Download Document

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Download Document Sofia Philosophical Review Alexander L. Gungov, Sofia University, Editor Peter S. Borkowski, American University in Cairo, Associate Editor Karim Mamdani, Toronto, Canada Book Review Editor Kristina Stöckl, University of Rome Tor Vergata, International Editor Vol. V, No. 1 Special Issue Beckett/Philosophy 2011 Editors in charge of the special issue: Matthew Feldman, University of Northampton, Guest Editor Karim Mamdani Academic Community in Civil Society This special issue on Beckett/Philosophy is printed with the kind support of the Embassy of Ireland in Sofia. The Sofia Philosophical Review is especially grate- ful to H.E. Mr. John Rowan for his constant encouragement of this project. Sofia Philosophical Review is a peer reviewed journal indexed by The Philoso- pher’s Index and The MLA International Bibliography. Sofia Philosophical Review accepts papers in the fields of Social, Political, and Moral Philosophy from a Continental Perspective; Continental Philosophy in general; and Philosophy of Medicine. Please send a hard copy of the manu- scripts accompanied by an electronic version of the same to: Editor, Sofia Philosophical Review Faculty of Philosophy Sofia University 15 Tsar Osvobodoitel Blvd. Sofia 1504 BULGARIA E-mail: [email protected] Web site: www.sphr-bg.org All prospective contributions should follow the Chicago Manual of Style. Review materials should be sent to the Book Review Editor at the above address. ISSN 1313-275X © Aglika Gungova, artist Beckett/Philosophy Edited by Matthew Feldman and Karim Mamdani In memoriam Sean Lawlor (1948-2011) The day that is darkest Is the day without laughter (Nicolas-Sébastien de Chamfort via Samuel Beckett’s “Long After Chamfort”, trans. Sean Lawlor) The editors would like to graciously thank the editor of the Sofia Phi- losophical Review, Alexander Gungov, for his consistent encourage- ment, patience, and enthusiasm for this project. We are also sincerely grateful to the Beckett Estate for permission to reproduce unpub- lished material in chapters by Emilie Morin, Chris Ackerley, David Tucker and Matthew Feldman. Matthew Feldman would also like to thank the University of Bergen, Norway, for a Senior Research Fel- lowship with the “Modernism and Christianity” research project, fa- cilitating the completion of this volume. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION TO BECKETT/PHILOSOPHY .................................... 8 Matthew Feldman (University of Northampton, UK) “I AM NOT READING PHILOSOPHY”: BECKETT AND SCHOPENHAUER ..................................................... 19 Erik Tonning (University of Bergen, Norway) “SPEAK OF TIME, WITHOUT FLINCHING … TREAT OF SPACE WITH THE SAME EASY GRACE”: BECKETT, BERGSON AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPACE ............. 45 David Addyman (University of Bergen, Norway) “OF BEING – OR REMAINING”: BECKETT AND EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY ......................................................................... 67 Peter Fifield (St. John’s College, University of Oxford, UK) SAMUEL BECKETT, WILHELM WINDELBAND AND NOMINALIST PHILOSOPHY ....................................................... 89 Matthew Feldman (University of Northampton, UK) MONADOLOGY: SAMUEL BECKETT AND GOTTFRIED WILHELM LEIBNIZ ............................................................................. 122 Chris Ackerley (University of Otago, New Zealand) “THE BOOKS ARE IN THE STUDY AS BEFORE”: SAMUEL BECKETT’S BERKELEY .................................................... 146 Steven Matthews (Oxford Brookes University, UK) BECKETT’S GUIGNOL WORLDS: ARNOLD GEULINCX AND HEINRICH VON KLEIST............................................................ 169 David Tucker (University of Sussex, UK) BECKETT’S CRITIQUE OF KANT ..................................................... 193 P.J. Murphy (Thompson Rivers University, Canada) “EFF IT”: BECKETT AND LINGUISTIC SKEPTICISM ....................... 210 Dirk Van Hulle (University of Antwerp, Belgium) TABLE OF CONTENTS 7 BECKETT, SAMUEL JOHNSON AND THE “VACUITY OF LIFE”...... 228 Emilie Morin (University of York, UK) BECKETT AND ABSTRACTION ........................................................ 251 Charlotta Palmstierna Einarsson (University of Stockholm, Sweden) BECKETT AND THE REFUSAL OF JUDGMENT: THE QUESTION OF ETHICS AND THE VALUE OF ART ................. 265 Mireille Bousquet (Université Paris-8 – Vincennes – Saint-Denis, France) “I CAN’T GO ON, I’LL GO ON”: BECKETT’S FORM OF PHILOSOPHY............................................................................... 