Voluntaryism: the Political Thought of Auberon Herbert

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Voluntaryism: the Political Thought of Auberon Herbert VOLUNTARYISM: THE POLITICAL THOUGHT OF AUBERON HERBERT ERIC MACK Deportment o/Philosophy, Tulane Universily Auberon Herbert (1838- 1906) was one of the in history and jurisprudence. In 1865, as a Con- distinctive figures in the profound and wide servative, he unsuccessfully sought a seat in the ranging intellectual debate which took place House of Commons. By 1868, however, he was during the late Victorian age. It was during this seeking a Parliamentary seat, again unsuc- period, in the intellectual and social ferment of cessfully, as a Liberal. Finally, in 1870, Herbert the 1880s and 1890s, that Herbert formulated successfully contested a by-election and entered and expounded voluntaryism, his system of the Commons as a Liberal representing Not- "thorough" individualism. Carrying natural tingham. Throughout this period one of rights theory to its logical limits, Herbert Herbert's major occupations seems to have demanded complete social and economic been observing wars. He spent much time near freedom for all non-coercive individuals and the front during the Prusso-Danish, Franco- the radical restriction of the use of force to the Prussian, and American Civil wars. He only role of protecting those freedoms - including missed viewing the Austro-Prussian war of the freedom of peaceful persons to withhold 1866 "owing to its short duration".''' In the support from any or all state activities. All course of the Prusso-Danish war his cooperative activity must be founded upon the courageous aid to wounded Danish troops led free agreement of all those parties whose to his decoration by the Danish government. rightful possessions are involved. Like many With.respect to the Civil War, he wrote, "I am other Victorian figures, Herbert had wide- very glad that slavery is done away with, but I ranging interests. He wrote poetry and accounts think the manner is very bad and wrong". of his travels. And the subjects of his non- Whether he meant by this to emphasize the political essays included religion, clean air and hypocrisy of the North, which had always forest conservation. But Herbert's major ef- preached "the sacredness of revolution", or forts were devoted to his writings in political meant that even slavery should not be forcibly theory. This has been long neglected and it is trampled out is unclear."' For, as we shall see, the purpose of this essay to begin to redress that there is in Herbert a pacifist tendency toward wrong.''' denouncing the use of all force - even force Auberon Herbert was by birth and marriage directed against force. Herbert's accounts of a well-placed member of the British aristocracy. these excursions illustrate how safe war was in He was educated at Eton and at St. John's Col- the nineteenth century for non-combatants - lege, Oxford. As a young man be held commis- at least for aristocratic English non- sions in the army for several years and served combatants. briefly with the 7th Hussars in India (1860). In During his time in the House of Commons, a letter from India he expresses his opposition Herbert's most noteworthy political acts were to the caste system while maintaining that the to join Sir Charles Dilke in his declaration of British attempt to eliminate the system forcibly republicanism and to support Joseph Arch's at- was likely to "trample the evil in, not out".['l tempts to form an agricultural laborer's union. On his return to Oxford he formed several Con- Although, in hindsight, many of Herbert's ac- servative debating societies, was elected a tions and words during the sixties and early Fellow of St. John's, and lectured occasionally seventies can be read as harbingers of his later, 300 ERIC MACK consistent, libertarianism, he was in reality writings of his mentor, Herbert Spencer, and throughout this period lacking in any consistent had resolved to do full justice to "the moral set of political principles. During this period, side" of the case for a society of fully free and for .instance, he supported compulsory State voluntarily cooperative individuals.['' And education - albeit with strong insistence on its while Spencer grew more and more crusty, con- being religiously neutral. servative and pessimistic during the last decades In late 1873, Herbert met and was much im- of the nineteenth century, Herbert, who con- pressed by Herbert Spencer. As he recounts in tinued to think of himself as Spencer's disciple, "Mr. Spencer and the Great Machine", a study remained idealistic, radical and hopeful. And of Spencer led to the insight that, while he willingly addressed, he refused to join, such organizations as the Liberty and Property . thinking and acting for others had always hindered, not helped, the real progress; that all Defense League which he felt to be "a little forms of compulsion deadened the living forces in a more warmly attached to the fair sister Proper- nation; that every evil violently stamped out still per- ty than . to the fair sister Liberty".ts1 sisted, almost always in a worse form, when driven out of sight, and festered under the surface. Similarly, Herbert held himself separate from I no longer believed that the handful of us - the Personal Rights Association whose chief however well-intentioned we might be - spending mover, J. H. Levy, favored compulsory taxa- our nights in the House, could manufacture the life of a nation, could endow it out of hand with hap- tion for the funding of State protective ac- piness, wisdom, and prosperity, and clothe it in all tivities. With the exception of the in- the virtues."' dividualistic "reasonable anarchists", Herbert However, it was even before this intellectual :hought of himself as occupying the extreme transformation that Herbert had decided, left wing of the individualist camp, i.e. the wing perhaps out of disgust with party politics or that was most willing to carry liberty uncertainty about his own convictions, not to furthe~t."