Philosophy of Nature and of Science Volume I: the Foundations

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophy of Nature and of Science Volume I: the Foundations Gianfranco Basti Philosophy of Nature and of Science Volume I: The Foundations Translation by Philip Larrey not revised by the Author For Students Use Only Rome 2012 (Italian Original 2002, Published by Lateran University Press©) Gianfranco Basti Philosophy of Nature and of Science Volume I: The Foundations Translated by Philip Larrey [*Image on the cover*. Capture, occurred about 40 million years ago, of the spiral galaxy (IC2163) into the gravitational field of another one (NGC2207). They are destined, in few billion years to become one only galaxy. (NASA, Hubble Space Telescope Institute© ]. , ) 0. General Introduction Introductory remarks concerning the purpose and struc- ture of this work as well as its contents 0.1 General Framework his book intends to be a manual with the ambitious goal of de- fining a systematic link between two disciplines: the philosophy of T nature and the philosophy of science, in terms of their often prob- lematic relationship with mathematical and natural sciences. The Philosophy of Nature is a special discipline within General Metaphysics, which has as its object the universe of physical beings with their specific structures, properties and causal relationships, examined on the level of their fundamental ontology. The Philosophy of Nature is therefore distinguished from the other natural sciences (physical, biological and cognitive), which, from a modern perspective, are limited to the study of natural phenomena, in as much as they are measurable, and of laws, usually formalized with the help of mathematics, which govern the evolution in time of these phe- nomena. The Philosophy of Science, on the other hand, is recent a discipline within the philosophical panorama, dating from less than a century ago. It is characterized as a special discipline of the Philosophy of Knowledge or Gnose- ology, and has as its object the logical and epistemological foundations of the natural sciences and mathematics. Often, due to the eclipse of the phi- losophy of nature in modern culture, it has come to occupy a vicarious role for the philosophy of nature, dealing with questions of an ontologi- cal nature, if not directly metaphysical, i.e., the origin and destiny of the universe in cosmology; the nature of matter, space and time in the physical sciences; the nature of life in the biological sciences; or the na- ture of knowledge or of the mind in cognitive sciences. Given that the question concerning the foundations is the key to under- stand the complex relations between science and mathematics in mod- ernity, and, today, also between philosophy of science and philosophy of nature, the development of these issues in the first two parts of the book will entail a good part of this work. 6 PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE AND OF SCIENCE This work is therefore divided into volumes. The First Volume is exclu- sively dedicated to the First and Second part of the treatise, i.e., the defi- nition of the historical and theoretical framework of the issue concern- ing the foundations. The Second Volume is dedicated to the other three parts that deal with the applications of logical and metaphysical princi- ples, discussed in the First Volume, and with the objects of the physical, biological and cognitive sciences. Volume I: Philosophy of Nature and of Science. The Foundations. First Part: Historical Framing of the Issue. – 0. Introduction – 1. Science: from the origins until the Nineteenth Century – 2. The Twentieth Cen- tury and its scientific revolutions – 3. The search for foundations in the Twentieth Century. Second Part: Theoretical Framing of the Issue. – 4. Philosophy of Nature and Philosophy of Science. – 5. Classical metaphysics and modern thought. – 6. Highlights concerning a metaphysics of physical being. Volume II. Philosophy of Nature and of Science. Physical, Biological and Cognitive Sciences. Third Part: Physical Sciences and their Objects – 1. The structure of matter and its complexity – 2. Scientific cosmology and the origin of the universe. Fourth Part: Biological Sciences and their Objects. – 3. Different ontologies about living beings and the biological sciences. – 4. Scientific hypothesis concerning evolution and the origins of life. Fifth Part: Cognitive Sciences and their Objects – 5. Cognitive functions and their neurophysiological bases – 6. Freedom and psycho-physical de- terminisms – 7. Psychophysical unity of the person and the origins of human life. 0.2 Contents of this volume 0.2.1 Advice on how to read this book Three suggestions for reading this The vastness and complexity of this first volume of the complete work book may appear to be in contradiction of the desire to construct a ‘manual’. In order to make reading easier, aside from the indexes and the glossary of scientific terms at the end of the book, chapters summaries have been introduced to synthesize the content of each one. INTRODUCTION 7 What we recommend to the reader and especially to students is to pro- ceed step-by-step while reading this book. 1. Above all, read this introduction carefully which will clarify the aims of the whole treatise, placing it within the modern and contemporary de- bate concerning the issue, and summarizing the logical develop- ment of the entire work. For this reason, frequent allusions are made to different parts of the book which deal with the same ar- guments in a more complete way. An attentive reader will be able to locate those areas of the book which interest him the most. 2. Secondly, read the chapter summaries. From this second level of under- standing, one can obtain a clear idea of the different parts of the treatise while at the same time retaining a clear vision of its unity. 