The Stoic Method of Happiness

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Stoic Method of Happiness Haverford College Haverford Scholarship Faculty Publications Philosophy 2006 The Stoic Method of Happiness Ian Blecher Haverford College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.haverford.edu/philosophy_facpubs Repository Citation Blecher, I. “The Stoic Method of Happiness” Apeiron 39(2):157-176. 2006. This Journal Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Haverford Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Haverford Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. TheStoic Method of Happiness Ian Blecher Leta stoicarise who shall reveal the resources of man. - Emerson 1 TheStoics - mostof them, anyway1 - heldthat: (1) Virtueis thesole good. (2) Outsidethe scope of virtue, some items are preferable to others. Not,however, without discomfort. From (1), and fromancient plati- tudesconnecting goodness with happiness, we mayinfer that virtue is notonly necessary, but also sufficientfor happiness; and thattherefore happinessis alwayswithin reach, even on therack (de Fin III 42; cf.EN 1000b22-1101a8).To be fair,the Stoics never claimed happiness must be alwayswithin easy reach; they were comfortable with the thought that onlySocrates and Cato theYounger - ifanyone at all - had thestuff forit.2 But this will hardly ease theimpression - widespread,unfortu- nately- thattheirs is a severeand joyless doctrine - thus,for example, Hegel,in thePhenomenology ofSpirit: 'Stoicism is the freedomwhich 1 DiogenesLaertius reports that Panaetius and Posidonius reject (1) (DL VII 103,128). 2 Fora discussionof the problems posed by this possibility, see Inwood2005. APEIRONa journalfor ancient philosophy and science 0003-6390/2006/3902157-176 $20.00 ©Academic Printing & Publishing This content downloaded from 165.82.134.26 on Fri, 2 Jan 2015 08:42:53 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 158 Ian Blecher alwayscomes directly out ofbondage [viz.,]freedom in thought... a truthlacking the fullness of life' (§§ 199-200).3 In replyit might be observedthat the Stoics also expoundeddoctrine (2); thatthey demonstrated sufficient concern for 'the fullness of life', for 'theresources of man', just by rankingexternal goods. But- ranking themaccording to what ? Itis notthat it is obviouslyincoherent to prefer healthand wealth and renown4 to say, having one's limbs torn from their sockets.5It is thatthe sense in whichsuch thingsare supposedto be preferredis difficultto makeout ifthey are notsimply better than the alternatives- if,that is, they are irrelevantto happiness.If it is intelli- gibleto prefersomething, one would think,this can onlybe because havingit is good (thoughperhaps in a sensedifferent from the sense in whichvirtue is good)(de Fin TV 20-2, 41, 57-60). This, presumably, is what movesAristotle to saythat virtue and its material conditions are needed fora happylife. ButAristotle's view is notwithout problems.6 The crassconclusion thatan increaseof wealth or other so-called external good should always cause greaterhappiness cannot be easilyavoided once some role in the happylife has beenprovided external goods. In particular,it cannotbe avoidedby attributingto Aristotlethe view thatonly that a minimum standardof external goods is required,increase beyond which does not makefor a betterlife.7 For thisis evidentlyto allow thatdecrease of externalgoods below that point makes for a worselife: and that Aristotle was unwillingto concede.'[T]he happy man can neverbecome miser- able,'says he (EN llOlaó). Whatis leftis somethingof a hodgepodge: 'Successor failure in life does not depend on [externalgoods], but human life,as we said, needs theseas well,while excellent activities or their oppositesare what determine happiness or the reverse' (EN 1100b9-ll). 3 Cf. also Diss 1 19. 4 For catalogs of externalgoods, see, e.g., de Fin TV20, 49. 5 This is not,however, a unanimous opinion. For Pyrrho,Herillus of Carthage and Aristoof Chios, among others,external goods simplydid not rate (de Fin II 35, 43; IV 42f.;V 23; DL VÜ 160, 165). 6 The positiondeveloped in thisparagraph closely followsthat of Julia Annas 1993, 364-84. 7 Cf. Annas 1993,382. This content downloaded from 165.82.134.26 on Fri, 2 Jan 2015 08:42:53 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheStoic Method of Happiness 159 This sounds somethinglike the Stoicview, actually:but ratherthan followit through to thelogical (though pruna facie unintuitive) conclu- sionthat external goods arenot, after all, good, Aristotle maintains that humanlife needs externalgoods if it is to attainto theevocative but obscurestatus of 'blessed' (¿iccmpioç - EN 1100b25et passim). And this is unhelpful.For either it is better to be blessedthan to be happy,in which case we oughtproperly to have in view the one and notthe other as our ultimateend (and theoriginal problem with happiness now arisesfor blessedness),or itis notbetter to be blessedthan to be happy,in which caseit is unclearwhy one should want to be blessed.