~' stand for re-election in 1874. Later, in 1879, he In 1885 Herbert sought to establish a Party again sought Liberal support to regain a seat of Individual Liberty and under this rubric he from Nottingham. But at that point his uncom- gave addresses across England. His central promising individualist radicalism was not ac- theoretical essay, The Right and Wrong of ceptable to the majority of the Central Council Compulsion by the State, was written as a state- of the Liberal Union of Nottingham. In the in- ment of the bases for, the character of, and the terim, he had organized, in 1877, "The Per- implications of, the principles of this Party. sonal Rights and Self-Help Association". And, Again with the aim of advancing libertarian in 1878, he had been one of the chief organizers opinion, Herbert published the weekly (later along with William Morris[a' of the anti- changed to monthly) paper, Free Life, "The Jingoism rallies in Hyde Park against war with Organ of Voluntary Taxation and the Volun- Russia. Along with other consistent classical tary State", from 1890 to 1901. Free Life was liberals, Herbert repeatedly took anti- devoted to "One Fight More - The Best and imperialist stands. He consistently called for the Last" -the fight against the aggressive use Irish self-determination. In the early 1880s, he of force which is "a mere survival of bar- opposed British intervention in Egypt as a use barism, a mere perpetuation of slavery under of the power of the nation to guarantee the new names, against which the reason and moral results of particular speculations. And, later, he sense of the civilized world have to be called in- opposed the Boer War."' to rebellion".'"' Also during the 1890s. In 1880, following his rejection by the Herbert engaged in lengthy published ex- Liberals of Nottingham, Herbert turned to the changes with three prominent socialists of his publication of addresses, essays, and books in day, E. Belfort Bax, Grant Allen and J. A. defense of consistent individualism and against Hobson.1"' Herbert continued to write and all forms of political regimentation. Even in speak into this century and two of his best 1877, Auberon Herbert had been disturbed by essays, "Mr. Spencer and the Great Machine" "a constant undertone of cynicism" in the and "A Plea for Voluntaryism", were written VOLUNTARYISM: THE POLITICAL THOUGHT OF AUBERON HERBERT 301 in 1906 - the last year of his life. claim that each individual has a right to judge In all his mature writings Auberon Herbert of his own happiness with the conclusion that defended a Lockean -Spencerian conception each individual has a special claim over the use of natural rights according to which each per- of his own faculties in the implementation of son has a right to his own person, his mind and those judgments. body, and hence to his own labor. Further- In his most systematic work, The Right and more, each person has a right to the products of Wrong of Compulsion by the State, Herbert the productive employment of his labor and adds several further arguments for rights. He faculties. Since each person has these rights, again ties the individual's claim to freedom to each is under a moral obligation to respect these the conditions necessary for the individual's rights in all others. In virtue of each person's well-being. But here the emphasis is on moral sovereignty over himself, each individual must well-being. Freedom is presented as both a consent to any activity which directly affects his causal and a logical precondition of a man's ac- person or property before any such activity can tions being truly self-beneficial - be morally legitimate. Specifically, each must '4.
Recommended publications
  • Ryley, Peter. "The English Individualists." Making Another World Possible: Anarchism, Anti- Capitalism and Ecology in Late 19Th and Early 20Th Century Britain
    Ryley, Peter. "The English individualists." Making Another World Possible: Anarchism, Anti- Capitalism and Ecology in Late 19th and Early 20th Century Britain. New York: Bloomsbury Academic, 2013. 51–86. Contemporary Anarchist Studies. Bloomsbury Collections. Web. 24 Sep. 2021. <http://dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781501306754.ch-003>. Downloaded from Bloomsbury Collections, www.bloomsburycollections.com, 24 September 2021, 12:22 UTC. Copyright © Peter Ryley 2013. You may share this work for non-commercial purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher, and provide a link to the Creative Commons licence. 3 The English individualists There is a conventional historical narrative that portrays the incremental growth of collectivist political economy as something promoted and fought for by popular movements, an almost inevitable part of the process of industrial modernization. Whether described in class terms as the ‘forward march of labour’ or ideologically as the rise of socialism, the narrative is broadly the same. The old certainties had to give way in the face of modern mass societies. This poses no problem for anarcho-communism. It can be accommodated comfortably on the libertarian wing of collectivism. But what of individualism? It seems out of place, a curiosity; the last gasp of a liberal England that was about to die. Perhaps that explains its comparative neglect. Yet seen as part of the radical milieu of the time, it seems neither anomalous nor a fringe movement. It stood firmly in the tradition of a left libertarian radicalism that was a serious competitor of the collectivist left. There were two main groupings of individualists in late Victorian Britain.