3. Thirdly, start reading the contents of each chapter, understanding the subject of the entire work by way of concentric circles. 0.2.2 Truth and causality in Science Three basic In this first volume, dedicated to the «foundations», we will examine questions of this some basic questions concerning the problem of the relation between Volume philosophy of nature on the one hand, and between philosophy of na- ture and philosophy of science on the other hand. There are two ques- tions of immediate metaphysical importance which will occupy our at- tention and which are particularly relevant for modern thinkers: 1. Truth and realism The problem concerning the truth and realism of scientific construc- of scientific tions within the natural sciences, with particular reference (from knowledge within the hypothetical-deductive method) to the question of the real foundation of the hypotheses that are at the base of different sci- entific theories; against the thesis (common to both logical neo- positivism and Popperian falsificationism) of the non rational char- acter of invention and of the construction of the same theories. 2. Logical necessity, The problem of causality and its foundation in the natural sciences in causal necessity relation to the problem of the logical necessity of demonstrations and and their relation of its foundation. Notice that classical thought and modern thought are at opposite ends of the debate concerning this issue. While for classical thought, especially Aristotelian-thomistic, it was the neces- sity of real relations (causal) – those that determine the existence (or common being) and the being (or being of the essence) of the in- dividual natural beings – that through abstraction grounded the ne- 8 PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE AND OF SCIENCE cessity of logical relations, for modern thought after Kant, the exact opposite is true. It is the necessity of the self-evidence of the logical a priori, of the formal relation between logical antecedent and conse- quent that grounded the necessity of the causal relation between predecessor and empirical successor, placed in temporal succession and made evident by experimental knowledge. In such a way, Kant intended to solve Hume’s famous “problem of induction”. Such a solution was derived from two tacit suppositions: Critique of the a. One supposition that tied the causal relation exclusively to the Humian-Kantian temporal relation between predecessor and successor of the model of causality in the sciences: process, because the paradigm used was that of Newtonian me- a. Causal relation chanics*1 of dynamic integrated systems, where the final state of grounded by time the process depends univocally on the initial conditions. In this and therefore by way, for the first time causality was tied to the knowledge of consciousness the phenomenon, instead of to the being of the thing, since without the mind there can not be even time. b. Apodictic b. A second supposition dealt with a apodictic foundation of the Foundation of logical a priori, a foundation based on the Cartesian principle of necessity based on evidence, evidence not only of the first principles of formal evidence and therefore on logic (principle of non-contradiction, of identity, etc.) and of consciousness their application to «being in terms of being» of metaphysics, as it was for classical thought, but also of the postulates of the different sciences. Above all, the postulates of Euclidean geome- try* in its «algebraic» or «analytical» form as proposed by Des- cartes were considered self-evident and therefore apodictic. However, after Newton, the three fundamental postulates (laws) of mechanics were also considered in this manner. In this way, we see an abandoning of the classical distinction be- tween self-evident axioms (or «first principles» of logics and metaphysics) and postulates (or «first principles» of the various scientific, physical and mathematical disciplines), anything but self evident for classical thought – one need think only of the difficulties that the famous fifth postulate of Euclid caused the ancient mathematicians -- , given that they did not deal with the common being (existence) of any being as with general 1 The terms indicated with an asterisk «*» are defined in the «Glossary», added as an Ap- pendix at the end of the book, because they are terms which are not defined and ex- plained within the treatise itself.