(Indeed it is unclear in preciselythe sense that it is unclearwhy one shouldwant external goodsif having them does notmake for a betterlife, which is ofcourse thequestion in responseto which the category of 'blessedness' was first introduced.) I agreewith Julia Annas that claims (1) and (2) oughtto be regarded as an attemptto clarify and stabilizeAristotle's position8 (though I think she is wrongabout how theStoics think it ought to be revised).Now it seemsto me that any such attempt can succeed only if it does notsimply cordonoff virtue on theone handand externalgoods on theother, and declarefor each a separatesense of 'good' and a correspondingsense of 'happy'.For from this the problem of the relation of the two sorts of good inevitablyarises. We would be leftwith a versionof, and not an improve- mentupon, Aristotle's solution to theproblem (indeed, the Stoics were oftenaccused - unfairly,I think - offailing sufficiently to distinguish themselvesfrom Aristotle in thisrespect [cf. e.g., de Fin TV11-13, 43; Commnot 1071B-C]). The right approach will instead derive both claims (1) and (2) froma singleaccount of actions - one whichshows them to have bothvirtue and externalgoods in view,but in such a way that successwith regard to theone is necessaryfor the success of a given action,while success with regard to theother is not. Theclaim of this paper is thatwhat I havecalled 'the right approach' is, indeed,the Stoic approach. I shall try,in whatfollows, to give an accountof it. 8 I do notclaim, nor does Annas, that the Stoics took themselves to be respondingto Aristotlein particular. They may simply have had inmind a positionsimilar to his; orthey may have been thinking of a positiondeveloped by Aristotle's followers. This content downloaded from 165.82.134.26 on Fri, 2 Jan 2015 08:42:53 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 160 Ian Blecher 2 A popular sortof introduction to theStoic conceptionof virtue takes the formof an analogybetween virtue and some set ofeveryday doings. The - following drawn by several Stoics,beginning with Antipaterin the thirdcentury BC9 is perhaps thebest-known example: Justas a manwhose task it is to shoot(conliniare) a spear or arrowat somethinghas, as his ultimateend, to do everythingin his powerto shootstraight, so itis withwhat we callthe ultimate end in life.In the case (ofthe archer), it is to shootstraight that he mustdo all he can; nonetheless,it is to do all he can to dischargethe task (of shooting straight)that is (really)his ultimate end. So itis withwhat we call the supremegood in life. But to hit something is, as we say,to be "selected" not"sought", (de Fin III 22; cf.Stob 5b3, 6a-c; Comm not 1071B-D.) The manuscript has perhaps been corrupted somewhat,10and Cicero's Latin is uncharacteristicallydense here (perhaps in an attempt to ape thestyle of Stoic dialectic[cf. de Fin Hl 19]). The idea seems in any case to be this:first, the ultimate end fora given archeris not thata given targetbe hit;rather his ultimateend is thathe do the thingsrequired of him by the task in the appropriateway. And second, someone tryingto be virtuousis like our archerin thisrespect. The analogy has neverfared well outside theStoa. Posidonius is said to have thought it contained 'a manifestinconsistency and nothing honorable or productiveof happiness' (fr.187; LS 1, 405). Alexander of Aphrodisiascalled it 'absurd' (de An II 164.6;LS 1, 401). And, of course, thereis Plutarch'scanonical objection: Ifsomeone were to say that archer does everything inhis power not for thesake of hitting the target but for the sake of doing everything in his power,one would suppose him to be speakingin riddling and fantastic way.So itis withthe idiots who insistthat the end ofaiming at things inaccordance with nature is notthe getting but the taking and selecting ofthem, and thatbeing healthy is noteach man's end in his desire and 9 Annas1993, 402. Striker 1996, 310 gives another suggestion about its origin. Cf. also Alpers-Gölz1976, 82. 10 Butcf. LS 2,398. This content downloaded from 165.82.134.26 on Fri, 2 Jan 2015 08:42:53 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheStoic Method of Happiness 161 pursuitof health, but on thecontrary being healthy has referenceto the desireand pursuit of being healthy. For what is thedifference between someone'ssaying that health has comeinto being for the sake of drugs, notdrugs for the sake ofhealth, and one who makesthe selection of drugsand theircomposition and use morechoiceworthy than
