Locke and Leibniz on Perception*
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
ROCZNIKI FILOZOFICZNE Tom LXV, numer 2 – 2017 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.18290/rf.2017.65.2-8 ADAM GRZELIŃSKI * LOCKE AND LEIBNIZ ON PERCEPTION* The publication of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz’s Nouveaux essais (written 1703–1704, published 1765), which are entirely dedicated to the analysis of the content of John Locke’s An Essay concerning Human Understanding (1690), gives researchers a rare opportunity to study the differences in both philosophers’ views. It is not surprising that the polemics of these two crea- tors of such diverse philosophical conceptions have been the cause for nu- merous historical and philosophical analyses: Leibniz’s philosophy crowned 17th century metaphysics along with its major category of substance, Locke’s concept heralded modern British empiricism which shortly afterwards in Da- vid Hume’s works was to lead to the sceptical negation of traditional meta- physics. Naturally, researchers’ attention has been most often drawn to these issues, which are equally fundamental for both thinkers: namely the relation- ship between reason and religious beliefs, the understanding of substance, the conception of nature or the problem of personal identity, because they best reveal the differences in views taken by those philosophers.1 In this article, I have addressed a different issue, namely Leibniz’s criti- cism of Locke’s understanding of perception. In my judgement, the criticism is the result of a quite superficial understanding of An Essay concerning Hu- man Understanding, and additionally comes more from various general philo- Prof. dr hab. ADAM GRZELIŃSKI —dyrektor Instytutu Filozofii na Wydziale Humanistycznym Uniwersytetu Mikołaja Kopernika w Toruniu; adres do korespondncji: ul. Fosa Staromiejska 1a, 87-100 Toruń; e-mail: [email protected] * This research was carried out as a part of a Polish National Science Centre (NCN) grant (UMO-2012/07/B/HS1/01619). 1 Brandon C. LOOK, Leibniz and Locke on Natural Kinds, pdf online, accessed 30.03.2017, https://www.uky.edu/~look/Leibniz&Locke.pdf; Ben Lazar MIJUSKOVIC, “Locke and Leibniz on Personal Identity,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy” 13 (1975), 2: 205–214, Paul LODGE and Benjamin CROWE, “Leibniz, Bayle, and Locke on Faith and Reason,” American Catholic Philoso- phical Quarterly 76 (2002), 4: 575–600. 168 ADAM GRZELIŃSKI sophical grounds than actually different views on the process of perception it- self. The cause of this misunderstanding may be the one-sided understanding of Locke’s thesis in which he advances that the whole content of thinking is the object of consciousness, along with the belief about the entirely acquired nature of human knowledge.2 Emphasizing the dissimilarity between his stand and Locke’s views, Leibniz claims that the process of perception does not merely apply to the content that we are aware of, but also to the content which is implicite. At the same time, he highlights Locke’s statement that even though perception constitutes the most basic operation of the mind, it is at the same time one of the reflective ideas, namely the object of thought in human con- sciousness. However, Locke’s declaration that “Every man being conscious to himself that he thinks, and that which his mind is applied about, whilst thinking, being the ideas that are there” (E, II,1,1, p. 77) does not necessarily mean that all the processes taking place in the mind are conscious operations. His recognition that the process called perception occurs even beyond the gate of consciousness allows Leibniz not only to claim that knowledge is in- nate, but also to state that the essence of the substance, such as a human soul, is activity.3 According to Leibniz, Locke attributed passivity to the 2 This statement needs a clarification, which goes beyond the scope of this paper. It should be noted, however, that Locke opposes the innate character of impressions and principles (E, I,1,1–2, p. 13–14), which denies the possibility of divine revelation and establishes the grounds for three levels of his investigations: the history of human understanding—the analysis breaking up men- tal content into simple elements (which is of a psychological character) for experimental sciences, and the source of all ideas, being the activity of external bodies acting mechanically on our sense organs, as well as the activity of the human mind. An attack on the notion of innatism with reference to natural law and religion can be found as early as his Questions concerning the Law of Nature from the mid-1660s. See John LOCKE, “Is the Law of Nature inscribed in the minds of Men? It is not,” in IDEM, Questions concerning the Law of Nature, ed. and trans. Robert Horwitz, Jenny Strauss Clay, and Diskin Clay (Ithaca–London: Cornell University Press, 1990), 139–152. Quotations from the two main source texts according to the following editions: Gottfried Wilhelm LEIBNIZ, New Essays Concerning Human Understanding, trans. Alfred Gideon Langley (London: MacMillan Company, 1896 — abbr. NE, I give the numbers of the book, the chapter and the page); Gottfried Wilhelm LEIBNIZ, Monadology, trans. Robert Latta, revised by Donald Rutherford, accessed 30 March 2017, http://philosophyfaculty.ucsd.edu/faculty/rutherford/Leibniz/translations/ Monadology.pdf — abbr. M, I give the number of the paragraph; John LOCKE, An Essay Con- cerning Human Understanding, in: IDEM, The Works of John Locke, vol. 1–2 (London: Rivington 1824 — abbr. E, I give the numbers of the book, the chapter, the paragraph, and the page; the first book of the Essay and the first six chapters of the second book are contained in the first volume of the edition). 