Locke, Kant, and Synthetic a Priori Cognition

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Locke, Kant, and Synthetic a Priori Cognition Brian A. Chance Locke, Kant, and Synthetic APriori Cognition Abstract: This paper attempts to shed light on threerelated issues that bear di- rectlyonour understandingofLockeand Kant.The first is whether Kant believes Lockemerelyanticipates his distinction between analytic and synthetic judg- ments or also believes Lockeanticipateshis notion of synthetic apriori cogni- tion. The second is what we as readers of Kant and Lockeshould think about Kant’sview whatever it turnsout to be, and the third is the nature of Kant’sjus- tification for the comparison he drawsbetween his philosophyand Locke’s. I argue(1) that Kant believes Lockeanticipates both the analytic-synthetic distinc- tion and Kant’snotion of synthetic apriori cognition, (2)thatthe best justifica- tion for Kant’sclaim drawsonLocke’sdistinction between trifling and instruc- tive knowledge,(3) that the arguments against this claim developed by Carson, Allison, and Newman fail to undermine it,and (4) that Kant’sown jus- tification for his claim is quite different from what manycommentators have thoughtitwas (or should have been). Introduction Kant’srelationship to his empiricist predecessors is complex, and this complex- ity is perhaps no more evident than in the caseofLocke, whose philosophyin- fluenced not onlythe likes of Berkeley,Hume, and Reid but alsoageneration of Kant’sGermanpredecessors.¹ The “famous Locke” is the first philosopher Kant mentionsinthe Critique of Pure Reason (CPR), but he is also critical of Locke’s “physiology of the human understanding” and contrasts his transcendental de- Citations from the Critique of Pure Reason use the standardA/B formattorefer to the pagesof the first (A) and second (B) editions. Citations from Kant’sother worksuse the volume number and pagination of KantsgesammelteSchriften,edited by the Royal Prussian(laterGerman, then Berlin-Brandenburg) Academy of the Sciences. vols. (Berlin: De Gruyter —). Quotations from Kant aretaken from the CambridgeEdition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, in some cases withslight modifications. All other translations aremyown. Citations from Locke’s Essay Concerning Human Understanding (Essay)givethe book, chapter, and section numbers and follow the Nidditch edition. See Pollok (), the literaturecitedtherein, and Beiser (, –)for discussionof Locke’sinfluenceoneighteenth-century German philosophy. 10.1515/kantyb-2015-0003 Authenticated | [email protected] author's copy Download Date | 8/15/15 4:19 PM 48 Brian A. Chance duction of the pure concepts of the understanding with Locke’sattempted empir- ical deduction of them (CPR Aix, Axand B127).² Elsewhere, however,Kant is far more complimentary of Locke. Forheclaims in anumber of places that Locke’s Essay Concerning Human Understanding contains ahint of the distinction be- tween synthetic and analytic judgments, and in the Prolegomena he appears to claim that Lockeevenanticipates his notion of synthetic apriori cognition.³ Giventhe importance of these distinctions to Kant’sepistemology,this is high praise indeed. Commenters are in general agreementthat Kant believes Lockeanticipates the analytic-synthetic distinction,but they disagree about whether he endorses the further claim thatLockeanticipates his notion of synthetic apriori cogni- tion.⁴ There is alsodisagreement about which, if either,ofthese views is true as athesis about Lockeand Kant,independent of what Kant mayunderstand his relationship to Locketobe.⁵ Finally, on the assumption that Kant endorses the stronger claim that Lockeanticipates boththe analytic-synthetic distinction and his notion of synthetic apriori cognition, an assumption Ishallargue is cor- rect,questions have been raised about Kant’sjustification for this claim and, in particular, about whyhedoes not appeal to the Lockean distinction between tri- fling and instructive knowledge,adistinction that Ishall argueprovides good evidence for the stronger claim.