The Concept of Prophecy and Allegorical Interpretation (Taʾwīl) Within Abū Ḥāmid Al- Ghazzālī‘S and Maimonides‘ Oeuvres

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Concept of Prophecy and Allegorical Interpretation (Taʾwīl) Within Abū Ḥāmid Al- Ghazzālī‘S and Maimonides‘ Oeuvres The Concept of Prophecy and Allegorical Interpretation (taʾwīl) within Abū Ḥāmid al- Ghazzālī‘s and Maimonides‘ Oeuvres By Soroosh Shahriari Department of Jewish Studies McGill University Montreal, Canada March 2018 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the degree of Master of Arts © Soroosh Shahriari, 2018 Table of Contents Abstract ........................................................................................................................................ ii Résumé ......................................................................................................................................... iii Acknowledgments ..................................................................................................................... iv Introduction ................................................................................................................................. v Chapter One: What is the Revelation?&Who is a Prophet? A Philosophical Background 1 Al-Fārābī ................................................................................................................................... 4 Ibn Sīnā ..................................................................................................................................... 7 Chapter Two: The Notion of Prophecy and Allegorical Interpretation: Al-Ghazzālī‘s Perspective ................................................................................................................................... 13 I. Al-Ghazzālī the dialectician: Critique of the falāsifa ................................................... 14 II. Al-Ghazzālī the Theologian: Public Defense of the Ashʿarism............................... 21 III. Al-Ghazzālī between the Worlds: A Conservative Mystic ....................................... 37 IV. Al-Ghazzālī the Freelance Sufi: Philosophizing Mysticism .................................... 46 V. Summary ....................................................................................................................... 60 Chapter Three: Prophecy and Allegorical Interpretation: Maimonides‘ View ................... 62 I. Commentary on the Mishnah ......................................................................................... 64 a. Introduction to the Seder Zeraʿim ............................................................................... 65 b. Introduction to the Pereq Ḥeleq .................................................................................. 74 II. The Guide of the Perplexed ......................................................................................... 88 III. Summary ..................................................................................................................... 104 Conclusion ................................................................................................................................ 106 Appendix A................................................................................................................................ 111 Appendix B................................................................................................................................ 113 Appendix C................................................................................................................................ 117 Bibliography .............................................................................................................................. 120 i Abstract Abū Ḥāmid al-Ghazzālī (1055-1111) and Rabai Mosheh ben Maimun (1138-1204), better known in English as Maimonides, share the same religiously motivated concern towards scriptural exegesis: How one ought to interpret the divine (or divinely inspired) texts when a literal reading of the passages is at odds with one‘s reasoning. Since they consider the intellect (al-ʿaql) to be divinely endowed as well, al-Ghazzālī and Maimonides take it upon themselves to reconcile the belief in the authority of the revealed text(s) with what each author understands by independent intellectual reasoning. Their goal is to balance the limits of faithful belief in the prophets‘ veracity and their commitment to the reliability of the intellect. To this end, they argue for the presence of (at least) two layers of