Recommended publications
  • Commentary on Englert Martha Nussbaum I Admire Englert's
    Commentary on Englert Martha Nussbaum I admire Englert's paper. I find its major conclusions entirely convincing: (1) the analysis of the difference between Epicurean and Stoic attitudes to suicide; (2) the account of the original Stoic position; (3) the argument that Seneca is an orthodox Stoic about suicide; and (4) the very interesting claims about the role of dif- ferent sorts of freedom in Seneca's arguments. Although I am persuaded by his analysis, I am inclined to be somewhat more critical of the Stoic position than he seems inclined to be: for I think that in a crucial way it is internally incoherent. In what follows, therefore, I want to focus on a problem in the Stoic account itself, with respect to the ambivalence the suicide theory reveals toward the importance of externals. I shall do this by focusing on one line of argument leading to suicide, in Seneca's De Ira.l 1. The Stoics famously hold that only virtue is worth choosing for its own sake. And virtue all by itself suffices for a complete- ly fulfilled and fulfilling human life, that is, for eudaimonia. Virtue is something unaffected by external contingency—both, apparently, as to its acquisition and as to its maintenance once acquired? Items that are not fully under the control of the 1. My interpretation of this work is developed at greater length in Nussbaum 1994. My general account of Stoic virtue theory and its relationship to the call for the extirpation of passion is in chapter 10, my detailed analysis of the argu- ments about anger in the De Ira in chapter 11.
    [Show full text]
  • Aidws in Epictetus Rachana Kamtekar Classical Philology, Vol. 93, No. 2
    Aidws in Epictetus Rachana Kamtekar Classical Philology, Vol. 93, No. 2. (Apr., 1998), pp. 136-160. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0009-837X%28199804%2993%3A2%3C136%3AAIE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-0 Classical Philology is currently published by The University of Chicago Press. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/ucpress.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is an independent not-for-profit organization dedicated to and preserving a digital archive of scholarly journals. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Thu May 17 17:41:17 2007 AIARX IN EPICTETUS RACHANA KAMTEKAR N CHARACTERIZING THE virtuous ideal, Epictetus departs from the tradi- tional list of Stoic virtues.' Often, instead of describing the virtuous I person as dv6psio~(courageous), ohcppov (temperate), cpp6v~poq(pru- dent), or ~~KULO<(just), Epictetus says that he is Ehe60epoq
    [Show full text]
  • Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,  (), – at – )
    Offprint from OXFORDSTUDIES INANCIENT PHILOSOPHY EDITOR:BRADINWOOD VOLUMEXLIX 3 MAKINGSENSEOF STOICINDIFFERENTS JACOBKLEIN . Introduction A to the older Stoics, virtue is the only good and the sole constituent of happiness, but certain ordinary objects of desire, such as health and wealth, possess a kind of value that makes them fitting objects of pursuit. These items are indifferent, the Stoics say, but nonetheless promoted. Though health and wealth make no con- tribution to the human good, the Stoics argue that we are to pursue them whenever circumstances allow. Indeed, a failure to maintain one’s health and wealth in ordinary circumstances is a failure of ra- tionality and an impediment to virtue, in their view. This doctrine has provoked criticism in ancient commentators and puzzlement in modern ones. An ancient line of criticism— prominent in Plutarch and Alexander of Aphrodisias—can be © Jacob Klein For help with this paper, I especially thank Terry Irwin and Tad Brennan. Terry patiently read, commented on, and discussed early drafts, helping me formulate and sharpen my claims. Though I have ventured to disagree with him, I am grateful for the skill and patience with which he pressed me to clarify my views. Tad Brennan provided input and guidance at a later stage. I owe much to his work on Stoicism and to our conversations over the years. I am especially grateful for feedback re- ceived from students in his graduate course on Stoic ethics, offered at Cornell Uni- versity in the Spring of . Brad Inwood provided extensive comments on later drafts, correcting mistakes and suggesting improvements.
