The Background to Proclus and Damascius

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Background to Proclus and Damascius chapter 1 The Background to Proclus and Damascius The issues faced by Proclus and Damascius for the first principle go back to the very beginning of the Neoplatonic tradition with Plotinus and his for- mulation of the first principle as the One. For Plotinus and all subsequent Neoplatonists, the One transcends Being and all beings as their cause: it can- not be characterized by any attributes which pertain to Being, chief among which is plurality. Yet this gives rise to the basic tension faced by all Neo- platonists: while transcending its effects, the One as the first cause must pre- contain what it produces. Hence, it must pre- contain, in some sense, plurality and all the other attributes of Being as their cause, while not itself being a plurality or in any sense like Being and other beings. Balancing the One’s transcendence and causality becomes one of the central perennial is- sues faced for all Neoplatonists and philosophers influenced by this line of thought. As we will see after this chapter, this ultimately motivates Proclus’ and Damascius’ respective positions to maintain a hard distance between the first principle and Being: for Proclus this must be the One as unparticipated, and for Damascius this must be the Ineffable rather than the One. To understand what leads us to both figures’ refined positions, we should first see the com- mon foundation laid by Plotinus and his successors, especially Porphyry and Iamblichus, inasmuch as the latter become the intermediaries to which Pro- clus and Damascius directly respond. We will first start with Plotinus in Section 1.1 and see how he comes to assert the One as the first principle over Intellect, and how his description of the One as the ‘power of all things’ (δύναμις πάντων) leads to the possibility for postu- lating the One as paradigmatic of Intellect’s being. And in Sections 1.2–1.3 we will see how Porphyry and Iamblichus, as Plotinus’ successors, adapt his for- mulation of the One, as both ‘one’- only ad extra and characterized by plurality ad intra. As we will see, the reception of Plotinus’ framework in these latter figures becomes an important background for Proclus in establishing a new understanding of causality to support the One’s transcendence over— and causality of— all things. In turn, this also gives us the background to see how Damascius represents a return back to Plotinus (via Iamblichus), while also radically transforming Proclus’ framework. © Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2021 | DOI:10.1163/9789004439092_003 26 Chapter 1 1.1 Plotinus Among Plotinus’ many arguments for the One throughout the Enneads, one we find is his emphasis on the One’s independence in certain, specific re- spects: namely the One does not imply dependence on parts; lacks mixture with the effects after it; and thereby does not imply potentiality in any sense. The formulation is loosely similar to Aristotle’s argument for the unmoved mover as the first cause in Metaphysics Λ.6– 9, where Aristotle shows that the principle must always be in act (ἐνέργεια) and without matter and potentiality.1 For Aris- totle, these criteria imply that the principle is an intellect that thinks itself.2 In- asmuch as the principle must be simple, Plotinus certainly agrees with Aristotle, alongside various prior Middle Platonists, yet he departs from this view in two ways: first, by arguing that intellection inherently implies duality, and second, that any kind of intellect implies a principle that is not such. This final view comes about when Plotinus evaluates how unity is a pre- condition for all Forms and entities, and that it eventually leads to an entity that is simply pure unity. We see the start of this argument in Ennead v.4.1 with Plotinus’ definition of simplicity as the ground for all composed beings: For there must be something before all things— this being simple— and [it must be] something distinct from the things which come after it, ex- isting by itself, not mixed with the things which are from it, and again able to be present in a different way to the other things, being really one (ὄντως ἕν)— and not a different being and then one—according to which it is false even to say that it is ‘one’,3 and there is no account or knowledge of it. It is indeed also said to be beyond being (ἐπέκεινα οὐσίας): for if it will not to be simple, outside all coincidence and composition and really one, it could not be a principle. And it is the most self- sufficient (αὐταρ- κέστατόν), being simple and the first among all things: for that which is not the first is in need of that which is before it, and what is not simple is in need of the simple things in it (τῶν ἐν αὐτῷ ἁπλῶν), so that it can come into existence from them.4 Enn. v.4.1, 5– 15 1 Aristotle, Met. Λ.6, esp. 1071b12– 31. 2 Cf. Aristotle, Met. Λ.9, 1075a5– 10. 3 Cf. Plato, Parm. 141e7 ff. 4 Compare this passage with Plotinus, Enn. v.6.4, esp. 1– 11, where ‘one’ and ‘simple’ (ἁπλοῦς) are contrasted: Intellect is ‘one’ as is the Good/One, but only the One is ‘simple’. All subsequent citations of Enn. in this section are from Plotinus..