283 Kathryn White (University of Ulster, UK) CONCLUSION: BECKETT IN THESES ............................................. 299 Karim Mamdani ANNOUNCEMENET MASTER'S AND DOCTORAL STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY TAUGHT IN ENGLISH AT SOFIA UNIVERSITY................................ 312 INFORMATION ABOUT THE AUTHORS AND EDITORS ................. 318 8 SOFIA PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW Introduction to Beckett/Philosophy Matthew Feldman (University of Northampton, UK) The connections between Samuel Beckett (1906-1989) and philosophy were redoubtably present throughout his life, and remain alive and kicking more than a generation after his death. Characteristically and perhaps unsur- prisingly, evasive comments by the former shed only a half-light upon his relationship with the latter, in keeping with Beckett’s famed reticence to discuss his work or intellectual influences. To take just the 1960s as an ex- ample – at the end of which he received the Nobel Prize for Literature – Beckett repeatedly declaimed all knowledge or understanding of Western philosophy to interviewers on one hand, while on the other simultaneously recommending to Sighle Kennedy, amongst others, that a starting point for his work could be found in two maxims of Arnold Geulincx and Democritus of Abdera, respectively: “where you are worth nothing you should want nothing,” and “naught is more real than nothing.”1 This emphasis upon the void, no less than the syzygy of his position on philosophy, offers a fitting reminder that the texts to follow collectively explore that contradictory, paradoxical and spartan terrain sometimes called the “Beckett Country”: 1 Two of Beckett’s more famous declamations of philosophical knowledge are found in interviews form the early 1960s with Gabriele D’Auberede and Tom Driver, reprinted in Samuel Beckett: The Critical Heritage, edited by Lawrence Graver and Raymond Federman (London: Routledge, 1997), 238-48; Beckett’s letter to Sighle Kennedy of 14 June 1967 on Arnold Geulincx and Democritus of Abdera– “already in Murphy and neither very rational” – is reprinted in the oft-cited collection of journalism and mis- cellany entitled Disjecta: Miscellaneous Writings and a Dramatic Fragment, edited by Ruby Cohn (New York: Grove Press, 1984), 113. A similar view was advanced five years earlier in an interview with Lawrence Harvey, as recounted in his Samuel Beckett: Poet and Critic (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970), 267. For a broad introduction to Beckett’s relationship with Western philosophy, see my “‘I am not a philosopher.’ Beckett and Philosophy: A Methodological and Thematic Introduc- tion,” Sofia Philosophical Review 3/2 (2010). INTRODUCTION TO BECKETT/PHILOSOPHY 9 Closed place. All needed to be known for say is known. There is nothing but what is said. Beyond what is said there is nothing. What goes on in the arena is not said. Did it need to be known it would be. No interest. Not for imagining. Place consisting of an arena and a ditch. Between the two skirting the latter a track. Closed place. Beyond the ditch there is nothing. This is known because it needs to be said. Arena black vast. Room for millions. Wandering and still. Never seeing never hearing one another. Never touching. No more is known.2 There can be little doubt, then, as Dermot Moran has recently sug- gested, that such a “stark Beckettian world cries out for philosophical inter- pretation.”3 Yet at the same time, by the way of acknowleding the pitfalls facing any facile linking of Beckett’s (or any other modernist’s) literature with philosophical ideas – in no small measure due to the challenging opac- ity of Beckett’s (especially postwar) literature – Becket/Philosophy charts a narrow course. That is to say, the contributions to this collection examine specific philosophical interventions (or “slashes,” as suggested by this vol- ume’s title), in Beckett’s development and expression as a literary writer. Western philosophy is therefore selectively engaged here through the lens of Beckett’s engagement with a particular thinker, doctrine or theme, as regis- tered across his published prose, drama, and poetry, as well as in manu- scripts, letters, and reading notes. Moreover, in publishing this groundbreaking collection through the kind offices of the Sofia Philosophical Review, the cumulative implications throughout are that, first, Samuel Beckett was a particularly philosophically- minded writer; second, his knowledge of philosophy was extensive, perhaps 2 Samuel Beckett, “Closed Place,” in Texts for Nothing and Other Shorter Prose 1950- 1976, edited by Mark Nixon (London: Faber, 2009), 147. 3 Dermot Moran, “Beckett and philosophy,” in Samuel Beckett: 100 Years, edited by Christopher Murray (Dublin: New Island, 2006), 94. Despite merely seeing many phi- losophical allusions in Beckett’s work as simply “a kind of arbitrary collection or bricolage of philosophical ideas,” the philosopher nonetheless astutely continues: “Beckett’s relation to philosophy is difficult to complex. He was not a philosopher; if he had been,