    [Show full text]
  • Ideological Contributions of Celtic Freedom and Individualism to Human Rights
    chapter 4 Ideological Contributions of Celtic Freedom and Individualism to Human Rights This chapter emphasizes the importance of the often-overlooked contribu- tions of indigenous European cultures to the development of human rights. Attention is given to the ancient Celtic culture, the ideas of Celtic freedom and individualism, the distinctive role of the Scottish theologian, John Dunn Scotus and the Scottish Arbroath Declaration of Freedom (1320).1 It is from the Scottish Enlightenment and its subsequent influence on the late 18th century revolutions that we see an affirmative declaration of the Rights of Man, which is a precursor to the development of modern human rights. The importance of the Celtic-Irish-Scottish contribution to human rights is that it was the foun- dation for individual liberty and dignity in Western civilization. Indigenous Celtic culture staked an original and critical claim to the ideal of universal hu- man dignity. This is an important insight because it broadens the ideals that promote human rights, including within them those ideals of the indigenous cultures of the world, whose voices are oftentimes forgotten. It strengthens the universality of human rights. i The Intellectual and Philosophical Origins of International Law and Human Rights The intellectual and philosophical origins of human rights rhetoric and law, democracy, freedom and ideas supporting “consent of the governed” are in- tertwined in this composite explanation that attempts to explain all of these themes with the historical themes of Roman natural law, Athenian democracy and later the modern political philosophy of John Locke and his followers. The absence of a medieval connection between the alleged ancient Roman and Greek sources and the modern developments of human rights indicates that this perspective is faulty.
    [Show full text]
  • Editorial ...Tibor R. Machan
    Editor Tibor R. Machan/Phi/osophy Managing Editor Marty Zupan Editorial Assistant Lynn Scarlett Associate Editors Walter Block/Economics John Cody/Classics Douglas J . Den Uyl/Philosophy Davis Keeler/La w J. Roger Lee/Philosophy Leonard Liggio/History Eric Mack/Phi/osophy H . Joachim Maitre/Znternational Relations John 0. Nelson/Philosophy Ralph Raico/History Marry Sirridge/Philosophy Advisory Board D. T. Armentano/ University of Hartford Richard Bilas/California State College, Bakersfield Yale Brazen/ University of Chicago Nicholas Capaldi/Queens College R. L. Cunningham/ University of San Francisco John Hos per$/ University of Southern Californirs Israel M . Kirzner/New York University Kenneth G. Lucey/State University of New York College, Fredonia Fred D. Miller, Jr ./Bo wling Green State University Herbert Morris/ University of California, Los Angeles Paul Craig Roberts/Georgetown University Morton L. Schagrin/State University of New York College, Fredonia Thomas S. Szasz/State University of New York Medical Center, Syracuse E. G. West/Carleton University, Ottawa A Journal of Interdisciplinary Normative Studies Articles Is Economics Independent of Ethics? .............. .Jack High 3 How the Jacksonians Favored Industrialization ............... .Paul McGouldrick 17 Economic Warfare in Defense of Liberty. .................Juliana Geran Pilon 33 Choice and Rationality ........................ Antony Flew 49 On Improving Mankind by Political Means ....................... .Lester H. Hunt 61 Constraining the Choice Set: Lessons from the Software Revolution. ................ .David Levy 77 Discussion Notes The Randian Argument Reconsidered: A Reply to Charles King ................. .Paul St. F. Blair 91 Is "Flourishing" a True Alternative Ethics? ............... .David L. Norton 101 Review Essays & Reviews John Gray's Mill on Liberty: A Defence and Hayek on Liberty ...................Nicholas Capaldi 109 Tom Regan's The Case for Animal Rights.