Recommended publications
  • The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism the Alexandrian
    This article was downloaded by: 10.3.98.104 On: 25 Sep 2021 Access details: subscription number Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: 5 Howick Place, London SW1P 1WG, UK The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism Pauliina Remes, Svetla Slaveva-Griffin The Alexandrian classrooms excavated and sixth-century philosophy teaching Publication details https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/doi/10.4324/9781315744186.ch3 Richard Sorabji Published online on: 30 Apr 2014 How to cite :- Richard Sorabji. 30 Apr 2014, The Alexandrian classrooms excavated and sixth-century philosophy teaching from: The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism Routledge Accessed on: 25 Sep 2021 https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/doi/10.4324/9781315744186.ch3 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR DOCUMENT Full terms and conditions of use: https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/legal-notices/terms This Document PDF may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproductions, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The publisher shall not be liable for an loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. 3 The Alexandrian classrooms excavated and sixth-century philosophy teaching Richard Sorabji It was announced in 2004 that the Polish archaeological team under Grzegorz Majcherek had identifi ed the surprisingly well-preserved lecture rooms of the sixth-century Alexandrian school.1 Th is was a major archaeological discovery.2 Although the fi rst few rooms had been excavated twenty-fi ve years earlier, identifi cation has only now become possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens
    Trinity University Digital Commons @ Trinity Philosophy Faculty Research Philosophy Department 2014 Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens Damian Caluori Trinity University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.trinity.edu/phil_faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Repository Citation Caluori, D. (2014). Rhetoric and Platonism in fifth-century Athens. In R. C. Fowler (Ed.), Plato in the third sophistic (pp. 57-72). De Gruyter. This Contribution to Book is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at Digital Commons @ Trinity. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Research by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Trinity. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Damian Caluori (Trinity University) Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens There are reasons to believe that relations between Platonism and rhetoric in Athens during the fifth century CE were rather close.Z Both were major pillars of pagan cul- ture, or paideia, and thus essential elements in the defense of paganism against in- creasingly powerful and repressive Christian opponents. It is easy to imagine that, under these circumstances, paganism was closing ranks and that philosophers and orators united in their efforts to save traditional ways and values. Although there is no doubt some truth to this view, a closer look reveals that the relations be- tween philosophy and rhetoric were rather more complicated. In what follows, I will discuss these relations with a view to the Platonist school of Athens. By “the Platon- ist school of Athens” I mean the Platonist school founded by Plutarch of Athens in the late fourth century CE, and reaching a famous end under the leadership of Dam- ascius in 529.X I will first survey the evidence for the attitudes towards rhetoric pre- vailing amongst the most important Athenian Platonists of the time.
    [Show full text]
  • Persecution and Response in Late Paganism The
    Persecution and Response in Late Paganism: The Evidence of Damascius Author(s): Polymnia Athanassiadi Source: The Journal of Hellenic Studies, Vol. 113 (1993), pp. 1-29 Published by: The Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/632395 . Accessed: 01/12/2013 12:02 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Hellenic Studies. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 198.105.44.150 on Sun, 1 Dec 2013 12:02:11 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Journal of Hellenic Studies cxiii (1993) pp 1-29 PERSECUTIONAND RESPONSE IN LATE PAGANISM: THE EVIDENCE OF DAMASCIUS* THE theme of this paper is intolerance: its manifestation in late antiquity towards the pagans of the Eastern Mediterranean,and the immediate reactions and long-term attitudes that it provoked in them. The reasons why, in spite of copious evidence, the persecution of the traditional cults and of their adepts in the Roman empire has never been viewed as such are obvious: on the one hand no pagan church emerged out of the turmoil to canonise its dead and expound a theology of martyrdom, and on the other, whatever their conscious religious beliefs, late antique scholars in their overwhelming majority were formed in societies whose ethical foundations and logic are irreversibly Christian.
