Panayiotis Tzamalikos, Anaxagoras, Origen, and Neoplatonism. Te

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Panayiotis Tzamalikos, Anaxagoras, Origen, and Neoplatonism. Te Panayiotis Tzamalikos, Anaxagoras, Origen, and Neoplatonism. !e Legacy of Anaxagoras to Classical and Late Antiquity, Vol. I and II, Arbeiten zur Kirchengeschichte 128/I and 128/II, Berlin–Boston, De Gruyter 2016, XIX + IX + 1793 p., ISBN: 978-3-11-041946-7 Florin George Calian* !is massive book, with no less than 1822 pages, published in two volumes, aims to narrate how Anaxagoras, one of the most enigmatic Presocratics, indirectly in"uenced patristic thinking beyond what current scholarship would expect. !e overall work has four parts. !e #rst volume covers the Philosophy of Anaxagoras (the #rst part) and the Legacy of Anaxagoras to Classical and Late Antiquity (the second part), while the second volume is dedicated to Origen (the third part), and to the !eory of the Soul: from Anaxagoras to Antiquity (the fourth part). !e author intends to provide a comprehensive study on two di$cult ancient intellectuals who belong to two historically, culturally, and even geographically, di%erent areas. !e book has so far received little attention,1 and one would imagine a possible reason is that the reader of such an ambitious study should be equally pro#- cient both in Presocratic philosophy and Patristics thought. !e author announces epic goals as he aims to provide an overview of Anaxagoras’ philosophy and its heritage – in itself a considerable endeavor – and argues for the idea that Origen can be best understood through an Anaxagorean lens. !e Presocratic philosopher is well-known for his theory that ‘everything is in everything’, and for arguing that the Mind is the cause of the universe. Both Plato and Aristotle were not satis#ed with his philos- ophy, but not Origen, who, according to Tzamalikos (T.), found inspiring points in Anaxagoras’s philosophy. !roughout the book, T. advances his thesis in an almost dogmatic manner, to the point that he labels Origen “a pupil of Anaxagoras”. T. insists that the history of ancient philosophy that he provides here challenges W. K. C. Guthrie and his now classic A History of Greek * Florin George Calian, Lucian Blaga University of Sibiu, Institute for Ecumenical Re- search, Philosophy and Religious Studies Unit, 30 Mitropoliei St., 550179 Sibiu, Romania, [email protected]. 1 So far, I identi#ed only two reviews in the English-speaking scholarship: Mark J. Edwards, review of Anaxagoras, Origen, and Neoplatonism. !e Legacy of Anaxagoras to Classical and Late Antiquity, by Panayiotis Tzamalikos, Journal of Ecclesiastical History 69, no. 3 (July 2018): 610–12, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0022046918000507, and Ilaria L.E. Ramelli, review of Anaxagoras, Origen, and Neoplatonism. !e Legacy of Anaxagoras to Classical and Late Antiquity, by Panayiotis Tzamalikos, Gnomon 92, no. 2 (2020): 109–13, https://doi. org/10.17104/0017-1417-2020-2-109. RES 12 (3/2020), p. 556-561 DOI: 10.2478/ress-2020-0044 Book Reviews / Buchrezensionen Philosophy. !e book under review is based on “an entirely di%erent meth- odology” (p. 69) that evokes many elements elaborated by Harold Cherniss – especially in Aristotle’s criticism of the Presocratics. Cherniss’ methodolo- gy, T. caustically remarks, was avoided by Guthrie since “this would have been a far more demanding undertaking” (p. 69). While Guthrie et al. re- garded Aristotle as receptive to historical facts, and, consequently, a reliable source on the Presocratics, Cherniss and Tzamalikos place little value on Aristotle as a trustworthy historian of philosophy. T.’s methodology for read- ing Anaxagoras (explained at p. 42-55) is therefore based on the principle that it should not follow Aristotle’s explicit testimonies, “but also what he said of him implicitly, which calls for study of all of Aristotle’s commen- tators”. !e key commentator in T.’s new methodology