    [Show full text]
  • Republicanism in Nineteenth Century England
    NORBERT J. GOSSMAN REPUBLICANISM IN NINETEENTH CENTURY ENGLAND To one familiar with the attitude of "near devotion" accorded the monarchy by the majority of Englishmen today, it may come as a shock to discover a lack of this devotion in mid-Victorian England. A sampling of comments from the radical press is a striking example. Trie-regular arrival of Victoria's progeny evoked this impious sug­ gestion in the Northern Star: That, rather than reciting national prayers of thanksgiving, congregations should sing "hymns of despair for their misfortune in being saddled with another addition to the brood of royal Cormorants." 1 The National Reformer referred to "our good kind, and dear Queen, who... could easily dispense with the allowance which her loyal subjects make her... unless she desires to be the last of England's monarchs..." 2 Yet criticism of Victoria was mild in comparison with the criticism directed toward her immediate predecessors. Upon the death of George IV in June 1830, the Times had the following comment: "The truth is... that there never was an individual less regretted by his fellow- creatures than this deceased King... If George IV ever had a friend, a devoted friend - in any rank of life - we protest that the name of him or her has not yet reached us." 3 This attitude toward the monarchy can be explained partly by the personalities of some of the Hanoverians - George IV, for example, 4 partly by objections to the growing expense of monarchy, but it might also be explained by the feeling in some radical circles that the institution of monarchy was incompatible with the growth of demo­ cracy.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Worries About the Coherence of Left-Libertarianism Mathias Risse
    John F. Kennedy School of Government Harvard University Faculty Research Working Papers Series Can There be “Libertarianism without Inequality”? Some Worries About the Coherence of Left-Libertarianism Mathias Risse Nov 2003 RWP03-044 The views expressed in the KSG Faculty Research Working Paper Series are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect those of the John F. Kennedy School of Government or Harvard University. All works posted here are owned and copyrighted by the author(s). Papers may be downloaded for personal use only. Can There be “Libertarianism without Inequality”? Some Worries About the Coherence of Left-Libertarianism1 Mathias Risse John F. Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University October 25, 2003 1. Left-libertarianism is not a new star on the sky of political philosophy, but it was through the recent publication of Peter Vallentyne and Hillel Steiner’s anthologies that it became clearly visible as a contemporary movement with distinct historical roots. “Left- libertarian theories of justice,” says Vallentyne, “hold that agents are full self-owners and that natural resources are owned in some egalitarian manner. Unlike most versions of egalitarianism, left-libertarianism endorses full self-ownership, and thus places specific limits on what others may do to one’s person without one’s permission. Unlike right- libertarianism, it holds that natural resources may be privately appropriated only with the permission of, or with a significant payment to, the members of society. Like right- libertarianism, left-libertarianism holds that the basic rights of individuals are ownership rights. Left-libertarianism is promising because it coherently underwrites both some demands of material equality and some limits on the permissible means of promoting this equality” (Vallentyne and Steiner (2000a), p 1; emphasis added).
    [Show full text]
  • Mundella Papers Scope
    University of Sheffield Library. Special Collections and Archives Ref: MS 6 - 9, MS 22 Title: Mundella Papers Scope: The correspondence and other papers of Anthony John Mundella, Liberal M.P. for Sheffield, including other related correspondence, 1861 to 1932. Dates: 1861-1932 (also Leader Family correspondence 1848-1890) Level: Fonds Extent: 23 boxes Name of creator: Anthony John Mundella Administrative / biographical history: The content of the papers is mainly political, and consists largely of the correspondence of Mundella, a prominent Liberal M.P. of the later 19th century who attained Cabinet rank. Also included in the collection are letters, not involving Mundella, of the family of Robert Leader, acquired by Mundella’s daughter Maria Theresa who intended to write a biography of her father, and transcriptions by Maria Theresa of correspondence between Mundella and Robert Leader, John Daniel Leader and another Sheffield Liberal M.P., Henry Joseph Wilson. The collection does not include any of the business archives of Hine and Mundella. Anthony John Mundella (1825-1897) was born in Leicester of an Italian father and an English mother. After education at a National School he entered the hosiery trade, ultimately becoming a partner in the firm of Hine and Mundella of Nottingham. He became active in the political life of Nottingham, and after giving a series of public lectures in Sheffield was invited to contest the seat in the General Election of 1868. Mundella was Liberal M.P. for Sheffield from 1868 to 1885, and for the Brightside division of the Borough from November 1885 to his death in 1897.