meaning in the revealed tradition: outward (ẓāhir) vs. inward (bā‏ṭin) and endeavour to prove that the conflict exists only at the superficial level due to the reader‘s inability to comprehend the depth of inward message the text conveys. They both consider the issue important enough to dedicate a major part of their works to it, and hence the topic of allegorical interpretation (taʾwīl) plays, directly or indirectly, a central role in their intellectual projects. In this study, I explore the two authors‘ approach to the question of taʾwīl and try to demonstrate its dependence on the notions of prophecy and revelation (waḥy). ii Résumé Abū Ḥāmid al-Ghazzālī (1055-1111) et Rabai Mosheh ben Maimun (1138-1204), plus connu sous le nom de Maïmonide, partagent la même problématique à propos de l‘exégèse du texte sacré : comment devrait-on interpréter les textes révélés (ou d‘inspiration divine) lorsqu‘une lecture littérale du texte va à l‘encontre de la raison pure ? Puisqu‘ils considèrent la raison pure (al-ʿaql) comme étant également divinement dotée aux êtres humains par Dieu, al-Ghazzālī et Maïmonide se décident de réconcilier la croyance en l‘autorité des textes divins avec leur conception du raisonnement pur et indépendant. Leur but est de trouver le point d‘équilibre entre une foi fidèle en la véracité des prophètes et la conviction que la raison est un outil fiable. Pour cela, ils soutiennent la présence de (au moins) deux niveaux de signification dans la tradition révélée : ce qui relève de la signification extérieure (ẓāhir), et ce qui relève de la signification intérieure (bā‏ṭin). Ils cherchent ainsi à prouver que la tension entre foi et raison existe seulement au niveau superficiel, du fait de l‘incapacité du lecteur à saisir la profondeur du message intérieur du texte. Tous deux considèrent que la problématique est assez importante pour y dédier une majeure partie dans leur œuvre. Par conséquent, le sujet de l‘interprétation allégorique (taʾwīl) joue, directement ou indirectement, un rôle central dans leurs projets intellectuels. Cette étude examine l‘approche des deux auteurs à la question du taʾwīl et tente d‘établir la dépendence de ce dernier sur les notions de prophétie et de révélation (waḥy). iii Acknowledgments My thanks go first and foremost to my supervisor, Professor Carlos Fraenkel, for his unreserved help, support (both intellectually and emotionally), guidance (unlike Maimonides‘ which came to be more confusing at some points!), and his enthusiastic encouragements during these tough years. I have learnt a lot from him both as my academic mentor and a caring human being—I will be indebted to him forever. I have also been very fortunate to have Professor Lawrence Kaplan as my adviser. I benefited a lot from his encyclopaedic knowledge of Jewish Law, philosophy, history, and mysticism in the courses of my Master‘s studies at McGill University. I owe my other professors at the Department of Jewish Studies for their unconditional support and kindness: Eric Caplan, Yael Halevi-Wise, Gershon Hundert, and Barry Levy. I should also express my sincere gratitude to Professors Robert Wisnovsky, Alison Laywine, and Stephen Menn for letting me audit their courses on Islamic and Greek philosophy; those were indeed great opportunities for me to deepen my knowledge of falsafa. My dearest friend and former teacher at Carleton University, Professor Mohammed Rustom, is also among the ones I would like to thank. My graduate study was made possible through internal scholarships, awards, and prizes courtesy of the Department of Jewish Studies; I would like to express my gratitude to the respected families and individuals who supported me financially in the course of these years. My last, but not least, heartfelt thanks go to my family, in particular, my beloved wife, Azadeh, for her patience and absolute support in the hardest times. My lovely mother, Khobchehr, and my dearest sister, Mana, were always beside me during these years. And my tearful farewell words to my baba, Muhammad Ali, who passed away a couple of weeks before the first draft of this thesis was complete. He was the one who introduced me to al-Ghazzālī when I was a teenager; I still have his copy of Prof. Zarrrinkub‘s masterpiece on Ghazzālī‘s life, farār az madrese [flee from the madrasah]. I dedicate this work to his memory. iv Introduction Abū Ḥāmid Muḥammad bin Muḥammad al-Ghazzālī‘s (10551-1111) and Rabai Mosheh ben Maimun (11382-1204), better known in English as Maimonides, shared the same religiously motivated concern towards arbitrary conflicts found between the intellect (al-ʿaql) and the sacred revealed tradition (al- naql). They faced the same question many other (preceding or succeeding) religious philosophers as well as theologians had come up with: What one ought to do when the demonstrative proof (burhān) comes into conflict with the text of Scripture (or in that matter, the divinely inspired Talmud/ḥadith curpos)?3 If what the intellect dictates, which was perceived by the two sages as divinely endowed, contradicts messages the Scripture conveys, then what can be done to uphold the authority of both these two disagreeing sources? For al-Ghazzālī and Maimonides, the answer