    [Show full text]
  • Remembering Socrates Philosophical Essays
    Remembering Socrates Philosophical Essays Edited by LINDSAY JUDSON and VASSILIS KARASMANIS CLARENDON PRESS Á OXFORD 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With oYces in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York ß the several contributors 2006 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 2006 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose the same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Data available Typeset by SPI Publisher Services, Pondicherry, India Printed in Great Britain on acid-free paper by Biddles Ltd., King’s Lynn, Norfolk ISBN 0-19-927613-7 978-0-19-927613-4 13579108642 Contents Notes on Contributors and Editors vii Introduction 1 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Seneca-Letters.Pdf
    CLARENDON LATER ANCIENT PHILOSOPHERS Series editors: Jonathan Barnes, Universite´ de Paris IV—Sorbonne and A. A. Long, University of California, Berkeley SENECA SELECTED PHILOSOPHICAL LETTERS Seneca’s Letters to Lucilius are a rich source of information about ancient Stoicism, an influential work for early modern philosophers, and a fascinating philosophical document in their own right. This selection of the letters aims to include those which are of greatest philosophical interest, especially those which highlight the debates between Stoics and Platonists or Aristotelians in the first century AD, and the issue, still important today, of how technical philosophical enquiry is related to the various purposes for which philosophy is practised. In addition to examining the philosophical content of each letter, Brad Inwood’s commentary discusses the literary and historical background of the letters and to their relationship with other prose works by Seneca. Seneca is the earliest Stoic author for whom we have access to a large number of complete works, and these works were highly influential in later centuries. He was also a politically influential advisor to the Roman emperor Nero and a celebrated author of prose and verse. His philosophical acuity and independence of mind make his works exciting and challenging for the modern reader. Brad Inwood is Professor of Classics and Philosophy at the University of Toronto. PUBLISHEDINTHESERIES Alcinous: The Handbook of Platonism John Dillon Epictetus: Discourses, Book Robert Dobbin Galen: On the Therapeutic Method, Books I and II R. J. Hankinson Porphyry: Introduction Jonathan Barnes Seneca: Selected Philosophical Letters Brad Inwood Sextus Empiricus: Against the Ethicists Richard Bett Sextus Empiricus: Against the Grammarians David Blank SENECA SELECTED PHILOSOPHICAL LETTERS Translated with an Introduction and Commentary by BRAD INWOOD 1 1 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoic Ethics RICHARD BETT
    richard bett 27 Stoic Ethics RICHARD BETT Introduction The proper interpretation of the role of nature is among the most central, difficult, and debated topics in the study of Stoic ethics. Our sources make clear that, at several points in the exposition of their ethical system, the Stoics make an appeal to nature. We are told of numerous different Stoic formulations of the end or goal of life (the telos); most of them refer to some form of attunement to, or connectedness with, nature as the ideal to be strived for. Again, the Stoics have a complicated story to tell about human development – a development that might optimally result in the attain- ment of this ideal – in which the types of impulses given to us by nature figure promin- ently. And even for those who fall short of the ideal (which the Stoics were inclined to think included almost everyone who has ever lived), it is, they believe, possible to achieve a measure of what they call “value” (axia) by means of the judicious selection of a variety of items labeled “things according to nature” (ta kata phusin). The concept of nature, then, will play a central role in the present survey. I focus first on the Stoics’ conception of the ethical ideal, and of the character of the person who attains it. This is followed by an account of their picture of the optimal course of human development. The final main section is devoted to the condition, as the Stoics see it, of those of us who fail to achieve the ideal, and the ways in which we differ from those who do achieve it.1 Stoic philosophy, including Stoic ethics, underwent various developments over the several centuries in which it flourished.