Recommended publications
  • Machine Guessing – I
    Machine Guessing { I David Miller Department of Philosophy University of Warwick COVENTRY CV4 7AL UK e-mail: [email protected] ⃝c copyright D. W. Miller 2011{2018 Abstract According to Karl Popper, the evolution of science, logically, methodologically, and even psy- chologically, is an involved interplay of acute conjectures and blunt refutations. Like biological evolution, it is an endless round of blind variation and selective retention. But unlike biological evolution, it incorporates, at the stage of selection, the use of reason. Part I of this two-part paper begins by repudiating the common beliefs that Hume's problem of induction, which com- pellingly confutes the thesis that science is rational in the way that most people think that it is rational, can be solved by assuming that science is rational, or by assuming that Hume was irrational (that is, by ignoring his argument). The problem of induction can be solved only by a non-authoritarian theory of rationality. It is shown also that because hypotheses cannot be distilled directly from experience, all knowledge is eventually dependent on blind conjecture, and therefore itself conjectural. In particular, the use of rules of inference, or of good or bad rules for generating conjectures, is conjectural. Part II of the paper expounds a form of Popper's critical rationalism that locates the rationality of science entirely in the deductive processes by which conjectures are criticized and improved. But extreme forms of deductivism are rejected. The paper concludes with a sharp dismissal of the view that work in artificial intelligence, including the JSM method cultivated extensively by Victor Finn, does anything to upset critical rationalism.
    [Show full text]
  • Marko Malink (NYU)
    Demonstration by reductio ad impossibile in Posterior Analytics 1.26 Marko Malink (New York University) Contents 1. Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 ................................................................................. 1 2. Direct negative demonstration vs. demonstration by reductio ................................................. 14 3. Aristotle’s argument from priority in nature .............................................................................. 25 4. Priority in nature for a-propositions ............................................................................................ 38 5. Priority in nature for e-, i-, and o-propositions .......................................................................... 55 6. Accounting for Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 ................................................... 65 7. Parts and wholes ............................................................................................................................. 77 References ............................................................................................................................................ 89 1. Aristotle’s thesis in Posterior Analytics 1. 26 At the beginning of the Analytics, Aristotle states that the subject of the treatise is demonstration (ἀπόδειξις). A demonstration, for Aristotle, is a kind of deductive argument. It is a deduction through which, when we possess it, we have scientific knowledge (ἐπιστήμη). While the Prior Analytics deals with deduction in
    [Show full text]
  • The INPR Journal. Volume I, Fall 2020
    Crossing: The INPR Journal. Volume I, Fall 2020. Editor in chief Emmanuel Falque Editorial coordinators William L. Connelly Domenico Cambria Editorial committee Tamsin Jones Adam Graves Martin Koci William Woody S.J. Crossing: The INPR Journal. Volume I. November 2020. 26 Rue d’Assas 75006 Paris, France. ISSN (online): 2644-9242 DOI: 10.21428/8766eb43.b95a977c Web: https://inprjournal.pubpub.org/ http://www.network-inpr.org/ Email: [email protected] Crossing : une étape fondatrice de l’INPR (English Translation on Page III) L’international Network of Philosophy of Religion (INPR) est un réseau international de jeunes philosophes et théologiens (doctorants, post-doctorants, jeunes professeurs) réunis pour travailler ensemble autour de la question de Dieu et de sa pertinence dans un monde contemporain sécularisé. Essentiellement appuyé sur la philosophie continentale, mais pas exclusivement, il s’efforce d’être au service d’un renouveau de la philosophie et de la théologie chez les jeunes générations pour aujourd’hui. Loin de rester chacune sur leur pré-carré, philosophie et théologie sont appelées aujourd’hui à se croiser et à davantage se féconder mutuellement, dans le respect de la distinction des disciplines. Et les chercheurs de différents pays, en particulier ceux qui feront la pensée de demain, doivent eux aussi mieux dialoguer, sûrs que dans la confrontation des idées se fomente le terreau d’où naissent de nouvelles pensées. Inauguré en 2015, ce réseau international compte aujourd’hui plus d’une centaine de membres personnellement engagés, de plus de dix nationalités différentes, et venus en particulier d’Europe et des États-Unis. Les membres qui constituent ce réseau ont déjà fait la preuve par plusieurs séminaires (grands colloques ou séminaires doctoraux et post-doctoraux) du bien-fondé de leur démarche commune.
    [Show full text]
  • 'History, Method and Pluralism: a Re-Interpretation of Isaiah Berlin's
    HISTORY, METHOD, AND PLURALISM A Re-interpretation of Isaiah Berlin’s Political Thought Thesis submitted to the University of London for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy by HAOYEH London School of Economics and Political Science 2005 UMI Number: U205195 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Dissertation Publishing UMI U205195 Published by ProQuest LLC 2014. Copyright in the Dissertation held by the Author. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 S 510 Abstract of the Thesis In the literature on Berlin to date, two broad approaches to study his political thought can be detected. The first is the piecemeal approach, which tends to single out an element of Berlin’s thought (for example, his distinction between negative liberty and positive liberty) for exposition or criticism, leaving other elements unaccounted. And the second is the holistic approach, which pays attention to the overall structure of Berlin’s thought as a whole, in particular the relation between his defence for negative liberty and pluralism. This thesis is to defend the holistic approach against the piecemeal approach, but its interpretation will differ from the two representative readings, offered by Claude J.