⁶ My goal in this paper is to shed light on this difficult set of issues and, in the process, on the relationship between Lockeand Kant.Insection one, Iargue that Kant’scomments about Lockesuggest he believes Lockeanticipates both the an- alytic-synthetic distinction and the notion of synthetic apriori cognition. In sec- tion two, Ipresent what Itake to be the best justification for this claim by com- See Guyer ()for adiscussion of Kant and Lockeonthis point. See Prolegomena to any futuremetaphysics that may come forward as ascience (hereafter, Pro- legomena)AA:; On adiscoverywhereby anynew critique of purereason is to be made super- fluous by an older one (hereafter, On adiscovery)AA:;and R dated to –.I return to these passages in section one. Beck (, )and Cicovacki (, )hold that Kant endorses the stronger view,asdoes Guyer in Kant (, ,n), while Ayers (, )suggests Kant endorses onlythe weaker view. Fraser in the annotationscontained in Locke (:II, , ); Gibson (, ); and Ryle (, ff.) suggest the stronger view is true, while Caird (, f.) and Ewing(, )suggest onlythe weakerview is true. Carson (, )assumes the truth of the strong view for the purposes of her paper, but her criticisms of Lockemake clear that she would onlyendorsethe weakerview,while Allison (, )and Newman (, –)reject both views. See Beck (, )and Cicovacki (, ). Authenticated | [email protected] author's copy Download Date | 8/15/15 4:19 PM Locke, Kant, and Synthetic APriori Cognition 49 paring these Kantian distinctions to Locke’sdistinction between trifling and in- structive knowledge.Insection three, Iconsider three arguments against the claim thatinstructive knowledge meetsthe criteria Kant lays out for synthetic apriori cognition and arguethat each is unsatisfactory.Insection four,Iidentify Kant’sjustification for the claim that Lockeanticipates his notion of synthetic a priori cognitionand arguethat it is plausible but different in important ways from the justification presented in section two. In particular, while the justifica- tion Iprovide and which manyofKant’scommentators believeheshould have provided drawsheavilyonLocke’saccount of mathematical judgment,Kant’sac- tual justification ignores Locke’saccount of mathematical judgment completely and focuses instead on claims he makes about bodyand the mechanics of bodily motion. While the strongest argument thatcan be made on Kant’sbehalf for the claim that Lockeanticipates his notion of synthetic apriori cognitionrelies on Locke’strifling-instructivedistinction and his use of mathematical judgments to illustrate that distinction,the best reconstruction of Kant’sjustification for this claim relies,surprisingly in my view,onsimilarities between aclaim Lockemakes about motion and arguments Kant develops in the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. 1Kant’scomments on Locke Although Kant credits Hume in the Prolegomena with striking aspark he will later kindle, thereisnoindication there or elsewherethathebelieves Hume an- ticipates his notion of synthetic apriori cognition and onlythe passingsugges- tion that he believes Hume anticipates the analytic-synthetic distinction.⁷ With Locke, however,there is good reason to think Kant believes he anticipates both. Kant discusses Lockeinanumber of places,but onlythreeofthem bear directlyonthe question at hand: Locke sawthe distinctionbetween analytic and syntheticjudgmentsinhis essayconcern- ing human understanding.(AA 17:278) By contrast Ifind ahint [Wink]ofthis division [between analytic and synthetic judgments] alreadyinLocke’s essays on human understanding.For in Book IV,ChapterIII, §9f., after he had alreadydiscussed the various connections of representationsinjudgments and the sourcesofthe connections,ofwhich he located the one in identity or contradiction (ana- lytic judgments) but the other in the existenceofrepresentationsinasubject (synthetic See AA : and CPR A /B . Authenticated | [email protected] author's copy Download Date | 8/15/15 4:19 PM 50 Brian A. Chance judgments),hethen acknowledgesin§10 that our cognition (apriori)ofthese last is very restricted and almost nothingatall. (AA4:270) In order to be satisfied of this, we have onlytoexamine the examplesthat have been pre- viouslyintroduced [die man bisher angeführt hat]toprove that the distinction in question [between analytic and synthetic judgments] is alreadyknown and fullydeveloped in phi- losophy, albeit under other names.The first one (pointed out by myself, though onlyas somewhat like it) is from Locke,who assigns whathecalls cognition of coexistencetojudg- ments of experience, and cognition of relation to moral judgments;but he does not give a name to the syntheticaspect of judgments in general; nor,bythis distinction frompropo- sitions of identity,has he extractedthe most minimal of general rules for pure apriori cog- nition as such. (AA8:245,translation modified) The first of these passages is anote Kant made in the 1760s to his copy of Baum- garten’s Metaphysica,and it claims unambiguouslythat Lockeanticipates the analytic-syntheticdistinction. Unfortunately, it tells us nothing about whether Kant also thoughtLockeanticipates the notion of the synthetic apriori since it was written at atime when Kant thoughtthatall synthetic cognitionwas apos- teriori. The second passageisfrom the Prolegomena. It is part of the first paragraph of the section of the Prefaceentitled “Note on the general division of judgments into analytic and synthetic”.Herewefind aweaker version of Kant’sclaim in the reflection from the 1760s (instead of simply ‘seeing’ the analytic-synthetic dis- tinction, Lockeisonlycredited with ‘hinting’ at it), but
