Introduction to the History of Modern Political Thought

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Introduction to the History of Modern Political Thought Istvan Hont Introduction to the History of Modern Poiiticai Thought: L From Locke to Hume Michelmas Term 1990, first four weeks Mondays and Wednesdays 10.00 History Faculty, West Road, (For History Trlpos Part I, Paper 19; Part II, Paper 3; and SPS Tripos Part II, Paper 17) [Part II of this course, 'Rousseau and Smith' will be given on Mondays and Wednesdays 10:00 In the second four weeks of Michaelmas 1990, Part III, 'From Kant to J.S. Mill' In Lent Term 1991, on Tuesdays and Thursdays 11:00] Schedule of lectures: 1./ 15 October, Monday: Introduction: The Idioms of Modern Political Thought 2./ 17 October, Wednesday: Locke: Property, Civilisation and Consent 3./ 22 October, Monday: Locke: The Legitimate Polity 4./ 24 October, Wednesday: Locke: Trust, Toleration and Resistance 5./ 29 October, Monday: Hume: Justice as an Artflclal Virtue 6./ 31 October, Wednesday: Hume: The Politics of Commercial Society 7./ 5 November, Monday: Montesquieu: The Spirit of the Laws and the Principles of Government 8./ 7 November, Wednesday: Montesquieu: Despotism, Civilisation and Doux Commerce Texts on which questions will be set in Section A of the Trioos papers: John Locke, Two Treatises of Government David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature. Book III. Montesquieu, The Soririt of Laws, trans, A. Cohler, B. Miller and H. Stone Past TriPOS Questions addressed to these texts f 1985-90): Locke Were Locke's Two Treatises self-contained and self-explanatory? What do Locke's argument for toleration tell us about his general political theory? 'One of the clearest legitimations of revolution In English political thought'. How far can this be said of Locke's Two Treatises^ What were the limits on revolutionary activity In the Two Treatises^ Can we elucidate Locke's arguments In the Two Treatises by studying his other works? What were the grounds for revolutionary activity In Locke's Two Treatise^ Why did Locke lay so much emphasis on the distinction between society and governmental power? Why did Locke make property so central to the argument of the Second TreatiseR Consider Locke's Two Treatises as an Intervention In the 'Exclusion Controversy'. Do you find Locke's elimination of consent from the explanation of the origin of Individual property convincing? Hume 'What corresponds In Hume's politics to his dislike of religion Is a distaste for all forms of political enthusiasm'. Discuss. 'Hume simply replaced the social contract with social conventions'. Discuss. What effect did Hume's atheism have on his political theory? What Is sceptical about Hume's political thinking? What Is the significance of Hume's claim that 'politics may be reduced to a science'? 8 Forbes, Duncan, 'Natural Law and the Scottish Enlightenment', in R.H.Campbell and A.S.Sklnner (eds.), ThQ Origins ami Nature of the Scottish Enlightenment. (Edinburgh, 1982), pp.186-204, Moore, James, 'The Two Systems of Francis Hutcheson: On the Origins of the Scottish Enlightenment' in M.A. Stewart (ed.). Studies In the Philosophy of the Scottish Enlightenment (Oxford, 1990), pp. 37-59. Haakonssen, Knud, 'Natural Law and the Scottish Enlightenment' in D. Jory and J.C. Stewart-Robertson (eds.), Man and Nature/ L'homme et la nature, vol. 4 (1985), pp. 47-80. Haakonssen, Knud, 'Natural Jurisprudence in the Scottish Enlightenment: Summary of an Interpretation' in D.N. MacCormick (ed.). Enlightenment. Rights and Revolutions (Aberdeen, 1989), pp. 36-49. Pocock, J.G.A., 'Virtues, rights, and manners: A model for historians of political thought' in Pocock, Virtue. Commerce and Libertv: Essavs on Political Thought and Historv. Chieflv in the Eighteenth Centurv (Cambridge, 1985), pp. 37-50. Pocock, J.G.A., 'Cambridge paradigms and Scotch philosophers: a study of the relation between the civic humanist anbd the civil jurisprudential