Hermann Cohen - Kant Among the Prophets1

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hermann Cohen - Kant Among the Prophets1 The Journal ofJewish Thought and Philosphy, Vol. 2, pp. 185-199 © 1993 Reprints available directly from the publisher Photocopying permitted by licence only Hermann Cohen - Kant among the Prophets1 Gillian Rose University of Warwick, UK The selective reception by general philosophy and social scientific methodology in the European tradition of the mode of neo- Kantianism founded by Hermann Cohen (1842-1918) has con- tributed to the widespread undermining of conceptual thinking in favour of the hermeneutics of reading. To assess Cohen's thought as a reading and re-originating of the Jewish tradition involves a predicament of circularity: for the question of reading and origin is not neutral but derives from the partial reception of the object addressed. The task of reassessment changes from a methodologi- cally independent survey to a challenge posed by current thought, unsure of its modernity or post-modernity, to re-establish contact with a formative but long-forgotten part of itself. No longer solely academic, this exercise will have to confront two especially difficult aspects of Cohen's thought. First, he did not "read" Kant, he destroyed the Kantian philosophy. In its place, he founded a "neo- Kantianism" on the basis of a logic of origin, dif- ference and repetition. As a logic of validity, this neo-Kantian math- esis is often at stake when its practitioners prefer to acknowledge 1 This paper was originally prepared for the Symposium, "The Playground of Textuality: Modern Jewish Intellectuals and the Horizon of Interpretation," First Annual Wayne State University Press Jewish Symposium, held in Detroit, 20-22 March, 1988. Each of the eight participants elected to reassess an individual thinker by focussing on that thinker as a reader of the tradition - ancient and modern. In addition, we were asked to consider the following issues: 1. What is the contribution of Jewish intellectuals/writers to what is characteristically modern and post-modern in how we read texts? 2. How have Jewish intellectuals/writers in the twentieth century created new ways of thinking and employed new ways of reading? 3. How has this new way of reading re-originated what it means to be a Jew in the modern and post-modern world? 4. Have these Jewish thinkers and writ- ers - some at the centre and others at the margin of Judaism - created a new modern Jewish hermeneutic theory and tradition? 185 186 Gillian Rose themselves as the progeny of Nietzsche, Heidegger or Benjamin.2 Second, as I hope to demonstrate in this paper, Cohen's logic is inseparable from his ethics and his philosophy of Judaism. This implies that, since Cohen, the connection between the philosophy of Judaism and general philosophy has been fundamental, in a sense that has not hitherto been imagined or explored. Moses Mendelssohn - so Altmann, his biographer, relates - eventually managed to write a letter to Kant, and tell him that he could not fathom the Critique of Pure Reason.3 In Morgenstunden (1785), however, Mendelssohn refers to "the all crushing Kant [der alles zermalmende Kant]," and implores him to rebuild, "with the same spirit with which he had torn down."4 Hermann Cohen renews Mendelssohn's Judaic Enlightenment by embracing Kant's destructive method, but, paradoxically, he employs it against the critical philosophy itself. Although Cohen's invention of a philoso- phy of Being as "productive origin," developed in his three part System, remains largely unknown and is not available in English translation,5 its panlogism has released, and continues to release generations of thinkers who remain beholden to Kant from the criti- cal philosophy as such, as well as from engagement with any of the forms of critique which succeeded it.6 If, as I hope to show, Cohen's 2 In his comment "Vertaiischte Fronten,"" on the Davos Disputation between Ernst Cassirer and Martin Heidegger in March, 1929, Rosenzweig himself argued that Heidegger, successor to Cohen's chair at Marburg, furthered the spirit of Cohen's thought more than Cassirer, the more orthodox neo-Kantian (op.cit. May, 1929, in Zweistromland, GesammeIte Schriften, 3 (Dordrecht, Nijhoff, 1984), 235-7; for an English translation of the Davos Disputation, see "Appendices"" to Heidegger, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, trans. Richard Taft, Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 1990, pp. 169-85). 3 Alexander Altmann, Moses Mendelssohn: A Biographical Study, London, Routledge, 1973, pp. 705,629. 4 Ibid., p. 673 trans. amended; see Mendelssohn, Morgenstunden oder Vorlesungen iiber das Dasein Gottes, Dominique Bourel (ed.), Stuttgart, Reclam, pp. 5, 7. 