Recommended publications
  • The Alleged Activity of Active Intellect: a Wild Goose Chase Or a Puzzle to Be Solved?1
    The alleged activity of active intellect: A wild goose chase or a puzzle to be solved?1 Sonia Kamińska Summary Trying to describe the activity of Aristotle’s active intellect, we will sooner or later realize that we cannot find its right description, because Aristotle did not provide for one. He left us with many ir- reconcilable statements and questions with no answers. In the fa- | LIV • 2014 w Nauce Zagadnienia Filozoficzne mous text Aristotle’s Two Intellects: a Modest Proposal Victor Cas- ton claims that Aristotle did not describe the activity, because there simply is no such activity and we should therefore identify nous poietikos with God, because God too does nothing. Trying to find this lacking description is like going on a wild goose chase – Caston argues. In my text I will show that his solution, albeit tempting, is in fact a kind of “dissolution” and that a wild goose chase, although for many doomed to failure, can be fruitful. I will do so by present- ing three groups or clusters of views on active intellect which – I believe – are philosophically significant. Caston’s proposal will be 1 �����������������������������������������������������������������This publication was supported by Copernicus Center for Interdis- ciplinary Studies under grant "The Limits of Scientific Explanation" founded by the John Templeton Foundation. 79 Sonia Kamińska one of them, but not the privileged one. These three types of inter- pretations will hopefully provide us with an imagery that will help us somewhat come to terms with Aristotle’s succinctness. Keywords nous, nous poietikos, nous pathetikos, soul, intellect, God, Deity, actuality, potentiality, philosophy of mind, Aristotle, Thomas Aqui- nas, Franz Brentano, Victor Caston 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Summary Essay"
    Muhammad Abdullah (19154) Book 4 Chapter 5 "Summary Essay" This chapter on 'The Peripatetic School' talks about this school and its decline. By 'peripatetic', it means the school of thought of Aristotle. Moreover, 'The Peripatetic School' was a philosophy school in Ancient Greece. And obviously its teachings were found and inspired by Aristotle. Other than that, its followers were called, 'Peripatetic'. At first, the school was a base for Macedonian influence in Athens. The school in earlier days -and in Aristotle's times- was distinguished by doing research in every field, like, botany, zoology, and many more. It tried to solve problems in every subject/field. It also gathered earlier views and writings of philosophers who came before. First, it talks about the difference in botanical writings of Theophrastus and Aristotle. Theophrastus was the successor of Aristotle in the Peripatetic School. He was a plant biologist. Theophrastus wrote treatises in many areas of philosophy to improve and comment-on Aristotle's writings. In addition to this, Theophrastus built his own writings upon the writings of earlier philosophers. The chapter then differentiates between Lyceum (The Peripatetic School) and Ptolemaic Alexandria. Moreover, after Aristotle, Theophrastus and Strato shifted the focus of peripatetic philosophy to more of empiricism and materialism. One of Theophrastus' most important works is 'Metaphysics' or 'A Fragment'. This work is important in the sense that it raises important questions. This work seems to object Aristotle's work of Unmoved Mover. Theophrastus states that there's natural phenomenon at work. However, some interpretations suggest that Theophrastus goes against Platonist. Theophrastus says, "...the universe is an organized system in which the same degree of purposefulness and goodness should not be expected at every level." Additionally, the chapter points out that objecting the writings and building your own work upon it is what the 'real' Aristotelian way of doing work is.
