Commentaries

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Commentaries The JapaneseAssociationJapanese Association of Indian and Buddhist Studies Jburnai oflhdian andBuddhist Studies Vbl. 61, No. 3, March 2013 (93) The Influence of the Avaivartikacakra Mahayana SUtra in Indian Buddhism Based on Its Citation in Indian Buddhist Commentaries James B. AppLE 1. Introduction A significant, yet previousty unstudied, selflproclaimed Mahay5na scripture, is the Avai- ') vartikocakrasijtra Discourse (`The on Irreversibility'). The Avaivartikacakrasijtnaisan early Mahiyelna scripture that focuses on the concept ofthe irreversibility (avaivartiha) of bodhisattvas ("Buddhas-in-training") from the attainment of fu11 Buddhahood. The con- cept of the irreversible (avaivartiko) bodhisattva is considered to be one of the most vita1 subjects in the historical development of Mahayana Buddhism due to the concept's preva- lence, as well as its transvaluing meaning, in early (pre-3rd century) MahAyEna literature.2) The Avaivartikacakrasabna provides the earliest and most comprehensive discussion ofthis concept among MahEyana scriptures other than the Prcu'nryiipdramitj literature. The sfitra is also notable for its advocation of ekoyana, its usage ofnarrative displacement, and its rhet- `word-play' 3) oric of through semantic elucidation or nirukti. One may infer that this text was an influential Mahayana sfitra in Buddhist culture as indicated by its preservation and transmission in South, Central, and East Asia over rnany centuries.4) 2. Citations in Indian Buddhist Commentaries The importance of the Avaivartikacakrasijtna is atso demonstrated through its active ci- tation in indigenous commentaries on the bodhisattva path by prominent Indian Mah5yAna Buddhist scholars from the second to twelfth centuries. Previous studies have discussed how Indian masters' citations of a sfitra demonstrate the importance of a panicular stitra 5) within the historical context of Indian Buddhism. As we will see, the Avaivartikacakra- stitra was an important text to support the views ofa number of Indian Buddhist scholars. 2.1. SiZtrasam"ccaya The Stitrasamuccaya is an anthology ofstitra citations traditionally attributed to Nagar- - - 1151 NII-Electronic Library Service The JapaneseAssociationJapanese Association of Indian and Buddhist Studies (94) TheInfluenceoftheAvaivartihacakraimhay5maSiminindianBuddhismBasedonItsCitmioiinIndianBudchixCommenimes(J.B.Apm.E) juna, although recent discussion in modern scholarship has indicated that the author may be different from the Nagatiuna who composed the Maddyamakakarika. Nevertheless, the anthology had great influence on later Indian Buddhist scholarship. The author of the Stitrasamuccaya cites the fbllowing portion frorn Avaivartikacakrasijtra to substantiate his view on ekayana: "Tb MafljuSri asked, what extent is this compatible with the dharma teachings of the Buddhas, the "The Blessed Ones?" [The Bhagavan ['Abhavrtapadmaphullitagatra] replied], dharma teaching ofthe Buddhas, the Blessed Ones, is compatible with the discourse on irreversible dharma (avai- "Bhagavan, vartikadhat:macakna) ." [The bodhisattva] asked, How is it that a Bhagavan sets forth the three vehicles arid presently teaches dharma? [The Bhagavan ['AbhEv;tapadrnaphullitagatra] `'Son replied] ofGood Family, sentient beings aspire for the inferior and when they do not enter the single vehicle, [the Buddhas] guide them with skill in means. Son of Good Family, the Buddhas, the Blessed Ones, have great skill in means. The Blessed One appears to those [sentient beings] at the time ofthe five degenerations and uses skill in means for those who do not aspire for the single vehicle.6) The citation is from the first chapter of the Avaivartikacakrasatra although, in this sec- tion of the sfitra itselC the discussion does not involve MafljuSri but rather the bodhisattva siryan) PleasantSound (*Anandokti,Tib.sgra . 2.2. Arya Vimuktisena (6th century) and Haribhadra (8th century) The Avaivartihacakrastitra was popular among commentators of the Abhisamaydlamkiira as a number of cornmentators to this Sdstra make reference to the sijtra. We know the San- skrit title ofthe text as Avaivartikaeakrastitra since the title of the sfitra is preserved ip the Abhisamayalamkdra commentaries of both Arya-Vimuktisena and Haribhadra,7) despite notable discrepancies among reconstmcted titles preserved in the various editions of the Tibetan Karijur.8) Arya-Vimuktisena and Haribhadra reference the Avaivartikacakrastitra in order to illustrate how the twenty types of samgha mentioned in verses 1.23-24 of the Abhisamayalamkiira are bodhisattvas.9} Other Indian Abhisamayalamkeira commentators will reference the Avaivartikacakrasijtra as well, with Dharmamitra in his Prasphulapadb (D 3796) providing several