is Simplicius, an author completely ignored by present-day scholarship on Anaxagoras, as the author claims. I #nd this dichotomy (Cherniss versus Guthrie) too exacting and ex- clusivist.2 One of the ensuing results for this methodological choice is that T. deliberately ignores modern scholarship, since it “has almost entirely relied on Aristotle’s parochial report” (p. 41). T. challenges not only the Guthrie’s apparent apology of Aristotle, but also the relevance of ‘the precarious’ Diels- Kranz fragments. !us, T. is “introducing a di%erent methodology, which is much more di$cult to pursue compared to deciphering ‘D-K’-passages”. !e attempt to avoid Aristotle’s testimony and to minimize Diels-Kranz fragments is unaccounted for in the scholarship on Anaxagoras, and T’s ar- guments are too feeble and inconsistent in order to be taken seriously. T. equally ignores the immense work that has been done on Origen. A little before T.’s book was issued, an important survey of recent publications on Origen and the Alexandrian Tradition was published,3 but almost none of the surveyed titles are present in T.’s book. All scholars must have felt, at some point, the fatigue of imposed controlled reading by the immense cor- pus of scholarship and the desire to read primary sources without the con- stant reference to other readings. Nevertheless, the unwillingness to enter into dialogue with current scholarship on Origen and on Anaxagoras is one of the book’s major weaknesses. As it is also the stated principle of its meth- odology, it casts a shadow across the whole enterprise. It would have been 2 Guthrie himself expressed his “general admiration and appreciation of the fact that [Cherniss’ work] it is a permanent contribution with which all future scholarship will have to reckon.” W. K. C. Guthrie, “Aristotle as a Historian of Philosophy: Some Preliminaries,” !e Journal of Hellenic Studies 77 (1957): 35–41, 35. 3 Lorenzo Perrone, “Pubblicazioni recenti su Origene e la tradizione alessandrina,” in Ada- mantius 21 (2015): 425–94. 557 Book Reviews / Buchrezensionen more honest and convincing if the author argued for a reading of Anaxagoras without referring to modern scholarship in a manner closer to philosophical commentaries rather than to exegetical ones. Despite the huge in"uence that Origen had on the development of Christian theology, several essential aspects concerning his philosophical and theological identity require further clari#cations. Several of Origen’s views remain uncanonical and his heresies were considered to be caused by the inherent Platonism of his theology. And indeed, he regularly uses Plato and develops his theology in a platonic mold. For T., this Platonism is readily apparent, while Origen’s thinking was fundamentally Anaxagorean. Despite there being no evidence that Origen ever alluded to Anaxagoras – although some tenets of his philosophy could have been known by Origen –, Origen was an Anaxagorean, and less of a Platonist, to the point that T. labelled him as an anti-Platonist. Furthermore, T. argues, if Origen used Plato in any way, he did so only to interpret his ideas through Anaxagorean principles. But which one of the Origens is he actually speaking about? !e pa- gan one or the Christian one? T. claims that both of them are the same person, although he presents no evidence, ignoring, once again, and with no justi#cation, the extant literature on the issue. How then can he accommo- date the anti-Platonist Origen with the pagan Platonist Origen, the student of Ammonius Saccas? !e author does not even start to discuss the problem. One of T.’s factual arguments in describing Origen as Anaxagorean, is that Proclus mentioned Origen in the Platonic !eology as one of those, and above all others, who a$rmed Mind (Nous) as the supreme principle – a statement which would indeed make Origen a disciple of Anaxagoras, and not of Plato. Proclus criticized Origen “as being an anti-Platonist who dis- missed the Plotinian