interpretation of eighteenth-century social thought' in I. Hont and M. Ignatieff (eds.). Wealth and Virtue: THe Shaping of Political Economv in the Scottish Enlightenment (Cambridge, 1983), pp. 235-52. Mackie, J.L., Hume's Moral Theorv. (London, 1980), Chs. 4-7. Norton, David Fate, David Hume: Cpmmon Sense Moralist. Sceptical Metaphyalcian, (Princeton, 1982), Chs. 1-3, 5-6. Wright, John P., The Sceptical Realism of David Hume (Manchester, 12983), Ch. 5. Ardai, Pdll S., Passion and Value in Hume's "Treatise" (Edinburgh, 1966), Chs. 6-8. Livingston, Donald w., Hume's Philosophy of Common Lifa (Chicago, 1984), Chs. 7- 12. Phiilipson, Nicholas, 'Hume as a Moralist: A Social Historian's Perspective' in S. Brown (ed.). Philosophers of the Enlightenment (Hassock, Sussex, 1979), pp. 140- 61. James T. King, 'The Place of the Language of Morals in Hume's Second "Enquiry" in D.W.Livingston and J.T.King, Hume: A Re-Evaluation, (New York,1976), pp. 343- 61. Moore, James, 'Hume's Theory of Justice and Property', Political Studies 24(1976), 114-19. Harrison, Jonathan, Hume's Theorv of Justice. (Oxford, 1981) Whelan, Frederick G., Order and Artifice in Hume's Political Philosoohv (Princeton, 1985), Chs. 4-5. Cottle, Charles E., 'Justice as Artificial Virtue in Hume's "Treatise'". Journal of the Historv of Ideas. 40(1979), 457-66. Castiglione, Dario, 'Hume's conventionalist anaiysis of justice', Annali delia Fondazione Luiqi Einaudi. 21(1987), 139-73. King, James, 'Hume's Classical Theory of Justice', Hume Studies. 7(1981), 32-54. Gauthier, David, 'David Hume, Contractarian', Phiiosoohicai Review. 88(1979), 3-38. Hayek, F.A., 'The Legal and Political Philosophy of David Hume', In V.C.Chappell (ed.), Hume. (Garden City, N.J., 1966), pp.335-360 Dickinson, H.T., Libertv and Property: Political Ideoloqv in Eiqhteenth-Centurv Britain (London, 1977) Robertson, John, The Scottish Enlightenment and the Militia Issue (Edinburgh, 1985), Chs. 2-4. Wolin, Sheldon 8., 'Hume and Conservatlvism', in D.W.Livingston and J.T.King, Hume: A Re-Evaiuatlon. (New York, 1976), pp. 239-56. Adair, Douglass, '"That Politics May Be Reduced to a Science": David Hume, James Madison and the Tenth "Federalist"', in D.W.Livingston and J.T.King, Hume: A Re- Evaluation. (New York, 1976), pp.404-417 Pocock, J.G.A., 'Hume and the American Revolution: The Dying Thoughts of a North Briton', in Pocock, Virtue. Commerce and Liberty: Essays on Political Thought and History. Chieflv in the Eighteenth Century (Cambridge, 1985), pp. 125-142. Teichgraeber, Richard F., 'Free Trade' and Moral Philosophy: Rethinking the Sources of Adam Smith's "Wealth of Nations" (Durham, N.C., 1986), Ch. 3. Davie, George, 'Berkeley, Hume, and the Central Problem of Scottish Philosophy', in D.F.Norton, N.Capaidi and W.L.Robison (eds.), McGili Hume Studies. (San Diego, Austin Hill, 1979), pp.43-62 Popkin, Richard H., 'David Hume: His Pyrrhonism and His Critique of Pyrrhonism', in V.C.Chappeli, Hume. (Garden City, N.J., 1966), pp. 53-98 Barfoot, Michael, 'Hume and the Culture of Science in the Early Eighteenth Century' in M.A. Stewart (ed.). Studies in the Phiiosophv of the Scottish Enlightenment (Oxford, 1990), pp. 151-90. Popkin, Richard H., 'Hume: Philosophical Versus Prophetic Historian' in K.R. Merrii and R.W. Shahan (eds.), David Hume: Manv-sided Genius (Norman, Oklahoma, 1976), pp. 83-95. Haakonssen, Knud, The Science of a Legislator: The Natural Jurisprudence of David Hume and Adam Smith (Cambridge, 1981), Ch. 2. Miller, David, Philosophy and Ideology in Hume'g Political Thought, (Oxford, 1981) Mossner, E.C., The Life of David Hume (Oxford, 1970) Montesquieu Shkiar, Judith N., Montesquieu (Oxford, 1987) 10 Keohane, Nannerl O., Philosophy and the State in France: The Renaissance to the Enlightenment (Princeton, 1980), Ch. 14. Hirschmann, Albert O., The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism before Its Triumph (Princeton, 1977). Berlin, Isaiah, 'Montesquieu' in Berlin, Against the Current: Essavs in