228 NOTE on THINKING and GROUP ACTIVITY the Essence Of

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

228 NOTE on THINKING and GROUP ACTIVITY the Essence Of NOTES NOTE ON THINKING AND GROUP ACTIVITY The essence of group activity is revealed in that the member of a group is, first and foremost, a participant of interdependent situations. He can create the ‘I-images’ as a result of either a cognitive or emotional blockade of communi- cation and, precisely because of this, he starts to realize that he is an object of a motivational control. Self-control is an inner acceptance of a role. It conventionalizes behavior and protects it from impulses that lead to unbalanced behavior. Self-control is directly linked to such behavior. The unbalanced behavior could be altered by confronting with a position of a joint activity ascribed to other members of group. In other words, the ‘I-role’ includes the acceptance of a picture of the world developed by a group. The major functional unit of norm-creation then becomes meaning which, after all, appears to be equivalent to an objective norm as an aspect of its inner experience. From a position of the theory of behavior, meaning reveals that an individual is linked to objects. He lives his life sur- rounded by meanings that are determined by what people do with objects. Meaning, as it seems, has two aspects: first, a characteristic of behavior directed by other members of group to an acting individual (meaning as a ‘promise of a certain reaction’), and, second, a specific property of an object (an ‘expression of reaction’). However, only within an abstraction of the second aspect, objec- tified as a sign, can meaning be regarded as a generalization of orientations of co-members of group activity into a norm, which does not depend upon an object of orientation: V —— N A special position is reserved for meanings of categories, i.e., for classes of objects and events. Although these meanings can be intentionally posited only by means of evaluative representations, which employ images in an exten- sional sense, categories of knowledge perform as an independent source of meanings. Categories are generalized forms of assertions about existence and, 228 NOTES 229 in their very organization, carry a trace of intention of a categorizing con- sciousness. Their ‘mythological essence’ is hidden not in a content of trans- ferred material, but in their structural organization which appears to be an immediate source of deontic influence occurring within an assimilation of a norm in an aspect of meaning. Every category, thus, represents a meaning or a norm of certain pre-dispositions to action which are clearly organized and established. In his Elementary Forms of the Religious Life Durkheim was the first to attempt to generalize this characteristic of categories in a culturological sense, although the original idea belongs to Kant. A degree of awareness of consciousness in meaning as compared to non- meaningful fragments in a field of experience immediately determines its [mean- ing’s] value. A subjective aspect of meaning is revealed in its expectancy. Expectancy presupposes a symbolic form of the appearance of meaning that makes its social ratification possible. What people see in a certain situation (i.e., grasp as a sign) depends on what they expect to see, while what they expect [to see] is linked to the meanings with which they enter this given situation. The region of perception within group activity should be organized in such way that it allows for the perception of as many signals related to meaningful sentences as possible, and not for reaction to other signals. From here a difference between norm and value within a culture becomes evident. Norm correlates with mean- ing that is always directed to a subject of group communication, whereas value corresponds to a sign that emanates from such a subject. And even if objective and subjective sides of value are distinguished as well, the latter is always objec- tified, not in valuable, but in normative aspects [ ...] Meanings, as well, as norms, are models [patterns] of activity residing in deontic modality. Taken in different situations and determined by social reasons they can be presented either as patterns of potential activity (and can thus be transferred into hypothetic modality) or as patterns of actual activity (and can thus be transferred into apodictic modality). In the first case, they are trans- formed into signs-values, since value in its essence always presupposes (‘hypoth- esizes’) an aspiration to it from a subject, because it can be realized [off-thought objectively] only within such aspiration. In the second case norms-meanings are converted into representations of knowledge. Human ideas [images] of reality compose an independent projection of a social process. What is called a reality for or by a psychological subject is a cer- tain operative orientation [of actions] to which a high degree of concord exists that should be known to a subject; otherwise, he