David Hume Foundations of the Classical School of Economics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

David Hume Foundations of the Classical School of Economics Economic Insights FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF DALLAS VOLUME 8, NUMBER 1 David Hume Foundations of the Classical School of Economics Adam Smith is the founder of the nomic essays] are all clearly written classical school of economics, but eco- and often contain an excellent sum- nomic theorizing predates Smith. The mary and synthesis of the ideas of his philosophic foundations of classical eco- predecessors. In that respect, how- nomics are found in the work of the ever, Cantillon’s Essai sur la nature Scottish Enlightenment thinkers of the du commerce en général, published early to mid-18th century, centered in 1755, but written over twenty years David Hume is primarily known as around the University of Edinburgh. previously, is superior. a philosopher and chronicler of English Notable among these great thinkers and writers is David Hume. It is impossible to know whether history. Less well known is his work on eco- Hume was born in Edinburgh, Smith was more influenced by Can- nomic theory and several political econ- Scotland, on May 7, 1711. The extent to tillon’s book or by personal discussions which Hume influenced Smith, his close with Hume. Schumpeter (1954, 124) omy issues, some of which remain salient friend, has to be inferred from their argues that Hume did influence Smith, today. Studying his economic work respective writings, but the warmth and and Rothbard (1995, 430) suggests that depth of their relationship is incon- Hume was one of Smith’s mentors. enables us to see how he reshaped John testable. Smith said of Hume: O’Brien (1975) gives Hume a large role Locke’s quantity theory of money and how in the development of classical econom- Upon the whole, I have always con- ic thought because of his participation he influenced the great Adam Smith, sidered him, both in his lifetime and in spreading natural law philosophy. Hume’s close friend and fellow Scottish since his death, as approaching as On the question of self-interest’s nearly to the idea of a perfectly wise role in human affairs, Hume seems to Enlightenment philosopher. Hume is one and virtuous man as perhaps the have influenced Smith greatly. For of the pillars of the classical school of eco- nature of human frailty will admit. Hume, and for much of the Western (Goldberg 1961) world after him, self-interest became the nomics, primarily founded by Smith. This primary motivating force that explained issue of Economic Insights offers some of Like Smith, Hume tried to use Isaac most of social reality (Herman 2001, Newton’s method of analysis in his in- 170). Hume’s early book expounding Hume’s economic theorizing for those who quiries. Hume also borrowed from phi- his idea of self-interest, A Treatise of want to pursue the intellectual history of losopher John Locke’s epistemology as Human Nature (1734), may have cost he related mostly moral concerns. Hume him a university teaching position. The modern economic theory. saw such moral concerns as the thread work so horrified other philosophers that connected his various writings, that some—notably Francis Hutcheson— — Bob McTeer which included political economy. actively sought to deny him such a pos- President While we shouldn’t overemphasize ition. He later repudiated this first Federal Reserve Bank of Dallas Hume’s economic influence on Smith, book. However, this was not the last their relationship—especially in light time Hume offended prevailing sensi- of the similarities of some of their bilities and challenged majority opinion analyses—is intriguing. As Roll (1953, on an issue. 117–18) writes: Hume’s view that self-interest could be channeled profitably only through In recent years the tendency has even economic cooperation and competi- arisen to regard him [Hume] as the tion—making civil society a possibility most important of the pre-Smithian so long as the rule of law prevailed— economists….[T]hey [Hume’s eco- was a pillar of Smith’s thinking as well. In this regard, Hume’s influence on erally pro-free trade and antimercan- automatically adjusts international trad- Smith is both clear and profound. Gov- tilist. Because of his extreme skepticism ing partners’ domestic price levels. As ernment is required, they argued, be- and presumed atheism, as well as his such, its intellectual lineage comes di- cause instinct may cause people to act view of human nature, academe was rectly from the quantity theory of against their interests, even though closed to him. He pursued instead a money—traceable back to Locke—as it they are driven primarily by those self- career in public life, traveling for tutor- was applied to international trade bal- interests (Rotwein 1987, 693). ing positions, becoming British chargé ances. Philosophers see Hume as a direct d’affaires in Paris and eventually Hume’s economic writings were link between the empiricist political becoming undersecretary of state. He usually concerned with the idea of eco- philosophy of Locke, the French lais- retired from public life in 1769 and nomic growth and its causes, perhaps sez-faire Physiocratic movement led by returned to Edinburgh. another example of an intellectual Francois Quesnay and early British pol- Hume’s most important foray into focus that he bequeathed to Smith. itical economy. Hume’s economic economic theory was his discussion of Hume was sometimes inconsistent in views overlapped both the mercantilist the price-specie-flow mechanism. The his economic theorizing. In one place and classical traditions, depending on movement of specie (gold and silver) he might praise the growth of the the topic he