the History of Ideas (Oxford, 1981), pp. 130-161. Plamenatz, John, 'Montesquieu' in Plamenatz, Man and Society, vol. 1 (London, 1963), pp. 253-298. Cranston, Maurice, 'Montesquieu' in Cranston, Philosophers and Pamphleteers: Political Theorists of the Enlightenment (Oxford, 1986), pp. 9-35. Shackleton, Robert, Montesquieu: A Critical Biography (Oxford, 1961) Pangle, Thomas L., Montesouieiu's Philosophy of Liberalism: A Commentary on 'The Spirit Of the Laws'(Chicago, 1973). Baker, Keith M., 'Public Opinion as Political Invention' in Baker, Inventing the French Revolution: Essays on French Political Culture inb the Eighteenth Century (Cambridge, 1990), pp. 167-99. Ellis, Harold E., 'Montesquieu's Modern Politics: "The Spirit of the Laws" and the Problem of Modern Monarchy in Old Regime France', History of Political Thought 10(1989), 665-700. Keohane, Nanneri O., 'Virtuous Republics and Glorious Monarchies: Two Models in Montesquieu's Political Thought', Political Studies 20(1972), 383-96. Price, E.H., 'Voltai re and Montesquieu's Three Principles of Government', Publications of the Modern Language Association 57(1942), 1046-52. Richter, Melvin, 'Despotism' in P.H. Wiener (ed.). Dictionary of the History of Ideas, vol. 2 (New York, 1973), pp. 1-18. Richter, Melvin, 'Montesquieu, the Politics of Language, and the Language of Polities', Historv of Political Thought 10(1989), 71-88. Hundert, E.J. and Nelles, P., 'Liberty and Theatrical Space in Montesquieu's Political Theory: THe Poetics of Public Life in "The Persian Letters'", Political Theory 17(1989), 223-46. Riley, Patrick, The General Will Before Rousseau: The Transformation of the Divine into the civio (Princeton, 1986), ch. 4. Althusser, Louis, 'Montesquieu: Politics and History' in Aithusser, Politics and Historv: Montesquieu. Rousseau. Hegel and Marx, trans. B. Brewster (London, 1972), pp. 9-109. Manicas, P.T., 'Montesquieu and the Eighteenth-Century Vision of the State', Historv of Political Thought 2(1981), 313-17. Huiiiung, Mark, Montesquieu and the Old Regime (Berkeley, 1976). Waddicor, Mark H., Montesquieu and the Philosophy of Natural Law (The Hague, 1970). 11 Baum, Alan, Montesquieu and Social Theory (Oxford, 1979) Rosow, Stephen J., 'Commerce, Power and Justice: Montesquieu on International Polities', Review of Politics 46(1984), 346-66.
Recommended publications
  • HUME and MILL on "UTILITY of RELIGION": a BORGEAN GARDEN of FORKING PATHS?L
    TEAO~ Reuista Iberoamericana de Estudios Utilitaristas-2005, XlVII: 117-129 ISSN 1132-0877 HUME AND MILL ON "UTILITY OF RELIGION": A BORGEAN GARDEN OF FORKING PATHS?l JOSE L. TASSET2 University ofA Coruiia ABSTRACT This work is not a specific assessment of Utility ofReligion by John Stuart Mill, but a defence of what I think is a utilitarian, but not millian, view on the problem that work states, the question of the utility of religion in contemporary societies. I construct that view from neohumeanism more than from millian positions, notwithstanding, I postulate that view as a genuine utilitarian one. Every cultural tradition makes a different approach to ethical and political theories. Spanish and Ibero-American utilitarians make precisely it with Clas­ sical Utilitarianism. From that point of view, Ibero-American people identifies utilitarianism with radical and enlightened tradition linked with the reform that through XVIIIth and XIXth centuries tried to undermine the foundations of conservative society in our nations. This aim was not achieved, at least not completely; because of that, the pursuit of Utilitarianism remains opened between us. In the end,I will argue that Spanish and Ibero-American utilitarians connect utilitarianism with philosophical and political radicalism, and inside that His­ panic utilitarianism, plays an important role the criticism of social and political functions of Religion. Maybe, part of the future of Utilitarianism in our cultural context depends on a return of the Theory to its radical roots, also in religious subjects. Keywords: J ohn Stuart Mill, David Hume, Jorge Luis Borges, religion, deism, theism, functionalism, truth. RESUMEN Este trabajo no pretende ser una evaluaci6n especifica de la Utilidad de la Religi6n de John Stuart Mill, sino una defensa de 10 que creo es una posici6n 1 Date of acceptance: 26/07/2006.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy.Pdf
