à une étape supplémentaire, sous l’impulsion de ses membres qui le font progresser. L’idée d’une revue, capable non seulement de recueillir nos débats philosophiques et théologiques, mais aussi de les créer, a fait l’objet d’une longue maturation - dans son organisation d’abord (comité d’édition) et dans son contenu ensuite (Expositio, Disputatio, Nostri Libri). Ce premier numéro, d’automne 2020, témoigne de l’extraordinaire vitalité de ce réseau, de l’engagement de chacun, et de l’effort pour y tracer sa propre voie. Les discussions sont parfois âpres, ou à tout le moins décidées, mais toujours dans le I respect de l’altérité, dans la volonté affichée de nous comprendre les uns les autres, et dans le désir aussi de nous laisser transformer. Ce que nous vivons dans la créativité de nos rencontres, nous voulons maintenant le produire aussi par l’écriture. Crossing n’est pas que la trace de débats antérieurs, mais un véritable lieu d’échange où se fomente la pensée. La rigueur philosophie est de mise, et l’entente cordiale aussi. Ces deux ingrédients qui font le cœur de l’INPR, dans le souci du renouvellement des générations, y sont pleinement représentés. D’où la très haute qualité des textes et des discussions ici exposés. Rien de tout cela n’aurait été possible sans la directrice du comité éditorial (Tamsin Jones), et les deux coordinateurs éditoriaux (William Connelly et Domenico Cambria). Qu’ils soient profondément remerciés pour ce travail sans faille, ainsi que tout les membres du comité de rédaction (Martin Koci, William Woody, Adam Graves). C’est à donner sans compter que l’on récolte ce que l’on a semé. Ce qui est une loi de la spiritualité une est une aussi de la pensée. Longue vie à l’INPR, à Crossing, le dernier né donc de cette aventure intellectuelle, spirituelle et amicale, qui nous rassemble et ne cesse de nous dépasser. Puissions-nous chacun demeurer fidèle à nos idées et à nos propres intuitions, mais toujours dans le respect des autres et de leurs différences. C’est ainsi que nous « apprendrons d’eux aussi », sans demeurer ancré dans nos seules convictions en quête de vouloir s’imposer. Se confronter ensemble aux « enjeux philosophiques et théologiques » de notre monde contemporain est une tâche à accomplir, dont nous avons l’intime conviction que l’INPR est actuellement, en partie au moins, en train d’y participer. Traverser - « Crossing » - des montagnes, des océans, des frontières, fût-ce un simple Rubicon, est une manière d’inventer de nouvelles voies pour ne pas rester dans une philosophie faite de la répétition du passé. Frayer de nouveaux chemins mène aussi « quelque part » - mais Dieu seul sait où (?) -, et devient d’autant plus urgent que les nations elles-mêmes semblent se refermer sur leurs propres identités. Paris, le 13 Octobre 2020. Emmanuel Falque Éditeur en chef II Crossing: A Founding Stage of INPR The International Network of Philosophy of Religion (INPR) is an international network of young philosophers and theologians (doctoral students, post-doctoral students, researchers, and young professors) gathered to work together on the question of God and its relevance in a secularized contemporary world. Essentially based on continental philosophy, but not exclusively, it strives to be at the service of a renewal of philosophy and theology among the younger generations of today. Far from each remaining isolated in their own squared off domain, philosophy and theology are called upon today to cross paths and become more mutually fruitful, while still respecting the distinction between disciplines. And researchers from different countries, especially those who will be thinking about tomorrow, must also engage in better dialogue, confident that in the confrontation of ideas, the breeding ground for new thoughts is cultivated. Inaugurated in 2015, this international network now has more than a hundred personally committed members of more than ten different nationalities, particularly from Europe and the United States. The members who make up this network have already demonstrated through several seminars (major conferences or doctoral and post-doctoral seminars) the value of their common approach. Seriousness in thought and bonds of friendship are the condition for the confrontation of ideas. The numerous presentations and debates that have already taken place at the heart of this network have allowed many to orient their own thinking. Today, INPR is moving to a new stage, under the impetus of its members who are taking it forward. The idea of a journal, capable not only of collecting our philosophical and theological debates, but also of creating them, has undergone a long maturation - first in its organization (editorial committee) and then in its content (Expositio, Disputatio, Nostri Libri). This first issue, in the fall of 2020, bears witness to the extraordinary vitality of this network, the commitment of each and every one of us, and the effort to chart our own course. The discussions are sometimes bitter, or at least decisive, but always with respect for otherness, in the willingness to understand each other, and in the desire to be transformed. III What we experience in the creativity of our encounters, we now want to produce it also through writing. Crossing is not just the trace of previous debates, but a real place of exchange where thought is fomented. Rigorous philosophy is the order of the day, and so is cordial understanding. These two ingredients, which are at the heart of the INPR, are fully represented here, with a view to the renewal of generations. Hence the very high quality of the texts and discussions presented here. None of this would have been possible without the