3 See Anne-Lise REY, “Perception and Individuality in Leibnizian Conception of Substance,” in Locke and Leibniz on Substance, edited by Paul Lodge and Tom Stoneham (New York: Routl- edge, 2015), 165 ff. LOCKE AND LEIBNIZ ON PERCEPTION 169 mind, at least when it comes to the simple elements of experience, that is simple ideas. Binding perception with activity, Leibniz considers perception as the factor differentiating individual substances; while Locke’s new way of ideas, emphasizing the psychological and social aspects of experience, aban- dons the metaphysics of substance to some extent: the identity of a thing is built in his opinion in a completely different way, dissimilar for objects of inanimate nature, living creatures and humans. His pessimism concerning the possibility of identifying the essence of a substance was accompanied by the isolation of the psychological plane of investigation and its independence from metaphysics, especially in its idealistic form. However, as we will see, despite all the differences mentioned, the psychological description of the process of perception presented by both philosophers is, contrary to Leib- niz’s declarations, surprisingly parallel. THE APPLE OF DISCORD: PERCEPTION AS AN OBJECT OF EXPERIENCE Let us begin with presenting three main points of Leibniz’s criticism. Firstly, according to Leibniz, all perceptions, as well as all mental processes in general, as described by Locke, would be the objects of consciousness, while in reality “there are at every moment an infinite number of perceptions in us, but without apperception and reflection, i.e. changes in the soul itself of which we are not conscious, because the impressions are either too slight and too great in number, or too even, so they have nothing sufficiently dis- tinguishing them from each other” (NE, Introduction, p. 47). In other words, it is not correct for Leibniz to compare the mind to white paper being written upon by experience, as Locke does, and to state that everything that appears in it is immediately detectable by our consciousness. The second reservation relates to the presumed passivity of the mind during perception. While, according to Locke, the activity of the mind al- lows constructing complex ideas, perception of simple elements of experi- ence is reduced to bare receptivity. Leibniz’s Philalethes summarises the concept as follows “in what we call perception the mind is ordinarily purely passive, not being able to avoid perceiving what it actually perceives” (NE, 2,9, p. 135). Philalethes also makes a reference to the fact that the passivity of the mind means the lack of voluntary attention; however, Leibniz himself understands the activity as the essence of the substance itself, and the result 170 ADAM GRZELIŃSKI of this activity is the change in the state of the substance called perception. Therefore, in Monadology, we read that “the natural changes of monads come from an internal principle, since an external cause cannot influence it internally […] The passing state that involves and represents a multitude in the unity, or in the simple substance, is nothing but what is called percep- tion, which is to be distinguished from apperception or consciousness” (M, 11,14). Leibniz expresses this claim even more clearly in a short passage in the work On the system of occasional causes (1689/90): “Each substance is the true and real cause of its own immanent actions, and has the power of acting, and although it is merely passive, and this is true both in the case of corporeal substances and incorporeal ones.”4 He also reiterates the opinion in Nouveaux essais stating that “a substance cannot exist without an action, and that there is indeed never a body without movement” (NE, Introduction, p. 47). Thus, because perceptions are distinct from apperceptions, it is ad- missible or even necessary to attribute them to every substance, not only to human beings and animals, but also to plants. Therefore, the third objection concerns Locke’s limited understanding of perception—it is a terminological objection (it concerns the scope of the concept of perception), as well as the one connected with a different under- standing of substance and the role of metaphysics in human cognition (for Leibniz the relationship between perception and the activity of non-corpo- real substances).