would not realize [presence of] reality as such. In an anthropological sense, a symbolic organization of human experience forms a genuine environment of human existence, the since realm of spontaneous perceptions is organized according to configurations of systems of meanings extracted from this environment. From a sociological point of view, culture is a product of symbolic communication. Pictures of the world are organized by means of symbols, and those who master these symbols, acquire a similar image 230 ANALOGY IN INDIAN AND WESTERN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT of this world. Every social world is a cultural region whose borders are determined not by territory or formal membership, but by the limits of effective communica- tions. But in order to become aware of these limits we need certain criteria shaped as regulative ideas of collective consciousness. A goal of traditional philosophy has consisted of working out of the concepts of these ultimate ideas (such was, for instance, Kant’s definition of the goal of philosophy). However, these concepts, and methodological conclusions created on the basis of their foundation, always appear to be limited by the reality of [a certain] culture. NOTE ON TIME AND SPACE / .../ Consciousness and, linked to it, planned behavior is a non-spatial form of behavior connected to an idea of causality and to the placing of an event within time. Consciousness does not have anything as its exterior motif. This is exactly what Kant meant when he called time a condition of an inner experience. Two major conditions of experience - an exterior (space) and an interior (time) - are linked to the two channels or varieties of means of transference of tradition men- tioned above. The acoustic channel that permits us to separate and objectify a con- dition of a subjects is associated with a ‘gestalt of space’, whereas an eidetic channel, which does not allow such separation, [is linked] to a ‘gestalt of time’, when a subject is not in a position to leave its stream. It seems, then, there is a con- tradiction here: an eidetic representation is simultaneously posited in space and time, whereas an acoustic, on the contrary, develops in time’s succession and is never actually present in all its elements. In fact, everything is contrariwise: in an eidetic representation a sense of correlation between elements and an entity is achieved as the result of a consecutive ‘looking round’ and a placing its evaluations into a temporal axis. This is why a logical connection is usually associated with a genetic one when notions of cause and action are under scrutiny. Any visual object perceived in its totality cannot be a sign. On the contrary, an idea of the integrity of a fragment of phonation can be achieved only as a result of ‘placing’ its elements on a non-temporal screen of ‘Space’ (see the image of eternity in William Blake’s interpretation). Quite remarkable seems to be the difference between two types of logical thinking established within two cultures where an acoustic or eidetic type of tradition appeared to be predominant: Indian and Hellenic correspondingly. Logical thinking developed because of the participation [of individuals] in social groups. Logic combines rules of persuasion, which make thinking more effective. Formal deduction is verification according to conventional categories, i.e., to principles of reference accepted within a certain group. Logical proce- dures are formed under the influence of group approval or disapproval. Logical thinking is rational because [it is] social. These general ideas can be presented differently depending on the type of tra- dition. In the Hellenic case, where group relations are based on transformation V—I, it resulted in the Aristotelian syllogistic; predicates are placed there on the NOTES 231 foundation of a formal gender-specific principle, according to which a particu- lar judgment is subjected to the jurisdiction of a more general one. This pre- supposes a unity of time with a subject of a judgment, as well as with a reflecting subject which analyses [establishes] this linkage. Such a relation can never be real in a spatial sense, only in a temporal one. For instance, ‘horse’, ‘cock’, and ‘animal’ cannot simultaneously be placed in space, whereas they can in time: e.g., when someone first makes an assertion about animals, and then about horses or cocks. Eidetic Greek thinking is genuinely reflective. Moreover, because it also simultaneously possesses ‘gestalt of time’, nothing can prevent a Platonic eidetic hierarchy, where a relation of particular and general is not dis- tinguished from a relation of cause and effect, from transforming into a foun- dation of a theory of formal deduction. Contrariwise, in India, where thinking is not reflective (because it is not subjective) but constructive, a development of logical form is slowed down, since additional efforts to place judgments in a sys- tem of successive elements not connected by a factor of time become necessary.