addressed, but were gen- between countries balances trade and money supply, while in another he would correctly show that larger sup- plies of money lead to rising prices. Smith might also have taken from Public Debt: Does Anything Ever Really Change? Hume the deeply flawed labor theory of value, as Hume routinely argued that But though the injury that arises to commerce and industry from our public funds will appear, only labor conveyed value. On bal- upon balancing the whole, not inconsiderable, it is trivial in comparison of the prejudice that results ance, Hume favored “hard money”— to a state considered as a body politic, which must support itself in the society of nations, and have that is, money made of precious metals various transactions with other states in wars and negotiations. The ill there is pure and unmixed, that had “intrinsic value.” He also seemed without any favorable circumstance to atone for it; and it is an ill too of a nature the highest and to support ultrasound banking, as when most important. We have indeed been told, that the public is no weaker on account of its debts, since they are he praised the Bank of Amsterdam for mostly due among ourselves, and bring as much property to one as they take from another. It is its policy of 100 percent specie-backed like transferring money from the right hand to the left, which leaves the person neither richer nor deposit reserves (Rothbard 1995, 428). poorer than before. Such loose reasoning and specious comparisons will always pass where we While arguing that an increase in judge not upon principles. I ask, Is it possible, in the nature of things, to overburden a nation with the money supply is neutral regarding taxes, even where the sovereign resides among them? The very doubt seems extravagant, since it the rate of interest, he also concluded is requisite, in every community, that there be a certain proportion observed between the laborious that, in the long run, such a continuing and the idle part of it. But if all our present taxes be mortgaged, must we not invent new ones? And increase might actually lower the inter- may not this matter be carried to a length that is ruinous and destructive? est rate. Although Hume had insights In every nation there are always some methods of levying money more easy than others, into many important economic issues, agreeably to the way of living of the people, and the commodities they make use of…. Duties upon his analysis was primarily one of com- consumptions are more equal and easy than duties upon possessions. What a loss to the public that the former are all exhausted, and that we must have recourse to the more grievous method of parative statics, or examinations of levying taxes!… equilibrium positions. He seldom dis- It will scarcely be asserted, that no bounds ought ever to be set to national debts, and that the cussed in detail the microeconomic public would be no weaker were twelve or fifteen shillings in the pound, land-tax, mortgaged, with adjustment processes that occur be- all the present customs and excises. There is something, therefore, in the case, beside the mere tween these equilibria, with the excep- transferring of property from the one hand to another. In five hundred years, the posterity of those tion of his essay Of Money. now in the coaches, and of those upon the boxes, will probably have changed places, without affect- Smith’s analysis of economic ing the public by these revolutions….The funds, created and mortgaged, will by that time bring in growth and society owes a great deal a large yearly revenue, sufficient for the defense and security of the nation: money is perhaps lying to his having read Hume’s massive The in the exchequer, ready for the discharge of the quarterly interest: necessity calls, fear urges, rea- History of England. Hume wrote the son exhorts, compassion alone exclaims: the money will immediately be seized for the current ser- four-volume work between 1754 and vice, under the most solemn protestations, perhaps of being immediately replaced.
Recommended publications
  • Ayn Rand? Ayn Rand Ayn
    Who Is Ayn Rand? Ayn Rand Few 20th century intellectuals have been as influential—and controversial— as the novelist and philosopher Ayn Rand. Her thinking still has a profound impact, particularly on those who come to it through her novels, Atlas Shrugged and The Fountainhead—with their core messages of individualism, self-worth, and the right to live without the impositions of others. Although ignored or scorned by some academics, traditionalists, pro- gressives, and public intellectuals, her thought remains a major influence on Ayn Rand many of the world’s leading legislators, policy advisers, economists, entre- preneurs, and investors. INTRODUCTION AN Why does Rand’s work remain so influential? Ayn Rand: An Introduction illuminates Rand’s importance, detailing her understanding of reality and human nature, and explores the ongoing fascination with and debates about her conclusions on knowledge, morality, politics, economics, government, AN INTRODUCTION public issues, aesthetics and literature. The book also places these in the context of her life and times, showing how revolutionary they were, and how they have influenced and continue to impact public policy debates. EAMONN BUTLER is director of the Adam Smith Institute, a leading think tank in the UK. He holds degrees in economics and psychology, a PhD in philosophy, and an honorary DLitt. A former winner of the Freedom Medal of Freedom’s Foundation at Valley Forge and the UK National Free Enterprise Award, Eamonn is currently secretary of the Mont Pelerin Society. Butler is the author of many books, including introductions on the pioneering economists Eamonn Butler Adam Smith, Milton Friedman, F.