5 For Logik der reinen Erkenntnis (1902), see Gillian Rose, Hegel contra Sociology, London, Athlone, 1981, pp. 1-47; for Ethik des reinen Willens (1904), see Rose, Dialectic of Nihilism: Post-Structuralism and Law, Blackwells, Oxford, 1984, pp. 25-51. The third part of Cohen's System is Asthetik des reinen Gefiihls, 1,2,1912. 6 Compare the discussion of Cohen and Marburg, neo-Kantianism by Steven S. Schwarzschild, "Authority and Reason contra Gadamer," 1981, in Studies in Jewish Philosophy: Collected Essays of the Academy for Jewish Philosophy" 1980-1985, Norbert M. Samuelson (ed.), Lanham, University Press of America, 1987, pp. 161-90; and the remarks on Cohen and jurisprudence by the same author in "An Agenda for Jewish Philosophy in the 1980s," 1980, in ibid., p. 106..
Recommended publications
  • HERMANN COHEN and LEO STRAUSS Leora Batnitzky
    JJTP_addnl_186-213 4/26/06 4:00 PM Page 187 HERMANN COHEN AND LEO STRAUSS Leora Batnitzky Princeton University Introduction Leo Strauss concluded both his first and last major works with ref- erence to Hermann Cohen.1 The arguments of Strauss’s first pub- lished book—Spinoza’s Critique of Religion—are rooted in Strauss’s initial work on Cohen’s interpretation of Spinoza. Strauss’s second book— Philosophy and Law—begins and ends by declaring that Cohen is right that the philosophy of Maimonides represents “true rationalism” and more particularly that Maimonides is better understood as a Platonist than as an Aristotelian. Strauss’s last published work, Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy, published posthumously, ends with an essay on Cohen, which was also the introduction to the English translation of Religion of Reason out of the Sources of Judaism. Interestingly, though this essay on Cohen is the final essay in Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy, it doesn’t have much to say about Plato. Although Strauss claims in this essay not have read Religion of Reason for forty years, those familiar with Strauss’s project will recognize that it is from an engagement with Cohen that Strauss forms his basic reading of Maimonides and then Plato. These readings changed in emphasis throughout Strauss’s career but they nevertheless remained funda- mental to his philosophical program. In this essay, I explore Strauss’s philosophical relation to Cohen. It is not an overstatement to suggest that Cohen is responsible for Leo Strauss’s turn to medieval Jewish philosophy. The focus of this essay, however, is not primarily on the details of Cohen and Strauss’s Presented at “Hermann Cohen’s Ethics,” the University of Toronto, August 2001.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Thomas Meyer Leo Strauss's Religious Rhetoric
    Thomas Meyer Leo Strauss’s Religious Rhetoric (1924-1938) Although he had been regarded as shy and restrained since his period of study in Marburg, Strauss was a master of religious rhetoric in his letters and [published] texts. This rhetoric was, for him, neither a [form of] compensation [for insufficient argument], nor a superficial adornment. On the contrary, he deployed religious rhetoric in same way that he analysed [its function] in Plato and Aristotle, through Maimonides and Abravanel, into Spinoza and Hobbes, and up to Hermann Cohen and Julius Guttmann: as an expression of the complex contest between philosophy and religion. After his engagement with Hermann Cohen’s critique of Spinoza in 1924, religious rhetoric was, for Strauss, no longer a feature of Zionist debates alone. Instead, it was a constitutive element of a problematic that Strauss strikingly and provocatively dubbed the “querelle des anciens et des modernes.” In order to understand this change in the function of religious rhetoric [in Strauss’ work], I shall consider three stations of Strauss’ intellectual development. First of all, I shall present several articles that I found in the “Jewish Weekly for Cassel, Hessen, and Waldeck”, which have remained unknown to scholarship until now. Strauss published these articles between February 1925 and January 1928. If we connect these texts with Strauss’s conclusions regarding Spinoza, we can develop a stable account of his religious rhetoric up to about 1934. But [Strauss’s use of religious rhetoric in these texts] can be understood only if we consider it in light of Strauss’ translation of a different religious rhetoric [into the terms of his own thought]: namely, the way Strauss enriched his religious rhetoric through an understanding of, and in dialogue with, the most radical position in Protestant [thought]—that of the dialectical theologian Friedrich Gogarten.
