The Hemlock Papers an Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Hemlock Papers an Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy 1 The Hemlock Papers An Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy University of Idaho Department of Politics and Philosophy Volume 17 Spring 2020 2 Letter from the Editors It is a great pleasure and privilege to present the 17th volume of The Hemlock Papers. Our team has worked diligently to revitalize our journal in the past two years following a significant hiatus, and we are delighted to share the following philosophical works with the greater academic community. The Hemlock strives to feature exemplary undergraduate scholarship and promote fruitful discourse, and we find this edition to be an outstanding realization of these goals. We chose to call for a wide range of philosophical subjects this year; the enclosed works, we hope, will present the reader with a richly diverse set of perspectives, styles of argument, and academic engagement. I want to give special thanks to the members of the PST society for engaging with and reviewing our submissions. I would also like to thank our chapter advisor, Dr. Graham Hubbs, and administrative assistant Omni Francetich for their unwavering support throughout this process. Editors Emma French Trevor Woodward The Team Michael Bivens Braden Farrar AJ Bruce Cameron Haylett Diana Cervantes Lauren Moon Sam Clements Landon Moulding 3 Contents The Benefits of Epistemological Skepticism in Philosophical Inquiry 4 Kyle Smith Definitional Inconsistency and Conceptual Misrepresentation: A Critique of Thomas Kelly’s 11 “Peer Disagreement and Higher Order Evidence” Grace Forster Philosophy and the Muslim Masses: A Discussion Surrounding Ibn Rushd’s Decisive Treatise 20 Fatima Najdi Aristotle is a Rationalist: Necessity in Aristotle’s Metaphysics and Ethics 27 Nicholas M. Michieli A Critique of Hume’s Skepticism of Reason John H. Cooney 35 4 The Benefits of Epistemological Skepticism in Philosophical Inquiry Kyle Smith Humboldt State University ABSTRACT: The inductive skeptic argues that we can know no inductive inferences to be certain. Although the skeptic’s methodology is sound, it is impos- sible to carry out the skeptical belief system into one’s actions. In this paper, I ar- gue for a less radical skepticism than that held of the traditional inductive skeptic. I posit that we can make use of skepticism in philosophical discourse through use of a restricted domain of focus which allows us to aside the practical issues of a more complete skepticism. Epistemological skepticism is throughout our philosophical investi- both sound and not a fruitless inquiry, gations. which many have contended in the The classical skeptical argument past. Skepticism is widely regarded as is that we have no proper grounds to an impractical viewpoint due to the assert any statement’s certainty. There consequential rejection of all positive are two methods of reasoning to deter- philosophical theories and the impos- mine the certainty of a statement: de- sibility of action. I argue that the re- duction and induction. Deduction in- stricted form of skepticism I describe, volves the logical and systematic as opposed to radical universal skepti- “elimination” of statements in order to cism which most are familiar with, is reach a truly verified conclusion (i.e. philosophically beneficial. I will be mathematical, logical, and definitional pulling primarily from the arguments truths). Induction is the method of of Abraham Meiden and Peter Unger drawing a probabilistic conclusion to establish my position on different from some evidence. I will be con- forms of skepticism. I will conclude by cerned with inductive skepticism as offering an overview of more plausible deductive arguments are uninforma- and pragmatic uses of skepticism, re- tive by nature (e.g. “all teenagers are lying on domain of focus and degree of between the ages of 13 and 19” or probability, pulling from Brian “A=A”). An inductive skeptic cri- Skyrms’ “Grades of Inductive Skepti- tiques induction on the grounds of its cism”. All accounts of the refutation of uncertainty. Philosopher David Hume skepticism, while well intended, fall is widely regarded as the founder of short of the skeptical scope. Skepti- modern inductive (Humean) skepti- cism is sound in all accounts put forth cism. Hume claimed that “to try to jus- thus far and as epistemologists we tify (it) inductively is to beg the ques- must contend with this fact and at- tion: “It is impossible, therefore, that tempt to make use of skepticism any arguments from experience can 5 prove this resemblance of the past to being conducted in epistemology, phi- the future, since all these arguments losophy as a whole, or any discipline are founded on the supposition of that for that matter is fruitless and contin- resemblance.”1 gent upon the weakly assumed reliabil- Philosopher Abraham Meiden ity of human belief. A notable group lays out some popular formulations of which took on the challenge of skepti- the