Recommended publications
  • In Search of Enlightenment by Reading Samuel Beckett’S Waiting for Godot
    LITERARIA An International Journal of New Literature Across the World ISSN: 2229-4600 VOL. 5, No. 1-2, JAN-DEC 2015 In Search of Enlightenment by Reading Samuel Beckett’s Waiting for Godot SYED ISMYL MAHMOOD RIZVI Patna University, Patna ABSTRACT Beckett’s philosophical indebtedness has long been recognised – especially in conjunction with Dante, Descartes and Geulincx. In this article, I examine Beckettian universal values of Enlightenment, which will be exposed as self-serving mystifications that rationalize and instrumentalize the meaning of life. In this context, the awareness of the Enlightenment nature of Beckett’s writing in Waiting for Godot will be analysed along with the freedom appeal of his reader as he strives to attain the enlightenment. ‘For enlightenment, all that is needed is freedom.’ (Kant 1991 [1784]) Suppose an individual in the world which is a hard shell that he attempts to toss it away, but for what; to think beyond it, and to relocate him beyond it in order to attain enlightenment. Whenever he looks above into the sky, the high sky, the clouds, the flying birds, the stars, the moon, the sun and the cosmos, those make him to forget the hard shell for a while until his eyes fell upon it and he is recaptured. Still into the pupil of his eyes he is reflecting the cosmos. This energy within him, within anyone has vitality and potentiality to reflect the cosmos, and to look beyond the hard shell. Let’s say that he has had an enlightenment experience. Enlightenment is a fact. It is the Truth itself.
    [Show full text]
  • In the Period Immediately After the Personal Catastrophe That Brought
    Louis Althusser and the End of Classical Russian Marxism: Spinoza, Hegel and the Critique of Dogmatic Marxism David Campbell Abstract: An attempt to restate Marx’s critical method in terms of Spinozist dogmatic epistemology was central to Louis Althusser’s conception of Marxist philosophy. Though it is no longer necessary to argue that this ‘restatement’ had almost no ground in Marx’s own thinking, it was a highly significant expression of the essence of dialectical materialism. Through discussion of Hegel’s critique of Spinoza, it will be argued that a democratically acceptable method of criticism of the mistaken beliefs of others, such as Marx developed in Capital, must take a resolutely anti-dogmatic approach which has the principle of winning subjective conviction at its core. Keywords: critical method; dogmatism; dialectical materialism; Spinoza; Hegel; Althusser Word count: 10,300 (14,385 including apparatuses) Contact details: School of Law, Lancaster University, Lancaster, LA1 4YN; 01524 594123; [email protected] Biographical note: David Campbell is a Professor of Law at Lancaster University. His research interests are in the economic, legal and social theory of regulation, and in particular in the law of contract as the general regulation of exchange. Working in areas which have throughout his professional life been dominated by Chicagoan law and economics, he has sought to advance a socialist alternative to that approach. Louis Althusser and the End of Classical Russian Marxism: Spinoza, Hegel and the Critique of Dogmatic
    [Show full text]
  • UCC Library and UCC Researchers Have Made This Item Openly Available
    UCC Library and UCC researchers have made this item openly available. Please let us know how this has helped you. Thanks! Title Revisiting Irish poetic modernisms Author(s) Whittredge, Julia Katherine Publication date 2011-03 Original citation Whittredge, Julia Katherine, 2011. Revisting Irish Poetic Modernisms. PhD Thesis, University College Cork. Type of publication Doctoral thesis Link to publisher's http://library.ucc.ie/record=b2006564~S0 version Access to the full text of the published version may require a subscription. Rights © 2011, Julia Katherine Whittredge http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/ Embargo information Pages 25-346 have been restricted Item downloaded http://hdl.handle.net/10468/324 from