    [Show full text]
  • Deconstruction for Critical Theory Handbook
    Deconstruction Johan van der Walt Introduction Deconstruction is a mode of philosophical thinking that is principally associated with the work of the French philosopher Jacques Derrida. Considered from the perspective of the history of philosophical thinking, the crucial move that Derrida’s way of thinking makes is to shift the focus of inquiry away from a direct engagement with the cognitive content of ideas put forward in a text in order to focus, instead, on the way in which the text produces a privileged framework of meaning while excluding others. Instead of engaging in a debate with other philosophers – contemporary or past – about the ideas they articulated in their texts, Derrida commenced to launch inquiries into the way their texts relied on dominant modes of writing (and reading) to produce a certain semantic content and intent while excluding other modes of reading and, consequently, other possible meanings of the text. By focusing on the textuality of texts – instead of on their semantic content – Derrida’s thinking endeavoured to pay attention, not only to that which the text does not say, but also that which it cannot say. The explanation that follows will show that the “method” of deconstruction does not just consist in finding that other meanings of the text are possible or plausible, but, more importantly, in demonstrating that the possibility or plausibility of other meanings – supressed by the organisation of the text – alerts one to the infinite potentiality of meaning that necessarily exceeds the margins of the text and remains unsayable. In other words, by pointing out the instability of the dominant meaning organised by the text, deconstruction alerts one to the unsayable as such, that is, to that which no text can say but on which all texts remain dependent for being able to say what they manage to say.
    [Show full text]
  • Depopulation: on the Logic of Heidegger's Volk
    Research research in phenomenology 47 (2017) 297–330 in Phenomenology brill.com/rp Depopulation: On the Logic of Heidegger’s Volk Nicolai Krejberg Knudsen Aarhus University [email protected] Abstract This article provides a detailed analysis of the function of the notion of Volk in Martin Heidegger’s philosophy. At first glance, this term is an appeal to the revolutionary mass- es of the National Socialist revolution in a way that demarcates a distinction between the rootedness of the German People (capital “P”) and the rootlessness of the modern rabble (or people). But this distinction is not a sufficient explanation of Heidegger’s position, because Heidegger simultaneously seems to hold that even the Germans are characterized by a lack of identity. What is required is a further appropriation of the proper. My suggestion is that this logic of the Volk is not only useful for understanding Heidegger’s thought during the war, but also an indication of what happened after he lost faith in the National Socialist movement and thus had to make the lack of the People the basis of his thought. Keywords Heidegger – Nazism – Schwarze Hefte – Black Notebooks – Volk – people Introduction In § 74 of Sein und Zeit, Heidegger introduces the notorious term “the People” [das Volk]. For Heidegger, this term functions as the intersection between phi- losophy and politics and, consequently, it preoccupies him throughout the turbulent years from the National Socialist revolution in 1933 to the end of WWII in 1945. The shift from individual Dasein to the Dasein of the German People has often been noted as the very point at which Heidegger’s fundamen- tal ontology intersects with his disastrous political views.