radically skeptical argument2 as cism are known as the justificationists. follows: The justificationists argue that “skep- tical arguments show just that state- (a.1.) To show that a statement is ments such as ‘The sun will rise to- in fact certain is to prove or jus- morrow' are not certain; but they do tify it. In order to do so, one must not show that such statements are not justify all assumptions within the justified, plausible or probable. There- statement and subsequently jus- fore, we may still claim that it is ra- tify all assumptions within those tional to believe that the sun will rise justification statements… Form- tomorrow and irrational to deny it.”4 ing an infinite regress of (doubt- The justificationists agree with the ful) justificatory statements. skeptics in their fundamental argu- (b.1.) Human information (e.g. ment of uncertainty, but posit that we perception and thought) is imper- ought to shift the focus of our episte- fect by nature. mological pursuit of knowledge to a (c.1.) It is logically possible that more pragmatic model concerned with some ‘evil demon’ is controlling justification, plausibility, and proba- our beliefs and causes us to be bility rather than the former quest for mistaken.3 absolute truth and certainty. Despite the fact that the justifica- Arguments such as these lead the tionists agree with the skeptics on their skeptic to form the conclusion that we foundational claims, some strong- can know nothing at all to be certain. willed skeptics have still found a way Many philosophers have adopted in which to refute the justificationary the project of attempting to find a thesis. The justificatory skeptic claims sound argument against skepticism, that a statement like ‘I have a body’ (or for highly rational reasons. It seems as any statement supposing a belief to be though if we cannot know anything to true) is not only uncertain, but is also be certain, then much of the work no more justifiable than any other 1 David Hume, An Inquiry Concerning 3Abraham Meiden, Arguments for Skepti- Human Understanding, (Oxford, Claren- cism, (Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 don, 1896), 32. no. 2, 1986), 298. 2 These radically skeptical arguments are 4Abraham Meiden, Arguments for Skepti- applicable to both deductive and inductive cism, 299. reasoning, but once again I am concerned only with inductive skepticism here. 6 claim, including the claim that ‘I do diminishes quickly and tends to not have a body.’5 The justificatory be zero, or rather close to it.9 skeptic effectively applies modifica- tions of the classical skeptical argu- With this, I intend to have per- ment to disprove the probability, plau- suaded you to adopt the belief that the sibility, and justification of claims in skeptical thesis (in both the certain and order to assert their position against justificatory formulation) is sound. I the justificationists. Consider the fol- will further show how that plays out in lowing skeptical argument modifica- terms of human experience. tions which target justificationists: If one were to accept the radically skeptical position as more than a mere (a.2.) The justificationist argues conceptual philosophical outlook, that that statement p is not certain but is to incorporate the core thesis of is in fact justified. It follows then skepticism into their belief system and that the justification of p is not live according to its principles, said in- certain, but at most only justified. dividual would run quickly into some The justification of p is at most damning consequences. Suppose that only justified, which is at most you, the reader of this paper, was ut- only justified and so on, leading terly amazed by the arguments for to yet another infinite regress.6 skepticism laid out above and immedi- (b.2.) Consider an extremely sim- ately self-indoctrinated yourself into plistic and widely accepted scien- the skeptical camp. Following the tific theory7 such as: “All physi- guidelines of true skepticism, you cal objects on earth are affected would likely stop reading, as it is skep- by gravity.” This leads to the in- tical whether you were ever reading at finite conjunction of justificatory all and whether some evil scientist was claims that ‘object x on earth is not actually making you believe you affected by gravity.’ According were reading per usual when in fact to skeptical tradition, this theory with each statement you read you are (‘all physical objects on earth are killing thousands of innocent sheep in affected by gravity’) is not cer- some pasture in Maryland. You tain, as proved formerly, leading quickly would become skeptical of the probability of the theory to be your need to perform essential human less than one.8 It follows that the functions, such as drinking, eating, probability of the infinite con- breathing, and so on. Although these junctive sentences (‘object x on examples may seem rather deranged, earth is affected by gravity’) the global skeptic, in staying con- sistent with their belief system can 5 Ibid., 299.