Downloaded on 2021-10-01T07:01:51Z Revisiting Irish Poetic Modernisms Dissertation submitted in candidacy for the degree of doctor of philosophy at the School of English, College of Arts, National University of Ireland, Cork, by Julia Katherine Whittredge, MA Under the Supervision of Professor Patricia Coughlan and Professor Alex Davis Head of Department: Professor James Knowles March 2011 Over years, and from farther and nearer, I had thought, I knew you— in spirit—I am of Ireland. Thomas MacGreevy, “Breton Oracles” 2 For John 3 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Thanks to my parents for their encouragement, endless support, love, and for sharing their own love of books, art and music, for being friends as well as amazing parents. And for understanding my love for a tiny, rainy island 3,000 miles away. Thank you to my sister, Em, for her life-long friendship. Her loyalty and extraordinary creative and artistic talent are truly inspiring.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo-Kantianism: the Example of Cassirer’S Erkenntnisproblem", in from Hegel to Windelband, Eds
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-2015 Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo- Kantianism: The Example of Cassirer’s Erkenntnisproblem Sebastian Luft Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. "Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo-Kantianism: The Example of Cassirer’s Erkenntnisproblem", in From Hegel to Windelband, Eds. Gerald Hartung and Valentin Pluder. Boston : De Gruyter, 2015: 181-205. Publisher Link. © 2015 Walter De Gruyter. Used with permission. Sebastian Luft Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo-Kantianism: The Example of Cassirer's Erkenntnisproblem Introduction: Philosophical Historiography as Problem-History. Windelband as Paradigm We can think that "problem-history"l is exclusively a name for one way of philo­ sophical historiography among others. As such it is a method that recounts the history of philosophy in terms of its problems, and not in terms of philosophical personalities or cultural epochs. In this understanding, problem-history proceeds with the naIve assumption that problems exist "in themselves", that they are merely repeated and manifested differently in different epochs. Plainly stated, this sounds both trivial and problematic. And if this reading is true then it is no wonder that problem-history is accorded little interest today, despite the fact that the classical authors of problem-history writing are still readily consulted. Apart from the fact that such writers are still being constantly exploited for re­ search purposes in the present, their works are granted no independent philo­ sophical value. This applies equally to the authors of these works: they are not considered as independent philosophers but "only" as historians.
    [Show full text]
  • Final Draft Jury
    Freedom in Conflict On Kant’s Critique of Medical Reason Jonas Gerlings Thesis submitted for assessment with a view to obtaining the degree of Doctor of History and Civilization of the European University Institute Florence, 24 February 2017. European University Institute Department of History and Civilization Freedom in Conflict On Kant’s Critique of Medical Reason Jonas Gerlings Thesis submitted for assessment with a view to obtaining the degree of Doctor of History and Civilization of the European University Institute Examining Board Prof. Dr. Martin van Gelderen, EUI, Lichtenberg-Kolleg – The Göttingen Institute for Advanced Study (Supervisor) Dr. Dr. h.c. Hans Erich Bödeker, Lichtenberg-Kolleg – The Göttingen Institute for Advanced Study Prof. Stéphane Van Damme, European University Institute Senior Lecturer, Dr. Avi Lifschitz, UCL © Jonas Gerlings, 2016 No part of this thesis may be copied, reproduced or transmitted without prior permission of the author Researcher declaration to accompany the submission of written work Department of History and Civilization - Doctoral Programme I Jonas Gerlings certify that I am the author of the work Freedom in Conflict – Kant’s Critique of Medical Reason I have presented for examination for the Ph.D. at the European University Institute. I also certify that this is solely my own original work, other than where I have clearly indicated, in this declaration and in the thesis, that it is the work of others. I warrant that I have obtained all the permissions required for using any material from other copyrighted publications. I certify that this work complies with the Code of Ethics in Academic Research issued by the European University Institute (IUE 332/2/10 (CA 297).