    [Show full text]
  • Allan Gotthelf's Teleology, First Principles, And
    Reason Papers Vol. 35, no. 1 Review Essays Review Essay: Allan Gotthelf’s Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Biology and James G. Lennox and Robert Bolton’s (ed.) Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle Owen Goldin Marquette University Although readers of Reason Papers are no doubt familiar with Allan Gotthelf’s extensive efforts aimed at a more widespread appreciation of Ayn Rand’s philosophical thought, he is best known among historians of philosophy and science for his contributions to the understanding of Aristotle’s biological works, which have shed much light on Aristotle’s scientific methodology, epistemology, and metaphysics. Two new books allow us to take account of Gotthelf’s contributions to Aristotelian studies. The first is a collection of Gotthelf’s most important papers on Aristotle.1 Although the papers were written independently, there is little superfluous repetition, and taken together they constitute a comprehensive and coherent account of Aristotle’s biology and its philosophical significance. The second, which has its origin in a 2004 conference in Gotthelf’s honor, is a collection of papers on Aristotle, most of which focus on themes that Gotthelf himself has discussed.2 Some of the papers further his thought, taking it in new directions; others depart from Gotthelf in philosophically interesting ways. Gotthelf believes that one of his most important contributions to Aristotelian studies lies in his account of teleology in the biological writings. For this he gives credit to Rand (p. viii) (who personally led Gotthelf to the study of Aristotle), for she had argued that scientific explanation must identify potentials inherent in natures.
    [Show full text]
  • Catalogue of Titles of Works Attributed to Aristotle
    Catalogue of Titles of works attributed by Aristotle 1 To enhance readability of the translations and usability of the catalogues, I have inserted the following bold headings into the lists. These have no authority in any manuscript, but are based on a theory about the composition of the lists described in chapter 3. The text and numbering follows that of O. Gigon, Librorum deperditorum fragmenta. PART ONE: Titles in Diogenes Laertius (D) I. Universal works (ta kathalou) A. The treatises (ta syntagmatika) 1. The dialogues or exoterica (ta dialogika ex terika) 2. The works in propria persona or lectures (ta autopros pa akroamatika) a. Instrumental works (ta organika) b. Practical works (ta praktika) c. Productive Works (ta poi tika) d. Theoretical works (ta the r tika) . Natural philosophy (ta physiologia) . Mathematics (ta math matika) B. Notebooks (ta hypomn matika) II. Intermediate works (ta metaxu) III. Particular works (ta merika) PART TWO: Titles in the Vita Hesychii (H) This list is organized in the same way as D, with two exceptions. First, IA2c “productive works” has dropped out. Second, there is an appendix, organized as follows: IV. Appendix A. Intermediate or Particular works B. Treatises C. Notebooks D. Falsely ascribed works PART THREE: Titles in Ptolemy al-Garib (A) This list is organized in the same way as D, except it contains none of the Intermediate or Particular works. It was written in Arabic, and later translated into Latin, and then reconstructed into Greek, which I here translate. PART FOUR: Titles in the order of Bekker (B) The modern edition contains works only in IA2 (“the works in propria persona”), and replaces the theoretical works before the practical and productive, as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Eidos Fecha De Recepción: Diciembre 1 De 2010 ISSN 1692-8857 Fecha De Aceptación: Enero 21 De 2011 Issne 2011-7477
    eidos Fecha de recepción: diciembre 1 de 2010 ISSN 1692-8857 Fecha de aceptación: enero 21 de 2011 ISSNe 2011-7477 PRAGMATISM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY AND RESEARCH SHANE J. RALSTON Penn State University, Department of Philosophy [email protected]. RESUMEN Este artículo examina la literatura reciente sobre la intersección entre pragmatismo filosófico y relaciones internacionales (RI), incluyendo la teoría y la metodología de investigación de las RI. Se sostiene que uno de los obstáculos que motivan las teorías y metodologías pragmatistas de las RI es la dificultad de definir el pragmatismo, en particular si existe la necesidad de una definición más genérica de pragmatismo, o una más específica que se vincule con las metas de teó ricos e investigadores de las rela cio nes internacionales. Aunque el prag matismo filosófico no se ajusta fá cilmente a ninguno de los marcos teóricos tradicionales en RI, aquí esbozo una teoría pragmatista de las RI que se inspira en los tra- bajos de John Dewey y Richard Rorty. Sobre la metodología de las RI, señalo de qué manera la combina ción del pragmatismo filosófico y los métodos de investigación en RI se han beneficiado enormemente de las contribuciones de algunos prag matistas líderes de las RI y que hay signos de esperanza en que dicha relación puede enriquecerse pos teriormente. PALAB R AS CLAVE Pragmatismo, relaciones internacionales, investigación, teoría, práctica, John Dewey, Richard Rorty. ABSTRACT The goal of this paper is exami ne the recent literature on the intersec- tion between philosophical pragmatism and International Relations (IR), including IR theory and IR re search methodology.