Recommended publications
  • Marko Malink (NYU)
    Demonstration by reductio ad impossibile in Posterior Analytics 1.26 Marko Malink (New York University) Contents 1. Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 ................................................................................. 1 2. Direct negative demonstration vs. demonstration by reductio ................................................. 14 3. Aristotle’s argument from priority in nature .............................................................................. 25 4. Priority in nature for a-propositions ............................................................................................ 38 5. Priority in nature for e-, i-, and o-propositions .......................................................................... 55 6. Accounting for Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 ................................................... 65 7. Parts and wholes ............................................................................................................................. 77 References ............................................................................................................................................ 89 1. Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 At the beginning of the Analytics, Aristotle states that the subject of the treatise is demonstration (ἀπόδειξις). A demonstration, for Aristotle, is a kind of deductive argument. It is a deduction through which, when we possess it, we have scientific knowledge (ἐπιστήμη). While the Prior Analytics deals with deduction in
    [Show full text]
  • The INPR Journal. Volume I, Fall 2020
    Crossing: The INPR Journal. Volume I, Fall 2020. Editor in chief Emmanuel Falque Editorial coordinators William L. Connelly Domenico Cambria Editorial committee Tamsin Jones Adam Graves Martin Koci William Woody S.J. Crossing: The INPR Journal. Volume I. November 2020. 26 Rue d’Assas 75006 Paris, France. ISSN (online): 2644-9242 DOI: 10.21428/8766eb43.b95a977c Web: https://inprjournal.pubpub.org/ http://www.network-inpr.org/ Email: [email protected] Crossing : une étape fondatrice de l’INPR (English Translation on Page III) L’international Network of Philosophy of Religion (INPR) est un réseau international de jeunes philosophes et théologiens (doctorants, post-doctorants, jeunes professeurs) réunis pour travailler ensemble autour de la question de Dieu et de sa pertinence dans un monde contemporain sécularisé. Essentiellement appuyé sur la philosophie continentale, mais pas exclusivement, il s’efforce d’être au service d’un renouveau de la philosophie et de la théologie chez les jeunes générations pour aujourd’hui. Loin de rester chacune sur leur pré-carré, philosophie et théologie sont appelées aujourd’hui à se croiser et à davantage se féconder mutuellement, dans le respect de la distinction des disciplines. Et les chercheurs de différents pays, en particulier ceux qui feront la pensée de demain, doivent eux aussi mieux dialoguer, sûrs que dans la confrontation des idées se fomente le terreau d’où naissent de nouvelles pensées. Inauguré en 2015, ce réseau international compte aujourd’hui plus d’une centaine de membres personnellement engagés, de plus de dix nationalités différentes, et venus en particulier d’Europe et des États-Unis. Les membres qui constituent ce réseau ont déjà fait la preuve par plusieurs séminaires (grands colloques ou séminaires doctoraux et post-doctoraux) du bien-fondé de leur démarche commune.
    [Show full text]
  • Allan Gotthelf's Teleology, First Principles, And
    Reason Papers Vol. 35, no. 1 Review Essays Review Essay: Allan Gotthelf’s Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Biology and James G. Lennox and Robert Bolton’s (ed.) Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle Owen Goldin Marquette University Although readers of Reason Papers are no doubt familiar with Allan Gotthelf’s extensive efforts aimed at a more widespread appreciation of Ayn Rand’s philosophical thought, he is best known among historians of philosophy and science for his contributions to the understanding of Aristotle’s biological works, which have shed much light on Aristotle’s scientific methodology, epistemology, and metaphysics. Two new books allow us to take account of Gotthelf’s contributions to Aristotelian studies. The first is a collection of Gotthelf’s most important papers on Aristotle.1 Although the papers were written independently, there is little superfluous repetition, and taken together they constitute a comprehensive and coherent account of Aristotle’s biology and its philosophical significance. The second, which has its origin in a 2004 conference in Gotthelf’s honor, is a collection of papers on Aristotle, most of which focus on themes that Gotthelf himself has discussed.2 Some of the papers further his thought, taking it in new directions; others depart from Gotthelf in philosophically interesting ways. Gotthelf believes that one of his most important contributions to Aristotelian studies lies in his account of teleology in the biological writings. For this he gives credit to Rand (p. viii) (who personally led Gotthelf to the study of Aristotle), for she had argued that scientific explanation must identify potentials inherent in natures.