    [Show full text]
  • Against the Heteronomy of Halakhah: Hermann Cohen's Implicit Rejection of Kant's Critique of Judaism
    Against the Heteronomy of Halakhah: Hermann Cohen’s Implicit Rejection of Kant’s Critique of Judaism George Y. Kohler* “Moses did not make religion a part of virtue, but he saw and ordained the virtues to be part of religion…” Josephus, Against Apion 2.17 Hermann Cohen (1842–1918) was arguably the only Jewish philosopher of modernity whose standing within the general philosophical developments of the West equals his enormous impact on Jewish thought. Cohen founded the influential Marburg school of Neo-Kantianism, the leading trend in German Kathederphilosophie in the second half of the nineteenth and the first decade of the twentieth century. Marburg Neo-Kantianism cultivated an overtly ethical, that is, anti-Marxist, and anti-materialist socialism that for Cohen increasingly concurred with his philosophical reading of messianic Judaism. Cohen’s Jewish philosophical theology, elaborated during the last decades of his life, culminated in his famous Religion of Reason out of the Sources of Judaism, published posthumously in 1919.1 Here, Cohen translated his neo-Kantian philosophical position back into classical Jewish terms that he had extracted from Judaism with the help of the progressive line of thought running from * Bar-Ilan University, Department of Jewish Thought. 1 Hermann Cohen, Religion der Vernunft aus den Quellen des Judentums, first edition, Leipzig: Fock, 1919. I refer to the second edition, Frankfurt: Kaufmann, 1929. English translation by Simon Kaplan, Religion of Reason out of the Sources of Judaism (New York: Ungar, 1972). Henceforth this book will be referred to as RR, with reference to the English translation by Kaplan given after the German in square brackets.
    [Show full text]
  • Gillian Rose: a Good Enough Justice
    blo gs.lse.ac.uk http://blogs.lse.ac.uk/lsereviewofbooks/2013/08/27/book-review-gillian-rose-a-good-enough-justice/ Book Review: Gillian Rose: A Good Enough Justice Blog Admin Kate Schick makes the case for the rediscovery of British philosopher Gillian Rose’s unique but neglected voice. Engaging with the work of Benjamin, Honig, Zizek and Butler, she locates Rose’s ideas within central debates in contemporary social theory: trauma and memory, exclusion and difference, tragedy and messianic utopia. Liane Hartnett finds that this work is a compelling invitation to read more Rose. Gillian Rose: A Good Enough Justice. Kate Schick. Edinburgh University Press. July 2012. Find this book: Gillian Rose (1947-1995) was a Jewish thinker and British Hegelian. Educated at Oxf ord, Rose was a reader at the University of Sussex f or many years bef ore accepting a Chair of Social and Political Thought at the University of Warwick. She was also an advisor to the Polish Commission f or the Future of Auschwitz. Rose is perhaps best known f or her moving philosophical memoir, Love’s Work, which was written when she was dying of ovarian cancer. However, Rose also wrote on a wide range of topics including philosophy, sociology and f aith. Her major works include The Melancholy Science, Hegel Contra Sociology, The Dialectic of Nihilism, Broken Middle, Judaism and Modernity and Mourning Becomes the Law. Rose’s thought has inf luenced theologians, philosophers and poets: people like Rowan Williams, John Milbank, Slavoj Zizek and Geof f rey Hill. Yet, she remains a largely neglected philosopher.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Persistence of the Genealogical in Contemporary Theology
    On the Persistence of the Genealogical in Contemporary Theology Abstract There is a persistence of genealogical discourse in a certain strand of contemporary theology. Opting for the genealogical shapes the theological task of remembrance and engagement with the historical tradition in important, but also problematic ways. In this article I discuss how genealogical discourse was appropriated by theology, and then uncover its implicit assumptions and tendencies. Analysing some encounters between theological genealogies and various Hegelian thinkers, I draw a contrast between Nietzschean genealogy and Hegelian ‘phenomenology’. This comparison brings to light some fundamental ways in which the genealogical might distort theological writing and practice. Word count: 10634. It is very easy to forget; even easier to remember wrongly. For theologians whose work involves remembering well, this fact might induce in us a combination of mourning and regret. Much is unintentionally lost to time, yet even more is wittingly let go in a deceitful attempt to cover up our tracks. The theological task must involve a keen attention to what we remember, how we so often run from our memories, and, importantly, the ways in which remembering takes place. Acts of remembrance are intertwined with their objects, and a critique of our practices of remembrance must involve considering the complexity of these relationships. In The Anatomy of Misremembering: Von Balthasar’s Response to Philosophical Modernity, Cyril O’Regan draws attention to the importance of remembering rightly. 1 O’Regan is concerned with a certain ‘misremembering’ in modern thought, such that things are not merely displaced and forgotten, but seriously misconstrued—deliberately or not.