    [Show full text]
  • Sylvain Delcomminette, Pieter D'hoine, Marc-Antoine Gavray (Eds
    Reviews 245 Sylvain Delcomminette, Pieter d’Hoine, Marc-Antoine Gavray (eds.), Ancient Readings of Plato’s Phaedo. Leiden-Boston: Brill, 2015, viii+364 p.; ISBN 978-90-0428217-9, € 126. Reviewed by Peter Lautner, Department of Philosophy, Pázmány Péter Catholic University, Piliscsaba-Budapest, H-2087 Piliscsaba, Egyetem utca 1, Hungary. Email: [email protected] https://doi.org/10.1515/rhiz-2018-0013 This volume grew out of a conference held in Brussels on the reception of the Phaedo in antiquity, concentrating on the period before Damascius and Olympi- odorus. Its subject-matter fits neatly with the recent trend of following the after- math of some of Plato’s dialogues in antiquity. Aristotle’s approach to the themes exposed in Plato’s dialogue focuses on not only the theory of the soul (in De anima and in the lost dialogue Eudemus), but also physics. Sylvain Delcomminette draws attention to the fact that Aristotle puts the emphasis elsewhere, on the account of the causes. He argues that Aris- totle had the Phaedo in mind when he discussed the material in Phys I, Met. A, and Gen. et Corr. The Aristotelian causal theory was developed with a view to Plato’s account. Furthermore, the description of the earlier philosophers’ views in Met. A much resembles Socrates’ account of the earlier views he encountered in his youth. The important difference is that Aristotle’s description is impersonal and fully anti-Platonic in claiming that “all men by nature desire to know”. Of course, he also rejects the causal efficiency of the Ideas. However, Aristotle seems to admit the principle of the “second sail”, which involves attaining knowledge through λόγοι.
    [Show full text]
  • The School of Ammonius, Son of Hermias, on Knowledge of the Divine
    ELIAS TEMPELIS THE SCHOOL OF AMMONIUS, SON OF HERMIAS, ON KNOWLEDGE OF THE DIVINE ΕΚΔΟΣΕΙΣ ΦΙΛΟΛΟΓΙΚΟΥ ΣΥΛΛΟΓΟΥ ΠΑΡΝΑΣΣΟΣ ΑΘΗΝΑΙ 1998 THE SCHOOL OF AMMONIUS, SON OF HERMIAS, ON KNOWLEDGE OF THE DIVINE ELIAS TEMPELIS THE SCHOOL OF AMMONIUS, SON OF HERMIAS, ON KNOWLEDGE OF THE DIVINE ΕΚΔΟΣΕΙΣ ΦΙΛΟΛΟΓΙΚΟΥ ΣΥΛΛΟΓΟΥ ΠΑΡΝΑΣΣΟΣ ΑΘΗΝΑΙ 1998 ISBN 960­85212­5­4 1998 © Ηλίας Τεμπέλης, 'Ογδόη οδός 3,152 36 Π. Πεντέλη ΕΚΔΟΣΕΙΣ ΦΙΛΟΛΟΓΙΚΟΥ ΣΥΛΛΟΓΟΥ ΠΑΡΝΑΣΣΟΣ Πλατεία Αγ. Γεωργίου Καρύτση 8,105 61 'Αθήναι Υπεύθυνος Τυπογραφείου: ΕΥΑΓΓ. ΜΠΟΥΛΟΥΚΟΣ Όδός Μίλωνος 26,117 45 Αθήναι Τηλ.: 93.45.204 - Fax: 93.17.188 To my wife Christina PREFACE This book is a slightly revised version of my Ph.D. thesis, on which I ' began work in 1990 and which I defended at the University of London in 1994. My study undertakes a reconstruction and critical assessment of the theory of the Neoplatonic school of Ammonius, son of Hermias, on the presuppositions of the acquisition of knowledge of the divine and also on the contents and the purpose of this knowledge. The metaphysical position of the human soul between the intelligible and the sensible worlds allows it to know the intelligible world and the divine, in particular, provided that the cognitive reason-principles in the human intellect are activated. The purpose of such knowledge is the as• similation to the divine and is achieved by means of a personal struggle with the help of theoretical and practical philosophy. The school of Am• monius compared its own philosophical attempt at knowledge of the di• vine to previous similar methods.