    Philosophy 1 PHIL:1401 Matters of Life and Death 3 s.h. Contemporary ethical controversies with life and death Philosophy implications; topics may include famine, brain death, animal ethics, abortion, torture, terrorism, capital punishment. GE: Chair Values and Culture. • David Cunning PHIL:1636 Principles of Reasoning: Argument and Undergraduate major: philosophy (B.A.) Debate 3 s.h. Undergraduate minor: philosophy Critical thinking and its application to arguments and debates. Graduate degrees: M.A. in philosophy; Ph.D. in philosophy GE: Quantitative or Formal Reasoning. Faculty: https://clas.uiowa.edu/philosophy/people/faculty PHIL:1861 Introduction to Philosophy 3 s.h. Website: https://clas.uiowa.edu/philosophy/ Varied topics; may include personal identity, existence of The Department of Philosophy offers programs of study for God, philosophical skepticism, nature of mind and reality, undergraduate and graduate students. A major in philosophy time travel, and the good life; readings, films. GE: Values and develops abilities useful for careers in many fields and for any Culture. situation requiring clear, systematic thinking. PHIL:1902 Philosophy Lab: The Meaning of Life 1 s.h. Further exploration of PHIL:1033 course material with the The department also administers the interdisciplinary professor in a smaller group. undergraduate major in ethics and public policy, which it offers jointly with the Department of Economics and the PHIL:1904 Philosophy Lab: Liberty and the Pursuit of Department of Sociology and Criminology; see Ethics and Happiness 1 s.h. Public Policy in the Catalog. Further exploration of PHIL:1034 course material with the professor in a smaller group. Programs PHIL:1950 Philosophy Club 1-3 s.h.
    [Show full text]
  • A Rationalist Argument for Libertarian Free Will
    A rationalist argument for libertarian free will Stylianos Panagiotou PhD University of York Philosophy August 2020 Abstract In this thesis, I give an a priori argument in defense of libertarian free will. I conclude that given certain presuppositions, the ability to do otherwise is a necessary requirement for substantive rationality; the ability to think and act in light of reasons. ‘Transcendental’ arguments to the effect that determinism is inconsistent with rationality are predominantly forwarded in a Kantian manner. Their incorporation into the framework of critical philosophy renders the ontological status of their claims problematic; rather than being claims about how the world really is, they end up being claims about how the mind must conceive of it. To make their ontological status more secure, I provide a rationalist framework that turns them from claims about how the mind must view the world into claims about the ontology of rational agents. In the first chapter, I make some preliminary remarks about reason, reasons and rationality and argue that an agent’s access to alternative possibilities is a necessary condition for being under the scope of normative reasons. In the second chapter, I motivate rationalism about a priori justification. In the third chapter, I present the rationalist argument for libertarian free will and defend it against objections. Several objections rest on a compatibilist understanding of an agent’s abilities. To undercut them, I devote the fourth chapter, in which I give a new argument for incompatibilism between free will and determinism, which I call the situatedness argument for incompatibilism. If the presuppositions of the thesis are granted and the situatedness argument works, then we may be justified in thinking that to the extent that we are substantively rational, we are free in the libertarian sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Retreat : a Play in Two Acts 35057008493487 PHILOSOPHY-IN-DRAMA SERIES