    [Show full text]
  • The British Empiricism Locke, Berkeley and Hume
    The British Empiricism Locke, Berkeley and Hume copyleft: nicolazuin.2018 | nowxhere.wordpress.com 1 The problem of knowledge • Please, look out of the window (or into the box, or just in front of you…) and answer the following questions: ‣ What do you see? ‣ Are you sure that what you see is what truly exists out there? ‣ What do you know about it? ‣ How do you know it? ‣ What make you sure of it? • Here you are: this is the problem of knowledge! • Now try to formalise it in a single question or definition. copyleft:nicolazuin.2018 | nowxhere.wordpress.com 1 A long way behind In a certain way, we could say that the problem of knowledge is the problem of philosophy itself, since its birth. • Think for example on this quotations: Parmenides: «the same thing is for thinking as is for being” Eraclitus: «The things of which there is sight, hearing, experience, I prefer». (But he also says: «Poor witnesses for men are their eyes and ears if they have barbarian souls» Gorgia: «Nothing exists; Even if something exists, nothing can be known about it; and Even if something can be known about it, knowledge about it can't be communicated to others. Even if it can be communicated, it cannot be understood». • Or try to imagine the discussion between Plato and Aristotle in the famous Raffaello’s School of Athens. • Now try to build a mind-map of all the different answers to the problem of knowledge given by the philosophers you already know copyleft:nicolazuin.2018 | nowxhere.wordpress.com 2 The terrible heritage of Descartes: The modern problem of knowledge originates from the conclusions of Descartes’s research, which was inspired by the successful advancement of geometry and natural sciences and was aimed to find a certain knowledge for philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Essential ADAM SMITH ADAM SMITH the Essential
    The Essential The Essential ADAM SMITH ADAM SMITH The Essential Udetiort elintrem popteride fac re nostemusa porae tem in te iaes moves- cid nequastil viliu menatiae te pris. Ips, quiusus er que fuidemquon supica; novero etidemusque cae, Cationsus ad Caticatus opultilius et; nes mante nonsulo sultilina comnitem praveriae fore cla nihi, Ti. Em tem inam num, nes SMITH ADAM conte curnit? Mulus. Evitem sis? Opiordica dit. Go es voltum omanunc iam nox maximil conduconiam. Quo voludem iam dientru ntuscru deperfe rcereo, quideme catiam tem potala restra? Quiderniu conem cone cones nonsum optis conorbit. Nem hostiquo elicon ac mored ina, pracia vitra prariciam Romnora torum, me etres hoca in rehenih iliemus rendam quam ret; Cupionf erorunum opublie ndemus erferfex none curem denatanum is cripio conem et, con dem tabenat icerei consilius, untem morit, paturaetrum te periosti publicus praecero ius fecte consis, que iae nos esse consustrunt. James Otteson by James Otteson Copyright © by the Fraser Institute. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission except in the case of brief quotations embodied in critical articles and reviews. Th e author of this publication has worked independently and opinions expressed by him are, therefore, his own, and do not necessarily refl ect the opinions of the Fraser Institute or its supporters, directors, or staff . Th is publication in no way implies that the Fraser Institute, its directors, or staff are in favour of, or oppose the passage of, any bill; or that they support or oppose any particular political party or candidate.
