Political Libertarianism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Political Libertarianism 9 Political Libertarianism Jacob T. Levy part 1 Benjamin Constant, the great classical liberal theorist and constitutionalist, under- stood the problem. In “The Liberty of the Ancients Compared With That of the 1 Moderns,” his defense and celebration of the modern liberty of pluralism and the private sphere, he warned that the very richness of our modern private lives would lead moderns to neglect what was vital in the liberty of the ancients. Wrapped up in our private lives, we would find democratic politics too burdensome and time- consuming; anxious to protect what is ours, we would find elections too unpredict- able. And so we – by which he meant, especially, the commercial and propertied middle classes – will easily be tempted by the Bonapartist offer: I will take the trouble of governing off your hands and protect you from unpredictable political give and take. Constant was sure that such offers are made in bad faith, and that they would represent a bad exchange even if they were not; they end with even our private modern liberty being at the mercy of strongmen and dictators. But this wouldn’t make us immune to the temptation. He worried, in short, that liberals would not be committed enough democrats to make good constitutionalists. And this would ultimately mean that we are not good enough liberals. For all the transformations of modernity, the regime of religious liberty and free speech, commercial liberty and free trade, and the rule of general law with protection against arbitrary punishment could never be taken for granted. It could always be politically undone. While at first glance Constant’s essay seems to turn on progress driven by grand historical change – the rise of commerce, the Reformation, the abolition of slavery – in an important way it’s an argument about the fundamental status of politics. All our modern goods are vulnerable to bad politics, and they are 1 Benjamin Constant, “The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with That of the Moderns,” in Biancamaria Fontana, ed. and trans., Political Writings (1989)[1819]. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. McGill University 153Libraries, on 06 Sep 2018 at 20:45:33, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108242226.011 154 Jacob T. Levy only secure if we secure them with better politics. And it is of course to this task that he devoted the final decades of his life, both as a key liberal parliamentarian and as a 2 public theorist publishing his Cours de politique constitutionnelle – a course on constitutional politics, aimed at teaching the French citizenry how to practice it. (That the phrase “constitutional politics” sounds as surprising to us today as it does is a good synecdoche for the problems this paper will examine.) While Constant was sometimes (and not very happily) involved in constitution-writing, his constitutional- ism was not ultimately about getting a founding text just right. It was about something more public and more ongoing than that. A classical liberal constitutionalism that is capable of withstanding the populist, authoritarian, and nationalist threats of our day must find a way to overcome Constant’schallenge.Itmustbeabletocometotermswithdemocracy,andmust offer a constitutional politics. It must resist the temptation he described: to so prioritize our modern liberty, our freedom of religion and freedom of commerce, that we disdain the time-consuming business of political democracy and try to find shortcuts. I think that the modern classical liberal renaissance that began in the mid-twentieth century has often neglected politics, and that it can no longer afford to do so. The lack of a properly political libertarianism has in some respects left advocates of the liberal order poorly equipped to defend it in light of rising threats, and in other respects has entangled them directly with those threats themselves. In calling for a political libertarianism I mean a few different, though overlapping, things. The most familiar one to many readers is also probably the least important: 3 an analogy to the political liberalism advocated by John Rawls. Rawls’ liberalism is, in his terms, political not metaphysical; it is not grounded in a particular compre- hensive theory of the human good, like Millian or Kantian autonomy, and it is supposed to be compatible with a wide range of such theories, including religious ones. I certainly think the turn to political liberalism was right, and is applicable to classical liberalism as well. But, notwithstanding some occasional arguments about culturally “thick” libertarianism that would exceed the bounds of the Rawlsian “political,” I think “political not metaphysical” is not especially controversial in 4 classical liberal thought, and I take it for granted rather than examining it further. 2 Posthumously collected as Benjamin Constant, Cours de politique constitutionnelle (1861), 3 John Rawls, Political Liberalism (1993). 4 For more on the relationship between Rawlsian political liberalism and classical liberalism, see Gaus, The Order of Public Reason and The Tyranny of the Ideal. While he does not put it quite this way, Gaus reconstructs political liberalism to show the importance of liberal institutions that can be endorsed by those who espouse a wide range of ultimate visions of justice – a range of visions of the political ideal. In so doing he pushes Rawlsian political liberalism toward the kind of politicalness associated with Waldron and political realism, which will be discussed subsequently. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. McGill University Libraries, on 06 Sep 2018 at 20:45:33, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108242226.011 Political Libertarianism 155 But the deflationary ambition of Rawlsian political liberalism only goes so far. Rawls insists on the importance of widespread endorsement of liberalism as a “freestanding political doctrine,” and maintains that the stability of a constitutional order is not secure if it rests on merely strategic action that generates a modus vivendi. Religious liberty might begin in the standoff among religious groups none of which are powerful enough to stamp out the others, but it must eventually be endorsed as a political value in its own right. Without meaning to import the whole Rawlsian apparatus, I do think that this much must be true of a political libertarianism. It should be a thin doctrine about political and legal institutions, not a comprehensive account of the good life; but it should still be a doctrine and it cannot do without affirmation by adherents. Although I am much more sympathetic 5 to modus vivendi theorizing (and political practice) than Rawls or Rawlsians, I ultimately agree that we cannot simply back into a liberal order through clever balancing of interests or institutional standoffs. There is no constitutional design so clever, no multiplication of veto points so elaborate, that the liberal order can be formally guaranteed. There need to be some actual liberals involved. A second sense of “political” is the ordinary, everyday sense of the word. Liberal- ism is a set of ideas and principles, but they are ideas and principles about what is to be done in politics. I have elsewhere referred to liberalism, conservatism, and 6 socialism as “party ideas.” In the era of modern politics anticipated by British parliamentarism in the eighteenth century and fully inaugurated by the American founding and the French Revolution, what David Hume characterized as “parties of 7 principle” have been crucial institutional participants, making representative dem- ocracy in large states possible and coherent, allowing some measure of political accountability, and extending governmental time horizons beyond the career of one or another ambitious person. I will discuss below the centrality of both parties and representative democracy to a revitalized liberal constitutionalism in Section 3 of this chapter. But for now, I will offer a slogan to parallel “political not metaphysical.” This second sense is “political not contractarian.” As against the recurring fantasy of being done with political work, of a great supermajoritarian once-and-for-all victory or a hypothetical and imputed unanimity, I suggest that we need a firm liberal embrace of electoral democracy that includes the willingness to work for temporary plurality victories and that understands the legitimacy of temporary plurality losses. This leads directly to the most important sense of “political” for current purposes: that used by Jeremy Waldron in his call for “political political theory,” and by Bernard Williams in his recommendation of “realism in political theory” that treats 5 See discussion in Jacob T. Levy, “Contextualism, Constitutionalism, and Modus Vivendi approaches,” in Cultural Pluralism and Political Theory, Anthony Laden and David Owen, eds. (2007) 6 Jacob T. Levy, Rationalism, Pluralism, and Freedom 10 (2015). 7 David Hume, “Of Parties in General,” in Eugene F. Miller, ed., Essays Moral, Political, Literary (1987). Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. McGill University Libraries, on 06 Sep 2018 at 20:45:33, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108242226.011 156 Jacob T. Levy political conditions and norms as irreducible to moral conditions and norms: political not juridical, political not moral-philosophical. Waldron argues that a political political theory must rest on the sense of understanding that we exist amidst people who disagree with us, and we must share institutional space with them, not wish them away. Theories of justice and rights derived philosophically, especially when they are theorized in a way that demands they be constitutionalized and 8 imposed judicially, fail to be properly political. Waldron’s recent work in this direction aligns him closely with an important development in political theory in the past decade or so: the turn to, in a specialized sense, “realism” associated 9 especially with Williams and William Galston.
Recommended publications
  • Conceptual Framework Spring, 2014
    Conceptual Framework Spring, 2014 Conceptual Framework University of Arkansas at Monticello School of Education 1 Conceptual Framework Spring, 2014 UNIVERSITY OF ARKANSAS AT MONTICELLO (UAM) SCHOOL OF EDUCATION THE CONCEPTUAL FRAMEWORK Introduction The University of Arkansas at Monticello (UAM) has a rich educational heritage of teaching and learning that has provided a “Century of Opportunity” for the residents of southeast Arkansas and the state since its humble beginnings as The Fourth District Agricultural School in 1909. To understand the history of teacher education at UAM, the beginnings of the university itself must be explored. Classes began in 1911 with students in the sixth through twelfth grades attending. Freshman and sophomore college courses were added in 1923 and the institution was accredited as a junior college in 1928. Senior college courses were added in 1933 and, the following year, the first degrees were granted by Arkansas A&M College. The campus was established on what was once part of a 6,000 acre cotton plantation owned by Judge and Mrs. William Turner Wells. “Judge Billy” and “Miss Pattie” were prominent figures in southeast Arkansas and the name of Wells is imbedded in the social and political history of the state. Judge and Mrs. Wells lived the idyllic life of Southern planters and entertained frequently in their plantation home that was located on what is now the site of the Fred J. Taylor Library. In April of 1909, the Arkansas General Assembly passed Act 100 which created four district agricultural schools. For the southeast district, descendants of Judge and Mrs. Wells offered the Wells Plantation home site with 200 acres of contiguous land for the new school/experiment farm.