    [Show full text]
  • Islamic Economic Thinking in the 12Th AH/18Th CE Century with Special Reference to Shah Wali-Allah Al-Dihlawi
    Munich Personal RePEc Archive Islamic economic thinking in the 12th AH/18th CE century with special reference to Shah Wali-Allah al-Dihlawi Islahi, Abdul Azim Islamic Economics Institute, King Abdulaziz University, Jeddah, KSA 2009 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/75432/ MPRA Paper No. 75432, posted 06 Dec 2016 02:58 UTC Abdul Azim Islahi Islamic Economics Research Center King Abdulaziz University Scientific Publising Center King Abdulaziz University http://spc.kau.edu.sa FOREWORD The Islamic Economics Research Center has great pleasure in presenting th Islamic Economic Thinking in the 12th AH (corresponding 18 CE) Century with Special Reference to Shah Wali-Allah al-Dihlawi). The author, Professor Abdul Azim Islahi, is a well-known specialist in the history of Islamic economic thought. In this respect, we have already published his following works: Contributions of Muslim Scholars to th Economic Thought and Analysis up to the 15 Century; Muslim th Economic Thinking and Institutions in the 16 Century, and A Study on th Muslim Economic Thinking in the 17 Century. The present work and the previous series have filled, to an extent, the gap currently existing in the study of the history of Islamic economic thought. In this study, Dr. Islahi has explored the economic ideas of Shehu Uthman dan Fodio of West Africa, a region generally neglected by researchers. He has also investigated the economic ideas of Shaykh Muhammad b. Abd al-Wahhab, who is commonly known as a religious renovator. Perhaps it would be a revelation for many to know that his economic ideas too had a role in his reformative endeavours.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Thinking ( Noêsis )
    Aristotle on Thinking ( Noêsis ) The Perception Model DA III.4-5. Aristotle gives an account of thinking (or intellect—noêsis ) that is modeled on his account of perception in Book II. Just as in perception, “that which perceives” ( to aisthêtikon ) takes on sensible form (without matter), so in thinking “that which thinks” ( to noêtikon ) takes on intelligible form (without matter). Similarly, just as in perception, the perceiver has the quality of the object potentially, but not actually, so, too, in understanding, the intellect is potentially (although not actually) each of its objects. Problem This leaves us with a problem analogous to the one we considered in the case of perception. There we wondered how the perceiver of a red tomato could be potentially (but not actually) red (prior to perceiving it), and yet become red (be actually red) in the process of perceiving it. Here the question is how the intellect that thinks about a tomato (or a horse) is potentially a tomato (or a horse), and then becomes a tomato (or a horse) in the process of thinking about it. The problem about thinking seems more severe: for although there is a sense in which the perceiver becomes red (the sense organ becomes colored red), there does not seem to be a comparable sense in which the intellect becomes a tomato (or a horse). (1) there is no organ involved, and (2) there does not seem to be room in there for a tomato (let alone a horse). The Differences from Perception As we will see, there are important differences between perceiving and understanding, beyond the fact the one involves taking on perceptible form and the other intelligible form.
    [Show full text]
  • Volume 7: Shaping Global Islamic Discourses : the Role of Al-Azhar, Al-Medina and Al-Mustafa Masooda Bano Editor