Recommended publications
  • The British Empiricism Locke, Berkeley and Hume
    The British Empiricism Locke, Berkeley and Hume copyleft: nicolazuin.2018 | nowxhere.wordpress.com 1 The problem of knowledge • Please, look out of the window (or into the box, or just in front of you…) and answer the following questions: ‣ What do you see? ‣ Are you sure that what you see is what truly exists out there? ‣ What do you know about it? ‣ How do you know it? ‣ What make you sure of it? • Here you are: this is the problem of knowledge! • Now try to formalise it in a single question or definition. copyleft:nicolazuin.2018 | nowxhere.wordpress.com 1 A long way behind In a certain way, we could say that the problem of knowledge is the problem of philosophy itself, since its birth. • Think for example on this quotations: Parmenides: «the same thing is for thinking as is for being” Eraclitus: «The things of which there is sight, hearing, experience, I prefer». (But he also says: «Poor witnesses for men are their eyes and ears if they have barbarian souls» Gorgia: «Nothing exists; Even if something exists, nothing can be known about it; and Even if something can be known about it, knowledge about it can't be communicated to others. Even if it can be communicated, it cannot be understood». • Or try to imagine the discussion between Plato and Aristotle in the famous Raffaello’s School of Athens. • Now try to build a mind-map of all the different answers to the problem of knowledge given by the philosophers you already know copyleft:nicolazuin.2018 | nowxhere.wordpress.com 2 The terrible heritage of Descartes: The modern problem of knowledge originates from the conclusions of Descartes’s research, which was inspired by the successful advancement of geometry and natural sciences and was aimed to find a certain knowledge for philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle & Locke: Ancients and Moderns on Economic Theory & The
    Xavier University Exhibit Honors Bachelor of Arts Undergraduate 2015-4 Aristotle & Locke: Ancients and Moderns on Economic Theory & the Best Regime Andrew John Del Bene Xavier University - Cincinnati Follow this and additional works at: http://www.exhibit.xavier.edu/hab Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, and the Ancient Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Del Bene, Andrew John, "Aristotle & Locke: Ancients and Moderns on Economic Theory & the Best Regime" (2015). Honors Bachelor of Arts. Paper 9. http://www.exhibit.xavier.edu/hab/9 This Capstone/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Undergraduate at Exhibit. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Bachelor of Arts by an authorized administrator of Exhibit. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Aristotle & Locke: Ancients and Moderns on Economic Theory & the Best Regime Andrew John Del Bene Honors Bachelor of Arts – Senior Thesis Project Director: Dr. Timothy Quinn Readers: Dr. Amit Sen & Dr. E. Paul Colella Course Director: Dr. Shannon Hogue I respectfully submit this thesis project as partial fulfillment for the Honors Bachelor of Arts Degree. I dedicate this project, and my last four years as an HAB at Xavier University, to my grandfather, John Francis Del Bene, who taught me that in life, you get out what you put in. Del Bene 1 Table of Contents Introduction — Philosophy and Economics, Ancients and Moderns 2 Chapter One — Aristotle: Politics 5 Community: the Household and the Πόλις 9 State: Economics and Education 16 Analytic Synthesis: Aristotle 26 Chapter Two — John Locke: The Two Treatises of Government 27 Community: the State of Nature and Civil Society 30 State: Economics and Education 40 Analytic Synthesis: Locke 48 Chapter Three — Aristotle v.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy.Pdf