    [Show full text]
  • An Ethical Defense of Global-Warming Skepticism —William Irwin and Brian Williams Adam Smith on Economic Happiness —Douglas J
    REASON PAPERS A Journal of Interdisciplinary Normative Studies Articles An Ethical Defense of Global-Warming Skepticism —William Irwin and Brian Williams Adam Smith on Economic Happiness —Douglas J. Den Uyl and Douglas B. Rasmussen Direct and Overall Liberty: Areas and Extent of Disagreement —Daniel B. Klein and Michael J. Clark Violence and Postmodernism: A Conceptual Analysis —Iddo Landau Providing for Aesthetic Experience —Jason Holt Why Has Aesthetic Formalism Fallen on Hard Times? —David E. W. Fenner Austro-Libertarian Publishing: A Survey and Critique —Walter E. Block Discussion Notes Left-Libertarianism—An Oxymoron? —Tibor R. Machan Rejoinder to Hoppe on Indifference Once Again —Walter E. Block with William Barnett II Review Essay Review Essay: Edward Feser’s Locke and Eric Mack’s John Locke —Irfan Khawaja Book Review James Stacey Taylor’s Practical Autonomy and Bioethics —Thomas D. Harter Vol. 32 Fall 2010 Editor-in-Chief: Aeon J. Skoble Managing Editors: Carrie-Ann Biondi Irfan Khawaja Editor Emeritus: Tibor R. Machan Editorial Board: Jordon Barkalow Walter Block Peter Boettke Donald Boudreaux Nicholas Capaldi Andrew I. Cohen Douglas J. Den Uyl Randall Dipert John Hasnas Stephen Hicks John Hospers William T. Irwin Kelly Dean Jolley N. Stephan Kinsella Stephen Kershnar Israel M. Kirzner Shawn Klein Leonard Liggio Eric Mack Fred D. Miller, Jr. Jennifer Mogg James Otteson Douglas Rasmussen Ralph Raico Lynn Scarlett David Schmidtz James Stacey Taylor Edward Younkins Matthew Zwolinski Reason Papers Vol. 32 Editorial The editorial to volume 26 of Reason Papers began with this: Reason Papers was founded in 1974 by Professor Tibor R. Machan, who edited the first twenty-five volumes.
    [Show full text]
  • The Russian Revolutions: the Impact and Limitations of Western Influence
    Dickinson College Dickinson Scholar Faculty and Staff Publications By Year Faculty and Staff Publications 2003 The Russian Revolutions: The Impact and Limitations of Western Influence Karl D. Qualls Dickinson College Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.dickinson.edu/faculty_publications Part of the European History Commons Recommended Citation Qualls, Karl D., "The Russian Revolutions: The Impact and Limitations of Western Influence" (2003). Dickinson College Faculty Publications. Paper 8. https://scholar.dickinson.edu/faculty_publications/8 This article is brought to you for free and open access by Dickinson Scholar. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Karl D. Qualls The Russian Revolutions: The Impact and Limitations of Western Influence After the collapse of the Soviet Union, historians have again turned their attention to the birth of the first Communist state in hopes of understanding the place of the Soviet period in the longer sweep of Russian history. Was the USSR an aberration from or a consequence of Russian culture? Did the Soviet Union represent a retreat from westernizing trends in Russian history, or was the Bolshevik revolution a product of westernization? These are vexing questions that generate a great deal of debate. Some have argued that in the late nineteenth century Russia was developing a middle class, representative institutions, and an industrial economy that, while although not as advanced as those in Western Europe, were indications of potential movement in the direction of more open government, rule of law, free market capitalism. Only the Bolsheviks, influenced by an ideology imported, paradoxically, from the West, interrupted this path of Russian political and economic westernization.