citations from the stitra itselfi Here, the teaching refers te the bodhisattva as a Strearn-enterer and so forth since both the basis ofa term and the emanator are emanantions and, since sentient beings are known to be afraid of the great waves of the sublime vehicle and aspire for the inferior, bodhisattvas become Srbvakas and are indicated to achieve pratyekabuddha awakening. It is construed through the basis ef a term [, the -1152- NII-Electronic Library Service The JapaneseAssociationJapanese Association of Indian and Buddhist Studies lhe hiuence of the Avaivartikzicakea Mdnytrna Satra in Indian Budchisrn Based on Its Citmian in Indim Budnist Commendnes (J, B, Appm)(95) Avaivartikacakrasfitrastates]; "The unfabricated, unstained, passionless realm is indicated, it is indicated having perceived al[ the buddha-qualities. That which the Buddhas teach does not conceptualize things afar nor conceptualize things near, therefore, their teachings are uncontaminated. Proclaiming the contaminated to not exist, elucidated to immeasurable sentient beings, Those sentient beings do not see. In this way, a bodhisattva is called a Sravaka. Ananda, with this intention, I have thoroughly taught [the meaning ofi Srdvaka. Unrestricted is a bodhisattva, and therefbre [a bodhisattva] should be known as a jravaka.' LHaving Likewise: understood these conditions, a bodhisattva is unrestricted and I have indicated `pratyekabuddha."' a bodhisattva with the term Further, these bodhisattvas are taught with the basis ofthe word having three distinctions fbr the 1O) Stream-enterer and so fbrth. This is cited from the Iiya-avatvamkocakrasiitiu. 2.3. Bhaviyeka (6th century) and Candrakirti (7th century) An unacknowledged Sanskrit verse from the Avaivartikaeakrastitra is preserved in Can- drakirti's Prasannapada, and the verse is unattributed in the Tibetan translations of Bhfiviveka's Projn'"opradipa and Avalokitavrata's Projnnyopradipagikd. The Sanskrit as pre- served in Poussin's edition of the Prasannapada, which is based on 18th century manu- scripts from Nepal, is as fo11ows: anirvanam hi nirvanam lokanathena desiitam f ii) akdsena krto akiigenaiva mocitah !1 granthir "The leader ofthe world has taught that there is no nirvdna in nirvdna. A knot tied in space is released through space itselfl" The verse is cited in the commentaries in the context of the twenty-fifth chapter of Nfi- gEniuna's MadhyamakaSa-stra that analyzes nirva4a. The earliest commentary to cite the i2) verse is Bhaviveka in his Prcu'n-lipradipa. Bhaviveka does not state the textual source fbr the verse whereas the tikii subcommentary to Bhaviveka by Avalokitavrata notes the source "the i3) ofthe verse as extensive MahayEna satras." Likewise, Candrakirti cites the verse as spoken by the Bhagavan (Poussin 1970: 540: uktam ca bhagavata), but in the context of the Avaivartikacakrastitra the verse is spoken by Ananda at the beginning ofthe eleventh i4) chapter. The version ofthe verse as it occurs in the 12th century the Tibetan Prasanna- padd translation of Kanakavarma and Pa-tshab nyi-ma grags is the yersion most cited in Tibetan commentaries. Just as the Tibetan commentaries do not recognize the source ofthe verse, I have located at least five Euro-American anicles and books that do not source this - - 1153 NII-Electronic Library Service The JapaneseAssociationJapanese Association of Indian and Buddhist Studies (96) the hiuence ofthe Avaiva,n'hacakTa Mdnyina Stm in Indm Bndchism Based on Its Chation in lidian Buddhist Commenimes (J, B, AppLE) IS) verse either, even as the verse is a favorite among those who study Buddhist philosophy. 2.4. Avalokitavrata (late 7th century) argued recent the Avaivartikacakrasfitra is one arnong several lhave in publicationsthat early Mah5yEna sfitras that utilize nirukti, or semantic elucidation, as a fbrrn of rhetoric to i6) transvalue mainstream Buddhist categories into bod7iisattva embodied values. The claim that such Mahaydna sijtras like the Avaivartikacakrasfitra are employing nirukti is also fbund among traditional commentators. although the underlying purport fbr traditional au- thors may be different from my modern critical standpoint. Avalokitavrata (1ate 7th centu- ry?) cites the Avaivartikacakrastitra three times in his Prcu'n-iipradipatika (D 3859) to provide nirukti for the terms bhagavan, tathZigata, and badttha. Avalokitavrata's citation fbr tathligata is as fbllows: another way, has elucldation from the Arya-avaivartiha- Or in the Blessed One stated a semantic "In is not fbund, cakrastitra: the way that childish beingshave imputed,inthatway awakening .17) since all things cannot be fbund, therefore, he is called 7hthagata. Avalokitavrata is not the only traditional commentator to cite the Avaivartikacaki"czsfitra fbr the Buddha's use of semantic elucidation.