    Philosophy 1 PHIL:1401 Matters of Life and Death 3 s.h. Contemporary ethical controversies with life and death Philosophy implications; topics may include famine, brain death, animal ethics, abortion, torture, terrorism, capital punishment. GE: Chair Values and Culture. • David Cunning PHIL:1636 Principles of Reasoning: Argument and Undergraduate major: philosophy (B.A.) Debate 3 s.h. Undergraduate minor: philosophy Critical thinking and its application to arguments and debates. Graduate degrees: M.A. in philosophy; Ph.D. in philosophy GE: Quantitative or Formal Reasoning. Faculty: https://clas.uiowa.edu/philosophy/people/faculty PHIL:1861 Introduction to Philosophy 3 s.h. Website: https://clas.uiowa.edu/philosophy/ Varied topics; may include personal identity, existence of The Department of Philosophy offers programs of study for God, philosophical skepticism, nature of mind and reality, undergraduate and graduate students. A major in philosophy time travel, and the good life; readings, films. GE: Values and develops abilities useful for careers in many fields and for any Culture. situation requiring clear, systematic thinking. PHIL:1902 Philosophy Lab: The Meaning of Life 1 s.h. Further exploration of PHIL:1033 course material with the The department also administers the interdisciplinary professor in a smaller group. undergraduate major in ethics and public policy, which it offers jointly with the Department of Economics and the PHIL:1904 Philosophy Lab: Liberty and the Pursuit of Department of Sociology and Criminology; see Ethics and Happiness 1 s.h. Public Policy in the Catalog. Further exploration of PHIL:1034 course material with the professor in a smaller group. Programs PHIL:1950 Philosophy Club 1-3 s.h.
    [Show full text]
  • Individuality in John Locke and John Stuart Mill: a Response to Michael J
    Individuality in John Locke and John Stuart Mill: A Response to Michael J. Sandel by Cara Camcastle BA. Hon. Econ., University of British Columbia, 1995 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES Department of Political Science We accept this thesis as conforming to the required standard THE UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA August 1998 © Cara Camcastle, 1998 In presenting this thesis in partial fulfilment of the requirements for an advanced degree at the University of British Columbia, I agree that the Library shall make it freely available for reference and study. I further agree that permission for extensive copying of this thesis for scholarly purposes may be granted by the head of my department or by his or her representatives. It is understood that copying or publication of this thesis for financial gain shall not be allowed without my written permission. Department The University of British Columbia Vancouver, Canada DE-6 (2/88) Abstract This thesis examines from a philosophical and theoretical standpoint, the validity of the communitarian claim that liberalism promotes an abstract, asocial, and atomistic conception of the self. To better understand the inner logic of Lockean and Millian arguments, I analyse 'individuality' the concept at the centre of the dispute between liberals and communitarians. The thesis illustrates the essentially contested nature of this concept, and the complexity and diversity of the liberal tradition which has been generally overlooked by communitarian critics. Locke's conception of individuality is morphological because it emphasises how an individual assisted by the right kind of education constructs his individuality through deliberation and self-control.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz: the Last Great Christian Platonist
    chapter 3 Leibniz: The Last Great Christian Platonist Jack Davidson Many of the Platonic doctrines are … most beautiful.1 ∵ Leibniz (1646–1716) was the last great philosopher in the rich tradition of Christian Platonism that began before Augustine (354–430) and ran through Pseudo-Dionysius (early sixth century), John Scottus Eriugena (c. 800– c. 877), Anselm (1033–1109), Nicholas of Cusa (1401–64) and Marsilio Ficino’s (1433–1499) Florentine Academy. With the advent of figures like John Locke (1632–1704), David Hume (1711–1776), Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778) and Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), philosophy became both mundane and largely secular. This chapter focuses on the most influential of the 17th-century German Platonists, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. As anyone who knows of the history of Platonism from Plato onward realizes, classifying Leibniz as a Platonist is to place him in the company of philosophers who hold (sometimes wildly) different views, so some specifi- cation is necessary. These days, “Platonism” is used by scholars of ancient philosophy to describe what they take to be actual doctrines in the Platonic canon, doctrines Plato developed or continued to hold in the dialogues after the early, Socratic dialogues, e.g., the theory of the Forms.2 In contemporary metaphysics, “Platonism” refers to the view that certain abstract truths, like those of mathematics and logic, exist independently of time and space and human thought. Frege, Gödel, and Russell were all Platonists in this sense, as 1 D ii 222/l 592. Leibniz citations in the text and notes are by abbreviation keyed to the bibli- ography.