    [Show full text]
  • Religion and Representation in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 11-2017 The perversion of the absolute: religion and representation in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit Thomas Floyd Wright DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Wright, Thomas Floyd, "The perversion of the absolute: religion and representation in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit" (2017). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 240. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/240 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PERVERSION OF THE ABSOLUTE Religion and Representation in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit A Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2017 BY Thomas Floyd Wright Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, Illinois Contents 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Hegel contra Theology . 1 1.2 Marx, Ante-Hegel . 5 1.3 Hegel, post Hegel mortum . 11 1.4 Speculation and perversion . 16 2 The perversion of identity 22 2.1 The evil of ontotheology . 22 2.2 The perversion of desire: Augustine . 26 2.3 The perversion of speech: Hobbes . 30 2.4 The perversion of reason: Kant .
    [Show full text]
  • PHILOSOPHY 474 (Winter Term): PHENOMENOLOGY (Tues; Thurs, 1:00-2:30Pm)
    MCGILL UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY (2017-2018) PHILOSOPHY 474 (Winter Term): PHENOMENOLOGY (Tues; Thurs, 1:00-2:30pm) Instructor: Professor Buckley Office: Leacock 929 Office Hours: Wednesday 3:30pm-5:30pm or by appointment (preferably sign-up by email: [email protected]) Teaching Assistant: Mr. Renxiang Liu (email: [email protected] ); Office: Leacock 923 Office Hours: Monday: 12:30-1:30 COURSE DESCRIPTION: This course serves as an introduction to the phenomenological movement. It focuses upon the motives behind Husserl's original development of "phenomenological reduction" and investigates the manner in which the thought of subsequent philosophers constitutes both an extension and a break with Husserl's original endeavour. TOPIC FOR 2017-2018: The course will consist of a careful reading of Martin Heidegger's seminal work Being and Time (trans. J. Macquarrie and J. Robinson (New York: Harper-Collins, 1962); Sein und Zeit (Tübingen: Max Niemeyer, 1979). The text is available at the Word Bookstore (cash or cheque only). SOME QUESTIONS TO BE CONSIDERED: 1) Background: How can Being and Time be read in view of Husserl's "transcendental" phenomenology? In what way are Husserl's and Heidegger's concerns similar? What other philosophical currents form the horizon within which this text was written (e.g. Neo-Kantianism, positivism, psychologism)? How does Heidegger see his work within the context of the entire history of Western philosophy? 2) The project: What does Heidegger mean by the "recollection of the question
    [Show full text]
  • Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Sebastian Luft Marquette University, [email protected]
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 7-1-2018 Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Sebastian Luft Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology (07/18). DOI. © 2018 Oxford University Press. Used with permission. Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Sebastian Luft The Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology Edited by Dan Zahavi Print Publication Date: Jun 2018 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind, History of Western Philosophy (Post-Classical) Online Publication Date: Jul 2018 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198755340.013.5 Abstract and Keywords This chapter offers a reassessment of the relationship between Kant, the Kantian tradi­ tion, and phenomenology, here focusing mainly on Husserl and Heidegger. Part of this re­ assessment concerns those philosophers who, during the lives of Husserl and Heidegger, sought to defend an updated version of Kant’s philosophy, the neo-Kantians. The chapter shows where the phenomenologists were able to benefit from some of the