    [Show full text]
  • Hermann Cohen's Das Princip Der Infinitesimal-Methode
    Hermann Cohen’s Das Princip der Infinitesimal-Methode: The History of an Unsuccessful Book Marco Giovanelli Abstract This paper offers an introduction to Hermann Cohen’s Das Princip der Infinitesimal-Methode (1883), and recounts the history of its controversial reception by Cohen’s early sympathizers, who would become the so-called ‘Marburg school’ of Neo-Kantianism, as well as the reactions it provoked outside this group. By dissecting the ambiguous attitudes of the best-known represen- tatives of the school (Paul Natorp and Ernst Cassirer), as well as those of several minor figures (August Stadler, Kurd Lasswitz, Dimitry Gawronsky, etc.), this paper shows that Das Princip der Infinitesimal-Methode is a unicum in the history of philosophy: it represents a strange case of an unsuccessful book’s enduring influence. The “puzzle of Cohen’s Infinitesimalmethode,” as we will call it, can be solved by looking beyond the scholarly results of the book, and instead focusing on the style of philosophy it exemplified. Moreover, the paper shows that Cohen never supported, but instead explicitly opposed, the doctrine of the centrality of the ‘concept of function’, with which Marburg Neo-Kantianism is usually associated. Long Draft 24/12/2015 Introduction Hermann Cohen’s Das Princip der Infinitesimal-Methode (Cohen, 1883) was undoubtedly an unsuccessful book. Its devastating reviews are customarily mentioned in the literature, but less known and perhaps more significant, is the lukewarm, and sometimes even hostile, reception the book received from Cohen’s early sympathizers. Some members of the group dissented publicly, while others expressed their discomfort in private correspondence.
    [Show full text]
  • Coversheet for Thesis in Sussex Research Online
    A University of Sussex DPhil thesis Available online via Sussex Research Online: http://eprints.sussex.ac.uk/ This thesis is protected by copyright which belongs to the author. This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the Author The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the Author When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given Please visit Sussex Research Online for more information and further details Tracing ‘a literary fantasia’ Arnold Geulincx in the works of Samuel Beckett DAVID TUCKER DPhil University of Sussex June 2010 ii I hereby declare that this thesis has not been and will not be, submitted in whole or in part to another University for the award of any other degree. Signature………………………………………… iii University of Sussex David Tucker DPhil English Literature Tracing ‘a literary fantasia’: Arnold Geulincx in the works of Samuel Beckett Summary This thesis investigates Beckett’s interests in the seventeenth-century philosopher Arnold Geulincx, tracing these interests first back to primary sources in Beckett’s own notes and correspondence, and then forward through his oeuvre. This first full-length study of the occasionalist philosopher in Beckett’s works reveals Geulincx as closely bound, in changeable and subtle ways, to Beckett’s altering compositional methodologies and aesthetic foci. It argues that multifaceted attentiveness to the different ways in which Geulincx is alluded to or explicitly cited in different works is required if the extent of Geulincx’ importance across Beckett’s oeuvre is to be properly understood.
    [Show full text]
  • RENÉ DESCARTES (1596-1650) Author: (W.W.; X.) = William Wallace (1844-1897) Encyclopedia Britannica (New York 1911) Vol
    RENÉ DESCARTES (1596-1650) Author: (W.W.; X.) = William Wallace (1844-1897) Encyclopedia Britannica (New York 1911) vol. 8: 79-90. Electronic Text edited, modernized & paginated by Dr Robert A. Hatch© DESCARTES, RENÉ (1596-1650), French philosopher, was born at La Haye, in Touraine, midway between Tours and Poitiers, on the 31st of March 1596, and died at Stockholm on the 11th of February 1650. The house where he was born is still shown, and a métairie about 3 miles off retains the name of Les Cartes. His family on both sides was of Poitevin descent. Joachim Descartes, his father, having purchased a commission as counsellor in the parlement of Rennes, introduced the family into that demi-noblesse of the robe which, between the bourgeoisie and the high nobility, maintained a lofty rank in French society. He had three children, a son who afterwards succeeded to his father in the parlement, a daughter who married a M. du Crevis, and René, after whose birth the mother died. Descartes, known as Du Perron, from a small estate destined for his inheritance, soon showed an inquisitive mind. From 1604 to 1612 he studied at the school of La Flèche, which Henry IV. had lately founded and endowed for the Jesuits. He enjoyed exceptional privileges; his feeble health excused him from the morning duties, and thus early he acquired the habit of reflection in bed, which clung to him throughout life. Even then he had begun to distrust the authority of tradition and his teachers. Two years before he left school he was selected as one of the twenty-four who went forth to receive the heart of Henry IV.