Recommended publications
  • Skepticism and Pluralism Ways of Living a Life Of
    SKEPTICISM AND PLURALISM WAYS OF LIVING A LIFE OF AWARENESS AS RECOMMENDED BY THE ZHUANGZI #±r A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 2004 By John Trowbridge Dissertation Committee: Roger T. Ames, Chairperson Tamara Albertini Chung-ying Cheng James E. Tiles David R. McCraw © Copyright 2004 by John Trowbridge iii Dedicated to my wife, Jill iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS In completing this research, I would like to express my appreciation first and foremost to my wife, Jill, and our three children, James, Holly, and Henry for their support during this process. I would also like to express my gratitude to my entire dissertation committee for their insight and understanding ofthe topics at hand. Studying under Roger Ames has been a transformative experience. In particular, his commitment to taking the Chinese tradition on its own terms and avoiding the tendency among Western interpreters to overwrite traditional Chinese thought with the preoccupations ofWestern philosophy has enabled me to broaden my conception ofphilosophy itself. Roger's seminars on Confucianism and Daoism, and especially a seminar on writing a philosophical translation ofthe Zhongyong r:pJm (Achieving Equilibrium in the Everyday), have greatly influenced my own initial attempts to translate and interpret the seminal philosophical texts ofancient China. Tamara Albertini's expertise in ancient Greek philosophy was indispensable to this project, and a seminar I audited with her, comparing early Greek and ancient Chinese philosophy, was part ofthe inspiration for my choice ofresearch topic. I particularly valued the opportunity to study Daoism and the Yijing ~*~ with Chung-ying Cheng g\Gr:p~ and benefited greatly from his theory ofonto-cosmology as a means of understanding classical Chinese philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: the Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory Robert Justin Lipkin
    Cornell Law Review Volume 75 Article 2 Issue 4 May 1990 Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: The Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory Robert Justin Lipkin Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Robert Justin Lipkin, Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: The Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory , 75 Cornell L. Rev. 810 (1990) Available at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr/vol75/iss4/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Cornell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BEYOND SKEPTICISM, FOUNDATIONALISM AND THE NEW FUZZINESS: THE ROLE OF WIDE REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM IN LEGAL THEORY Robert Justin Liphint TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION .............................................. 812 I. FOUNDATIONALISM AND SKEPTICISM ..................... 816 A. The Problem of Skepticism ........................ 816 B. Skepticism and Nihilism ........................... 819 1. Theoretical and PracticalSkepticism ................ 820 2. Subjectivism and Relativism ....................... 821 3. Epistemic and Conceptual Skepticism ................ 821 4. Radical Skepticism ............................... 822 C. Modified Skepticism ............................... 824 II. NEW FOUNDATIONALISM
    [Show full text]
  • Gottlob Frege Patricia A
    Gottlob Frege Patricia A. Blanchette This is the penultimate version of the essay whose final version appears in the Oxford Handbook of Nineteenth-Century German Philosophy, M. Forster and K. Gjesdal (eds), Oxford University Press 2015, pp 207-227 Abstract Gottlob Frege (1848-1925) made significant contributions to both pure mathematics and philosophy. His most important technical contribution, of both mathematical and philosophical significance, is the introduction of a formal system of quantified logic. His work of a more purely- philosophical kind includes the articulation and persuasive defense of anti-psychologism in mathematics and logic, the rigorous pursuit of the thesis that arithmetic is reducible to logic, and the introduction of the distinction between sense and reference in the philosophy of language. Frege’s work has gone on to influence contemporary work across a broad spectrum, including the philosophy of mathematics and logic, the philosophy of language, and the philosophy of mind. This essay describes the historical development of Frege’s central views, and the connections between those views. Introduction Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege was born on November 8, 1848 in the Hanseatic town of Wismar. He was educated in mathematics at the University of Jena and at the University of Göttingen, from which latter he received his doctorate in 1873. He defended his Habilitation the next year in Jena, and took up a position immediately at the University of Jena. Here he spent his entire academic career, lecturing in mathematics and logic, retiring in 1918. His death came on July 26, 1925 in the nearby town of Bad Kleinen.1 Frege is best known for three significant contributions to philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant Was Born in 1724, and Published “Religion Within The