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by eCommons@AKU eCommons@AKU Exploring Muslim Contexts ISMC Series 3-2015 Volume 7: Shaping Global Islamic Discourses : The Role of al-Azhar, al-Medina and al-Mustafa Masooda Bano Editor Keiko Sakurai Editor Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.aku.edu/uk_ismc_series_emc Recommended Citation Bano, M. , Sakurai, K. (Eds.). (2015). Volume 7: Shaping Global Islamic Discourses : The Role of al-Azhar, al-Medina and al-Mustafa Vol. 7, p. 242. Available at: https://ecommons.aku.edu/uk_ismc_series_emc/9 Shaping Global Islamic Discourses Exploring Muslim Contexts Series Editor: Farouk Topan Books in the series include Development Models in Muslim Contexts: Chinese, “Islamic” and Neo-liberal Alternatives Edited by Robert Springborg The Challenge of Pluralism: Paradigms from Muslim Contexts Edited by Abdou Filali-Ansary and Sikeena Karmali Ahmed Ethnographies of Islam: Ritual Performances and Everyday Practices Edited by Badouin Dupret, Thomas Pierret, Paulo Pinto and Kathryn Spellman-Poots Cosmopolitanisms in Muslim Contexts: Perspectives from the Past Edited by Derryl MacLean and Sikeena Karmali Ahmed Genealogy and Knowledge in Muslim Societies: Understanding the Past Edited by Sarah Bowen Savant and Helena de Felipe Contemporary Islamic Law in Indonesia: Shariah and Legal Pluralism Arskal Salim Shaping Global Islamic Discourses: The Role of al-Azhar, al-Medina and al-Mustafa Edited by Masooda Bano and Keiko Sakurai www.euppublishing.com/series/ecmc
    [Show full text]
  • The Agent Intellect As" Form for Us" and Averroes's. Critique of Al-Farabi
    Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía ISSN: 0188-6649 [email protected] Universidad Panamericana México Taylor, Richard C. The Agent Intellect as "form for us" and Averroes's. Critique of al-Farabi Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía, núm. 29, 2005, pp. 29-51 Universidad Panamericana Distrito Federal, México Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=323027318003 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative The Agent Intellect as "form for us" and Averroes's Critique of al-FarabT Richard C. Taylor Marquette University This article explicates Averroes's understanding of human knowing and abstraction in this three commentaries on Aristotle's De Anima. While Averroes's views on the nature of the human material intellect changes through the three commentaries until he reaches is famous view of the unity of the material intellect as one for all human beings, his view of the agent intellect as 'form for us' is sustained throughout these works. In his Long Commentary on the De Anima he reveals his dependence on al-Farabi for this notion and provides a detailed critique of the Farabian notion that the agent intellect is 'form for us' only as agent cause, not as our true formal cause. Although Averroes argues that the agent intellect must somehow be intrinsic to us as our form since humans 2tieper se rational and undertake acts of knowing by will, his view is shown to rest on an equivocal use of the notion of formal cause.
    [Show full text]
  • National Open University Nigeria School of Arts And
    NATIONAL OPEN UNIVERSITY NIGERIA SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SOCIAL SCIENCES COURSE CODE: ISL 402 COURSE TITLE: MODERN REFORM MOVEMENTS 1 NATIONAL OPEN UNIVERSITY OF NIGERIA SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SOCIAL SCIENCES COURSE CODE: ISL402 COURSE TITLE: Modern Reform Movements in Islam 2 COURSE MATERIAL ISL402: Modern Reform Movements in Islam Course Team: Prof. Asif Folarin Ahmed (H.O.U. Islamic Studies) NOUN Dr. Adejoro Raheem Mustapha (Course Developer/Writer, NOUN) Dr. Kahar Wahab Sarumi (Course Developer/Writer, NOUN) 3 National Open University of Nigeria Headquarters 14/16, Ahmadu Bello Way, Victoria Island, Lagos. Abuja Annex 245, Samuel Adesujo Ademulegun Street, Central Business District, Opposite Arewa Suites, Abuja. e-mail: [email protected] URL: www.nou.edu.ng National Open University of Nigeria First Printed 2013 ISBN: All Rights Reserved Printed by ……………. For National Open University of Nigeria 4 Module One: Unit 1: The Concept of Tajdīd and its Development 1.0 Introduction There is a strong tradition of revival and reform in Islam. The concept of Tajdid (renewal/revival) is a fundamental concept within Islam, based on the Qur'an and Sunnah of the Prophet. The preaching of Islam itself is presented in the Qur'an as the revival of the true religion of God and reform of corrupt practices that had crept into the practices of religion by earlier peoples. Islam regards itself as both the corroboration and the purification of the original faith as held by prophet Ibrahim, father of monotheism. Thus, Islam is not a new religion but a re-affirmation and renewal of the ancient Ibrahimic belief.