    [Show full text]
  • Posterior Analytics
    POSTERIOR ANALYTICS The Posterior Analytics contains Aristotle!> epistemology and philosophy of science. His approach is broadly speaking foundational. Some of what we know can be justified by being shown to follow logically from other things that we know, but some of what we know does not need to be justified in this way. Such items of foundational knowledge are the first principles of the various sciences. In the excerpts below, Aristotle sets out the axiomatic structure of a science and presents his theory of explanation. The final chapter provides a tantalizing but obscure presentation of his ideas on the acquisition of first principles. BOOK I 1 71a All teaching and all intellectual learning result from previous cognition. This is clear if we examine all the cases; for this is how the mathematical 5 sciences and all crafts arise. This is also true of both deductive and induc­ tive arguments, since they both succeed in teaching because they rely on previous cognition: deductive arguments begin with premisses we are as­ sumed to understand, and inductive arguments prove the universal by relying on the fact that the particular is already clear. Rhetorical arguments 10 also persuade in the same way, since they rely either on examples (and hence on induction) or on argumentations (and hence on deduction). Previous cognition is needed in two ways. In some cases we must presup­ pose that something is! (for example, that it is true that everything is either asserted or denied truly <of a given subject». In other cases we must 15 comprehend what the thing spoken of is (for example, that a triangle signifies this); and in other cases we must do both (for example, we must both comprehend what a unit signifies and presuppose that there is such a thing).
    [Show full text]
  • The Beginnings of Formal Logic: Deduction in Aristotle's Topics Vs
    Phronesis 60 (�0�5) �67-309 brill.com/phro The Beginnings of Formal Logic: Deduction in Aristotle’s Topics vs. Prior Analytics Marko Malink Department of Philosophy, New York University, 5 Washington Place, New York, NY 10003. USA [email protected] Abstract It is widely agreed that Aristotle’s Prior Analytics, but not the Topics, marks the begin- ning of formal logic. There is less agreement as to why this is so. What are the distinctive features in virtue of which Aristotle’s discussion of deductions (syllogismoi) qualifies as formal logic in the one treatise but not in the other? To answer this question, I argue that in the Prior Analytics—unlike in the Topics—Aristotle is concerned to make fully explicit all the premisses that are necessary to derive the conclusion in a given deduction. Keywords formal logic – deduction – syllogismos – premiss – Prior Analytics – Topics 1 Introduction It is widely agreed that Aristotle’s Prior Analytics marks the beginning of formal logic.1 Aristotle’s main concern in this treatise is with deductions (syllogismoi). Deductions also play an important role in the Topics, which was written before the Prior Analytics.2 The two treatises start from the same definition of what 1 See e.g. Cornford 1935, 264; Russell 1946, 219; Ross 1949, 29; Bocheński 1956, 74; Allen 2001, 13; Ebert and Nortmann 2007, 106-7; Striker 2009, p. xi. 2 While the chronological order of Aristotle’s works cannot be determined with any certainty, scholars agree that the Topics was written before the Prior Analytics; see Brandis 1835, 252-9; Ross 1939, 251-2; Bocheński 1956, 49-51; Kneale and Kneale 1962, 23-4; Brunschwig 1967, © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���5 | doi �0.��63/�5685�84-��34��86 268 Malink a deduction is (stated in the first chapter of each).