    CHAPTER FIVE THE PHENOMENOLOGY AND ‘FORMATIONS OF CONSCIOUSNESS’ It is this self-construing method alone which enables philosophy to be an objective, demonstrated science. (Hegel 1812) Immanuel Kant was born in 1724, and published “Religion within the limits of Reason” at the age of 70, at about the same time as the young Hegel was writing his speculations on building a folk religion at the seminary in Tübingen and Robespierre was engaged in his ultimately fatal practical experiment in a religion of Reason. Kant was a huge figure. Hegel and all his young philosopher friends were Kantians. But Kant’s system posed as many problems as it solved; to be a Kantian at that time was to be a participant in the project which Kant had initiated, the development of a philosophical system to fulfill the aims of the Enlightenment; and that generally meant critique of Kant. We need to look at just a couple of aspects of Kant’s philosophy which will help us understand Hegel’s approach. “I freely admit,” said Kant , “it was David Hume ’s remark [that Reason could not prove necessity or causality in Nature] that first, many years ago, interrupted my dogmatic slumber and gave a completely differ- ent direction to my enquiries in the field of speculative philosophy” (Kant 1997). Hume’s “Treatise on Human Nature” had been published while Kant was still very young, continuing a line of empiricists and their rationalist critics, whose concern was how knowledge and ideas originate from sensation. Hume was a skeptic; he demonstrated that causality could not be deduced from experience.
    [Show full text]
  • Gottlob Frege: on Sense and Reference Professor Jeeloo Liu [Introduction]
    Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #13] Gottlob Frege: On Sense and Reference Professor JeeLoo Liu [Introduction] I. Language and the World ___ How does language depict reality? Does reality have the same structure as the structure of language? For instance, the basic linguistic structure is a subject and a predicate, and the basic structure of the world is a particular and a universal (e.g. “Socrates is wise”). The subject usually is something of the world and we describe some property it has or does not have. A is F is true is A is really F, is false when A is not F. II. Different Elements of Language Singular terms: Terms that designate particular things Proper names Indexicals: now, today, here, I… Demonstratives: that, this… Pronouns (singular): he, she,… Definite descriptions (the so-and-so): Indefinite (singular) descriptions (a so-and-so) General terms: Terms that designate a kind of things or a certain property Mass nouns ___ natural kind terms (‘water,’ ‘tiger,’ ‘lemon’) ___ non-natural kind terms (‘bachelor’, ‘contract,’ ‘chair’) Adjectives (predicates): colors, shapes, etc. III. Traditional Theories of Meaning Prior to Frege [A] The Ideational Theory ___ The meaning of a linguistic expression is the speaker’s idea that is associated with the expression. [B] Mill’s Theory [the Object Theory] ___ The meaning of a singular term is the thing designated by that term; ___ the meaning of a name is just what the name stands for; the name does not have any other meaning e.g. ‘Socrates’ means Socrates e.g. ‘Dartmouth’ e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • 5. What Matters Is the Motive / Immanuel Kant
    This excerpt is from Michael J. Sandel, Justice: What's the Right Thing to Do?, pp. 103-116, by permission of the publisher. 5. WHAT MATTERS IS THE MOTIVE / IMMANUEL KANT If you believe in universal human rights, you are probably not a utili- tarian. If all human beings are worthy of respect, regardless of who they are or where they live, then it’s wrong to treat them as mere in- struments of the collective happiness. (Recall the story of the mal- nourished child languishing in the cellar for the sake of the “city of happiness.”) You might defend human rights on the grounds that respecting them will maximize utility in the long run. In that case, however, your reason for respecting rights is not to respect the person who holds them but to make things better for everyone. It is one thing to con- demn the scenario of the su! ering child because it reduces overall util- ity, and something else to condemn it as an intrinsic moral wrong, an injustice to the child. If rights don’t rest on utility, what is their moral basis? Libertarians o! er a possible answer: Persons should not be used merely as means to the welfare of others, because doing so violates the fundamental right of self-ownership. My life, labor, and person belong to me and me alone. They are not at the disposal of the society as a whole. As we have seen, however, the idea of self-ownership, consistently applied, has implications that only an ardent libertarian can love—an unfettered market without a safety net for those who fall behind; a 104 JUSTICE minimal state that rules out most mea sures to ease inequality and pro- mote the common good; and a celebration of consent so complete that it permits self-in" icted a! ronts to human dignity such as consensual cannibalism or selling oneself into slav ery.