    [Show full text]
  • Book Review | a Duty to Resist: When Disobedience Should Be Uncivil by Candice Delmas Page 1 of 4
    Democratic Audit: Book Review | A Duty to Resist: When Disobedience Should Be Uncivil by Candice Delmas Page 1 of 4 Book Review | A Duty to Resist: When Disobedience Should Be Uncivil by Candice Delmas In A Duty to Resist: When Disobedience Should Be Uncivil, Candice Delmas aims to foster understanding of resistance to injustice as a capacious concept that can include the possibility of lawful dissent, principled disobedience and revolution. This is a provocative and rewarding contribution to the literature, writes Suzanne Smith, that is particularly valuable for its attention to the question of the situational conditions of obligatory, potentially uncivil resistance. Marchers carrying banner reading ‘We march with Selma!’, Harlem, New York City. Picture: Stanley Wolfson, New York World Telegram & Sun. This image is available from the United States Library of Congress‘s Prints and Photographs division under the digital ID cph.3c35695. No known copyright restrictions) A Duty to Resist: When Disobedience Should Be Uncivil. Candice Delmas. Oxford University Press. 2018. ‘A commonly heard complaint’, remarked Alexis de Tocqueville in his analysis of events leading up to 1789, ‘is that the French have no respect for law’. To his mind, given the corruption characteristic of the Ancien Régime, this was not surprising. He blamed this lack of respect on the deficit of ‘intermediary powers’ capable of integrating the concerns of ‘private individuals’ with the policies of the state. Yet what Tocqueville wrote with respect to attitudes concerning law in pre-Revolutionary France is sometimes also said of the post-1945 Republic, when intermediary powers were quite robust. No sooner did World War II end than did resistance – often violent – arise against dirigisme économique.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critique of John Stuart Mill Chris Daly
    Southern Illinois University Carbondale OpenSIUC Honors Theses University Honors Program 5-2002 The Boundaries of Liberalism in a Global Era: A Critique of John Stuart Mill Chris Daly Follow this and additional works at: http://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/uhp_theses Recommended Citation Daly, Chris, "The Boundaries of Liberalism in a Global Era: A Critique of John Stuart Mill" (2002). Honors Theses. Paper 131. This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the University Honors Program at OpenSIUC. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of OpenSIUC. For more information, please contact [email protected]. r The Boundaries of Liberalism in a Global Era: A Critique of John Stuart Mill Chris Daly May 8, 2002 r ABSTRACT The following study exanunes three works of John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, Utilitarianism, and Three Essays on Religion, and their subsequent effects on liberalism. Comparing the notion on individual freedom espoused in On Liberty to the notion of the social welfare in Utilitarianism, this analysis posits that it is impossible for a political philosophy to have two ultimate ends. Thus, Mill's liberalism is inherently flawed. As this philosophy was the foundation of Mill's progressive vision for humanity that he discusses in his Three Essays on Religion, this vision becomes paradoxical as well. Contending that the neo-liberalist global economic order is the contemporary parallel for Mill's religion of humanity, this work further demonstrates how these philosophical flaws have spread to infect the core of globalization in the 21 st century as well as their implications for future international relations.
    [Show full text]
  • CONCEPTUAL FRAMEWORK Christian Brothers University
    CONCEPTUAL FRAMEWORK Christian Brothers University Christian Brothers University Education Unit Conceptual Framework The conceptual framework of the education unit has been influenced by the mission and core values of the university and the mission statement of the School of Arts. The university’s mission statement is: Educating minds. Touching hearts. Remembering the presence of God. We believe that this mission statement is best represented by the core values of the university. The core values are: Faith: Our belief in God permeates every facet of the University's life. Service: We reach out to serve one another and those beyond our campus. Community: We work to build better communities and a better society. The mission statement for the School of Arts was rewritten in 2013 and states: To advance the Lasallian synthesis of knowledge and service by teaching students to think, to communicate, to evaluate, and to appreciate. Building on the core values and the mission statement are the Department of Education’s candidate proficiencies as identified in the conceptual framework. This conceptual framework includes four themes – Servant- Leader, Effective and Reflective Practitioner, Champion of Individual Learner Potential, and Builder of Vibrant Learning Communities. These themes are outlined below: Theme/Core Concept: Servant-Leader 1. Candidates exhibit moral and ethical responsibility, skills of leadership, service and professionalism that represent concern for the welfare of others above self-concern and self- interest. 2. Candidates express commitment to the human mission of education and to the goals of access, equity, and opportunity. 3. Candidates show respect for others by honoring the worth and dignity of children, families, community, and colleagues.