    [Show full text]
  • Paolo Silvestri Anthropology of Freedom and Tax Justice: Between Exchange and Gift
    Paolo Silvestri Anthropology of Freedom and Tax Justice: between Exchange and Gift. Thoughts for an interdisciplinary research agenda1 1. Introduction The way in which fiscal institutions and fiscal policies are conceived and imple- mented raises problems at the intersection of so many ethical, institutional, legal, political and philosophical issues, both practical and theoretical, that a unified framework of all these rather fragmented issues seems to be quite impossible. Let us consider just a few of these issues. The performance of fiscal institutions is crucial for its effects on equality, inclusiveness and social mobility. Tax issues, or, rather, tax injustices are at the core, if not the origin of modern democratic and legal-political (and not only economic) institutions. The arrangement of fiscal institutions touches salient political-social issues, many of them at the heart of a sound and democratic good governance both at local and global level: transparency, accountability, efficacy, legitimacy, and trust. Last but not least, taxation is ambivalently connected to citi- zens’ trust/distrust relationships: among themselves as well as toward political, legal, and administrative institutions, since taxation is often perceived as the most immedi- ate presence (for better or for worse) of such institutions in their lives. 1 This little essay is dedicated to a great man, a man who one day gave me a great gift, rekindling my hopes for the future. At the time when I received that gift, I immediately felt an immense sense of gratitude, and an immediate boost to find ways to be able to pay my debts and honour, at my very best, the credit and trust I was given.
    [Show full text]
  • Universal Declaration of Human Rights
    Universal Declaration of Human Rights Preamble Whereas recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of freedom, justice and peace in the world, Whereas disregard and contempt for human rights have resulted in barbarous acts which have outraged the conscience of mankind, and the advent of a world in which human beings shall enjoy freedom of speech and belief and freedom from fear and want has been proclaimed as the highest aspiration of the common people, Whereas it is essential, if man is not to be compelled to have recourse, as a last resort, to rebellion against tyranny and oppression, that human rights should be protected by the rule of law, Whereas it is essential to promote the development of friendly relations between nations, Whereas the peoples of the United Nations have in the Charter reaffirmed their faith in fundamental human rights, in the dignity and worth of the human person and in the equal rights of men and women and have determined to promote social progress and better standards of life in larger freedom, Whereas Member States have pledged themselves to achieve, in cooperation with the United Nations, the promotion of universal respect for and observance of human rights and fundamental freedoms, Whereas a common understanding of these rights and freedoms is of the greatest importance for the full realization of this pledge, Now, therefore, The General Assembly, Proclaims this Universal Declaration of Human Rights as a common standard of achievement for all peoples and all nations, to the end that every individual and every organ of society, keeping this Declaration constantly in mind, shall strive by teaching and education to promote respect for these rights and freedoms and by progressive measures, national and international, to secure their universal and effective recognition and observance, both among the peoples of Member States themselves and among the peoples of territories under their jurisdiction.
    [Show full text]
  • Quong-Left-Libertarianism.Pdf
    The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 19, Number 1, 2011, pp. 64–89 Symposium: Ownership and Self-ownership Left-Libertarianism: Rawlsian Not Luck Egalitarian Jonathan Quong Politics, University of Manchester HAT should a theory of justice look like? Any successful answer to this Wquestion must find a way of incorporating and reconciling two moral ideas. The first is a particular conception of individual freedom: because we are agents with plans and projects, we should be accorded a sphere of liberty to protect us from being used as mere means for others’ ends. The second moral idea is that of equality: we are moral equals and as such justice requires either that we receive equal shares of something—of whatever it is that should be used as the metric of distributive justice—or else requires that unequal distributions can be justified in a manner that is consistent with the moral equality of persons. These twin ideas—liberty and equality—are things which no sound conception of justice can properly ignore. Thus, like most political philosophers, I take it as given that the correct conception of justice will be some form of liberal egalitarianism. A deep and difficult challenge for all liberal egalitarians is to determine how the twin values of freedom and equality can be reconciled within a single theory of distributive justice. Of the many attempts to achieve this reconciliation, left-libertarianism is one of the most attractive and compelling. By combining the libertarian commitment to full (or nearly full) self-ownership with an egalitarian principle for the ownership of natural resources, left- libertarians offer an account of justice that appears firmly committed both to individual liberty, and to an egalitarian view of how opportunities or advantages must be distributed.