    [Show full text]
  • Werner Huber, Sandra Mayer, Julia Novak (Eds.)
    Werner Huber, Sandra Mayer, Julia Novak (eds.) IRELAND IN/AND EUROPE: CROSS-CURRENTS AND EXCHANGES Irish Studies in Europe Edited by Werner Huber, Catherine Maignant, Hedwig Schwall Volume 4 Werner Huber, Sandra Mayer, Julia Novak (eds.) IRELAND IN/AND EUROPE: CROSS-CURRENTS AND EXCHANGES Wissenschaftlicher Verlag Trier Ireland in/and Europe: Cross-Currents and Exchanges / Werner Huber, Sandra Mayer, Julia Novak (eds.). - Trier: WVT Wissenschaftlicher Verlag Trier, 2012 (Irish Studies in Europe; vol. 4) ISBN 978-3-86821-421-5 Umschlaggestaltung: Brigitta Disseldorf © WVT Wissenschaftlicher Verlag Trier, 2012 ISBN 978-3-86821-421-5 Alle Rechte vorbehalten Nachdruck oder Vervielfältigung nur mit ausdrücklicher Genehmigung des Verlags WVT Wissenschaftlicher Verlag Trier Bergstraße 27, 54295 Trier Postfach 4005, 54230 Trier Tel.: (0651) 41503, Fax: 41504 Internet: http://www.wvttrier.de E-Mail: [email protected] CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS 9 Werner Huber (Vienna), Sandra Mayer (Vienna), Julia Novak (Vienna) INTRODUCTION 11 Seamus Heaney (Dublin) MOSSBAWN VIA MANTUA: IRELAND IN/AND EUROPE: CROSS-CURRENTS AND EXCHANGES 19 Barbara Freitag (Dublin) HY BRASIL: CARTOGRAPHIC ERROR, CELTIC ELYSIUM, OR THE NEW JERUSALEM? EARLY LITERARY REPRESENTATIONS OF THE IMAGINARY BRASIL ISLAND 29 Eglantina Remport (Budapest) “MY CHANGE OF CHARACTER”: ROUSSEAUISME AND MARIA EDGEWORTH’S ENNUI 41 Gabriella Vö (Pécs) THE RISE OF THE HUNGARIAN DANDY: OSCAR WILDE’S CONTRIBUTION TO THE EXPERIENCE OF MODERNITY IN EARLY-TWENTIETH-CENTURY HUNGARY 51 Sandra Andrea O’Connell (Dublin) PUBLISHED IN PARIS: SAMUEL BECKETT, GEORGE REAVEY, AND THE EUROPA PRESS 65 Ute Anna Mittermaier (Vienna) FRANCO’S SPAIN: A DUBIOUS REFUGE FOR THE POETS OF THE ‘IRISH BEAT GENERATION’ IN THE 1960S 79 Sarah Heinz (Mannheim) FROM UTOPIA TO HETEROTOPIA: IRISH WRITERS NARRATING THE SPANISH CIVIL WAR 93 Michael G.
    [Show full text]
  • History of Western Philosophy II
    History of Western Philosophy II PHIL-2050 - Course Outlines Dr. Tze-wan Kwan Philosophy Department The Chinese University of Hong Kong Semester: Fall 2012 Time: 14:30-17:15 (T07-09) Venue: LSK210 Main Topics of this course I. Introduction: Recapitulation of some hitherto underlying philosophical problems as a preparation for forthcoming topics II. René Descartes III. Baruch de Spinoza IV. Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz V. John Locke VI. George Berkeley VII. David Hume VIII. Immanuel Kant IX. G.W.F. Hegel X. Karl Marx XI. Friedrich Nietzsche XII. Final summary and Revision Bibliographies: A. Text for History of Western Philosophy B. Other related references I. Introduction: Recapitulation of some hitherto underlying philosophical problems that linger on in subsequent development of the history of philosophy 1. The notion of "history of philosophy" revisited: (Begriffsgeschichte and Problemgeschichte) 19 2. The Ionian tradition vs. the Eleatic tradition 3. The double criteria of truth: reason and belief 4. Theodicy and the problem of evil 5. Controversy over the primacy of will and intellect 6. Problem of universals - controversy between realism and nominalism 7. Problem of individuals- peras, tode ti, principium individuationis, haeccitas, existential solus ipse 8. Subject and person in antiquity and in modern philosophy 9. Natural law vs. positive law - the physis/nomoi distinction 10. Questions concerning periodization and nomenclature in the historiography of philosophy II. René Descartes (*1596, 1650) 1. A brief sketch of Descartes' life 2. Philosophical doctrines a. Concept of method b. Sources of error c. Discovery of the "ego" d. Proof of the existence of God e. Existence of external things f.