director of the editorial board (Tamsin Jones), and the two editorial coordinators (William Connelly and Domenico Cambria). Many thanks to them for their hard work, and to all the members of the editorial board (Martin Koci, William Woody, Adam Graves). It is in giving without counting the cost that we come to reap what has been sown. What is at once a law of spirituality is also one of thought. Long life to INPR, to Crossing, the latest addition to this intellectual, spiritual and friendly adventure, which brings us together and never ceases to surpass us. May we each remain faithful to our own ideas and intuitions, but always with respect for others and their differences. In this way, we will "learn from them too", without remaining anchored in our own convictions and seeking to impose ourselves on others. Confronting together the "philosophical and theological stakes" of our contemporary world is a task to be accomplished, in which we have the deep conviction that INPR is currently, at least in part, participating. Traversing - "Crossing" - mountains, oceans, borders, even a simple Rubicon, is a way of inventing new ways not to remain in a philosophy made of repetition of the past. Crossing new paths also leads "somewhere" - but to where God alone knows (?) - and becomes all the more urgent as the nation’s themselves seem to be closing in on their own identities. Paris, October 13, 2020. Emmanuel Falque Editor in chief IV Introduction to first edition of Crossing: The INPR Journal At the end of a very successful meeting of the INPR in Paris (June 2019), the Founding and Directing Committee began discussions about how to foster continued engagement within the network in between the large bi-annual seminars. As membership of the network continues to increase and not everyone can attend the larger conference, we also wanted to offer ways to share ideas at a distance. “The confrontation of ideas remains the condition for the blossoming of thinkers.” This statement, taken from the charter of the International Network in Philosophy of Religion (INPR), encapsulates the spirit of this journal, Crossing: The INPR Journal: its primary purpose is to promote a crossing—engagement, confrontation, debate, and dialogue—of ideas and thinkers in philosophy of religion.
Recommended publications
  • Marko Malink (NYU)
    Demonstration by reductio ad impossibile in Posterior Analytics 1.26 Marko Malink (New York University) Contents 1. Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 ................................................................................. 1 2. Direct negative demonstration vs. demonstration by reductio ................................................. 14 3. Aristotle’s argument from priority in nature .............................................................................. 25 4. Priority in nature for a-propositions ............................................................................................ 38 5. Priority in nature for e-, i-, and o-propositions .......................................................................... 55 6. Accounting for Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 ................................................... 65 7. Parts and wholes ............................................................................................................................. 77 References ............................................................................................................................................ 89 1. Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 At the beginning of the Analytics, Aristotle states that the subject of the treatise is demonstration (ἀπόδειξις). A demonstration, for Aristotle, is a kind of deductive argument. It is a deduction through which, when we possess it, we have scientific knowledge (ἐπιστήμη). While the Prior Analytics deals with deduction in
    [Show full text]
  • Allan Gotthelf's Teleology, First Principles, And
    Reason Papers Vol. 35, no. 1 Review Essays Review Essay: Allan Gotthelf’s Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Biology and James G. Lennox and Robert Bolton’s (ed.) Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle Owen Goldin Marquette University Although readers of Reason Papers are no doubt familiar with Allan Gotthelf’s extensive efforts aimed at a more widespread appreciation of Ayn Rand’s philosophical thought, he is best known among historians of philosophy and science for his contributions to the understanding of Aristotle’s biological works, which have shed much light on Aristotle’s scientific methodology, epistemology, and metaphysics. Two new books allow us to take account of Gotthelf’s contributions to Aristotelian studies. The first is a collection of Gotthelf’s most important papers on Aristotle.1 Although the papers were written independently, there is little superfluous repetition, and taken together they constitute a comprehensive and coherent account of Aristotle’s biology and its philosophical significance. The second, which has its origin in a 2004 conference in Gotthelf’s honor, is a collection of papers on Aristotle, most of which focus on themes that Gotthelf himself has discussed.2 Some of the papers further his thought, taking it in new directions; others depart from Gotthelf in philosophically interesting ways. Gotthelf believes that one of his most important contributions to Aristotelian studies lies in his account of teleology in the biological writings. For this he gives credit to Rand (p. viii) (who personally led Gotthelf to the study of Aristotle), for she had argued that scientific explanation must identify potentials inherent in natures.