    [Show full text]
  • Catalogue of Titles of Works Attributed to Aristotle
    Catalogue of Titles of works attributed by Aristotle 1 To enhance readability of the translations and usability of the catalogues, I have inserted the following bold headings into the lists. These have no authority in any manuscript, but are based on a theory about the composition of the lists described in chapter 3. The text and numbering follows that of O. Gigon, Librorum deperditorum fragmenta. PART ONE: Titles in Diogenes Laertius (D) I. Universal works (ta kathalou) A. The treatises (ta syntagmatika) 1. The dialogues or exoterica (ta dialogika ex terika) 2. The works in propria persona or lectures (ta autopros pa akroamatika) a. Instrumental works (ta organika) b. Practical works (ta praktika) c. Productive Works (ta poi tika) d. Theoretical works (ta the r tika) . Natural philosophy (ta physiologia) . Mathematics (ta math matika) B. Notebooks (ta hypomn matika) II. Intermediate works (ta metaxu) III. Particular works (ta merika) PART TWO: Titles in the Vita Hesychii (H) This list is organized in the same way as D, with two exceptions. First, IA2c “productive works” has dropped out. Second, there is an appendix, organized as follows: IV. Appendix A. Intermediate or Particular works B. Treatises C. Notebooks D. Falsely ascribed works PART THREE: Titles in Ptolemy al-Garib (A) This list is organized in the same way as D, except it contains none of the Intermediate or Particular works. It was written in Arabic, and later translated into Latin, and then reconstructed into Greek, which I here translate. PART FOUR: Titles in the order of Bekker (B) The modern edition contains works only in IA2 (“the works in propria persona”), and replaces the theoretical works before the practical and productive, as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Posterior Analytics
    POSTERIOR ANALYTICS The Posterior Analytics contains Aristotle!> epistemology and philosophy of science. His approach is broadly speaking foundational. Some of what we know can be justified by being shown to follow logically from other things that we know, but some of what we know does not need to be justified in this way. Such items of foundational knowledge are the first principles of the various sciences. In the excerpts below, Aristotle sets out the axiomatic structure of a science and presents his theory of explanation. The final chapter provides a tantalizing but obscure presentation of his ideas on the acquisition of first principles. BOOK I 1 71a All teaching and all intellectual learning result from previous cognition. This is clear if we examine all the cases; for this is how the mathematical 5 sciences and all crafts arise. This is also true of both deductive and induc­ tive arguments, since they both succeed in teaching because they rely on previous cognition: deductive arguments begin with premisses we are as­ sumed to understand, and inductive arguments prove the universal by relying on the fact that the particular is already clear. Rhetorical arguments 10 also persuade in the same way, since they rely either on examples (and hence on induction) or on argumentations (and hence on deduction). Previous cognition is needed in two ways. In some cases we must presup­ pose that something is! (for example, that it is true that everything is either asserted or denied truly <of a given subject». In other cases we must 15 comprehend what the thing spoken of is (for example, that a triangle signifies this); and in other cases we must do both (for example, we must both comprehend what a unit signifies and presuppose that there is such a thing).
    [Show full text]
  • The Beginnings of Formal Logic: Deduction in Aristotle's Topics Vs
    Phronesis 60 (�0�5) �67-309 brill.com/phro The Beginnings of Formal Logic: Deduction in Aristotle’s Topics vs. Prior Analytics Marko Malink Department of Philosophy, New York University, 5 Washington Place, New York, NY 10003. USA [email protected] Abstract It is widely agreed that Aristotle’s Prior Analytics, but not the Topics, marks the begin- ning of formal logic. There is less agreement as to why this is so. What are the distinctive features in virtue of which Aristotle’s discussion of deductions (syllogismoi) qualifies as formal logic in the one treatise but not in the other? To answer this question, I argue that in the Prior Analytics—unlike in the Topics—Aristotle is concerned to make fully explicit all the premisses that are necessary to derive the conclusion in a given deduction. Keywords formal logic – deduction – syllogismos – premiss – Prior Analytics – Topics 1 Introduction It is widely agreed that Aristotle’s Prior Analytics marks the beginning of formal logic.1 Aristotle’s main concern in this treatise is with deductions (syllogismoi). Deductions also play an important role in the Topics, which was written before the Prior Analytics.2 The two treatises start from the same definition of what 1 See e.g. Cornford 1935, 264; Russell 1946, 219; Ross 1949, 29; Bocheński 1956, 74; Allen 2001, 13; Ebert and Nortmann 2007, 106-7; Striker 2009, p. xi. 2 While the chronological order of Aristotle’s works cannot be determined with any certainty, scholars agree that the Topics was written before the Prior Analytics; see Brandis 1835, 252-9; Ross 1939, 251-2; Bocheński 1956, 49-51; Kneale and Kneale 1962, 23-4; Brunschwig 1967, © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���5 | doi �0.��63/�5685�84-��34��86 268 Malink a deduction is (stated in the first chapter of each).