pattern”. But T. points out that “the guardians of the imperial orthodoxy accused him of making the Christian Trinity a Plotinian Triad” (p. 823). T. struggles to show that “the ‘object’ that the Father created in the Logos/Wisdom was not any Platonic Ideas: it was the logoi” (p. 868). !is is an important feature, since T. reasons that Origen’s concept of the Body of the Logos was Anaxagorean in its essence. According to T., Origen’s !eory of the Logoi is also evident for Gregory of Nyssa, an admirer of Origen, and even for Maximus Confessor, who avoids mentioning the forms, but does make reference to the logoi (p. 874). For T., Plato’s “failure” and “Aristotle’s ‘obscurity’” in explaining how the supreme principle relates to sensible objects drives Origen’s attention to the !eory of the Logoi, a theory which is “the most spectacular and stunning in"uence of Anaxagoras upon Late Antiquity” (p. 867). According to T., the Anaxagorean logoi make possible the link between the Mind and the world. 558 Book Reviews / Buchrezensionen Conceptualizing the logoi of Anaxagoras, and not those developed by stoi- cism, Origen took up the !eory of the Logoi in his philosophical theology (p. 891). Ironically, in T.’s aggressive attempts to purge Origen’s thought of pla- tonic elements, I could not help the feeling that the hidden protagonist of this book is actually Plato. !e author uses pejorative a$rmations on Plato, such us “[Plato] was too confused to have an opinion of its own” (p. 1524) on the theory of metempsychosis. In another fragment, the author claims that “it would be good to bear in mind how much of Plato’s work is the product of inconsistently adapted plagiarism” (p. 1524). Additional exam- ples include: “the Republic was allegedly a product of plagiarism from Egypt” (p. 1530), and “Plato was the most notorious plagiarist of all history” (p. 1181). Plato’s thought is too complex, and cannot be reduced to plagiarism in such simple terms.
Recommended publications
  • Plato As "Architectof Science"
    Plato as "Architectof Science" LEONID ZHMUD ABSTRACT The figureof the cordialhost of the Academy,who invitedthe mostgifted math- ematiciansand cultivatedpure research, whose keen intellectwas able if not to solve the particularproblem then at least to show the methodfor its solution: this figureis quite familiarto studentsof Greekscience. But was the Academy as such a centerof scientificresearch, and did Plato really set for mathemati- cians and astronomersthe problemsthey shouldstudy and methodsthey should use? Oursources tell aboutPlato's friendship or at leastacquaintance with many brilliantmathematicians of his day (Theodorus,Archytas, Theaetetus), but they were neverhis pupils,rather vice versa- he learnedmuch from them and actively used this knowledgein developinghis philosophy.There is no reliableevidence that Eudoxus,Menaechmus, Dinostratus, Theudius, and others, whom many scholarsunite into the groupof so-called"Academic mathematicians," ever were his pupilsor close associates.Our analysis of therelevant passages (Eratosthenes' Platonicus, Sosigenes ap. Simplicius, Proclus' Catalogue of geometers, and Philodemus'History of the Academy,etc.) shows thatthe very tendencyof por- trayingPlato as the architectof sciencegoes back to the earlyAcademy and is bornout of interpretationsof his dialogues. I Plato's relationship to the exact sciences used to be one of the traditional problems in the history of ancient Greek science and philosophy.' From the nineteenth century on it was examined in various aspects, the most significant of which were the historical, philosophical and methodological. In the last century and at the beginning of this century attention was paid peredominantly, although not exclusively, to the first of these aspects, especially to the questions how great Plato's contribution to specific math- ematical research really was, and how reliable our sources are in ascrib- ing to him particular scientific discoveries.