    [Show full text]
  • The Risk in the Educational Strategy of Seneca
    Journal of Ancient Philosophy Vol. V 2011 Issue 1 The Risk in the Educational Strategy of Seneca Stefano Maso (Università Ca’ Foscari, Venice) To his pupil Nero and to Lucilius (friend and, as metonymy, representative of the entire mankind), Seneca testifies to his pedagogic vocation. With conviction he applies himself to demonstrate the perfect correspondence between the Stoic doctrine and the educational strategy that he proposes. Firstly, the reciprocity of the relationship between educator and pupil appears fundamental; both further their individual knowledge. Secondly, the limitations of an ethical precept that is not anchored in the intensity and concreteness of human life becomes clearly apparent. Furthermore, it brings to question the weakness of a world vision not inspired by an innovative and original path. The starting point is therefore a rigorous examination of conscience to ultimately reach the revolutionary experience of risk in the moment of the last decision. In the name of truth the wise man must have the courage to embrace fate in order to really understand who he is (in a process of oikeiosis both as experience and as target), and he must instil in his pupils the courage to take risks along their own independent journey. In so doing, self-scrutiny and politics can become intertwined. It is herein that the educator’s risk and responsibilities lie. Thanks to the intercession of Agrippina, the new wife of the emperor Claudius1, Seneca had the opportunity to return from Corsican exile. To Seneca, Agrippina committed the education of his son, the young Nero, so he could learn the overall basis of eloquence, which was considered a necessary art in order to manage power.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction and Notes to the Fifth Book of Cicero's Tusculan Disputations
    REESE LIBRARY OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA. l8 - Deceived FEB- -10- 1-894 > 9 I Accessions*A No&ttTTY.... Class No. >/ INTRODUCTION AND NOTES TO THK- BOOK oiozmiRcrs TUSCULAN DISPUTATIONS -BY- FRANK SMALLEY, A. M.; PH. D. PROFESSOR OF THE LATIN LANGUAGE AND LITERATURE IN THE SYRACUSE UNIVERSITY. SYRACUSE, N. Y. T. W. DTJBSTON, 1892. CONTENTS. PAGE. Preface 3 Introduction 5 I. The Tusculan Disputations .r 5 II. Argument of Book V 7 III. A Brief View of Greek and Roman Ethical Philosophy 11 (a) Socrates 11 (b) The Cynics, (Antisthenes and Diogenes) 12 (c) The Cyrenaics, (Aristippus and Theodorus) 13 (d) Plato 15 (e) The Academies 18 (1) The Old Academy, (Speusippus, Xenocrates, Polemo, etc.) 18 (2) The Middle Academy, (Arcesilaus and Carneades) 18 (3) The New Academy, (Philo and Antiochus) 19 (f) Aristotle 20 (g) The Peripatetics, (Theophrastus, Aristo, Callipho, etc.) 21 (h) The Stoics, (Zeno, Aristo of Chios, Diogenes of Babylon, Panaetius, etc.) 22 (i) The Epicureans, (Epicurus, Metrodorus, etc.) 28 (j) Relations of Epicureanism to Stoicism 33 (k) The Eclectics, (Cicero) 34 Notes on the text. 36 PREFATORY NOTE. The Introduction and annotations here presented are advance sheets. They are printed now because needed for immediate use. The plan is to extend the latter to other portions of the text, and briefly to extend and adapt the former to the same. Some Latin text of the Disputations, as Teubner's or Harper's, will be used in the class. No scholar can feel any degree of confidence or any assurance of competence to present a commentary on this composition of Cicero without first devoting much thoughtful study to the great German editors, whose works have done so much to furnish a correct text and a clear exposition of the sometimes obscure passages, elucidat- ing the author's thought.