    [Show full text]
  • A Note on the Simile of the Rout in the Posterior Analytics Ii 19
    Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) ©Mathesis Publications 1 A Note on the Simile of the Rout in the Posterior Analytics ii 19 James Lesher In the Posterior Analytics (APo ) ii 19, Aristotle compares the way in which sense perception ( αἴσθησις ) gives rise to knowledge of the universal ( τὸ καθόλου ) with the way in which one soldier’s ceasing his flight from the enemy leads other soldiers to do the same (100a12-13). 1 While the philosophical lesson appears to be that the human soul has the capacity to retain and organize multiple sense impressions (just as soldiers have the capacity to stop and form themselves into an effective fighting unit), the simile’s concluding phrase, ἕως ἐπὶ ἀρχὴν ἦλθεν , has no clear meaning. In Lesher 2010a I argued that the phrase should not be taken to mean ‘until the soldiers return to the original location or arrange - ment’ since that would suggest that in grasping the universal the mind returns to a prior state or condition (a view proposed by Plato but rejected by Aristotle at APo 99b25-7). I also noted that no surviving ancient account of a battle makes any mention of soldiers who cease their flight from the enemy and ‘come or go to an ἀρχή . Accordingly, I proposed that we take the subject of the verb ἦλθε to be the stabilizing of the sensible image in the soul and the ἀρχή toward which this process advances to be ‘the ἀρχή of art and scientific knowledge’ mentioned in the previous sentence. It seems clear that the process Aristotle was seeking to explain consists (ini - tially) in the stabilizing of the sensible image (99b36-110a2) and (subsequently) in the situating of the universal within a network of broader universals (100a15- b3).
    [Show full text]
  • The University of Chicago Aristotle on the Necessity
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO ARISTOTLE ON THE NECESSITY OF WHAT WE KNOW A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DIVISION OF THE HUMANITIES IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY BY JOSHUA MENDELSOHN CHICAGO, ILLINOIS JUNE 2019 TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS . iv ABSTRACT . v 1 INTRODUCTION . 1 1.1 Aristotle on what we know ........................... 1 1.2 Previous approaches ............................... 7 1.3 Some first steps toward an answer ....................... 25 1.4 Chapter breakdown ................................ 34 2 ARISTOTLE’S DURABILITY ARGUMENTS . 36 2.1 Knowledge in the Categories ........................... 36 2.1.1 Knowledge as a relative: Categories 7 . 36 2.1.2 Knowledge as a state: Categories 8 ................... 51 2.1.3 The tension between the two principles . 59 2.2 When what is changeable goes out of view: Nicomachean Ethics VI.3 . 66 2.2.1 The sense of “necessity” ......................... 74 2.2.2 A Platonic precursor: Theaetetus 163c–164b . 75 2.3 Durability and demonstration: Posterior Analytics I.6 . 79 2.4 Knowledge of sensible particulars: Metaphysics Ζ.15 . 86 2.5 Taking stock ................................... 88 3 THE OBJECT OF KNOWLEDGE . 90 3.1 The introduction of the Forms ......................... 93 3.2 The irrelevance of the Forms .......................... 96 3.3 Essentiality and necessity: Posterior Analytics I.4 . 102 3.3.1 “Of all” and “per se” . 103 3.3.2 Per se predications and necessity . 108 3.3.3 “Universal” ................................112 3.3.4 Demonstrative necessities concerning individuals . 115 3.4 Per se necessity in natural science . 120 3.4.1 Per se necessity in biology: Parts of Animals II.3 .
    [Show full text]
  • Colloquium 7 What Use Is Aristotle's Organon? Robin Smith
    Colloquium 7 What Use Is Aristotle's Organon? Robin Smith My title is ambiguous. I might be construed as asking what use we, today, as philosophers, can make of the collection of treatises which has been known since the time of the Aristotelian commentators as the "organon." These treatises are, in the main, a collection of works on logic and closely related subjects, including fallacious arguments and demonstrative sci- ence. Tradition regarded them as giving Aristotle's account of scientific philosophical method: the "instrument" necessary for the attainment of knowledge. It was as such that Francis Bacon rejected Aristotle's Organon and offered his own as its replace- ment. Scientific method, he thought, should be a way to attain new knowledge; but he saw in the Aristotelian procedures he had learned at school nothing but rules for argumentation and deduction, which could never lead to the enlargement of what one already knew. For the purposes he took to be important, then, he found the Aristotelian instrument useless. More recent philosophical interpretation of Aristotle has been perhaps more sympathetic to its philosophical superstructure. If we regard the picture of demonstrative science of the Posterior Analytics as an account of scientific explanation rather than an account of scien- tific discovery, its plausibility is much greater. However, the logical theories on which Aristotle relies, especially its theory of inference, are now more or less universally recognized to be inadequate to any formalization even of the sciences Aristotle himself knew: Greek mathematical demonstrations steadfastly resist any translation into categorical syllogisms. Even the use of modern formal methods to interpret Aristotle's works seems at best to permit us to congratulate him for having come close, in his awkward way, to something we have a much better grasp of now.