    PHILOSOPHY IN DRAMA SERIES MA INC PS 8579 C66 P62 2002 O'Connell, Sean, 1944- Plato's retreat : a play in two acts 35057008493487 PHILOSOPHY-IN-DRAMA SERIES VOLUME V PLATO'S RETREAT FORTHCOMING IN THIS SERIES: VOLUME III Neecheemoos and Inuspi VOLUME IV Winter at Delphi PREVIOUSLY PUBLISHED: VOLUME I Cartesian Dreams VOLUME II Lives and Evils Of MI-MI miiiwu Copyright registered © 2002 by Phi-Psi Publishers. All rights reserved. Except for briefpassages quoted in reviews, no portion of this publication may be reproduced, transmitted, or performed in any manner whatsoever without written consent of the publisher. A play is performed whenever it is acted out for audiences, live or on film or on video, whether or not admission is charged. This book may not be resold or loaned-for-hire. Library loans do not constitute loans for hire. Address all inquiries to: Permissions Phi-Psi Publishers Box 75198, Ritchie P.O. Edmonton, Alberta, Canada T6E 6K1 Canadian Cataloguing in Publication Data O'Connell, Sean, 1944- Plato's retreat A play. (Philosophy-in-drama series; 5) ISBN 0-9686685-2-6 1. Plato. Republic-Drama. I. Title II. Series: O'Connell, Sean, 1944- Philosophy-in-drama series; 5 PS8579.C66P62 2001 C812'.6 C2001-911302-1 PR9199.3.Q3175P62 2001 Designer: Marcey Andrews Production Manager: Marcey Andrews Marketing Director: Patricia Sweet Printing and Binding: Dial Printing Inc., Swarm Enterprises Front cover art: Kallipolis. R. Mitchell Crozier. 8 112"x 11 " (Pen on paper) PRINTED IN CANADJ fnl-Ml BtUJUtlJ PLATO'S RETREAT A PLAY IN TWO ACTS by SEAN O'CONNELL CONTENTS PREFACE TO THE SERIES 1 INTRODUCTION 15 PLATO'S RETREAT39 ACT ONE Scene One *1 Scene Two 85 Scene Three ACT TWO Scene One 155 Scene Two 159 Scene Three 195 Scene Four 215 HUD'S JinlOT PHIL0S0PHY-IN-DRAIY1A LEARNING SERIES Volume V PREFACE TO THE SERIES The first great Western Philosopher and one to whom all others bow—if not in agreement then at least with reverence—wrote nearly all his works in quasi-dramatic form.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz: the Last Great Christian Platonist
    chapter 3 Leibniz: The Last Great Christian Platonist Jack Davidson Many of the Platonic doctrines are … most beautiful.1 ∵ Leibniz (1646–1716) was the last great philosopher in the rich tradition of Christian Platonism that began before Augustine (354–430) and ran through Pseudo-Dionysius (early sixth century), John Scottus Eriugena (c. 800– c. 877), Anselm (1033–1109), Nicholas of Cusa (1401–64) and Marsilio Ficino’s (1433–1499) Florentine Academy. With the advent of figures like John Locke (1632–1704), David Hume (1711–1776), Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778) and Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), philosophy became both mundane and largely secular. This chapter focuses on the most influential of the 17th-century German Platonists, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. As anyone who knows of the history of Platonism from Plato onward realizes, classifying Leibniz as a Platonist is to place him in the company of philosophers who hold (sometimes wildly) different views, so some specifi- cation is necessary. These days, “Platonism” is used by scholars of ancient philosophy to describe what they take to be actual doctrines in the Platonic canon, doctrines Plato developed or continued to hold in the dialogues after the early, Socratic dialogues, e.g., the theory of the Forms.2 In contemporary metaphysics, “Platonism” refers to the view that certain abstract truths, like those of mathematics and logic, exist independently of time and space and human thought. Frege, Gödel, and Russell were all Platonists in this sense, as 1 D ii 222/l 592. Leibniz citations in the text and notes are by abbreviation keyed to the bibli- ography.