    [Show full text]
  • Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition
    volume 19, no. 45 erfectionist ethical theories ground moral demands in the per- october 2019 fection or full realization of one’s essential nature.1 Perfection- P ism has a rich history. Perfectionist ideas can be found in Aristo- tle, the Stoics, Maimonides, Aquinas, Malebranche, Spinoza, Leibniz, von Humboldt, J. S. Mill, F. H. Bradley, T. H. Green, Nietzsche, and Marx, among others. Though individual perfectionist figures have received significant attention, their perfectionism has not always enjoyed the Normative Perfectionism same focus. Perfectionism has not been studied thoroughly as a dis- tinctive tradition, and it remains a neglected option in contemporary moral and political philosophy.2 This neglect may reflect doubts about the justification, content, and implications of perfectionist ideals. and the Kantian Tradition Different conceptions of perfectionism result from different con- ceptions of human nature. Some perfectionists and their critics un- derstand human nature as a biological kind. However, that conception of perfectionism gives rise to legitimate foundational doubts about whether there is anything substantive that is essential to human na- ture and whether, if there is, it would be normatively compelling. A different strand in the perfectionist tradition grounds perfectionist ide- als in a normative conception of human nature as involving personal- ity or agency. Normative perfectionism is a distinctive conception within 1. An earlier version of this material was presented at Sheffield University as part of a 2014 conference on Post-Kantian Perfectionism; a 2015 University of Pennsylvania conference on Ancient and Modern Conceptions of Happiness; David O. Brink Ohio and St. Louis Universities; a 2016 UCSD conference, Perfectionism: Ancient and Modern; the Chinese University of Hong Kong; and the 2019 University of California San Diego Pacific Division Meetings of the APA.
    [Show full text]
  • Life with Augustine
    Life with Augustine ...a course in his spirit and guidance for daily living By Edmond A. Maher ii Life with Augustine © 2002 Augustinian Press Australia Sydney, Australia. Acknowledgements: The author wishes to acknowledge and thank the following people: ► the Augustinian Province of Our Mother of Good Counsel, Australia, for support- ing this project, with special mention of Pat Fahey osa, Kevin Burman osa, Pat Codd osa and Peter Jones osa ► Laurence Mooney osa for assistance in editing ► Michael Morahan osa for formatting this 2nd Edition ► John Coles, Peter Gagan, Dr. Frank McGrath fms (Brisbane CEO), Benet Fonck ofm, Peter Keogh sfo for sharing their vast experience in adult education ► John Rotelle osa, for granting us permission to use his English translation of Tarcisius van Bavel’s work Augustine (full bibliography within) and for his scholarly advice Megan Atkins for her formatting suggestions in the 1st Edition, that have carried over into this the 2nd ► those generous people who have completed the 1st Edition and suggested valuable improvements, especially Kath Neehouse and friends at Villanova College, Brisbane Foreword 1 Dear Participant Saint Augustine of Hippo is a figure in our history who has appealed to the curiosity and imagination of many generations. He is well known for being both sinner and saint, for being a bishop yet also a fellow pilgrim on the journey to God. One of the most popular and attractive persons across many centuries, his influence on the church has continued to our current day. He is also renowned for his influ- ence in philosophy and psychology and even (in an indirect way) art, music and architecture.
    [Show full text]
  • API-119: Advanced Macroeconomics for the Open Economy I, Fall 2020
    Sep 1, 2020 API-119: Advanced Macroeconomics for the Open Economy I, Fall 2020 Harvard Kennedy School Course Syllabus: prospectus, outline/schedule and readings Staff: Professor: Jeffrey Frankel [email protected] Faculty Assistant: Minoo Ghoreishi [email protected] Teaching Fellow: Can Soylu Course Assistants: Julio Flores, Alberto Huitron & Yi Yang. Email address to send all questions for the teaching team: [email protected]. Times: Lectures: Tuesdays and Thursdays, 10:30-11:45 a.m. EST.1 Review Sessions: Tuesdays, 12:30-1:30 pm; Fridays, 1:30-2:30 pm EST.2 Final exam: Friday, Dec. 11, 8:00-11:00 am EST. Prospectus Course Description: This course is the first in the two-course sequence on Macroeconomic Policy in the MPA/ID program. It particularly emphasiZes the international dimension. The general perspective is that of developing countries and other small open economies, defined as those for whom world income, world inflation and world interest rates can be taken as given, and possibly the terms of trade as well. The focus is on monetary, fiscal, and exchange rate policy, and on the determination of the current account balance, national income, and inflation. Models of devaluation include one that focuses on the price of internationally traded goods relative to non-traded goods. A theme is the implications of increased integration of global financial markets. Another is countries’ choice of monetary regime, especially the degree of exchange rate flexibility. Applications include Emerging Market crises and problems of commodity-exporting countries. (Such topics as exchange rate overshooting, speculative attacks, portfolio diversification and debt crises will be covered in the first half of Macro II in February-March.) Nature of the approach: The course is largely built around analytical models.