    [Show full text]
  • A Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle
    ARISTOTELIAN METHODOLOGY A Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle By J. Athanasius Weisheipl, O.P. (f) S.T.Lr., Ph.D., D.Phil. (Oxon) Pontifical Institute of Philosophy Dominican House of Studies-River Forest, Illinois. (1958) Edited by John R. Catan Ph.D. (Toronto) Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle—Weisheipl 2 INTRODUCTION I. Importance of Methodology Since the time of Francis Bacon (1561-1626) and Rene Descartes (1596-1650) considerable attention has been given to “methodology” by both philosophers and physical scientists (since the 17th Century these have been distinct groups). All at least agree that methodology is concerned with the correct procedure of discovering truth, but not all agree as to what this “method”should be. Forsome the correct method is methodical doubt and justification by clear and distinct ideas (eg. R. Descartes); for others it is the experimental method (e.g., Robert Boyle, Robert Hooker); for others it is the exhaustive classification of individual observations (e.g., Francis Bacon, John Stuart Mill); for still others it is the mathematical method of the physical sciences (e.g., Galileo Galilei, Isaac Newton and most modem physicists). Everyone wants to discover truth. Man has a natural desire to know the truth, not just the facts, but the reasons for their reality. All philosophical investigation begins in curiosity about the unknown. “When we see certain nanifest effects, the causes of which are hidden from us, we are provoked to wonder; and for this reason wonder was responsible for the beginning of philosophy.”(St.Thomas, In I Metaph., lect.3, n.55; cf.
    [Show full text]
  • Theoretical Nous in the Posterior Analytics ______
    THEORETICAL NOUS IN THE POSTERIOR ANALYTICS _________ BENJAMIM MORISON https://orcid.org/0000-0002-6574-8058 Princeton University Department of Philosophy Princeton, New Jersey United States [email protected] Article info CDD: 185 Received: 16.10.2019; Accepted: 18.10.2019 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/0100-6045.2019.V42N4.BM Keywords Aristotle Knowledge Understanding Episteme Nous Abstract: According to Aristotle's definition of episteme (understanding) in the Posterior Analytics, you have episteme of the proposition that P when you know why P, and you know that it is necessary that P. Episteme is therefore only available for propositions which have an explanation, i.e. the theorems of the science. It is a demanding cognitive state, since knowing the explanation of a proposition in a science requires being able to demonstrate or prove it. Aristotle occasionally refers to the counterpart notion to episteme which applies to propositions which lack an explanation, i.e. the first principles of a science. This counterpart notion is nous, or non-demonstrative understanding. Aristotle never defines it, but it should turn out to be an equally demanding cognitive state to achieve. This paper proposes that you have nous of the proposition that P when you know that nothing explains why P, you know the various ways in which the Manuscrito – Rev. Int. Fil. Campinas, 2019. Theoretical Nous in the Posterior Analytics 2 proposition that P features in explanations in the science, and you know that it is necessary that P. §1 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEME Nous, sometimes translated ‘insight’ or ‘intuition’, is an indispensable part of Aristotle’s epistemological scheme in the Posterior Analytics.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Methodology for Natural Science in Physics
    Journal of Ancient Philosophy, vol. 14 issue 2, 2020. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v14i2p130-146 Aristotle’s Methodology for Natural Science in Physics 1-2: a New Interpretation Evan Dutmer In this essay I will argue for an interpretation of the remarks of Physics 1.1 that both resolves some of the confusion surrounding the precise nature of methodology described there and shows how those remarks at 184a15-25 serve as important programmatic remarks besides, as they help in the structuring of books 1 and 2 of the Physics. I will argue that “what is clearer and more knowable to us” is what Aristotle goes on to describe in 1.2—namely, that nature exists and that natural things change—his basic starting-point for natural science. This, I shall hope to show, is the kind of “immediate” sense datum which Aristotle thinks must be further analyzed in terms of principles (archai) and then causes (aitia) over the course of Physics books 1 and 2 to lead to knowledge about the natural world.1 Such an analysis arrives at, as I shall show, a definition (horismos) of nature not initially available from the starting-point just mentioned (i.e., it is in need of further analysis), and which is clearer by nature.2 It is not my aim here to resolve longstanding debates surrounding Aristotle’s original intent in the ordering and composition of the first two books of the Physics, nor how the Physics is meant to fit into the Aristotelian corpus taken as a coherent whole, but rather to show that the first two books of the Physics, as they stand, fit with the picture of methodology for natural science presented to us in 1.1.
    [Show full text]