Recommended publications
  • Bhaviveka Yogacara Critique
    Bhāvaviveka’s Critique of the Theory of Three Natures遍依圓三性in Karatalaratna 《掌珍論》 . Kaspars Eihmanis PhD student, National Chengchi University, Faculty of Philosophy 1. Introduction. Mou Zongsan 牟宗三 in his lectures on the philosophy of Daodejing,1 interprets the first line of the first chapter “道可道,非常道” as introducing the notion of two truths. The permanent dao and the impermanent dao, as Mou contends, belong to the universal tendency found in various traditions of philosophy, both European and Asian that tends to distinguish two layers of truth in its attempt to understand the world. This twofold view of truth is recognizable in Plato’s two-world theory: the bifurcation of the world into sensible and intelligible, with the following introduction of the dichotomies of truth and opinion, reality and appearance etc. Kant’s distinction between noumena and phenomena is another example of the two- truth theory, although Mou contends, that such a reading is not without problems: things in themselves are not directly knowable. The source of this highly idiosyncratic reading of Laozi comes from Mou’s application of the theory of two truths found in his application of the notion “one mind opens two gates” ⼀⼼開⼆⾨, borrowed from the Awakening of Faith in Mahāyāna 《⼤乘起信論》(“Mahāyāna Śraddhotpāda Śāstra”). Awakening of Faith is one of the most influential texts in the Far East Mahāyāna Buddhist tradition, which introduces a type of Yogācāra and Tathāgatagarbha synthesis. Leaving aside the questions of the authenticity of the text (Indian original vs. Chinese Apocrypha) and the authorship (Aśvaghoṣa vs. Paramārtha),2 what seems to be important, at least for Mou Zongsan, is the fact that the notion of the two the aspects of the mind ⼆⾨ that are found in the Awakening of Faith as the “thusness aspect of the mind” ⼼真如⾨ 1 Mou Zongsan 牟宗三, “Laozi Daodejing yanjianglu”⽼⼦《道德經》講演錄 (Lectures on Laozi’s “Daodejing”).
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies Vol. 54, No.3
    (100) Journalof Indian and BuddhistStudies Vol. 54, No.3,March 2006 Bhaviveka's Theory of Perception Akira SAITO Bhaviveka's magnum opus,Madhyamakahrdayakarika(MHK), is an important text for learning how the author explains the Madhyamika's standpoint in defiance of the then influential Yogacara"s theory of, in particular, the three natures(trisvabhava). In addition, unlike his two related works,prajnapradipa Da-cheng-zhang・ 一zhen- lun『 大 乗 掌 珍 論 』1), Bhaviveka therein clearly offershis critique of the Yogacara's theory of both perception and meaning in the context of his refutation of parik ta-svabhava, or the"imagined nature". Having already discussed hisalpi theory of meaning in which the referent of a word is explained as an entity possessing the universal(samanyavad vastu)2), I will here confine myself to dealing with the fbrmer topic, i.e. Bhaviveka's theory of perception. As is the case with his discussion of meaning, Bhaviveka's theory of perception is worth examining from at least the following three points of view: (1) the significant features of his theory of perception within his framework of the two truths (satya- dvaya), (2) the comparative analysis of these features with his later appellation, mDo sde [spyod pa'i] dBu ma pa (*Sautrantika-Madhyamika)", and (3) the" relation- ship of his theory of perception with theories found in other related texts belonging to the Sarvastivada and Sautrantika/Yogacara schools. The present paper examines the topic in question from mainly the first standpoint; however, when the occasion demands, it also approaches the same question from the second and third points of view.