    [Show full text]
  • How Far Is Vienna from Chicago? an Essay on the Methodology of Two Schools of Dogmatic Liberalism
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Paqué, Karl-Heinz Working Paper — Digitized Version How far is Vienna from Chicago? An essay on the methodology of two schools of dogmatic liberalism Kiel Working Paper, No. 209 Provided in Cooperation with: Kiel Institute for the World Economy (IfW) Suggested Citation: Paqué, Karl-Heinz (1984) : How far is Vienna from Chicago? An essay on the methodology of two schools of dogmatic liberalism, Kiel Working Paper, No. 209, Kiel Institute of World Economics (IfW), Kiel This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/46781 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence. www.econstor.eu Kieler Arbeitspapiere Kiel Working Papers Working Paper No.
    [Show full text]
  • Pablo Beramendi, Silja Häusermann, Herbert
    Socio-Economic Review, 2016, Vol. 14, No. 2, 383–394 doi: 10.1093/ser/mww007 Review Symposium Review Symposium Pablo Beramendi, Silja Häusermann, Herbert Kitschelt, and Hanspeter Kriesi (eds), 2015, Downloaded from The Politics of Advanced Capitalism, Cambridge University Press http://ser.oxfordjournals.org/ Key words: industrial relations, labor market policy inequality, institutional change, liberalization JEL classification: J50 labor-management relations, trade unions, and collective bargaining, P16 political economy Peter A. Hall* Minda de Gunzburg Center for European Studies, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, USA at London School of economics on June 14, 2016 *Correspondence: [email protected] Despite an efflorescence of work, much of it in this journal, the study of comparative political economy suffers from two conspicuous lacunae. The field continues to display the marks of its birth in an era when manufacturing still lay at the core of most economies. Although attention gradually shifted towards services, seen as a growing source of employment if a drag on prod- uctivity, with a few exceptions, the field has been slow to consider how a ‘fourth industrial revolution’ in information technology and biotech might be changing the nature of employ- ment and the basis for growth in the developed democracies. The eyes of the field also remained fixed on producer group politics, seeing it as the motor for developments in the political economy. The study of trade unions and employers’ associa- tions has often been its bread and butter. As a result, there has long been a gulf between studies in comparative political economy and studies of electoral politics, as Kitschelt et al.
    [Show full text]
  • The Restless Liberalism of Alexis De Tocqueville
    FILOZOFIA ___________________________________________________________________________Roč. 72, 2017, č. 9 THE RESTLESS LIBERALISM OF ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE JAKUB TLOLKA, London School of Economics and Political Science, London, UK TLOLKA, J.: The Restless Liberalism of Alexis de Tocqueville FILOZOFIA, 72, No. 9, 2017, pp. 736-747 This essay attempts to contextualise the purported novelty of Alexis de Tocqueville’s particular brand of liberalism. It regards the author not as an heir or precursor to any given political tradition, but rather as a compelled syncretist whose primary philosophical concern was the moral significance of the democratic age. It suggests that Tocqueville devised his ‘new political science’ with a keen view to the existential implications of modernity. In order to support that suggestion, the essay explores the genealogy of Tocqueville’s moral and political thought and draws a relation between his analysis of democracy and his personal experience of modernity. Keywords: A. de Tocqueville – Modernity – Liberalism – Inquiétude – Religion Introduction. Relatively few authors in the history of political thought have produced an intellectual legacy of such overarching resonance as Alexis de Tocqueville. Even fewer, perhaps, have so persistently eluded ordinary analytical and exegetical frameworks, presenting to each astute observer a face so nuanced as to preclude serious interpretive consensus. As writes Lakoff (Lakoff 1998), ‘disagreement over textual interpretation in the study of political thought is not uncommon’. However, ‘it usually arises around those who left writings of a patently divergent character’ (p. 437). When we thus consider the ‘extraordinarily coherent and consistent nature’ of Alexis de Tocqueville’s political philosophy, it appears somewhat odd that the academic consensus surrounding that author relates almost exclusively to the grandeur of his intellectual achievement (Lukacs 1959, 6).