    [Show full text]
  • Persuasive Rhetoric in Origen's Contra Celsum
    University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Masters Theses Graduate School 8-2003 Persuasive Rhetoric in Origen’s Contra Celsum. Daniel Charles Headrick University of Tennessee - Knoxville Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_gradthes Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Headrick, Daniel Charles, "Persuasive Rhetoric in Origen’s Contra Celsum.. " Master's Thesis, University of Tennessee, 2003. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_gradthes/1972 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Masters Theses by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. To the Graduate Council: I am submitting herewith a thesis written by Daniel Charles Headrick entitled "Persuasive Rhetoric in Origen’s Contra Celsum.." I have examined the final electronic copy of this thesis for form and content and recommend that it be accepted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree of Master of Arts, with a major in Philosophy. David Dungan, Major Professor We have read this thesis and recommend its acceptance: David Linge, James Fitzgerald Accepted for the Council: Carolyn R. Hodges Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School (Original signatures are on file with official studentecor r ds.) To the Graduate Council: I am submitting herewith a thesis written by Daniel Charles Headrick entitled “Persuasive Rhetoric in Origen’s Contra Celsum.” I have examined the final electronic copy of this thesis for form and content and recommend that it be accepted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts, with a major in Philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Plotinus and Augustine
    The Influence of Plotinus on the Writings of St. Augustine Josiah Meyer History of Ancient & Medieval Philosophy, PH 502 March 8, 2017 1 Introduction If Plato and Aristotle are the most important thinkers of the ancient world, St. Augustine could be a close runner up in brilliance and importance. Far less known, however, is the vital role of Plotinus. Serving as a link between Augustine and Plato, Plotinus was to have a lasting influence on Augustine, and through him on the Christian Church, especially in the West. This paper will bring illumination to the often overlooked intellectual contribution of Plotinus to the thoughts of Augustine. To that end, it will provide an overview of Plotinus’ thought, paying special attention to his use and modification of Plato and Aristotle. It will then turn its attention to Augustine’s appropriation of Plotinus, and the lasting mark he made on the shape of Augustinian theology. Section One: Plotinus Bibliography Plotinus was a native of Lycopolis (or Lycon) in Egypt.1 At the age of 28 he became interested in philosophy and moved to Alexandria to study. After expressing dissatisfaction in several teachers, he finally found Ammonius Saccas (175 AD - 240 AD), declaring, τοῦτον ἐζήτουν, “This is the man I was looking for!” and became his pupil for eleven years.2 This Ammonius Saccas is identified (probably wrongly) by Eusebius as a lapsed Christian. Eusebius 1 Frederick Copleston notes that Eunapis identifies his birthplace as Lycon, while Suidas identifies it as Lycopolis, leaving the exact location a mystery. Frederick Copleston, S.J., A History of Philosophy, vol.
    [Show full text]
  • The Protrepticus of Clement of Alexandria: a Commentary
    Miguel Herrero de Jáuregui THE PROTREPTICUS OF CLEMENT OF ALEXANDRIA: A COMMENTARY to; ga;r yeu'do" ouj yilh'/ th'/ paraqevsei tajlhqou'" diaskedavnnutai, th'/ de; crhvsei th'" ajlhqeiva" ejkbiazovmenon fugadeuvetai. La falsedad no se dispersa por la simple comparación con la verdad, sino que la práctica de la verdad la fuerza a huir. Protréptico 8.77.3 PREFACIO Una tesis doctoral debe tratar de contribuir al avance del conocimiento humano en su disciplina, y la pretensión de que este comentario al Protréptico tenga la máxima utilidad posible me obliga a escribirla en inglés porque es la única lengua que hoy casi todos los interesados pueden leer. Pero no deja de ser extraño que en la casa de Nebrija se deje de lado la lengua castellana. La deuda que contraigo ahora con el español sólo se paliará si en el futuro puedo, en compensación, “dar a los hombres de mi lengua obras en que mejor puedan emplear su ocio”. Empiezo ahora a saldarla, empleándola para estos agradecimientos, breves en extensión pero no en sinceridad. Mi gratitud va, en primer lugar, al Cardenal Don Gil Álvarez de Albornoz, fundador del Real Colegio de España, a cuya generosidad y previsión debo dos años provechosos y felices en Bolonia. Al Rector, José Guillermo García-Valdecasas, que administra la herencia de Albornoz con ejemplar dedicación, eficacia y amor a la casa. A todas las personas que trabajan en el Colegio y hacen que cumpla con creces los objetivos para los que se fundó. Y a mis compañeros bolonios durante estos dos años. Ha sido un honor muy grato disfrutar con todos ellos de la herencia albornociana.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter Two Democritus and the Different Limits to Divisibility
    CHAPTER TWO DEMOCRITUS AND THE DIFFERENT LIMITS TO DIVISIBILITY § 0. Introduction In the previous chapter I tried to give an extensive analysis of the reasoning in and behind the first arguments in the history of philosophy in which problems of continuity and infinite divisibility emerged. The impact of these arguments must have been enormous. Designed to show that rationally speaking one was better off with an Eleatic universe without plurality and without motion, Zeno’s paradoxes were a challenge to everyone who wanted to salvage at least those two basic features of the world of common sense. On the other hand, sceptics, for whatever reason weary of common sense, could employ Zeno-style arguments to keep up the pressure. The most notable representative of the latter group is Gorgias, who in his book On not-being or On nature referred to ‘Zeno’s argument’, presumably in a demonstration that what is without body and does not have parts, is not. It is possible that this followed an earlier argument of his that whatever is one, must be without body.1 We recognize here what Aristotle calls Zeno’s principle, that what does not have bulk or size, is not. Also in the following we meet familiar Zenonian themes: Further, if it moves and shifts [as] one, what is, is divided, not being continuous, and there [it is] not something. Hence, if it moves everywhere, it is divided everywhere. But if that is the case, then everywhere it is not. For it is there deprived of being, he says, where it is divided, instead of ‘void’ using ‘being divided’.2 Gorgias is talking here about the situation that there is motion within what is.