    [Show full text]
  • 'The Supreme Principle of Morality'? in the Preface to His Best
    The Supreme Principle of Morality Allen W. Wood 1. What is ‘The Supreme Principle of Morality’? In the Preface to his best known work on moral philosophy, Kant states his purpose very clearly and succinctly: “The present groundwork is, however, nothing more than the search for and establishment of the supreme principle of morality, which already constitutes an enterprise whole in its aim and to be separated from every other moral investigation” (Groundwork 4:392). This paper will deal with the outcome of the first part of this task, namely, Kant’s attempt to formulate the supreme principle of morality, which is the intended outcome of the search. It will consider this formulation in light of Kant’s conception of the historical antecedents of his attempt. Our first task, however, must be to say a little about the meaning of the term ‘supreme principle of morality’. For it is not nearly as evident to many as it was to Kant that there is such a thing at all. And it is extremely common for people, whatever position they may take on this issue, to misunderstand what a ‘supreme principle of morality’ is, what it is for, and what role it is supposed to play in moral theorizing and moral reasoning. Kant never directly presents any argument that there must be such a principle, but he does articulate several considerations that would seem to justify supposing that there is. Kant holds that moral questions are to be decided by reason. Reason, according to Kant, always seeks unity under principles, and ultimately, systematic unity under the fewest possible number of principles (Pure Reason A298-302/B355-359, A645- 650/B673-678).
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle & Locke: Ancients and Moderns on Economic Theory & The
    Xavier University Exhibit Honors Bachelor of Arts Undergraduate 2015-4 Aristotle & Locke: Ancients and Moderns on Economic Theory & the Best Regime Andrew John Del Bene Xavier University - Cincinnati Follow this and additional works at: http://www.exhibit.xavier.edu/hab Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, and the Ancient Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Del Bene, Andrew John, "Aristotle & Locke: Ancients and Moderns on Economic Theory & the Best Regime" (2015). Honors Bachelor of Arts. Paper 9. http://www.exhibit.xavier.edu/hab/9 This Capstone/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Undergraduate at Exhibit. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Bachelor of Arts by an authorized administrator of Exhibit. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Aristotle & Locke: Ancients and Moderns on Economic Theory & the Best Regime Andrew John Del Bene Honors Bachelor of Arts – Senior Thesis Project Director: Dr. Timothy Quinn Readers: Dr. Amit Sen & Dr. E. Paul Colella Course Director: Dr. Shannon Hogue I respectfully submit this thesis project as partial fulfillment for the Honors Bachelor of Arts Degree. I dedicate this project, and my last four years as an HAB at Xavier University, to my grandfather, John Francis Del Bene, who taught me that in life, you get out what you put in. Del Bene 1 Table of Contents Introduction — Philosophy and Economics, Ancients and Moderns 2 Chapter One — Aristotle: Politics 5 Community: the Household and the Πόλις 9 State: Economics and Education 16 Analytic Synthesis: Aristotle 26 Chapter Two — John Locke: The Two Treatises of Government 27 Community: the State of Nature and Civil Society 30 State: Economics and Education 40 Analytic Synthesis: Locke 48 Chapter Three — Aristotle v.