    [Show full text]
  • Atisa and Bha Vy a As Prasangikas
    THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN SVATANTRIKA AND PRASANGIKA IN LATE MADHYAMAKA: ATISA AND BHAVY A AS PRASANGIKAS* Jundo NAGASHIMA 1. Introduction: Distinction between Sviitantrika and Priisaligika In the long history of Indian Madhyamaka, differing views developed and doctrinal bifurcations took place. Of these bifurcations, we know of the distinction between Svatantrika and Prasailgika from Tibetan accounts. Nevertheless, it is not yet clear whether these terms were used by Indian Madhyamikas themselves, 1 or even whether this distinction existed in India.z Bhaviveka3 (ca. 500-570 CE), in the Prajfiiipradfpa, criticised Buddhapalita (ca. 470-540 CE) for not employing syllogistic inference to explicate Nagarjuna's teaching. In response to this, Candrakirti (ca. 600-650 CE), in the Prasannapadii, raised an objection to Bhaviveka in support of Buddhapalita. This is considered to be the origin of the dispute between the Svatantrika and the Prasailgika positions. It is, however, not known if this controversy over the use of inferential reasoning led to the development of opposed positions in India later * My thanks are due to Dr. Somadeva Vasudeva, Dr. Peter Ebbatson and Miss Dechen Rochard for carefully reading my draft and offering valuable suggestions. 1 To the best of my knowledge, the earliest text that mentions the term rang rgyud pa, which can be a translation of sviitantrika, is the Madhyamakiivatiiratikii (D. ra 281b6, ra 282a3, P. ra 337a8, ra 337b6) of Jayananda. See Ogawa [1984]. Yonezawa [1999] also mentions the use of a term svatantrasii[dha]naviidin in the *Lah;m:zatikii, which is probably written in the twelfth century CE. Because the *Lah;m:zatikii was written by a Tibetan Dharmaklrti in Sanskrit but with the dBu med script, and the Madhyamakiivatiiratikii was written outside India, they may not be regarded as Indian accounts in a strict sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Ba Mươi Bảy Phẩm Trợ Đạo Giác Ngộ
    Ba Mươi Bảy Phẩm Trợ Đạo Giác Ngộ Đức Đạt Lai Lạt Ma ---o0o--- Nguồn Chuyển sang ebook 20-01-2015 Người thực hiện : Nguyễn Ngọc Thảo - [email protected] Nam Thiên - [email protected] Link Audio Tại Website http://www.phapthihoi.org Mục Lục LỜI NGƯỜI DỊCH LỜI NHÀ XUẤT BẢN NGÀY THỨ NHẤT ĐIỀU THỨ NHẤT ĐIỀU THỨ HAI ĐIỀU THỨ BA ĐIỀU THỨ NĂM ĐIỂU THỨ SÁU NGÀY THỨ HAI ĐIỀU THỨ BẢY ĐIỀU THỨ TÁM ĐIỀU THỨ CHÍN ĐIỀU THỨ MƯỜI ĐIỀU THỨ MƯỜI MỘT NGÀY THỨ BA ĐIỀU THỨ MƯỜI HAI ĐIỀU THỨ MƯỜI BA ĐIỀU THỨ MƯỜI BỐN ĐIỀU THỨ MƯỜI LĂM ĐIỀU THỨ MƯỜI SÁU ĐIỀU THỨ MƯỜI BẢY ĐIỀU THỨ MƯỜI TÁM ĐIỀU THỨ MƯỜI CHÍN ĐIỀU THỨ HAI MƯƠI ĐIỀU THỨ HAI MƯƠI MỐT ĐIỀU THỨ HAI MƯƠI HAI ĐIỀU THỨ HAI MƯƠI BA ĐIỀU THỨ HAI MƯƠI BỐN ĐIỀU THỨ HAI MƯƠI LĂM: BỐ THÍ TOÀN THIỆN ĐIỀU THỨ HAI MƯƠI SÁU: TRÌ GIỚI TOÀN THIỆN ĐIỀU THỨ HAI MƯƠI BẢY: NHẪN NHỤC TOÀN THIỆN ĐIỀU THỨ HAI MƯƠI TÁM: TINH TẤN TOÀN THIỆN ĐIỀU THỨ HAI MƯƠI CHÍN: THIỀN TẬP TOÀN THIỆN ĐIỀU THỨ BA MƯƠI: TUỆ TRÍ TOÀN THIỆN ĐIỀU THỨ BA MƯƠI MỐT ĐIỀU THỨ BA MƯƠI HAI ĐIỀU THỨ BA MƯƠI BA ĐIỀU THỨ BA MƯƠI BỐN ĐIỀU THỨ BA MƯƠI LĂM ĐIỀU THỨ BA MƯƠI SÁU ĐIỀU THỨ BA MƯƠI BẢY 37 PHÁP HÀNH BỒ TÁT ĐẠO BA PHƯƠNG DIỆN CHÍNH CỦA CON ĐƯỜNG GIÁC NGỘ 01 - GIỚI THIỆU 02 - HÃY LÀ MỘT NGƯỜI ÂN CẦN VÀ TẾ NHỊ 03 - NHỮNG ĐẶC TRƯNG CỦA LUẬN GIẢI 04 - KỆ TÁN DƯƠNG, NGUYỆN ƯỚC TRƯỚC TÁC, VÀ KHUYẾN KHÍCH LẮNG NGHE TỐT 05 - SỰ LIÊN HỆ GIỮA BA CON ĐƯỜNG 06 - VIỄN LY 07 - TÂM GIÁC NGỘ (BODHICITA) 08 - MỘT QUAN ĐIỂM ĐÚNG ĐẮN VỀ TÍNH KHÔNG 09 - HUẤN THỊ ĐỂ THỰC TẬP KẾT LUẬN LƯU Ý TRÊN CHỦ TRƯƠNG KHÔNG TÔNG PHÁI LỜI GIỚI THIỆU VỀ TỔNG QUAN NHỮNG CON
    [Show full text]
  • Bh[Viveka's Concept of Prajfia in the Context of the Two Truths
    s c,^:??t fltrgyiyera ?f l::!ry 11!1. 9-on1"*1 9f it'!_lwo_Jrulhl Bh[viveka's Concept of Prajfia in the Context of the Two Truths Akira Sallo In analyzing Bhaviveka's discussions ofthc two truths lound in Ch.3 of thc Maグ リ,α777α たα力rヽ彎 αた′r,ス `(MllK)as wcll as his two othcr authentic α works,thc F)″ ″力″″α″r/9α (PP)Ch.24 and thc*itts′ α″α′η(大 乗掌珍論; ″a」 i力 ′ lⅡこ),it iS no doubt crucial for lls to considcr what role the conccpt ρ ,()r ``intencct'', plays in thcm. In thc llrst thirtccn vcrscs of ⅣIIIK Ch.3, the concept is uscd in thc sanl()sense as ″?α′ち わンググみ′ and dhtt and intencct ⑫″″力′)Or intelligcncc(″ α″)iS held to be oftwo kinds in relatk)n to the two trtlths. ′ ving thrcc pointsi First, what is 「hc prcscnt paper deals with the foHo、 the di∬erence bctwcenヽrasul)andhu and Bha宙 vcka's usagcs ol'ρ″″力′in the context of thc two trllths in Иlb力 ′グカα″777α たOζ αわ力′,ノα(AKBh)Ch.l and MIIK Ch. 3,rcspectivcly? Sccond, in this rcgard,、 vhat sensc(loes Bhaviveka have in mind whcn he uscs the same tcrm in PP Ch.24(*ル ν′αθ′″ b力′να′′777ッア `∂ ′ra」 iZ′ Or``intellect der市ed ittom learning,rcnection,and meditation'')when discussing onc of the threc)undcrstandings(」 Bα力νν/7カ ′)Of thC compound ′α″α777′ ″′力α?「Fhird, in 、vhal: sensc can 、vc thcn undcrstand thc titlc of his jた commcntary on Nagattuna's ルタ′α777α グカソα″αたαた′″α (MblK), ル″力″″αのα`′ I tthe title of Bhaviveka′ s commentary′ ρra」 月∂ρttσわa First, let us turn to the third question, the mcaning of thc title of Bhav市 cka's cornmentary,Prげ 力 ″α ・Ahhough Bhaviveka provdcs no ″ `"α dircct clucs br undcrstanding thc mcaning of this commentary's titic, thc 47 Akira Se,rro following verse ol MLIK 3.6 indicates his unclerstanding of the usage and relationship of the words c.mprisin git, prajfia and fpraldtpa: Intellcct ⑫″げ力∂)iS thC nectar that bl・ illgs salsfac■ On,the lamp wl10se Hght is unobstructcd,the stcps On the palacc()f liberatiOn,and thc flrc that burns the ftlel of the defilcments.