    [Show full text]
  • Proclus and Artemis: on the Relevance of Neoplatonism to the Modern Study of Ancient Religion
    Kernos Revue internationale et pluridisciplinaire de religion grecque antique 13 | 2000 Varia Proclus and Artemis: On the Relevance of Neoplatonism to the Modern Study of Ancient Religion Spyridon Rangos Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/kernos/1293 DOI: 10.4000/kernos.1293 ISSN: 2034-7871 Publisher Centre international d'étude de la religion grecque antique Printed version Date of publication: 1 January 2000 ISSN: 0776-3824 Electronic reference Spyridon Rangos, « Proclus and Artemis: On the Relevance of Neoplatonism to the Modern Study of Ancient Religion », Kernos [Online], 13 | 2000, Online since 21 April 2011, connection on 01 May 2019. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/kernos/1293 ; DOI : 10.4000/kernos.1293 Kernos Kernos, 13 (2000), p. 47-84. Proclus and Artemis: On the Relevance of Neoplatonism to the Modern Study of Andent Religion* Imagine the situation in which contemporary philosophers would find themselves if Wittgenstein introduced, in his Philosophical Investigations, the religious figure of Jesus as Logos and Son of God in order to illuminate the puzzlement ofthe private-language paradox, or if in the second division of Being and Time Heidegger mentioned the archangel Michael to support the argument of 'being toward death'. Similar is the perplexity that a modern reader is bound to encounter when, after a highly sophisticated analysis of demanding metaphysical questions about the relationship of the one and the many, finitude and infinity, mind and body, Proclus, l in ail seriousness and without the slightest touch of irony, assigns to some traditional gods of Greek polytheism a definitive place in the structure of being.
    [Show full text]
  • The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism the Alexandrian
    This article was downloaded by: 10.3.98.104 On: 25 Sep 2021 Access details: subscription number Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: 5 Howick Place, London SW1P 1WG, UK The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism Pauliina Remes, Svetla Slaveva-Griffin The Alexandrian classrooms excavated and sixth-century philosophy teaching Publication details https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/doi/10.4324/9781315744186.ch3 Richard Sorabji Published online on: 30 Apr 2014 How to cite :- Richard Sorabji. 30 Apr 2014, The Alexandrian classrooms excavated and sixth-century philosophy teaching from: The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism Routledge Accessed on: 25 Sep 2021 https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/doi/10.4324/9781315744186.ch3 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR DOCUMENT Full terms and conditions of use: https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/legal-notices/terms This Document PDF may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproductions, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The publisher shall not be liable for an loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. 3 The Alexandrian classrooms excavated and sixth-century philosophy teaching Richard Sorabji It was announced in 2004 that the Polish archaeological team under Grzegorz Majcherek had identifi ed the surprisingly well-preserved lecture rooms of the sixth-century Alexandrian school.1 Th is was a major archaeological discovery.2 Although the fi rst few rooms had been excavated twenty-fi ve years earlier, identifi cation has only now become possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens
    Trinity University Digital Commons @ Trinity Philosophy Faculty Research Philosophy Department 2014 Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens Damian Caluori Trinity University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.trinity.edu/phil_faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Repository Citation Caluori, D. (2014). Rhetoric and Platonism in fifth-century Athens. In R. C. Fowler (Ed.), Plato in the third sophistic (pp. 57-72). De Gruyter. This Contribution to Book is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at Digital Commons @ Trinity. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Research by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Trinity. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Damian Caluori (Trinity University) Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens There are reasons to believe that relations between Platonism and rhetoric in Athens during the fifth century CE were rather close.Z Both were major pillars of pagan cul- ture, or paideia, and thus essential elements in the defense of paganism against in- creasingly powerful and repressive Christian opponents. It is easy to imagine that, under these circumstances, paganism was closing ranks and that philosophers and orators united in their efforts to save traditional ways and values. Although there is no doubt some truth to this view, a closer look reveals that the relations be- tween philosophy and rhetoric were rather more complicated. In what follows, I will discuss these relations with a view to the Platonist school of Athens. By “the Platon- ist school of Athens” I mean the Platonist school founded by Plutarch of Athens in the late fourth century CE, and reaching a famous end under the leadership of Dam- ascius in 529.X I will first survey the evidence for the attitudes towards rhetoric pre- vailing amongst the most important Athenian Platonists of the time.
    [Show full text]
  • PROCLUS on HESIOD's WORKS and DAYS Patrizia Marzillo
    PERFORMING AN ACADEMIC TALK: PROCLUS ON HESIOD’S WORKS AND DAYS Patrizia Marzillo Abstract From Socrates onwards orality was the favoured means of expression for those wholaterlovedtocallthemselves‘Platonic’.Theyusedtodiscussphilosophical issues in debates that turned into academic lectures and seminars. According to Plato’s original teaching, these talks should have not been “fixed” in written compositions, yet Plato himself put most of his doctrine into fictive “written dia- logues”.His followers intensified their connection with writing, above all for the purposes of teaching. On the one hand, they made notes on the lessons of their teachers; on the other, they enlarged their own talks in written compositions. Neoplatonists’ commentaries are often an amplification of their academic talks. The lessons held in the school of Athens or in Platonic circles coalesced into texts that mostly constitute Neoplatonic propaganda intended for the outside world. When Proclus directed the school in Athens, Plato and Aristotle were taught, but also theologian poets such as Homer, Orpheus, Hesiod. As the Suda reports, Proclus wrote commentaries on all of these poets, but the only onepreservedisthecommentaryonHesiod’sWorks and Days.Througha comparison of some passages from this commentary, I show how Proclus’ commentary on Hesiod is not only a good example of an oral lesson that has become a written commentary, but also, importantly, of a text that aimed at the diffusion of Neoplatonic ideas among an audience of non-adherents. As his biographer and disciple Marinus of Neapolis relates, the neo- Platonist Proclus was accustomed to write about lines a day.1 Besides being a very prolific author, he was also an indefatigable teacher since in addition to his writing he held several classes during the day and also gave evening talks.2 What I propose to show in this paper is the profound interaction between the oral communication in his school and the written performance of his commentaries.
    [Show full text]
  • Neoplatonic Asclepius: Science and Religion at the Crossroads of Aristotelian Biology, Hippocratic Medicine and Platonic Theurgy
    Studia Antiqua et Archaeologica 23(2): 333–349 Neoplatonic Asclepius: Science and religion at the crossroads of Aristotelian biology, Hippocratic medicine and Platonic theurgy Eugene AFONASIN1 Abstract. In the first part of the paper, I will briefly discuss certain peculiarities of the medical profession in antiquity. In his Philosophical History (fr. 80–84 Athanassiadi) Damascius narrates about a philosopher, named Asclepiodotus, whose interests ranged from Platonic philosophy to Aristotelian natural sciences. Asclepiodotus’ instructor in medical matters, a son of a doctor from the island of Rhodos, Iacobus, is pictured by Damascius as an exemplary figure (fr. 84), who, unlike many of his contemporaries, always tested the opinions of others and gained a reputation of an extremely successful physician, although the methods of treatment, ascribed to him by Damascius, are highly reminiscent of those presented as the Pythagorean by Iamblichus (On the Pythagorean way of life 244). In this respect both Iacobus and Asclepiodotus are conformed to the best standards of medical ethics, and pass the test set by Galen in his “On examination by which the best physicians are recognized”, except perhaps by the fact that they preferred to base their activities on such authorities as Aristotle and the Methodist Soranus rather than on a list of the “dogmatists” proposed by Galen. In the second part of the paper, dedicated to the cult of Asclepius in Late Antiquity, I will look at various kinds of evidence taken from the Neoplatonic philosophers. Having discussed first the principal philosophical interpretations of Asclepius found in Apuleius, Aelianus, Macrobius, Julian, Porphyry, Iamblichus, Proclus, Damascius, etc., we turn to Proclus’ attitude to Athena and Asclepius as reflected in Marinus’ Vita Procli and finally discuss the cult of Eshmun as found in Damascius.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy in Ancient Greek Biography. Turnhout: Brepols, 2016
    Revista Classica, v. 30, n. 2, p. 137-142, 2017 137 BONAZZI, Mauro; SCHORN, Stefan. Bios Philosophos: Philosophy in Ancient Greek Biography. Turnhout: Brepols, 2016. 313p. ISBN 978-2-503-56546-0 Gustavo Laet Gomes* * Mestre em Filosofia Bernardo C. D. A. Vasconcelos** pela Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais. guslaet@ gmail.com Bios Philosophos. Philosophy in Ancient Greek Biography (Brepols, 2016), organized by Mauro Bonazzi and Stefan Schorn, delivers a ** Mestre em Filosofia pela both deep and wide tour through the philosophical aspects of Greek Universidade Federal biographical production. On one hand, it does not concentrate only in de Minas Gerais. the later periods of Greek philosophy, when biographical production bernardovasconcelos abounded, but goes all the way back to the fourth century BCE, when @gmail.com biographical texts were fragmentary and mingled with other styles. On the other, it tries to unveil the philosophical motives in the works of authors who tend to be disregarded as historians, biographers, hagiographers or even as mere fans of the most prominent figures of their own schools. In our review, we will attempt to give a brief account of the ten articles that make up this volume, which, in turn, will hopefully provide an overview of the different connections between the biographies and biographers and their philosophical motives. Thomas Bénatouïl’s Pythagore chez Dicéarque: anectodes biographiques et critique de la philosophie contemplative (p. 11-36) proposes an inversion of the traditional interpretation regarding the testimony of Dicaearchus of Messana about the life of Pythagoras. Since antiquity, Dicaearchus’ reports tend to be seen as positive, because they present a Pythagoras devoid of mysticism and apparently more interested in practical matters.
    [Show full text]
  • Persecution and Response in Late Paganism The
    Persecution and Response in Late Paganism: The Evidence of Damascius Author(s): Polymnia Athanassiadi Source: The Journal of Hellenic Studies, Vol. 113 (1993), pp. 1-29 Published by: The Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/632395 . Accessed: 01/12/2013 12:02 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Hellenic Studies. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 198.105.44.150 on Sun, 1 Dec 2013 12:02:11 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Journal of Hellenic Studies cxiii (1993) pp 1-29 PERSECUTIONAND RESPONSE IN LATE PAGANISM: THE EVIDENCE OF DAMASCIUS* THE theme of this paper is intolerance: its manifestation in late antiquity towards the pagans of the Eastern Mediterranean,and the immediate reactions and long-term attitudes that it provoked in them. The reasons why, in spite of copious evidence, the persecution of the traditional cults and of their adepts in the Roman empire has never been viewed as such are obvious: on the one hand no pagan church emerged out of the turmoil to canonise its dead and expound a theology of martyrdom, and on the other, whatever their conscious religious beliefs, late antique scholars in their overwhelming majority were formed in societies whose ethical foundations and logic are irreversibly Christian.
    [Show full text]