    [Show full text]
  • Die Deutsche Metaphysische Kantinterpretation Der 1920Er Jahre
    Zurich Open Repository and Archive University of Zurich Main Library Strickhofstrasse 39 CH-8057 Zurich www.zora.uzh.ch Year: 2004 Die deutsche metaphysische Kantinterpretation der 1920er Jahre Baertschi, Christian Abstract: Die Arbeit beginnt mit einer kurzen Situationsanalyse der Philosophie in Deutschland um 1920. Anschliessend grenzt der Autor den Begriff der ”metaphysischen” vom Begriff der ”ontologischen” Kantinterpretation ab, gibt eine Literaturübersicht und reflektiert Methodenfragen. Die in der Literatur nicht gemachte Unterscheidung fundiert er im Rekurs auf die im 18. Jahrhundert geläufige Einteilung der metaphysica in eine metaphysica generalis (Ontologie) und eine metapysica specialis (Kosmologie, Psychologie, rationale Theologie). Entsprechend ist die Dissertation aufgebaut. Auf die Darstellung der Kantinterpretationen von Friedrich Paulsen, Konstantin Oesterreich, Max Wundt, Erich Adickes und Heinz Heimsoeth, die Kant im Sinne der metaphysica specialis lesen, folgt die Analyse der ontologischen Deutungen von Nicolai Hartmann und Martin Heidegger. In diesen Hauptteil fragt der Autor im Hinblick auf die einzelnen Interpreten (1) nach deren eigenem Metaphysikverständnis und (2) nach der jeweiligen Ortung des Metaphysischen in Kants Denken. Die abschliessende systematische Diskussion ermittelt den Ertrag der metaphysischen Kantinterpretationen in den drei einschlägigen Problembereichen des Dinges an sich, des Subjekts und der Ideen. The dissertation begins with a short description of the state of philosophy in Germany around 1920. The author defines the notions ”metaphysical” and ”ontological interpretation” with regard to Kant’s philosophy. He gives a survey on the literature of the 20th century and considers a number of questions concerning the respective methods. The structure of the thesis is based on a division commonly made in 18th century German philosophy: The metaphysica was divided into a metaphysica generalis (Ontology) and a metaphysica specialis (Cosmology, Psychology, rational Theology).
    [Show full text]
  • CAUSAL SKEPTICISM and the DESTRUCTION of ANTIQUITY By
    CAUSAL SKEPTICISM AND THE DESTRUCTION OF ANTIQUITY by JASON M. JORDAN A DISSERTATION Presented to the Department of Philosophy and the Graduate School of the University of Oregon in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2011 DISSERTATION APPROVAL PAGE Student: Jason M. Jordan Title: Causal Skepticism and the Destruction of Antiquity This dissertation has been accepted and approved in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Doctor of Philosophy degree in the Department of Philosophy by: Dr. Naomi Zack Chairperson Dr. Cheney Ryan Member Dr. Colin Koopman Member Dr. Malcolm Wilson Outside Member and Kimberly Andrews Espy Vice President for Research & Innovation/Dean of the Graduate School Original approval signatures are on file with the University of Oregon Graduate School. Degree awarded December 2011 ii © 2011 Jason M. Jordan iii DISSERTATION ABSTRACT Jason M. Jordan Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy December 2011 Title: Causal Skepticism and the Destruction of Antiquity This dissertation examines the development of skeptical views concerning causation from the medieval to the early modern period. While causal skepticism is often overlooked by intellectual historians, I argue that, in spite of its typical motivation as a religious response to shibboleths of ancient philosophy that stood askance from the dogmas of Abrahamic theology, causal skepticism was the greatest intellectual development of post-antiquity and ultimately culminated into modern Science. The first chapter examines Hume's famous analysis of causation and serves as a foil for the prior history of causal skepticism addressed in the subsequent chapters. The second chapter addresses the dispute over causation in medieval Islamic philosophy.
    [Show full text]