    [Show full text]
  • A Translation of the Madhyamakahṛdayakārikā with the Tarkajvālā III. 137-146
    INSTITUT FUR TIBETOLOGIt UND BUDDHISMUSKUNDE UNIVERSITATSCAMPUS AAKH, HOF 2 SPITALGASSE 2-4, A-1090 WIEN AUSTRIA, EUROPE __ Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies Volume 21 • Number 1 • 1998 JOHANNES BRONKHORST Did the Buddha Believe in Karma and Rebirth? 1 JINHUACHEN The Construction of Early Tendai Esoteric Buddhism: The Japanese Provenance of Saicho's Transmission Documents and Three Esoteric Buddhist Apocrypha Attributed to Subhakarasirhha 21 MIRIAM LEVERING Dogen's Raihaitokuzui and Women Teaching in Sung Ch'an 77 TOM TILLEMANS A Note on Pramanavarttika, Pramdnasamuccaya and Nyayamukha. What is the svadharmin in Buddhist Logic? 111 CHIKAFUMIWATANABE A Translation of the Madhyamakahrdayakdrika with the Tarkajvala III. 137-146 125 YANG JIDONG Replacing hu with fan: A Change in the Chinese Perception of Buddhism during the Medieval Period 157 CHIKAFUMIWATANABE A Translation of the Madhyamakahrdayakarikd with the Tarkajvala III. 137-146J Introduction The Madhyamakahrdayakarikd (hereafter, MHK) is one of the works2 ascribed to Bhaviveka3 (A.D. c. 490-570)4, who was one of the eight known commentators on the Mulamadhyamakakdrika (hereafter, MMK)5 of Nagarjuna (A.D. c. 150-250) and who used formal proofs in ex­ pounding Madhyamaka thought.6 The only known manuscript of the MHK was discovered and hand-copied by RShula SAMKRTYAYANA at the la lu monastery in Tibet in 1936. Having hand-copied the manu­ script there, he registered his copy as "VII 2a lu Monastery, XXXVII, 1. 311. Tarkajvala {tfadhyamakahrdayaT in his handlist.7 Subsequently, SAMKRTYAYANA entrusted the copy to V.V. GOKHALE who later, when visiting Japan in 1971, allowed several scholars to copy his copy of the MHK, and entrusted further research on the MHK to them.