    [Show full text]
  • A Study in the Form and Meaning of the Pseudo-Dionysian Writings
    HIERARCHY AND THE DEFINITION OF ORDER IN THE LETTERS OF PSEUDO-DIONYSIUS HIERARCHY AND THE DEFINITION OF ORDER IN THE LETTERS OF PSEUDO-DIONYSIUS A Study in the Form and meaning of the Pseudo-Dionysian Writings by RONALD F. HA THA WAY University of California at Santa Barbara II MAR TINUS NIJHOFF - THE HAGUE - 1969 to 1969 by Marlinus Nijhott. The Hague, Netherlands AIl1'ights reurved. including the right to translate or to reproduce th is book 01' paris thereof in any f01'm ISBN 978-94-011-8468-7 ISBN 978-94-011-9183-8 (cBook) DOl 10.1007/978-94-011-9183-8 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS A debt of gratitude is owed by the author to Professor Heiko Oberman, in whose seminar this monograph was conceived in embryo, to Profes­ sors Herbert Marcuse and Peter Diamandopoulos for their assistance, and to Professor Alexander Altmann for his advice and guidance. Thanks are due to the officials of Brandeis University who allowed the author to transfer a graduate Fellowship in order to pursue research in the British Museum. Special words of gratitude are owing to both the staff and Fellows of the Dumbarton Oaks Research Library. Several persons, including Professors Jean Meyendorff, Romily Jenkins, Alfred Bellinger, and Donald Nicol, have read either the translation or the text or both and have offered many helpful suggestions. For advice and other kindnesses along the way the author would also like to offer up oblations to Professor Seth Benardete, and to Professors Richard Walzer and E. R. Dodds at Oxford. The author also thanks Mr.
    [Show full text]
  • Patterns of Perfection in Damascius' Life of Isidore
    Phronesis 51,1_f4_74-90II 1/9/06 3:32 PM Page 74 Patterns of Perfection in Damascius’ Life of Isidore DOMINIC J. O’MEARA In memory of Henry Blumenthal ABSTRACT In this article, it is shown that, following the precedent set in particular by Marinus’ Life of Proclus, Damascius, in his Life of Isidore, uses biography so as to illus- trate philosophical progress through the Neoplatonic scale of virtues. Damascius applies this scale, however, to a wide range of figures belonging to pagan philo- sophical circles of the fifth century AD: they show different degrees and forms of progress in this scale and thus provide an edificatory panorama of patterns of philo- sophical perfection. Each level of the scale of virtues is shown to be exemplified in Damascius’ biographies. It is suggested that few, in Damascius’ opinion, reached the highest levels of virtue and that philosophical decline is intimated in his descrip- tions of his contemporaries. In a paper given at the Institute of Classical Studies in London in 1983, Henry Blumenthal showed that, in his Life of Proclus, a eulogy commem- orating in 486 the first anniversary of Proclus’ death, Marinus praised his teacher by showing how Proclus, throughout his life, had ascended a scale of virtues leading to happiness.1 Biography here is panegyrical in purpose, and the virtues and deeds of a hero that are praised are those of a philoso- pher. In this respect we might compare Marinus’ Life of Proclus with two other philosophical ‘lives’ written earlier, towards the beginning of the fourth century, both as frontispieces to two editions: the Life of Plotinus that Porphyry placed at the beginning of his edition of Plotinus (the Enneads), and the Pythagorean Life which is the first volume of Iamblichus’ Pythagorean corpus.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy, Ἱερατική, and the Damascian Dichotomy: Pursuing the Bacchic Ideal in the Sixth-Century Academy Todd Krulak
    Philosophy, Ἱερατική, and the Damascian Dichotomy: Pursuing the Bacchic Ideal in the Sixth-Century Academy Todd Krulak HE BEGINNING of the sixth century CE found the venerable Athenian Academy unexpectedly struggling T to maintain its very existence. The institution enjoyed both curricular and political stability for much of the fifth century under the capable leadership of Proclus of Lycia, but after his death in 485, the school struggled to find a capable successor. Edward Watts has suggested that the failing fortunes of the Academy in this period were due to a dearth of candi- dates who possessed the right combination of the intellectual heft required to carry on the grand tradition of the Academy and the political deftness needed to protect it against encroach- ing Christian