    [Show full text]
  • David Hume Foundations of the Classical School of Economics
    Economic Insights FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF DALLAS VOLUME 8, NUMBER 1 David Hume Foundations of the Classical School of Economics Adam Smith is the founder of the nomic essays] are all clearly written classical school of economics, but eco- and often contain an excellent sum- nomic theorizing predates Smith. The mary and synthesis of the ideas of his philosophic foundations of classical eco- predecessors. In that respect, how- nomics are found in the work of the ever, Cantillon’s Essai sur la nature Scottish Enlightenment thinkers of the du commerce en général, published early to mid-18th century, centered in 1755, but written over twenty years David Hume is primarily known as around the University of Edinburgh. previously, is superior. a philosopher and chronicler of English Notable among these great thinkers and writers is David Hume. It is impossible to know whether history. Less well known is his work on eco- Hume was born in Edinburgh, Smith was more influenced by Can- nomic theory and several political econ- Scotland, on May 7, 1711. The extent to tillon’s book or by personal discussions which Hume influenced Smith, his close with Hume. Schumpeter (1954, 124) omy issues, some of which remain salient friend, has to be inferred from their argues that Hume did influence Smith, today. Studying his economic work respective writings, but the warmth and and Rothbard (1995, 430) suggests that depth of their relationship is incon- Hume was one of Smith’s mentors. enables us to see how he reshaped John testable. Smith said of Hume: O’Brien (1975) gives Hume a large role Locke’s quantity theory of money and how in the development of classical econom- Upon the whole, I have always con- ic thought because of his participation he influenced the great Adam Smith, sidered him, both in his lifetime and in spreading natural law philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • John Locke's Contemporaries' Reaction Against the Theory Of
    John Locke’s Contemporaries’ Reaction against the Theory of Substratum Mihretu P. Guta (Durham University) The goal of this paper is to critically examine the objections of John Locke’s contemporaries against the theory of substance or substratum. Locke argues in Essay that substratum is the bearer of the properties of a particular substance. Locke also claims that we have no knowledge of substratum. But Locke’s claim about our ignorance as to what substratum is, is contentious. That is, if we don’t know what substratum is, then what is the point of proposing it as a bearer of properties? This question underlies the criticism Locke’s contemporaries raise against the notion of substratum. In section I, I lay out the context for Locke’s theory of substratum by pointing out his main motivation in proposing his theory. In section II, I give a brief analysis of the theory of substratum. In section III, I discuss the objections of Locke’s contemporaries against the theory of substratum.1 I focus on Edward Stillingfleet, Lee Henry, G. W. Leibniz and John Sergeant. In section IV, I conclude that there is no warrant to dismiss Locke’s theory of substance. 1. The Need for Substratum Locke’s proposal of the theory of substratum aims at answering one key question. That is, do properties (e.g., color) or qualities need bearers? As we shall see, Locke answers this question affirmatively. But how does Locke go about the task of accounting for the bearer of properties? How does he describe it? Does the supposed property bearer have its own nature, i.e., its own identity via which we come to know what it is? Does Locke have a uniform and uncontentious way to characterize his theory of substratum? Such questions are still hotly debated and disagreements over what constitutes the right answer to them are far from over.2 1 For dialectical purposes, in section I, I consider the first objection against Locke’s theory of substratum.