    [Show full text]
  • Economist Series, GS-0110 TS-54 December 1964, TS-45 April 1963
    Economist Series, GS-0110 TS-54 December 1964, TS-45 April 1963 Position Classification Standard for Economist Series, GS-0110 Table of Contents SERIES DEFINITION.................................................................................................................................... 2 GENERAL STATEMENT.............................................................................................................................. 2 SPECIALIZATION AND TITLING PATTERN .............................................................................................. 5 SUPERVISORY POSITIONS...................................................................................................................... 13 FUNCTIONAL PATTERNS AND GRADE-LEVEL DISTINCTIONS .......................................................... 13 ECONOMIST, GS-0110-05..................................................................................................................... 15 ECONOMIST, GS-0110-07..................................................................................................................... 16 ECONOMIST, GS-0110-09..................................................................................................................... 17 ECONOMIST, GS-0110-11..................................................................................................................... 18 ECONOMIST, GS-0110-12..................................................................................................................... 20 ECONOMIST, GS-0110-13....................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Tomasz Koźluk Counsellor to the OECD Chief Economist
    Tomasz Koźluk Counsellor to the OECD Chief Economist Contact information [email protected] Education PhD, European University Institute, Florence, 2007 MA, International Economics, Sussex University, 2002 MA, Economics Department, Warsaw University, 2002 Professional experience 2021-present Counsellor to the OECD Chief Economist 2012-2017 Senior Economist, Head of Green Growth Workstream, joint Economics Department & Environment Directorate, OECD Chair of Research Committee on Metrics and Indicators, Green Growth, Green Growth Knowledge Platform 2007-2011 Economist, Economics Department , OECD Structural Policy Analysis Division, Macroeconomic Analysis Division and Country Studies Branch 2004-2007 Researcher, Bank of Finland Institute for Economies in Transition; European Central Bank (Financial Research); European Investment Bank (Economic and Financial Studies); CASE; Robert Schuman Centre for Advanced Studies, EUI Selected publications and working papers Empirical projects linking environmental policies and economic outcomes (http://oe.cd/eps) "Environmental policies and productivity growth: Evidence across industries and firms," (2017), Journal of Environmental Economics and Management vol. 81, (with V. Zipperer and S. Albrizio) “Environmental Policies and Productivity Growth – A Critical Review of Empirical Findings”, (2014), OECD Journal: Economic Studies, OECD Publishing, vol. 2014(1), (with V. Zipperer) “Effects of vintage-differentiated environmental regulations - evidence from survival analysis of coal-fired power plants”,
    [Show full text]
  • Adam Smith on Justice, Rights, and Law David Lieberman
    Adam Smith on Justice, Rights, and Law David Lieberman Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program University of California, Berkeley [forthcoming in Knud Haakonssen (ed.), Cambridge Companion to Adam Smith (Cambridge University Press)] Preliminary Draft - please do not cite or quote December, 1999 Adam Smith on Justice, Rights and Law 1. The Unexecuted Account of Law and Government “I shall in another discourse,” Adam Smith reported in the final paragraph of The Theory of Moral Sentiments, “endeavour to give an account of the general principles of law and government, and of the different revolutions they have undergone in the different ages and periods of society …” (TMS.VII.iv.37). Smith’s announcement of this future volume on the general principles of law and government - originally presented in the 1759 first edition of his moral treatise - was then reissued over the next three decades in all the subsequent editions of The Theory of Moral Sentiments published in Smith’s own lifetime. Even the heavily-revised sixth edition of 1790, published in the year of Smith’s death, retained the passage; though by this time Smith acknowledged that his “very advanced age” left him “very little expectation” of completing “this great work” which some thirty years earlier he “entertained no doubt of being able to execute” in its entirety (TMS, “Advertisement”, p.3) i. As in the case of Smith’s two most famous publications, the projected work on “the general principles of law and government” took shape as part of Smith’s duties as a professor at Glasgow University. He had, in fact, first lectured on law and jurisprudence even before he received election in 1751 to the first of his two Glasgow chairs.
    [Show full text]
  • Rand, Hayek, and the Ethics of the Micro- and Macro-Cosmos Steven Horwitz
    Centenary Symposium, Part II Ayn Rand Among the Austrians Two Worlds at Once: Rand, Hayek, and the Ethics of the Micro- and Macro-cosmos Steven Horwitz Moreover, the structures of the extended order are made up not only of individuals but also of many, often overlapping, sub-orders within which old instinctual responses, such as solidarity and altruism, continue to retain some importance by assisting voluntary collaboration, even though they are incapable, by themselves, of creating a basis for the more extended order. Part of our present difficulty is that we must constantly adjust our lives, our thoughts and our emotions, in order to live simultaneously within different kinds of orders according to different rules. So we must learn to live in two sorts of worlds at once. — F. A. Hayek (1989, 18; emphasis added) Introduction A title that contains Rand, Hayek, and the ethics of anything might well raise a few eyebrows among the cognoscenti. After all, Ayn Rand was a champion of an objective ethics and railed against anyone who suggested that a meaningful ethics could be anything but objective in her sense. F. A. Hayek (1989, 10), by contrast, argued explicitly that “Ethics is the last fortress in which human pride must now bow in recognition of its origins. Such an evolutionary theory of morality is . neither instinctual nor a creation of reason.” Thus we are faced with two thinkers who have strongly opposed explanations for the source of ethical rules. However, despite those differences, both Rand and Hayek do wind up with some similar conclusions. For one, both argued that there was a strong link between ethics, political philosophy, and the role of the state.
    [Show full text]