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Arendt's on Revolution After the Fall of the Wall
    Keeping the Republic: Reading Arendt’s On Revolution after the Fall of the Wall Dick Howard Introduction: From where do you speak, comrade? Two decades after the fall of the Wall seemed to announce – by default, as an unexpected gift – the triumph of democracy, optimism appears at best naïve, at worst an ideological manipulation of the most cynical type. The hope was that the twin forms of modern anti-politics – the imaginary planned society and the equally imaginary invisible hand of the market place – would be replaced by the rule of the demos; citizens together would determine the values of the commonwealth. The reality was at first the ‘New World Order’ of George H.W. Bush; then the indecisive interregnum of the Clinton years; and now the crass take over of democratic rhetoric by the neo-conservatives of George W. Bush. ‘Man is born free, yet everywhere he is in chains,’ wrote Rousseau at the outset of The Social Contract; how this came about was less important, he continued, than what made it legitimate: that was what needed explanation. So it is today; what is it about democracy that makes it the greatest threat to its own existence? In this context, it is well to reread Hannah Arendt’s On Revolution, published in 1963. On returning recently to my old (1965) paperback edition, I was struck by the spare red and black design of the cover, which was not (as I thought for a moment) a subtle allusion to the conflict of communism and anarchism for the realization of ‘true’ democracy, but simply the backdrop against which the editor stressed these sentences: ‘With nuclear power at a stalemate, revolutions have become the principal political factor of our time.
    [Show full text]
  • A Special Supplement: Reflections on Violence by Hannah Arendt | the New York Review of Books
    A Special Supplement: Reflections on Violence by Hannah Arendt | The New York Review of Books EMAIL Tweet Share A Special Supplement: Refections on Violence Hannah Arendt FEBRUARY 27, 1969 ISSUE I These reflections were provoked by the events and debates of the last few years, as seen against the background of the twentieth century. Indeed this century has become, as Lenin predicted, a century of wars and revolutions, hence a century of that violence which is currently believed to be their common denominator. There is, however, another factor in the present situation which, though predicted by nobody, is of at least equal importance. The technical development of implements of violence has now reached the point where no political goal could conceivably correspond to their destructive potential or justify their actual use in armed conflict. Hence, warfare—since times immemorial the final merciless arbiter in international disputes—has lost much of its effectiveness and nearly all of its glamor. “The apocalyptic” chess game between the superpowers, that is, between those that move on the highest plane of our civilization, is being played according to the rule: “if either ‘wins’ it is the end of both.”1 Moreover the game bears no resemblance to whatever war games preceded it. Its “rational” goal is mutual deterrence, not victory. Since violence—as distinct from power, force, or strength—always needs implements (as Engels pointed out long ago),2 the revolution in technology, a revolution in tool-making, was especially marked in warfare. The very substance of violent action is ruled by the question of means and ends, whose chief characteristic, if applied to human affairs, has always been that the end is in danger of being overwhelmed by the means, which it both justifies and needs.
    [Show full text]
  • Course Syllabus
    Freedom Political Theory Project Course Description: Freedom has been called the greatest political concept of the modern world. But what is freedom? And if freedom is important, what should we do about it? Does freedom conflict with other important values, such as gender equality or distributive fairness? Can political systems that claim allegiance to freedom also make room for other values? Is the best society the one that cares only about freedom? Format: This is a demanding, reading intensive freshman seminar. As a seminar, classroom discussion is of the utmost importance. Be sure to complete all the readings before class meets each week, and come to class ready to join in the conversation. In this class, we are a team. So join in. Presentations: Each week, seminar will be opened by a brief presentation prepared by a team of two students. When it is your turn to present, your mission is NOT to teach the whole class, or to become world-class experts on the issues at hand. Rather, each presentation team is expected to study the assigned readings carefully, briefly summarize the main points, and to identify a few fundamental questions or challenges posed by the readings that they found most interesting (or confusing!). Requirements: 1. Students are expected to attend in each seminar, and to participate actively. We will allow one excused absence during the semester. Any additional absence will be penalized by a grade unit deduction from your final grade (so, if you had an A++, your final grade would be reduced to a measly A+, though of course if you had a B-, that would become a C+.
    [Show full text]