    [Show full text]
  • Was Locke a Liberal?
    SUBSCRIBE NOW AND RECEIVE CRISIS AND LEVIATHAN* FREE! “The Independent Review does not accept “The Independent Review is pronouncements of government officials nor the excellent.” conventional wisdom at face value.” —GARY BECKER, Noble Laureate —JOHN R. MACARTHUR, Publisher, Harper’s in Economic Sciences Subscribe to The Independent Review and receive a free book of your choice* such as the 25th Anniversary Edition of Crisis and Leviathan: Critical Episodes in the Growth of American Government, by Founding Editor Robert Higgs. This quarterly journal, guided by co-editors Christopher J. Coyne, and Michael C. Munger, and Robert M. Whaples offers leading-edge insights on today’s most critical issues in economics, healthcare, education, law, history, political science, philosophy, and sociology. Thought-provoking and educational, The Independent Review is blazing the way toward informed debate! Student? Educator? Journalist? Business or civic leader? Engaged citizen? This journal is for YOU! *Order today for more FREE book options Perfect for students or anyone on the go! The Independent Review is available on mobile devices or tablets: iOS devices, Amazon Kindle Fire, or Android through Magzter. INDEPENDENT INSTITUTE, 100 SWAN WAY, OAKLAND, CA 94621 • 800-927-8733 • [email protected] PROMO CODE IRA1703 Was Locke a Liberal? —————— ✦ —————— JEROME HUYLER or more than thirty years social scientists have been debating the rela- tive influence of two ideological “languages,” liberalism and republi- F canism, on past periods and important literary productions. Modern communitarians vie with contemporary liberals, hoping to retrieve vital ele- ments of the republican tradition in order to ameliorate what they perceive to be the coarser aspects of liberal, capitalist life.
    [Show full text]
  • Uncomfortable Bedfellows: Locke and the Libertarian Theory of Property
    University of Missouri, St. Louis IRL @ UMSL Theses UMSL Graduate Works 8-17-2015 Uncomfortable Bedfellows: Locke and the Libertarian Theory of Property Garrett Dimond University of Missouri-St. Louis, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://irl.umsl.edu/thesis Recommended Citation Dimond, Garrett, "Uncomfortable Bedfellows: Locke and the Libertarian Theory of Property" (2015). Theses. 267. https://irl.umsl.edu/thesis/267 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the UMSL Graduate Works at IRL @ UMSL. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of IRL @ UMSL. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Fall 08 UNCOMFORTABLE BEDFELLOWS: LOCKE AND THE LIBERTARIAN THEORY OF PROPERTY by GARRETT DIMOND B.S. Environmental Horticulture A THESIS Submitted to the Graduate School of the UNIVERSITY OF MISSOURI- ST. LOUIS In partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree MASTER OF ARTS in PHILOSOPHY July, 2015 Advisory Committee Jill Delston, Ph.D. Chairperson Jon McGinnis, Ph.D. Stephanie Ross, Ph.D. Dimond, Garrett, 2015, UMSL, p. 2 Uncomfortable Bedfellows: Locke and the Libertarian Theory of Property Abstract: Libertarians, such as Robert Nozick, have often appealed to Locke’s labor theory as the basis in which to defend full ownership rights to property. My central claim is that this is a mistake. Locke, I argue, is not a comfortable libertarian bedfellow for the following three reasons. (1) Locke’s account of property neither implies rights to full ownership, nor was Locke himself committed to the view. (2) The conditions Locke's labor theory places on property rights would generate a state that more closely aligns with the welfare state than the libertarian minimal state.