    [Show full text]
  • A Note on the Simile of the Rout in the Posterior Analytics Ii 19
    Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) ©Mathesis Publications 1 A Note on the Simile of the Rout in the Posterior Analytics ii 19 James Lesher In the Posterior Analytics (APo ) ii 19, Aristotle compares the way in which sense perception ( αἴσθησις ) gives rise to knowledge of the universal ( τὸ καθόλου ) with the way in which one soldier’s ceasing his flight from the enemy leads other soldiers to do the same (100a12-13). 1 While the philosophical lesson appears to be that the human soul has the capacity to retain and organize multiple sense impressions (just as soldiers have the capacity to stop and form themselves into an effective fighting unit), the simile’s concluding phrase, ἕως ἐπὶ ἀρχὴν ἦλθεν , has no clear meaning. In Lesher 2010a I argued that the phrase should not be taken to mean ‘until the soldiers return to the original location or arrange - ment’ since that would suggest that in grasping the universal the mind returns to a prior state or condition (a view proposed by Plato but rejected by Aristotle at APo 99b25-7). I also noted that no surviving ancient account of a battle makes any mention of soldiers who cease their flight from the enemy and ‘come or go to an ἀρχή . Accordingly, I proposed that we take the subject of the verb ἦλθε to be the stabilizing of the sensible image in the soul and the ἀρχή toward which this process advances to be ‘the ἀρχή of art and scientific knowledge’ mentioned in the previous sentence. It seems clear that the process Aristotle was seeking to explain consists (ini - tially) in the stabilizing of the sensible image (99b36-110a2) and (subsequently) in the situating of the universal within a network of broader universals (100a15- b3).
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Events
    Journal of Artificial Intelligence Research 30 (2007) 361-412 Submitted 07/07; published 11/07 Natural Events John Bell [email protected] Department of Computer Science, Queen Mary, University of London, London E1 4NS, UK Abstract This paper develops an inductive theory of predictive common sense reasoning. The theory provides the basis for an integrated solution to the three traditional problems of reasoning about change; the frame, qualification, and ramification problems. The theory is also capable of representing non-deterministic events, and it provides a means for stating defeasible preferences over the outcomes of conflicting simultaneous events. 1. Introduction A great deal has been written on the logical representation of common sense reasoning about change since the publication of McCarthy and Hayes’s (1969) seminal paper, and many theories have been proposed; see, for example, the monographs by Sandewall (1994), Shanahan (1997), and Reiter (2001). Most theories treat events1 deductively, along the lines of the representation of actions used in the planner strips (Fikes & Nilsson, 1971). Each event type is defined by its preconditions and effects. For example, in the blocks world, the preconditions for unstacking block x from block y are that x is on y, x is clear (no block is on top of it), and the robot hand is empty. The effects are that the hand is holding x, y is clear, and each of the preconditions is false. Change is then a matter of deduction. If a particular event (a token of an event type) occurs and its particular preconditions hold, then its particular effects are deduced, and so necessarily follow, from it.
    [Show full text]
  • The University of Chicago Aristotle on the Necessity
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO ARISTOTLE ON THE NECESSITY OF WHAT WE KNOW A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DIVISION OF THE HUMANITIES IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY BY JOSHUA MENDELSOHN CHICAGO, ILLINOIS JUNE 2019 TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS . iv ABSTRACT . v 1 INTRODUCTION . 1 1.1 Aristotle on what we know ........................... 1 1.2 Previous approaches ............................... 7 1.3 Some first steps toward an answer ....................... 25 1.4 Chapter breakdown ................................ 34 2 ARISTOTLE’S DURABILITY ARGUMENTS . 36 2.1 Knowledge in the Categories ........................... 36 2.1.1 Knowledge as a relative: Categories 7 . 36 2.1.2 Knowledge as a state: Categories 8 ................... 51 2.1.3 The tension between the two principles . 59 2.2 When what is changeable goes out of view: Nicomachean Ethics VI.3 . 66 2.2.1 The sense of “necessity” ......................... 74 2.2.2 A Platonic precursor: Theaetetus 163c–164b . 75 2.3 Durability and demonstration: Posterior Analytics I.6 . 79 2.4 Knowledge of sensible particulars: Metaphysics Ζ.15 . 86 2.5 Taking stock ................................... 88 3 THE OBJECT OF KNOWLEDGE . 90 3.1 The introduction of the Forms ......................... 93 3.2 The irrelevance of the Forms .......................... 96 3.3 Essentiality and necessity: Posterior Analytics I.4 . 102 3.3.1 “Of all” and “per se” . 103 3.3.2 Per se predications and necessity . 108 3.3.3 “Universal” ................................112 3.3.4 Demonstrative necessities concerning individuals . 115 3.4 Per se necessity in natural science . 120 3.4.1 Per se necessity in biology: Parts of Animals II.3 .
    [Show full text]