authorities. As a result, the school was perched on the razor’s edge. In particular, Watts postulates that an im- politic emphasis on traditional forms of religious ritual in the Academy in the post-Proclan era, especially by the indiscrete Hegias, the head of the school around the beginning of the sixth century, intensified Christian scrutiny.1 Thus, the assump- tion of the position of scholarch, the head of the school, by the 1 See E. J. Watts, City and School in Late Antique Athens and Alexandria (Berke- ley 2006) 118–142; and “Athens between East and West: Elite Self-Presen- tation and the Durability of Traditional Cult,” GRBS 57 (2017) 191–213, which contends that, with regard to religion, Athens retained a decidedly traditional character well into the fifth century. Even after the temples were shuttered in the second quarter of that century, elites supportive of ancestral practices extended financial support to the Academy, for it was known to be sympathetic to traditional deities and rites.
    [Show full text]
  • JPT 009 01 89-98-Critical Review.Indd
    The International Journal The International Journal of the of the Platonic Tradition 9 (�0�5) 89-98 Platonic Tradition brill.com/jpt Critical Review ∵ Philoponus and His Development: Four Recent Translations on Nature, Knowledge, and the Physical World Philoponus, On Aristotle: Posterior Analytics 1.19-34. Translated by Owen Goldin & Marije Martijn. Bloomsbury, 2012. Pp. vi + 217. Philoponus, On Aristotle: Physics 4.1-5. Translated by Keimpe Algra & Johannes van Ophuijsen. Bloomsbury, 2012. Pp. vii + 151. Philoponus, On Aristotle: Physics 4.6-9. Translated by Pamela Huby. Bloomsbury, 2012. Pp. vi + 138. Philoponus, On Aristotle: Meteorology 1.4-9,12. Translated by Inna Kupreeva. Bloomsbury, 2012. Pp. vii + 198. These four volumes constitute the most recent translations of Philoponus’ commentaries to appear in the Ancient Commentators on Aristotle series edited by Richard Sorabji. They also bring to completion the translation of Philoponus’ extant commentaries on Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics, Physics, and Book 1 of the Meteorology in the Ancient Commentators series, along with the majority of the texts of Philoponus edited in the Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca. The exceptions are Philoponus’ commentaries on the Categories and Prior Analytics for which there are only currently limited plans (although a forthcoming joint volume of his commentary on Categories 1-5 along with his A Treatise on Whole and Parts is now planned for 2015). Since first appearing in hardcover, they are also now available both in paperback and eBook versions (a very welcome development for the series as a whole). Each of the four volumes supplies useful information for Philoponus’ approach and interpretation of Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Divine Man of Cynicism in Late Antiquity
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Jagiellonian Univeristy Repository Divine Men and Women in the History and Society of Late Hellenism Cracow 2013 Andrzej Iwo Szoka Jagiellonian University SALUSTIOS — Divine Man of CYNICISM IN LATE ANTIQUITY In the reconstructed Philosophical History of Damacius, which is our main source of repainting the circle of late platonic philosophers and their world in the 5th and early 6th century, the author mentioned Salustios of Emesa. In a few places Damas‑ cius gave this person the name of Cynic. He said: “His [Salustios’] philosophy was along the lines of Cynicism” (kunikèteron dќ ™filosТfei), and in another passage: “As a Cynic philosopher Salustios (Ὁ Saloύstioj kun…zwn) did not follow the well ‑trodden path of philosophy, but the one made jagged through criticism and abuse and especially through toil in the service of virtue1. According to his opinion, in the modern historiography Salustios is called the last Cynic philosopher of the antiquity, the last heir of philosophy and spiritual movement which was founded by the famous Diogenes of Sinope in the fourth century BC. He was not only the last one, but also the only Cynic philosopher known by name after 4th century who is described by sources. In the times of the Roman Empire cynicism was a vital philosophy, but also it be‑ came the widespread social movement which Giovanni Reale named the Phenomena of the Masses2. On the one hand, we have the Cynicism of well ‑educated philosophers like Demetrius — a friend of Seneca, or Dio of Prusa.