    [Show full text]
  • The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India
    A HISTORY OF INDIAN LITERATURE DAVID SEYFORT RUEGG THE LITERATURE OF THE MADHYAMAKA SCHOOL OF PHILOSOPHY IN INDIA OTTO HARRASSOWITZ • WIESBADEN A HISTORY OF INDIAN LITERATURE EDITED BY JAN GONDA VOLUME VII Fasc. 1 1981 OTTO HARRASSOWITZ • WIESBADEN DAVID SEYFORT RUEGG THE LITERATURE OF THE MADHYAMAKA SCHOOL OF PHILOSOPHY IN INDIA 1981 OTTO HARRASSOWITZ • WIESBADEN A HISTORY OF INDIAN LITERATURE Contents of Vol. VII Vol. VII: Buddhist and Jaina Literature Fasc. 1: D. Seyfort Ruegg The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India CIP-KurztlteTaufnahtne der Deutschen Bibliothek A history of Indian literature / ed. by Jan Gonda. - Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz. NE: Gonda, Jan [Hrsg.] Vol. 7. Buddhist and Jaina literature Vol. 7. Fasc. 1. -> Ruegg, David Seyfort: The literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India Ruegg, David Seyfort: The literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India / David Seyfort Ruegg. — Wiesbaden : Harrassowitz, 1981. (A history of Indian literature ; Vol. 7, Fasc. 1) ISBN 3-447-02204-3 © Otto Hatrassowitz, Wiesbaden 1Q81. Alle Hecate vorbehalteu. Photographische und photomechatusche Wiedergabe nur mit ausdrucklicher Genehmigung des Verlages. Gesamtherstellung: Allgauer Zeitungsverlag GmbH, Kempten. Printed in Germany. Sigel: HIL CONTENTS Introduction 1 The early period: the formation of the Madhyamaka school 4 Nagarjuna 4 Commentaries on Nagarjuna's works 47 Aryadeva 50 Rahulabhadra 54 'Naga' 56 The middle period: the systematization of the Madhyamaka school .. .. 58 Buddhapalita 60 Bhavaviveka
    [Show full text]
  • Engaging Buddhism: Why Buddhism Matters to Contemporary Philosophy
    Engaging Buddhism: Why Buddhism Matters to Contemporary Philosophy Jay L Garfield Yale-NUS College National University of Singapore Yale University Smith College The University of Melbourne Central University of Tibetan Studies Draft of January 2014 Rough Draft—Do Not Quote or Distribute Comments Welcome [email protected] 2 Table of Contents Acknowledgements Preface 5 1. What is Buddhist Philosophy? 16 2. The Metaphysical Perspective I: Interdependence and Impermanence 43 3. The Metaphysical Perspective II: Emptiness 78 4. The Self 116 5. Consciousness 146 6. Phenomenology 202 7. Epistemology 243 8. Logic and the Philosophy of Language 273 9. Ethics 312 10. Methodological Postscript 359 References 379 Engaging Buddhism 3 Acknowledgements Parts of “The Conventional Status of Reflexive Awareness: What’s at Stake in a Tibetan Debate” are used in chapter 5. I am grateful to Philosophy East and West for permission to use this material. Parts of “What is it Like to be a Bodhisattva? Moral Phenomenology in Śāntideva’s Bodhicāryāvatāra appear in chapter 10. I am grateful to the Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies for permission to use this material. The translations from Alaṃbanāparikṣā, and from Gungthang’s and Dendar’s commentaries in chapter 6 are joint work with Douglas Duckworth, M David Eckel, John Powers and Sonam Thakchöe. I thank them for permission to use this material. Parts of chapter 2 in Moonshadows (“Taking Conventional Truth Seriously”) appear in chapter 6. I thank Oxford University Press for permission to use that material. Chapter 11 is published as “Methodology for Mādhyamikas” in Deguchi, Garfield, Tanaka and Priest, The Moon Points Back: Buddhism, Logic and Analytic Philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Nagarjuna's Madhyamaka
    Nagarjuna’s Madhyamaka A Philosophical Investigation Jan Christoph Westerhoff Department of Philosophy University of Durham 50 Old Elvet Durham DH1 3HN United Kingdom westerhof f Qcantab.net This dissertation is submitted for the degree Doctor of Philosophy at the School of Oriental and African Studies, University of London. O c t o b e r 2007 l ProQuest Number: 10731457 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a com plete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. uest ProQuest 10731457 Published by ProQuest LLC(2017). Copyright of the Dissertation is held by the Author. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States C ode Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. ProQuest LLC. 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106- 1346 Abstract This dissertation constitutes a discussion of Nagarjuna’s Madhyamaka as contained in his six main philosophical works. It presents a synoptic pre­ sentation of the main topics Nagarjuna investigates. Particular emphasis is put on an analysis of the philosophical content of Nagarjuna’s Madhyamaka. Apart from discussing the soundness of Nagarjuna’s arguments for particular conclusions I also want to examine to which extent Nagarjuna’s philosophy forms a coherent philosophical system rather than a collection of individual ideas. The dissertation consists of four parts. In the first part (chapter 2) I dis­ cuss the central concept of Madhyamaka philosophy, the notion ofsvabhava.