    [Show full text]
  • Catalogue of Titles of Works Attributed to Aristotle
    Catalogue of Titles of works attributed by Aristotle 1 To enhance readability of the translations and usability of the catalogues, I have inserted the following bold headings into the lists. These have no authority in any manuscript, but are based on a theory about the composition of the lists described in chapter 3. The text and numbering follows that of O. Gigon, Librorum deperditorum fragmenta. PART ONE: Titles in Diogenes Laertius (D) I. Universal works (ta kathalou) A. The treatises (ta syntagmatika) 1. The dialogues or exoterica (ta dialogika ex terika) 2. The works in propria persona or lectures (ta autopros pa akroamatika) a. Instrumental works (ta organika) b. Practical works (ta praktika) c. Productive Works (ta poi tika) d. Theoretical works (ta the r tika) . Natural philosophy (ta physiologia) . Mathematics (ta math matika) B. Notebooks (ta hypomn matika) II. Intermediate works (ta metaxu) III. Particular works (ta merika) PART TWO: Titles in the Vita Hesychii (H) This list is organized in the same way as D, with two exceptions. First, IA2c “productive works” has dropped out. Second, there is an appendix, organized as follows: IV. Appendix A. Intermediate or Particular works B. Treatises C. Notebooks D. Falsely ascribed works PART THREE: Titles in Ptolemy al-Garib (A) This list is organized in the same way as D, except it contains none of the Intermediate or Particular works. It was written in Arabic, and later translated into Latin, and then reconstructed into Greek, which I here translate. PART FOUR: Titles in the order of Bekker (B) The modern edition contains works only in IA2 (“the works in propria persona”), and replaces the theoretical works before the practical and productive, as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Posterior Analytics
    POSTERIOR ANALYTICS The Posterior Analytics contains Aristotle!> epistemology and philosophy of science. His approach is broadly speaking foundational. Some of what we know can be justified by being shown to follow logically from other things that we know, but some of what we know does not need to be justified in this way. Such items of foundational knowledge are the first principles of the various sciences. In the excerpts below, Aristotle sets out the axiomatic structure of a science and presents his theory of explanation. The final chapter provides a tantalizing but obscure presentation of his ideas on the acquisition of first principles. BOOK I 1 71a All teaching and all intellectual learning result from previous cognition. This is clear if we examine all the cases; for this is how the mathematical 5 sciences and all crafts arise. This is also true of both deductive and induc­ tive arguments, since they both succeed in teaching because they rely on previous cognition: deductive arguments begin with premisses we are as­ sumed to understand, and inductive arguments prove the universal by relying on the fact that the particular is already clear. Rhetorical arguments 10 also persuade in the same way, since they rely either on examples (and hence on induction) or on argumentations (and hence on deduction). Previous cognition is needed in two ways. In some cases we must presup­ pose that something is! (for example, that it is true that everything is either asserted or denied truly <of a given subject». In other cases we must 15 comprehend what the thing spoken of is (for example, that a triangle signifies this); and in other cases we must do both (for example, we must both comprehend what a unit signifies and presuppose that there is such a thing).