    [Show full text]
  • Hizb Ut-Tahrir Ideology and Strategy
    HIZB UT-TAHRIR IDEOLOGY AND STRATEGY “The fierce struggle… between the Muslims and the Kuffar, has been intense ever since the dawn of Islam... It will continue in this way – a bloody struggle alongside the intellectual struggle – until the Hour comes and Allah inherits the Earth...” Hizb ut-Tahrir The Centre for Social Cohesion Houriya Ahmed & Hannah Stuart HIZB UT-TAHRIR IDEOLOGY AND STRATEGY “The fierce struggle… between the Muslims and the Kuffar, has been intense ever since the dawn of Islam... It will continue in this way – a bloody struggle alongside the intellectual struggle – until the Hour comes and Allah inherits the Earth...” Hizb ut-Tahrir The Centre for Social Cohesion Houriya Ahmed & Hannah Stuart Hizb ut-Tahrir Ideology and Strategy Houriya Ahmed and Hannah Stuart 2009 The Centre for Social Cohesion Clutha House, 10 Storey’s Gate London SW1P 3AY Tel: +44 (0)20 7222 8909 Fax: +44 (0)5 601527476 Email: [email protected] www.socialcohesion.co.uk The Centre for Social Cohesion Limited by guarantee Registered in England and Wales: No. 06609071 © The Centre for Social Cohesion, November 2009 All the Institute’s publications seek to further its objective of promoting human rights for the benefit of the public. The views expressed are those of the author, not of the Institute. Hizb ut-Tahrir: Ideology and Strategy By Houriya Ahmed and Hannah Stuart ISBN 978-0-9560013-4-4 All rights reserved The map on the front cover depicts Hizb ut-Tahrir’s vision for its Caliphate in ‘Islamic Lands’ ABOUT THE AUTHORS Houriya Ahmed is a Research Fellow at the Centre for Social Cohesion (CSC).
    [Show full text]
  • Theories of the Soul Vs. Medical Knowledge: Averroës As an Authority in Thirteenth-Century France
    Theories of the Soul vs. Medical Knowledge: Averroës as an Authority in Thirteenth-Century France Heather Thornton McRae, University of Missouri The intellectual florescence of thirteenth-century France, and Paris in particular, was vibrant, yet it confronted scholastic thinkers with a range of both new and continuing problems. The most famous of the continuing problems was the how to fully reconcile Aristotelian philosophy with revealed scripture. Both had lengthy commentary traditions that complicated the attempt. Christian doctrine had the four Church Fathers as well as key medieval works, such as Peter Lombard’s Sentences, while Aristotle had commentaries from both the late antique and Islamic worlds as well as Christian commentaries for those few works available in Latin in the early Middle Ages. The most famous of the Muslim Aristotelian scholars in Europe was Ibn Rushd, known in Latin as Averroës, or often simply The Commentator. A twelfth-century Andalusi Islamic jurist, physician, theologian, and philosopher, Averroës presented curious and thoughtful scholars, such as Albertus Magnus, with the difficult question of how to use and learn from the knowledge that Averroës provided while not stumbling over his religiously problematic positions. At the heart of this conflict was the changing notion of auctoritas (authority). As late as the early twelfth century, men like William of St. Thierry were writing that knowledge was acquired through the intellect while auctoritas was exclusively the means for acquiring faith. 1 However, this long-held view changed at the turn of the twelfth century, which saw the end to what is sometimes called the Age of Authority, because men noted that authority was the weakest form of proof, as Thomas Aquinas observes time and again in his famous Summa 1 Heinrich Fichtenau, Heretics and Scholars in the High Middle Ages: 1000-1200, trans.