    [Show full text]
  • R.W. Sharples Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics an Introduction to Hellenistic Philosophy 1996
    STOICS, EPICUREANS AND SCEPTICS This study gives a comprehensive and readable account of the principal doctrines of the Stoics, Epicureans and various sceptical traditions from the death of Alexander the Great in 323 BC to about AD 200. The discussion is arranged according to topics, rather than schools, in order to bring out the underlying issues and make clear what the schools have in common and how they differ. At the same time, the coherence of each system as a whole is emphasised. The Hellenistic philosophers and schools of philosophy have emerged from the shadow of Plato and Aristotle and are increasingly studied for their intrinsic philosophical value. Yet not only are they interesting in their own right, but they also form the intellectual background of the late Roman Republic and the early Empire. A thorough understanding of them is therefore essential for the appreciation of Latin thought and literature. Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics provides an introduction to the subject for all who are interested in understanding the significance of this period of ancient thought. R.W.Sharples holds a personal Chair in Classics at University College London. He has published widely in Classical Studies and Philosophy. STOICS, EPICUREANS AND SCEPTICS An Introduction to Hellenistic Philosophy R.W.Sharples London and New York First published 1996 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2003. Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an International Thomson Publishing company © 1996 R.W.Sharples All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoicism Today Jean-Baptiste Gourinat
    Stoicism Today Jean-Baptiste Gourinat Abstract: The aim of this paper is to elucidate the meaning of Stoicism today. First, it roughly sketches Stoicism as a philosophical system, namely its logic, physics and ethics. It argues that many aspects of its logic and physics are outdated but that the general Stoic approach to these disciplines may still be relevant to modern philosophers. Moreover, the more persuasive part of Stoicism is ethics: Stoic ethics is naturalistic and intellectualist. Stoics argue that virtue is the only good, and attempt to force us to give up emotions and affections. These aspects of the Stoic approach frequently seem intolerable, but the strength of Stoicism depends on this intellectualism. One of the distinctive features of Stoicism, as well as of most ancient phi- losophies, is that philosophy is not only a theoretical system but a “way of Life.” In that respect, it is clear that Stoicism is still a living philosophy, as may be shown from the celebrated figure of J. Stockdale, the “philosophical fighter pilot.” Moreover, given its intellectualist approach, the Stoic theory of passions is obviously opposed to the psychoanalytic approach and its emphasis on unconscious processes. The theories known as “cognitive therapies” have close affinities with Stoicism, as they frequently proclaim. Therefore, Stoicism in more ways than one is a living philosophy. As an established school, stoicism enjoyed a relatively short life: it was founded in Athens by Zeno of Citium sometime around 300 BC1 and presumably lasted down to the death of the supposed last leader of the school, Panaetius, around 110/109 BC, a period of less than two hundred years in all.
    [Show full text]
  • Diogenes of Babylon: a Stoic on Music and Ethics
    Diogenes of Babylon: A Stoic on Music and Ethics Linda Helen Woodward UCL Submitted for the degree of Master of Philosophy in Classics 1 Diogenes of Babylon: A Stoic on Music and Ethics I, Linda Helen Woodward, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. 2 ABSTRACT The aim of this thesis is to analyse Diogenes of Babylon's musico-ethical theories, to place them into their historical context, and to examine the possible influences on his thought. Earlier treatments of this Stoic's work have been hampered by the lacunose state of Philodemus' surviving text, the major source, and in some cases an opponent's views have been mistakenly attributed to Diogenes. Conversely, the state of the text together with erroneous column numbering, have resulted in part of Diogenes' philosophy being ascribed to his Epicurean opponent. Taking Professor Delattre's recently reconstructed edition of Philodemus’ De musica as my starting point, I attempt to more fully analyse Diogenes' theory of music and ethics. Following a short introductory chapter, I briefly examine Diogenes' other interests, analyse his psychology compared with that of earlier Stoics, and examine how that fits into Diogenes' view on music in education. I outline Diogenes' general view on music, and compare the musical writings of Plato, Aristotle and the early Peripatetics with those of Diogenes, particularly in relation to education, and outline areas that might have influenced the Stoic. I also look at later writings where they can be seen as evidence for Diogenes' work.
    [Show full text]
  • Father of the Dogs? Tracking the Cynics in Plato's Euthydemus Author(S): Sara Rappe Source: Classical Philology, Vol
    Father of the Dogs? Tracking the Cynics in Plato's Euthydemus Author(s): Sara Rappe Source: Classical Philology, Vol. 95, No. 3 (Jul., 2000), pp. 282-303 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/270379 Accessed: 30/11/2010 07:27 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpress. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Classical Philology. http://www.jstor.org FATHER OF THE DOGS? TRACKING THE CYNICS IN PLATO'S EUTHYDEMUS SARA RAPPE INTRODUCTION: SOCRATES APATOR C RITO BEGINS the Euthydemusby asking Socrates, "with whom were you conversing yesterday in the Lyceum?" Critics have long echoed Crito'sopening question, as there continues to be controversyover the historical identity of those two arch-antilogists, Dionysodorus and Euthy- demus.
    [Show full text]