    [Show full text]
  • The Beginnings of Formal Logic: Deduction in Aristotle's Topics Vs
    Phronesis 60 (�0�5) �67-309 brill.com/phro The Beginnings of Formal Logic: Deduction in Aristotle’s Topics vs. Prior Analytics Marko Malink Department of Philosophy, New York University, 5 Washington Place, New York, NY 10003. USA [email protected] Abstract It is widely agreed that Aristotle’s Prior Analytics, but not the Topics, marks the begin- ning of formal logic. There is less agreement as to why this is so. What are the distinctive features in virtue of which Aristotle’s discussion of deductions (syllogismoi) qualifies as formal logic in the one treatise but not in the other? To answer this question, I argue that in the Prior Analytics—unlike in the Topics—Aristotle is concerned to make fully explicit all the premisses that are necessary to derive the conclusion in a given deduction. Keywords formal logic – deduction – syllogismos – premiss – Prior Analytics – Topics 1 Introduction It is widely agreed that Aristotle’s Prior Analytics marks the beginning of formal logic.1 Aristotle’s main concern in this treatise is with deductions (syllogismoi). Deductions also play an important role in the Topics, which was written before the Prior Analytics.2 The two treatises start from the same definition of what 1 See e.g. Cornford 1935, 264; Russell 1946, 219; Ross 1949, 29; Bocheński 1956, 74; Allen 2001, 13; Ebert and Nortmann 2007, 106-7; Striker 2009, p. xi. 2 While the chronological order of Aristotle’s works cannot be determined with any certainty, scholars agree that the Topics was written before the Prior Analytics; see Brandis 1835, 252-9; Ross 1939, 251-2; Bocheński 1956, 49-51; Kneale and Kneale 1962, 23-4; Brunschwig 1967, © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���5 | doi �0.��63/�5685�84-��34��86 268 Malink a deduction is (stated in the first chapter of each).
    [Show full text]
  • A Note on the Simile of the Rout in the Posterior Analytics Ii 19
    Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) ©Mathesis Publications 1 A Note on the Simile of the Rout in the Posterior Analytics ii 19 James Lesher In the Posterior Analytics (APo ) ii 19, Aristotle compares the way in which sense perception ( αἴσθησις ) gives rise to knowledge of the universal ( τὸ καθόλου ) with the way in which one soldier’s ceasing his flight from the enemy leads other soldiers to do the same (100a12-13). 1 While the philosophical lesson appears to be that the human soul has the capacity to retain and organize multiple sense impressions (just as soldiers have the capacity to stop and form themselves into an effective fighting unit), the simile’s concluding phrase, ἕως ἐπὶ ἀρχὴν ἦλθεν , has no clear meaning. In Lesher 2010a I argued that the phrase should not be taken to mean ‘until the soldiers return to the original location or arrange - ment’ since that would suggest that in grasping the universal the mind returns to a prior state or condition (a view proposed by Plato but rejected by Aristotle at APo 99b25-7). I also noted that no surviving ancient account of a battle makes any mention of soldiers who cease their flight from the enemy and ‘come or go to an ἀρχή . Accordingly, I proposed that we take the subject of the verb ἦλθε to be the stabilizing of the sensible image in the soul and the ἀρχή toward which this process advances to be ‘the ἀρχή of art and scientific knowledge’ mentioned in the previous sentence. It seems clear that the process Aristotle was seeking to explain consists (ini - tially) in the stabilizing of the sensible image (99b36-110a2) and (subsequently) in the situating of the universal within a network of broader universals (100a15- b3).