insights on the part of Kant and the neo-Kantians, but also clearly points to the differences. The aim of this chapter is to offer a fair evaluation of the relation of the main phenomenologists to Kant and to what was at the time the most powerful philosophical movement in Europe. Keywords: Immanuel Kant, neo-Kantianism, Edmund Husserl, Martin Heidegger, Marburg School of neo-Kantian­ ism 3.1 Introduction THE relation between phenomenology, Kant, and Kantian philosophizing broadly con­ strued (historically and systematically), has been a mainstay in phenomenological re­ search.1 This mutual testing of both philosophies is hardly surprising given phenomenology’s promise to provide a wholly novel type of philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Marburg Neo-Kantianism As Philosophy of Culture
    SamanthaMatherne (Santa Cruz) Marburg Neo-Kantianism as Philosophy of Culture 1Introduction Although Ernst Cassirer is correctlyregarded as one of the foremost figures in the Neo-Kantian movement thatdominated Germanyfrom 1870 – 1920,specifying ex- actlywhat his Neo-Kantianism amountstocan be achallenge. Not onlymustwe clarify what his commitments are as amember of the so-called MarburgSchool of Neo-Kantianism, but also giventhe shift between his earlyphilosophyof mathematics and naturalscience to his later philosophyofculture, we must con- sider to what extent he remained aMarburgNeo-Kantian throughout his career. With regard to the first task, it is typical to approach the MarburgSchool, which was foundedbyHermann Cohen and Paul Natorp, by wayofacontrast with the otherdominant school of Neo-Kantianism, the Southwest or Baden School, founded by Wilhelm Windelband and carried forward by Heinrich Rick- ert and Emil Lask. The going assumption is that these two schools were ‘rivals’ in the sense that the MarburgSchool focused exclusively on developing aKantian approach to mathematical natural sciences(Naturwissenschaften), while the Southwest School privileged issues relatingtonormativity and value, hence their primary focus on the humanities (Geisteswissenschaften). If one accepts this ‘scientist’ interpretation of the MarburgSchool, one is tempted to read Cas- sirer’searlywork on mathematicsand natural science as orthodoxMarburgNeo- Kantianism and to then regardhis laterwork on the philosophyofculture as a break from his predecessors, veeringcloser
    [Show full text]
  • Hermann Cohen's History and Philosophy of Science"
    "Hermann Cohen's History and Philosophy of Science" Lydia Patton Department of Philosophy McGill University, Montreal October, 2004 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the degree ofPh.D. © Lydia Patton 2004 Library and Bibliothèque et 1+1 Archives Canada Archives Canada Published Heritage Direction du Branch Patrimoine de l'édition 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Canada Canada Your file Votre référence ISBN: 0-494-06335-1 Our file Notre référence ISBN: 0-494-06335-1 NOTICE: AVIS: The author has granted a non­ L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive exclusive license allowing Library permettant à la Bibliothèque et Archives and Archives Canada to reproduce, Canada de reproduire, publier, archiver, publish, archive, preserve, conserve, sauvegarder, conserver, transmettre au public communicate to the public by par télécommunication ou par l'Internet, prêter, telecommunication or on the Internet, distribuer et vendre des thèses partout dans loan, distribute and sell th es es le monde, à des fins commerciales ou autres, worldwide, for commercial or non­ sur support microforme, papier, électronique commercial purposes, in microform, et/ou autres formats. paper, electronic and/or any other formats. The author retains copyright L'auteur conserve la propriété du droit d'auteur ownership and moral rights in et des droits moraux qui protège cette thèse. this thesis. Neither the thesis Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels de nor substantial extracts from it celle-ci ne doivent être imprimés ou autrement may be printed or otherwise reproduits sans son autorisation.
    [Show full text]