    [Show full text]
  • David Hume Foundations of the Classical School of Economics
    Economic Insights FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF DALLAS VOLUME 8, NUMBER 1 David Hume Foundations of the Classical School of Economics Adam Smith is the founder of the nomic essays] are all clearly written classical school of economics, but eco- and often contain an excellent sum- nomic theorizing predates Smith. The mary and synthesis of the ideas of his philosophic foundations of classical eco- predecessors. In that respect, how- nomics are found in the work of the ever, Cantillon’s Essai sur la nature Scottish Enlightenment thinkers of the du commerce en général, published early to mid-18th century, centered in 1755, but written over twenty years David Hume is primarily known as around the University of Edinburgh. previously, is superior. a philosopher and chronicler of English Notable among these great thinkers and writers is David Hume. It is impossible to know whether history. Less well known is his work on eco- Hume was born in Edinburgh, Smith was more influenced by Can- nomic theory and several political econ- Scotland, on May 7, 1711. The extent to tillon’s book or by personal discussions which Hume influenced Smith, his close with Hume. Schumpeter (1954, 124) omy issues, some of which remain salient friend, has to be inferred from their argues that Hume did influence Smith, today. Studying his economic work respective writings, but the warmth and and Rothbard (1995, 430) suggests that depth of their relationship is incon- Hume was one of Smith’s mentors. enables us to see how he reshaped John testable. Smith said of Hume: O’Brien (1975) gives Hume a large role Locke’s quantity theory of money and how in the development of classical econom- Upon the whole, I have always con- ic thought because of his participation he influenced the great Adam Smith, sidered him, both in his lifetime and in spreading natural law philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Rock of Atheism’
    Navigating around Hume’s ‘Rock of Atheism’ by Mike Tonks, Second Master, Shrewsbury School Published in ‘Dialogue: A journal of religion and philosophy’, issue 49, November 2017 _______________________________________________________________________________ Before starting work this morning I decided to check the BBC website to see what the main news headlines were. Exploring further I found myself confronted by numerous illustrations of what ‘philosophers of religion’ might call ‘The Problem of Evil.’ The inescapable truth is that the human condition is punctuated by suffering. At least twenty people had been killed in a bomb attack in Bangkok. The refugee crisis continued in many areas of Europe including France, Italy and Macedonia. Another headline reported the establishment of a new enquiry into child abuse in the Roman Catholic Church of Scotland. A tornado had struck the southern coast of Mexico, fires blazed out of control on the Idaho / Oregon border and a state of emergency had been declared in Ecuador due to growing activity in the Cotopaxi volcano. Reading these and many other similar accounts a question presents itself – ‘Are such events necessary and inevitable?’ Can one imagine a world without such brutality, pain and torment? And perhaps most challenging of all, does this world present itself as the creative work of a supremely perfect, powerful and benevolent personal deity who enjoys a loving relationship with all of his creation? Welcome to the study of what ‘philosophers of religion’ refer to as The Problem of Evil! There is an enormous amount of material available on this topic and therefore part of the challenge at ‘A’ Level lies in establishing a structured approach to your investigations.
    [Show full text]
  • Bentham and the Scots J.H
    UCL Bentham Project Journal of Bentham Studies, vol. 7 (2004) Bentham and the Scots J.H. Burns Emeritus Professor of History, University College London What I have to offer here is not so much a paper as some scraps of paper. These represent, on the whole, the result of enquiries on which I have embarked at various times, but which I have not pursued rigorously to their appropriate conclusions. Nor does it now seem likely that I shall ever do so. To some extent, therefore, what I am presenting is an agenda of unfinished business, in the hope that some of the themes I have partially discussed will seem to others to be worth taking further. To this I must add that, even if this were a paper rather than a scrapbook, it would still be an imperfectly structured and incomplete paper. I shall present, to some extent, the beginning of the story and the end – though I shall, perversely, reverse their chronological order. The middle, however, will be all but completely missing. This is because my explorations, such as they have been, have never taken me beyond the threshold of Bentham’s Scotch Reform writings, which ought clearly to constitute the missing part of the story, falling as they do in that middle ground between the Bentham of the radical Enlightenment and the Bentham of philosophical radicalism. One more preliminary point before I begin – at the end.1 One reason for raising this subject at all is, I suggest, that there is something of a paradox to be considered.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume on the Nature of Moral Freedom
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy Summer 7-11-2012 Hume on the Nature of Moral Freedom Getty L. Lustila Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Recommended Citation Lustila, Getty L., "Hume on the Nature of Moral Freedom." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2012. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/118 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HUME ON THE NATURE OF MORAL FREEDOM by GETTY L. LUSTILA Under the Direction of Eric E. Wilson ABSTRACT Paul Russell argues that the interpretation of Hume as a classical compatibilist is misguided. Russell defends a naturalistic reading of Humean freedom and moral responsibility. On this account, Hume holds two theses: that moral responsibility is a product of our moral sentiments, and that our concept of moral freedom is derived from our considerations of moral responsibility. Russell claims that Hume’s theory of the passions is non-cognitivist, and thus that his account of moral judgment fails to distinguish between voluntary and involuntary actions or qualities of mind. He concludes that Hume’s account of moral responsibility is inadequate. I argue that Hume has a cognitivist account of the passions. For Hume, our character is judged to be a proper object of praise or censure on account of our ability to partake in a moral community with our fellows.