    [Show full text]
  • The University of Chicago Aristotle on the Necessity
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO ARISTOTLE ON THE NECESSITY OF WHAT WE KNOW A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DIVISION OF THE HUMANITIES IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY BY JOSHUA MENDELSOHN CHICAGO, ILLINOIS JUNE 2019 TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS . iv ABSTRACT . v 1 INTRODUCTION . 1 1.1 Aristotle on what we know ........................... 1 1.2 Previous approaches ............................... 7 1.3 Some first steps toward an answer ....................... 25 1.4 Chapter breakdown ................................ 34 2 ARISTOTLE’S DURABILITY ARGUMENTS . 36 2.1 Knowledge in the Categories ........................... 36 2.1.1 Knowledge as a relative: Categories 7 . 36 2.1.2 Knowledge as a state: Categories 8 ................... 51 2.1.3 The tension between the two principles . 59 2.2 When what is changeable goes out of view: Nicomachean Ethics VI.3 . 66 2.2.1 The sense of “necessity” ......................... 74 2.2.2 A Platonic precursor: Theaetetus 163c–164b . 75 2.3 Durability and demonstration: Posterior Analytics I.6 . 79 2.4 Knowledge of sensible particulars: Metaphysics Ζ.15 . 86 2.5 Taking stock ................................... 88 3 THE OBJECT OF KNOWLEDGE . 90 3.1 The introduction of the Forms ......................... 93 3.2 The irrelevance of the Forms .......................... 96 3.3 Essentiality and necessity: Posterior Analytics I.4 . 102 3.3.1 “Of all” and “per se” . 103 3.3.2 Per se predications and necessity . 108 3.3.3 “Universal” ................................112 3.3.4 Demonstrative necessities concerning individuals . 115 3.4 Per se necessity in natural science . 120 3.4.1 Per se necessity in biology: Parts of Animals II.3 .
    [Show full text]
  • Colloquium 7 What Use Is Aristotle's Organon? Robin Smith
    Colloquium 7 What Use Is Aristotle's Organon? Robin Smith My title is ambiguous. I might be construed as asking what use we, today, as philosophers, can make of the collection of treatises which has been known since the time of the Aristotelian commentators as the "organon." These treatises are, in the main, a collection of works on logic and closely related subjects, including fallacious arguments and demonstrative sci- ence. Tradition regarded them as giving Aristotle's account of scientific philosophical method: the "instrument" necessary for the attainment of knowledge. It was as such that Francis Bacon rejected Aristotle's Organon and offered his own as its replace- ment. Scientific method, he thought, should be a way to attain new knowledge; but he saw in the Aristotelian procedures he had learned at school nothing but rules for argumentation and deduction, which could never lead to the enlargement of what one already knew. For the purposes he took to be important, then, he found the Aristotelian instrument useless. More recent philosophical interpretation of Aristotle has been perhaps more sympathetic to its philosophical superstructure. If we regard the picture of demonstrative science of the Posterior Analytics as an account of scientific explanation rather than an account of scien- tific discovery, its plausibility is much greater. However, the logical theories on which Aristotle relies, especially its theory of inference, are now more or less universally recognized to be inadequate to any formalization even of the sciences Aristotle himself knew: Greek mathematical demonstrations steadfastly resist any translation into categorical syllogisms. Even the use of modern formal methods to interpret Aristotle's works seems at best to permit us to congratulate him for having come close, in his awkward way, to something we have a much better grasp of now.
    [Show full text]
  • A Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle
    ARISTOTELIAN METHODOLOGY A Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle By J. Athanasius Weisheipl, O.P. (f) S.T.Lr., Ph.D., D.Phil. (Oxon) Pontifical Institute of Philosophy Dominican House of Studies-River Forest, Illinois. (1958) Edited by John R. Catan Ph.D. (Toronto) Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle—Weisheipl 2 INTRODUCTION I. Importance of Methodology Since the time of Francis Bacon (1561-1626) and Rene Descartes (1596-1650) considerable attention has been given to “methodology” by both philosophers and physical scientists (since the 17th Century these have been distinct groups). All at least agree that methodology is concerned with the correct procedure of discovering truth, but not all agree as to what this “method”should be. Forsome the correct method is methodical doubt and justification by clear and distinct ideas (eg. R. Descartes); for others it is the experimental method (e.g., Robert Boyle, Robert Hooker); for others it is the exhaustive classification of individual observations (e.g., Francis Bacon, John Stuart Mill); for still others it is the mathematical method of the physical sciences (e.g., Galileo Galilei, Isaac Newton and most modem physicists). Everyone wants to discover truth. Man has a natural desire to know the truth, not just the facts, but the reasons for their reality. All philosophical investigation begins in curiosity about the unknown. “When we see certain nanifest effects, the causes of which are hidden from us, we are provoked to wonder; and for this reason wonder was responsible for the beginning of philosophy.”(St.Thomas, In I Metaph., lect.3, n.55; cf.