    [Show full text]
  • University of Southampton Research Repository
    University of Southampton Research Repository Copyright © and Moral Rights for this thesis and, where applicable, any accompanying data are retained by the author and/or other copyright owners. A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. This thesis and the accompanying data cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the copyright holder/s. The content of the thesis and accompanying research data (where applicable) must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holder/s. When referring to this thesis and any accompanying data, full bibliographic details must be given, e.g. Alastair Paynter (2018) “The emergence of libertarian conservatism in Britain, 1867-1914”, University of Southampton, Department of History, PhD Thesis, pp. 1-187. UNIVERSITY OF SOUTHAMPTON FACULTY OF HUMANITIES History The emergence of libertarian conservatism in Britain, 1867-1914 by Alastair Matthew Paynter Thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy March 2018 UNIVERSITY OF SOUTHAMPTON ABSTRACT FACULTY OF HUMANITIES History Doctor of Philosophy THE EMERGENCE OF LIBERTARIAN CONSERVATISM IN BRITAIN, 1867-1914 by Alastair Matthew Paynter This thesis considers conservatism’s response to Collectivism during a period of crucial political and social change in the United Kingdom and the Anglosphere. The familiar political equipoise was disturbed by the widening of the franchise and the emergence of radical new threats in the form of New Liberalism and Socialism. Some conservatives responded to these changes by emphasising the importance of individual liberty and the preservation of the existing social structure and institutions.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Concepts of Liberty
    “No chains around my feet, but I’m not free.” – Bob Marley (Concrete Jungle) Two Concepts of Liberty 1. Positive vs Negative Liberty: Isaiah Berlin’s highly influential article brought to light the nature of the disagreement about political freedom. Largely until his time, the default assumption was that ‘liberty’ referred to what Berlin calls ‘negative liberty’. Negative Liberty: Roughly, freedom FROM. One is free in this sense to the extent that their actions are not hindered or prevented by outside interferers. Jefferson & Madison: This is, for instance, how the founding fathers understood liberty. Consider our constitutionally recognized rights of freedom of speech, freedom of religion (in James Madison’s Bill of Rights), and rights to life, liberty, and pursuit of happiness (in Thomas Jefferson’s Declaration of Independence). Example: Freedom of Speech: Having this right means that the government will not interfere with your speech (e.g., they will not pass laws forbidding you from saying whatever you want, and they will pass laws forbidding others from coercively preventing you from saying whatever you want, etc.). The same can be said for all of the others I listed. (For instance, as one more example, the government will allow you to pursue happiness, and they will not interfere with you or try to prevent you from doing so.) But, negative liberty of, say freedom of speech, doesn’t do me any good if I lack the ability to speak. For instance, imagine that I was raised by wolves and I don’t know how to speak any human languages, or read, or write, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Nozick's Libertarian Critique of Regan
    68 BETWEEN THE SPECIES Nozick’s Libertarian Critique of Regan ABSTRACT Robert Nozick’s oft-quoted review of Tom Regan’s The Case for Animal Rights levels a range of challenges to Regan’s philosophy. Many commentators have focused on Nozick’s putative defense of speciesism, but this has led to them overlooking other aspects of the critique. In this paper, I draw attention to two. First is Nozick’s criti- cism of Regan’s political theory, which is best understood relative to Nozick’s libertarianism. Nozick’s challenge invites the possibility of a libertarian account of animal rights – which is not as oxymo- ronic as it may first sound. Second is Nozick’s criticism of Regan’s axiological theory, which is best understood relative to Nozick’s own axiological inegalitarianism. While Nozick’s axiology has distaste- ful consequences, it should not be dismissed out-of-hand. Nozick’s challenges to Regan – and Nozick’s wider animal ethics – are rich and original, warranting attention from contemporary theorists for reasons beyond mere historical interest. Josh Milburn University of York Volume 21, Issue 1 Spring 2018 http://digitalcommons.calpoly.edu/bts/ 69 Josh Milburn Tom Regan published The Case for Animal Rights (hereaf- ter, The Case) in 1983, spawning a literature of responses, cri- tiques, developments and applications. It continues to have con- siderable influence on philosophical literature in animal ethics to this day – as this special issue demonstrates. Regan belongs on a short list of the most influential and significant normative philosophers of the 21st century. Another philosopher who un- doubtedly belongs on this list is Robert Nozick, most famous as the author of the 1974 Anarchy, State, and Utopia (hereafter, ASU), in which he offers a right libertarian theory of justice.
    [Show full text]