    [Show full text]
  • A Defense of Moderate Invariantism
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Philosophy Dissertations, Theses, & Student Research Philosophy, Department of July 2008 A DEFENSE OF MODERATE INVARIANTISM Leo W. Iacono University of Nebraska at Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosophydiss Part of the Philosophy Commons Iacono, Leo W., "A DEFENSE OF MODERATE INVARIANTISM" (2008). Philosophy Dissertations, Theses, & Student Research. 1. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosophydiss/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Dissertations, Theses, & Student Research by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. A DEFENSE OF MODERATE INVARIANTISM by Leo Iacono A DISSERTATION Presented to the Faculty of The Graduate College at the University of Nebraska In Partial Fulfillment of Requirements For the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Major: Philosophy Under the Supervision of Professor Albert Casullo Lincoln, Nebraska August, 2008 A DEFENSE OF MODERATE INVARIANTISM Leo Iacono, Ph.D. University of Nebraska, 2008 Adviser: Albert Casullo This dissertation is a defense of moderate invariantism, the traditional epistemological position combining the following three theses: invariantism, according to which the word ‘know’ expresses the same content in every context of use; intellectualism, according to which whether one knows a certain proposition does not depend on one’s practical interests; and anti- skepticism, according to which we really do know much of what we ordinarily take ourselves to know. Moderate invariantism needs defending because of seemingly powerful arguments for contextualism, the view that, like ‘I’ and ‘now’, ‘know’ expresses different contents in different contexts.
    [Show full text]
  • Moonshadows: Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy
    Moonshadows This page intentionally left blank Moonshadows Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy T HE C OWHERDS 2011 Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further Oxford University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education. Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offi ces in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Copyright © 2011 by Oxford University Press, Inc. Published by Oxford University Press, Inc. 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016 www.oup.com Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Oxford University Press. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Cowherds (Authors) Moonshadows : conventional truth in Buddhist philosophy / the Cowherds. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-19-975142-6; ISBN 978-0-19-975143-3 (pbk.) 1. Truth—Religious aspects—Buddhism. 2. Buddhist philosophy. I. Title. BQ4255.C69 2011 121.088′2943—dc22 2009050158 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper Preface This is an unusual volume. It is neither an anthology nor a monograph. We prefer to think of it as a polygraph— a collectively written volume refl ecting the varying views of a large collection of authors.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle, Kant, JS Mill and Rawls Raphael Cohen-Almagor
    1 On the Philosophical Foundations of Medical Ethics: Aristotle, Kant, JS Mill and Rawls Raphael Cohen-Almagor Ethics, Medicine and Public Health (Available online 22 November 2017). Abstract This article aims to trace back some of the theoretical foundations of medical ethics that stem from the philosophies of Aristotle, Immanuel Kant, John Stuart Mill and John Rawls. The four philosophers had in mind rational and autonomous human beings who are able to decide their destiny, who pave for themselves the path for their own happiness. It is argued that their philosophies have influenced the field of medical ethics as they crafted some very important principles of the field. I discuss the concept of autonomy according to Kant and JS Mill, Kant’s concepts of dignity, benevolence and beneficence, Mill’s Harm Principle (nonmaleficence), the concept of justice according to Aristotle, Mill and Rawls, and Aristotle’s concept of responsibility. Key words: Aristotle, Immanuel Kant, John Stuart Mill, autonomy, beneficence, benevolence, dignity, justice, nonmaleficence, responsibility, John Rawls Introduction What are the philosophical foundations of medical ethics? The term ethics is derived from Greek. ἦθος: Noun meaning 'character' or 'disposition'. It is used in Aristotle to denote those aspects of one's character that, through appropriate moral training, develop into virtues. ἦθος is related to the adjective ἠθικός denoting someone or something that relates to disposition, e.g., a philosophical study on character.[1] 2 Ethics is concerned with what is good for individuals and society. It involves developing, systematizing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong behaviour. The Hippocratic Oath (c.