    [Show full text]
  • John Locke and the Fable of Liberalism
    This is a repository copy of John Locke and the fable of liberalism. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/121796/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Stanton, Tim orcid.org/0000-0002-8282-9570 (2018) John Locke and the fable of liberalism. Historical Journal. pp. 597-622. ISSN 0018-246X https://doi.org/10.1017/S0018246X17000450 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ The Historical Journal JOHN LOCKE AND THE FABLE OF LIBERALISM Journal: The Historical Journal Manuscript ID HJ-2017-062.R1 Manuscript Type: Article Perio : 1600-99, 1700-99, 1800-99, 1900-99, 2000- Intellectual, Historiographical, Religious, Political, A ministrative ( Legal, Thematic: Social Geographic: ,urope, Continental, .ritain, America, North Cambridge University Press Page 1 of 46 The Historical Journal Locke and the fable of liberalism JOHN LOCKE AND THE FABLE OF LIBERALISM TIMOTHY STANTON University of York ABSTRACT. This essay explores the ways in which John Locke was claimed by liberalism and refashioned in its image.
    [Show full text]
  • Locke and the Contemporary Situation New.Qxp
    APORIA ASTUDENT JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY Editor Jeffrey Johnson Associate Editors Russell Farr Tully Minoski Justin Perry Justin White Aporia is published twice each year by the Department of Philosophy at Brigham Young University and is dedicated to recognizing exemplary philosophical work at the undergraduate level. The spring issue each year includes the winning essays of the annual David H. Yarn Philosophical Essay Competition, which is open to BYU undergraduates only, along with other outstanding philosophical essays submitted by undergraduate philosophy students from around the world. The winners of the Yarn Competition are selected by a faculty committee independent of the student editors and staff, who make all other publishing decisions. The fall issue is pub- lished online and consists of papers selected by the editorial staff. Submissions are welcome from all undergraduate students, both at BYU and elsewhere. The Aporia staff is especially grateful to those who support makes this journal possible. Special thanks go to Professor Dennis Rasmussen, chair of the Department of Philosophy, Professor David Jensen, our faculty advisor, and to Linda Hunter Adams of the Humanities Publication Center. Aporia is funded by a generous con- tribution from the David H. Yarn Endowment. Those wishing to contribute to this fund may do so by contacting the BYU Department of Philosophy. Opinions expressed herein are those of the respective authors and do not nec- essarily reflect the opinions of the editors, the Philosophy Department, or Brigham Young University. http://humanities.byu.edu/philosophy/aporia.html Aporia Vol. 16 number 2-2005 Locke and the Contemporary Situation TYSON MOHR t the time of its writing, the political theory put forth in Locke’s Second Treatise of Government was a powerful source for individual- Aists.
    [Show full text]
  • The Propriety of Liberty
    Copyrighted Material • INTrODUCTION • The Propriety of Liberty This is an intellectual history of some of the major ways in which the idea of liberty was understood by John Locke, Charles Louis Secondat, Baron de la Brède et de Montesquieu, Adam Smith, John Stuart Mill and Thomas Hill Green. It might well then be asked what could possibly be said that merits yet another book on these thinkers in general, and on the topic of liberty especially. For a great many people have written on any one or all of these men, and often with specific reference to the idea of liberty. My answer to this reasonable question is simple, but perhaps surprising. It seems to me that despite the agglomeration of commentary and critique, indeed perhaps because of it, many interpreters have missed something absolutely crucial. This is particularly the case amongst those who have been keen to incorporate these writers into a canon of modern liberalism, and who often tend to read the concerns of contemporary liberal political theory backwards onto these putative founders of such a tradition. In this reading, what is typically missed is the relentless focus of these writers on the way in which the quality of individual agency is related to an understanding of freedom. My central claim is that the writers discussed in this book typically conceive of liberty as a form of propriety, or appropriate agency. Although they do not cultivate explicit theories of liberty as propriety, my use of the term ‘propriety’ with refer- ence to liberty is designed to illustrate the connections between governed conduct and free agency that are central to each of these writers.
    [Show full text]