    [Show full text]
  • David Hume's Reductionist Epistemology of Testimony
    DAVID HUME’S REDUCTIONIST EPISTEMOLOGY OF TESTIMONY Paul Faulkner –––––––––– ABSTRACT David Hume advances a reductionist epistemology of testimony: testimonial beliefs are justified on the basis of beliefs formed from other sources. This reduction, however, has been misunderstood. Testimonial beliefs are not justified in a manner identical to ordinary empirical beliefs; it is true, they are justified by observation of the conjunction between testimony and its truth, it is the nature of the conjunctions that has been misunderstood. The observation of these conjunctions provides us with our knowledge of human nature and it is this knowledge which justifies our testimonial beliefs. Hume gives a naturalistic rather than sceptical account of testimony. –––––––––– Testimony is a unique source of belief. It is unique in the sense that many of our beliefs have been formed only through accepting testimony. Examples are easy to enumerate; my belief that a major ocean current flows from the Gulf of Mexico to North-West Europe and my belief that there have been two World Wars this century both depend on testimony. I have not seen the entire passage of the North Atlantic Drift. Nor do I remember the 1 Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, December 1998, vol. 79, no. 4, pp. 302-313. __________________________________________________________________ catastrophic events that were World War One and Two. It is equally clear that testimony is a unique source of knowledge. Again, unique in the sense that much of our knowledge has been acquired only through accepting testimony. Unless one is to propose a revisionary account of what it is to know, I do not merely believe that there is a major ocean current flowing from the Gulf of Mexico to North-West Europe but I know that there is.
    [Show full text]
  • David Hume: the Making of a Philosophical Historian
    David Hume: The Making of a Philosophical Historian A Reconsideration Moritz Baumstark Ph.D The University of Edinburgh 2007 DECLARATION The present PhD thesis has been composed by myself alone and represents my own work, which has not been submitted for any other degree or qualification. ______________________________ Moritz Baumstark ABSTRACT OF THESIS The thesis is concerned with the exploration of the interconnections between philosophy and history in David Hume’s work and seeks to provide a reassessment of his remarkable transition from metaphysical philosopher and polite essayist to philosophical and narrative historian. The first part of the thesis puts forth a detailed reappraisal of Hume’s intellectual preoccupations and literary pursuits in the crucial but neglected period 1748-1752, a period that witnessed Hume’s tour of several European courts in 1748, his intensive reading of the classics and his engagement with Montesquieu’s new system of socio-political analysis. These years saw a decisive shift in Hume’s thinking about human nature that resulted in an increasing emphasis on its historicity. It is argued that this helps to explain his growing insistence on the necessity of accounting for the varied manifestations of human nature in different historical periods by a reconstruction of the social, political and economical conditions of past societies as well as their customs, manners and belief systems. It is furthermore argued that Hume’s new holistic view of past civilisations found its expression in a number of diverse pieces which can be read as fragments of a cultural history of classical antiquity and contain an important agenda for a new kind of cultural history.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine on Testimony
    c Peter King and Nathan Ballantyne, forthcoming in the Canadian Journal of Philosophy. AUGUSTINE ON TESTIMONY Philosophical work on testimony has flourished in recent years. Testi- mony roughly involves a source affirming or stating something in an attempt to transfer information to one or more persons. It is often said that the topic of testimony has been neglected throughout most of the history of philoso- phy, aside from contributions by David Hume (–) and Thomas Reid (–).1 True as this may be, Hume and Reid aren’t the only ones who deserve a tip of the hat for recognizing the importance of testimony: Augus- tine of Hippo (–) affirms the place of testimony in human cognition, at least in his later writings. In what follows, we consider three questions raised by Augustine’s think- ing about testimony: the analytical question of what sources count as testi- mony (§); the epistemological question about the status of testimony-based belief (§); and the doxastic question about the circumstances in which it is appropriate to believe on the basis of testimony (§). We outline Augustine’s view of testimony by examining his answers to these three questions. Finally, we’ll briefly situate Augustine within the tradition of thinking about testimony (§), by way of conclusion. A few preliminaries. Augustine occasionally uses ‘testimonia’ to talk about one thing being a sign for another thing. For example, Augustine remarks that a Stoic philosopher’s pallor during heavy seas testified to his fear (ciu. .).2 This isn’t the philosophically interesting sort of testimony; any sign would ‘testify’ to its significate in this sense.
    [Show full text]