    [Show full text]
  • Durham E-Theses „He €Roof of Imptiness ! Fh©—Vivek—9S Tewel In
    Durham E-Theses The Proof of Emptiness Bh©aviveka'sJewel in the Hand FONG, LAI,YAN How to cite: FONG, LAI,YAN (2015) The Proof of Emptiness Bh©aviveka'sJewel in the Hand, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/11319/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk Title: The Proof of Emptiness – Bhāviveka’s Jewel in the Hand Author: Lai Yan Fong Abstract: This study seeks to examine the Svātantrika-Madhyamaka proof of emptiness in Bhāviveka’s Jewel in the Hand (* Karatalaratna , KR). The proof comprises two inferences, the first of which is to the ultimate emptiness of conditioned things and the other to the ultimate unreality of unconditioned things. However, emptiness and logical reasoning are seemingly mutually -exclusive, in that emptiness is non-conceptual and ineffable while logical reasoning is conceptual and verbal.
    [Show full text]
  • Materials for a Mādhyamika Critique of Foundationalism: an Annotated Translation of Prasannapadā 55.11 to 77.13
    MATERIALS FOR A MADHYAMIKA CRITIQUE OF FOUNDATIONALISM: AN ANNOTATED TRANSLATION OF PRASANNAPADA 55.11 TO 75.13 DAN ARNOLD Introduction1 The Prasannapada is an important but sometimes frustrating text. Nagar- juna’s Mulamadhyamakakarika (MMK) is available to us today in the original Sanskrit only as embedded in this commentary by Candrakirti (fl. 600 CE), which is the only commentary on Nagarjuna’s text known to have survived in the original Sanskrit2. But Candrakirti himself seems to have had little influence on the subsequent course of Indian philoso- phy; it was, rather, almost invariably the works of Dharmakirti and his philosophical heirs that were taken up by later Indian philosophers (Brah- manical and Buddhist alike). Despite that fact, Candrakirti’s influence on the larger reception of Indian Madhyamaka has been considerable, owing to his having been judged by most Tibetan traditions of interpretation to represent the definitive interpretation of Madhyamaka philosophy, which is almost unanimously claimed by Tibetans to represent the pinnacle of Buddhist thought. This fact itself is striking, not only because of Can- drakirti’s negligible influence in the Indian context, but because the scholastic traditions of Buddhist philosophy were directly introduced to Tibet by SantarakÒita (725-788) and Kamalasila (740-795) — whose 1 My work on this text has benefited, over the years, from conversations and study with several people. I would like to thank, in particular, Larry McCrea (with whom I read through the whole text) and Shelly Pollock for discussions concerning various aspects of the Sanskrit; and, for their generously detailed and thoughtful readings of one of the most recent drafts of this article, Rick Nance and Ulrich T.
    [Show full text]
  • Buddhist Critiques of the Veda and Vedic Sacrifice
    Buddhist Critiques of the Veda and Vedic Sacrifice: A Study of Bhāviveka’s Mīmāṃsā Chapter of the Madhyamakahṛdayakārikā and Tarkajvālā by Hyoung Seok Ham A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Asian Languages and Cultures) in the University of Michigan 2016 Doctoral Committee: Professor Madhav M. Deshpande, Chair Assistant Professor Benjamin Brose Professor Donald S. Lopez Jr. Emeritus Professor Thomas R. Trautmann yasya kasya taror mūlaṃ yena kenāpi miśritam/ yasmai kasmai pradātavyaṃ yad vā tad vā bhavisyati// One mixes the root of this or that tree with this or that. It is to be given to somebody. Then something will happen. (Subhāṣitam from Madhav M. Deshpande’s Saṃskṛtasubodhinī, p. 414) © Hyoung Seok Ham 2016 DEDICATION To Minkyung who dreamed the same dream with me ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I am fortunate to have the following gurus on my dissertation committee. Professor Madhav Deshpande, my advisor, taught me the dharma of being a Sanskrit scholar. He showed me the world of Sanskrit, inspired me to experience the depth of each line of text, and taught me to appreciate its beauty. Professor Donald Lopez taught me the dharma of professionalism. He guided me to face the real problem and to take the right path. Most importantly, they both demonstrated to me what it means to be a scholar with the manner in which they live their everyday lives. This dissertation is mainly a product of my encounter with these two masters. Professor Benjamin Brose was a key source of encouragement during the difficult times. His seminar on Modern Chinese Buddhism planted a seed of a grand-scale project in me; I hope this seed will bear fruit in the future.
    [Show full text]