    [Show full text]
  • Porphyry and Plotinus' Metaphysics
    forthcoming in G. Karamanolis and A. Sheppard, eds. Studies in Porphyry for the most part purely Plotinian and often taken verbatim or nearly so from the Enneads, as can Porphyry and Plotinus’ Metaphysics 4 Steven K. Strange be seen from the excellent apparatus fontium in Lamberz’s Teubner edition: what is supplied by Emory University Porphyry himself seems intended to help clarify and only occasionally to expand upon his Plotinian basis.5 If this picture of the Sententiae as a sort of handbook, like the Encheiridion of As editor and popularizer of his teacher Plotinus, as a founding figure of Neoplatonism, Epictetus, intended for Plotinian progressors, is correct, then any originality or innovation to be and as an important commentator on Plato and Aristotle, Porphyry deserves to be considered a found in the work will have been unintentional on the part of its author, and it is therefore not major figure in the history of philosophy. But though a first-rate scholar of philosophy as well as surprising to find the work cited somewhat rarely in discussions of Porphyry’s own thought. of other fields—and as such a worthy successor to his first tutor in Platonic philosophy, the A.C. Lloyd in his important article in the Cambridge history of later Greek and early medieval learned Longinus—it is much less clear to what extent Porphyry can be considered an original philosophy6 did claim to find in the Sententiae a new conception of the soul’s return to the contributor to the development of ancient philosophy.1 Indeed, much of Porphyry’s extant work intelligible realm (by abstracting in thought from all logical particularity),7 but he admits that this consists of excerpts, often extensive verbatim excerpts, from earlier writers: this is true of his De conception seems to have been suggested to Porphyry by the final chapter of Ennead VI.4-5, abstinentia, of his Pythagoras biography,2 and of his philosophical epistle to his wife, the Ad Plotinus’ treatise on the omnipresence of Being in the sensible world (VI.5.12).
    [Show full text]
  • Butler Damascius Procession
    The Henadic Origin of Procession in Damascius∗ Edward P. Butler** The question of procession occupies much of the third volume of Westerink’s and Combès’ edition of the Aporiai kai Lyseis, and as usual it is incumbent upon us, as readers of Platonists like Damascius, in whom hypostatic refinements have reached a very advanced stage, to restore for ourselves an immediacy of philosophical significance to the speculative language of the text. This process begins, I would argue, with discerning the distinction in these Platonists between the first, self-constituting entities and the elements implied by their self-constitution. Procession is never for Damascius, nor for other Platonists, a question of the generation of an abstract multiplicity from an abstract unity. Rather, the question Damascius asks within the first few pages of the Aporiai kai Lyseis is how, among the existentially given manifold of things, reciprocal determination and a certain intelligible organization is immediately present: “All things are seen at once in some sort of manifold [plêthos] and in a certain determinacy [diakrisis]; indeed, we do not conceive the All without these <traits>; how, then, has a certain determinacy and a manifold appeared immediately [euthus]?” (DP I 2.21-23).1 Damascian protology, therefore, can only truly be understood from the viewpoint of procession already accomplished. ∗ This article was originally published in Dionysius 31 (December 2013), 79-100. Pagination from this publication appears in brackets. ** I am grateful to Antonio Vargas for comments and criticisms on a prior draft of this essay. 1 DP: Damascius: Traité des Premiers Principes, 2nd ed., ed.
    [Show full text]