    [Show full text]
  • Avicenna's Emanated Abstraction
    volume 20, no. 10 ne of the largest ongoing debates in contemporary schol- april 2020 arship on Avicenna (Ibn Sīnā, the 10th−11th-century Per- O sian philosopher) concerns his epistemology of the acqui- sition of intelligible forms (or concepts) between the more traditional “emanationists” and the more recent “abstractionists”. It is encourag- ing to see a topic in Avicenna (and Islamic philosophy more broadly) receive the kind of detailed scholarly attention regularly afforded to Avicenna’s Emanated many other figures in the history of philosophy. And for good reason. This is a paramount issue in Avicenna’s philosophy (which went on to influence both the Islamic and Western traditions in unrivaled fash- ion), and the two accounts need to be reconciled in a much more sat- Abstraction isfactory way. Emanationists — such as Rahman, Davidson, and Black, follow- ing major historical sources such as Averroes (Ibn Rushd) and Aqui- nas — argue that Avicenna envisions the universal intelligibles as emanated directly into human minds from the separate and eternal Active Intellect (hereafter AI). Abstractionists — such as Hasse and Gutas — argue that the intelligibles are rather the result of the hu- man intellectual activity of abstraction from sensory images. The debate boils down to this: From where do the intelligibles initially come — from above, i.e., the AI (in a more “Neo-Platonic” fashion), or from below, i.e., from sense experience and images (in a more “Aristo- Stephen R. Ogden telian” fashion)? Both sides can point to numerous seemingly proba- tive texts in Avicenna’s corpus.1 The Catholic University of America 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Article (PDF)
    Advances in Social Science, Education and Humanities Research, volume 329 4th International Conference on Contemporary Education, Social Sciences and Humanities (ICCESSH 2019) Political Philosophy of Al-Ghazali* Nur Kirabaev Maythem Al-Janabi Department of History of Philosophy Department of History of Philosophy Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences Peoples’ Friendship University of Russia Peoples’ Friendship University of Russia Moscow, Russia Moscow, Russia E-mail: [email protected] E-mail: [email protected] Abstract—The article is dedicated to the major issues of the embodiment in the spirit and way of Sufism, so cherished by political philosophy of the prominent medieval philosopher of al-Ghazali. His political philosophy had changed and formed the Muslim East al-Ghazali (1058 - 1111). It is exactly the under these complex processes. consideration of both the historical circumstances and political practice of the state (Caliphate / Imamate) of his days that An analysis of his works on socio-philosophical and allowed al-Ghazali to re-examine the traditional Sunni dogma political issues shows that he allowed himself moderate of combining the authority and power, and to take a different freedom of thought yet within the framework of the Sunni look at the nature of the state in his teaching about the tradition. His position is that of a rational jurist and moralist Imamate, which differed both from the model found during the who well understood Islam being both spiritual and worldly, reign of the Prophet and the Rashidun Caliphs, and from al- for all Muslim movements were as well political ones, be it Ghazali’s predecessors and contemporaries among the fuqaha Kalām, fiqh, or philosophy of Sufism.
    [Show full text]
  • Albert the Great
    ALBERT THE GREAT (Albert of Lauingen, Albert of Cologne)—theologian, philsopher, natural scientist, Bishop of Regensburg, called doctor universalis, doctor expertus, a doctor of the Church, b. around 1200 in Lauingen in Swabia, d. November 15, 1280 in Cologne. Albert came from a family of Swabian knights. He studied in northern Italy, chiefly in Padua. In Padua in 1223 he entered the Dominicans. He was in the novitiate in Cologne and after completing his theological studies and receiving Holy Orders, from 1223 on he had the role of lector of the order in various convents (Hildesheim, Freiburg im Breisgau, Regensburg, and Strassburg). In the early 1240s, at the recommendation of the Dominican authorities, he went to Paris where he lectured on the Sentences of Peter Lombard and prepared for a magisterium in theology, which he obtained in 1245. In Paris he developed his scholarly and didactic work and his writings, bearing fruit in many eminent works and acquiring exceptional renown. In 1248 Albert was transferred to Cologne to organize a studium generale for the Dominicans of the German province, and he directed this until 1254. One of his students at that school was Thomas Aquinas, who probably also heard Albert’s lectures while in Paris. In 1252 Albert recommended Thomas for the position of Master of theology at the University of Paris. From 1254 to 1257 Albert was the provincial of the extensive German province. In Anagni, at the court of Pope Alexander IV, he participated in a defense of the mendicant orders (1256). He also led a disputation concerning Averroes’ doctrine of the unicity of the intellect.
    [Show full text]