    [Show full text]
  • When the Kingdom of God Became the Kingdom of Ends: Altruism’S Development Into a Normative Ideal
    When the Kingdom of God Became the Kingdom of Ends: Altruism’s Development into a Normative Ideal A Senior Honor Thesis Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for graduation with distinction in Political Science in the College of Social and Behavioral Sciences by Benjamin T. Jones The Ohio State University December 10, 2006 Project Advisors: John M. Parrish, Department of Political Science (Loyola Marymount University) Michael A. Neblo, Department of Political Science (The Ohio State University) Table of Contents Abstract ii Acknowledgements iii Introduction 1 The Paradox at the Heart of Altruism 4 Defining Altruism and Normativity 6 What Are We Looking For? 11 Roadmap of What’s to Come 14 Part I Towards a Problem: The Ancient Debate over Public Life 17 Eudaimonia and Ancient Ethics 18 Plato and Aristotle 24 Epicurus and the Stoics 40 A Solution from an Unlikely Source 47 Augustine’s Reconciliation of the Two Cities 55 Conclusion 63 Part II Self-Love’s Fall from Grace: How Normative Altruism Developed out of the Augustinian Tradition 65 Entangled in Self-love: Augustine’s Normative Argument 67 Augustine Goes Secular 75 Kant’s Problematic Solution 83 Reworking Kant—And Altruism 89 Conclusion 91 Part III The Problems with Normative Altruism 93 Two Conceptions of Altruism 93 Evidence for Altruism on a Descriptive Level 95 Motivational Barriers to Normative Altruism 113 Changing the Way We Talk About Altruism 121 Conclusion 126 Bibliography 131 i Abstract In contemporary moral philosophy, altruism holds a place of prominence. Although a complex idea, the term seeps into everyday discourse, by no means confined to the esoteric language of philosophers and psychologists.
    [Show full text]
  • Does 2 + 3 = 5? : in Defense of a Near Absurdity
    This is a repository copy of Does 2 + 3 = 5? : In Defense of a Near Absurdity. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/127022/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Leng, Mary Catherine orcid.org/0000-0001-9936-5453 (2018) Does 2 + 3 = 5? : In Defense of a Near Absurdity. The Mathematical Intelligencer. ISSN 1866-7414 https://doi.org/10.1007/s00283-017-9752-8 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Does 2 + 3 = 5? In defence of a near absurdity1 Mary Leng (Department of Philosophy, University of York) James Robert Brown asks, “Is anyone really agnostic about 2 + 3 = 5, and willing only to give assent to PA 2 + 3 = 5?” (where PA stands for the Peano axioms for arithmetic). In fact Brown should qualify his ‘anyone’ with ‘anyone not already hopelessly corrupted by philosophy’, since, as he knows full well, there are plenty of so-called nominalist philosophers – myself included – who, wishing to avoid commitment to abstract (that is, non-spatiotemporal, acausal, mind- and language- independent) objects, take precisely this attitude to mathematical claims.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato on the Foundations of Modern Theorem Provers
    The Mathematics Enthusiast Volume 13 Number 3 Number 3 Article 8 8-2016 Plato on the foundations of Modern Theorem Provers Ines Hipolito Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/tme Part of the Mathematics Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Hipolito, Ines (2016) "Plato on the foundations of Modern Theorem Provers," The Mathematics Enthusiast: Vol. 13 : No. 3 , Article 8. Available at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/tme/vol13/iss3/8 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Mathematics Enthusiast by an authorized editor of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. TME, vol. 13, no.3, p.303 Plato on the foundations of Modern Theorem Provers Inês Hipolito1 Nova University of Lisbon Abstract: Is it possible to achieve such a proof that is independent of both acts and dispositions of the human mind? Plato is one of the great contributors to the foundations of mathematics. He discussed, 2400 years ago, the importance of clear and precise definitions as fundamental entities in mathematics, independent of the human mind. In the seventh book of his masterpiece, The Republic, Plato states “arithmetic has a very great and elevating effect, compelling the soul to reason about abstract number, and rebelling against the introduction of visible or tangible objects into the argument” (525c). In the light of this thought, I will discuss the status of mathematical entities in the twentieth first century, an era when it is already possible to demonstrate theorems and construct formal axiomatic derivations of remarkable complexity with artificial intelligent agents the modern theorem provers.
    [Show full text]