    [Show full text]
  • Theoretical Nous in the Posterior Analytics ______
    THEORETICAL NOUS IN THE POSTERIOR ANALYTICS _________ BENJAMIM MORISON https://orcid.org/0000-0002-6574-8058 Princeton University Department of Philosophy Princeton, New Jersey United States [email protected] Article info CDD: 185 Received: 16.10.2019; Accepted: 18.10.2019 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/0100-6045.2019.V42N4.BM Keywords Aristotle Knowledge Understanding Episteme Nous Abstract: According to Aristotle's definition of episteme (understanding) in the Posterior Analytics, you have episteme of the proposition that P when you know why P, and you know that it is necessary that P. Episteme is therefore only available for propositions which have an explanation, i.e. the theorems of the science. It is a demanding cognitive state, since knowing the explanation of a proposition in a science requires being able to demonstrate or prove it. Aristotle occasionally refers to the counterpart notion to episteme which applies to propositions which lack an explanation, i.e. the first principles of a science. This counterpart notion is nous, or non-demonstrative understanding. Aristotle never defines it, but it should turn out to be an equally demanding cognitive state to achieve. This paper proposes that you have nous of the proposition that P when you know that nothing explains why P, you know the various ways in which the Manuscrito – Rev. Int. Fil. Campinas, 2019. Theoretical Nous in the Posterior Analytics 2 proposition that P features in explanations in the science, and you know that it is necessary that P. §1 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEME Nous, sometimes translated ‘insight’ or ‘intuition’, is an indispensable part of Aristotle’s epistemological scheme in the Posterior Analytics.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Methodology for Natural Science in Physics
    Journal of Ancient Philosophy, vol. 14 issue 2, 2020. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v14i2p130-146 Aristotle’s Methodology for Natural Science in Physics 1-2: a New Interpretation Evan Dutmer In this essay I will argue for an interpretation of the remarks of Physics 1.1 that both resolves some of the confusion surrounding the precise nature of methodology described there and shows how those remarks at 184a15-25 serve as important programmatic remarks besides, as they help in the structuring of books 1 and 2 of the Physics. I will argue that “what is clearer and more knowable to us” is what Aristotle goes on to describe in 1.2—namely, that nature exists and that natural things change—his basic starting-point for natural science. This, I shall hope to show, is the kind of “immediate” sense datum which Aristotle thinks must be further analyzed in terms of principles (archai) and then causes (aitia) over the course of Physics books 1 and 2 to lead to knowledge about the natural world.1 Such an analysis arrives at, as I shall show, a definition (horismos) of nature not initially available from the starting-point just mentioned (i.e., it is in need of further analysis), and which is clearer by nature.2 It is not my aim here to resolve longstanding debates surrounding Aristotle’s original intent in the ordering and composition of the first two books of the Physics, nor how the Physics is meant to fit into the Aristotelian corpus taken as a coherent whole, but rather to show that the first two books of the Physics, as they stand, fit with the picture of methodology for natural science presented to us in 1.1.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Aristotle's Understanding of Logic Lonergan Institute for the “Good
    1 Aristotle's Understanding of Logic Lonergan Institute for the “Good under Construction” In a methodological note which refers thus to the role or the significance of Aristotle's logic, it is to be admitted that, in some of his logical texts, Aristotle has identified his understanding of logic with the proper kind of method which belongs, in general, to the ways and means of our scientific inquiry. As we have already noted, logic exists as a species of necessary, preparatory tool for any kind of later work which is to be done within philosophy and science. In the study of logic, through the instrumentality of our human reason or by the use of our reasoning, we attend to our reasoning; we attend to how we function in our acts of human reasoning in a way which can know about how we should properly order all its parts or elements into an order which is distinctive of the kind of activity which properly belongs to us with respect to the being and the functioning of our human reason.1 Hence, as we have noted and as we attend to the conceptualization of Aristotle's language (in the Greek), in order to signify what is being meant by “tool” or “instrument,” Aristotle speaks about an organon: a "tool for [our] thinking" as this applies to any objects that we would want to ponder and think about. As a species of cognitive guide or norm, logic should order or it must order the form of our thinking and reasoning when our reasoning is engaged in deductions of one kind or another from something which is known at A toward something which would be known
    [Show full text]