Why Is Aspasia a Woman? Reflections on Plato's Menexenus

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Why Is Aspasia a Woman? Reflections on Plato's Menexenus Why is Aspasia a Woman? Reflections on Plato’s Menexenus Peter Adamson Though there were many women philosophers in antiquity, we do not have a single philosophical work that can be ascribed with any confidence to a female author. One apparent exception, the letters written by early female Pythagoreans like Theano and Myia, has proved upon closer inspection to date from centuries after these women lived.1 In light of this our best access to the ideas of ancient women philosophers is provided by male ancient phi- losophers, especially in dialogues that feature female characters as speakers. We have several such works from late antiquity, including early writings by Augustine that feature his mother Monica and a remarkable work by Gregory of Nyssa in which his sainted sister Macrina, like a latter day Socrates, discours- es on the immortality of the soul from her deathbed. From classical antiquity, for most people the example that leaps to mind would be Diotima in Plato’s Symposium. But she is not the only woman to take center stage in a Platonic dialogue. There is also the Menexenus,2 which consists almost entirely of a speech composed by Aspasia, who unlike Diotima was certainly a real person and indeed a significant player on the political scene of Periclean Athens. Commentators on the Menexenus sometimes lament that it does not get much attention from scholars of the Platonic corpus.3 But that is only true relative to the voluminous secondary literature that has been devoted to other dialogues. In fact this brief work has been considered from a variety of standpoints. Its central speech has been compared to other antique funeral orations,4 notably the speech of Pericles which the Menexenus also credits to Aspasia (236b5); we know it through the version recorded by Thucydides. The funeral speech within the dialogue is recited by Socrates from memory, having had it drilled into him by Aspasia, his “teacher of oratory” (236a1). She 1 Huizenga 2013, Nails 1989, Pomeroy 2013 and, for a survey of these and other female thinkers from antquity, Waithe 1987. 2 I use the Greek text from Plato 1903 and quote with occasional modifications from the trans- lation of Paul Ryan in Plato 1997. 3 For instance Monoson 1998, 489: “a far more interesting dialogue than is usually supposed.” 4 Clavaud 1980, Glenn 1994, Henderson 1975 (“Plato’s purpose was to write a pastiche of the funeral speech,” 33), Loraux 1986. © Wilhelm Fink Verlag, 2020 | doi:10.30965/9783846765333_005 70 Peter Adamson composed it by combining improvisation with bits written earlier as a model funeral speech for fallen Athenian warriors (236b3-4). For many interpreters the dialogue is partly, or entirely, ironic and critical in character. Some take it to be little more than a parody of rhetorical techniques on Plato’s part, and especially of Gorgias’ style.5 Others see it as serving an immediate political purpose. It may have been a rebuke to the policies of dem- ocratic Athens,6 or be intended to encourage respectful and well-funded treat- ment of fallen soldiers.7 Still others, noting the chronological impossibilities in the dialogue and the intriguing fact that “Menexenus” was also the name of one of the historical Socrates’ children, have advanced the notion that Socrates appears here as a kind of ghost speaking from the grave to his own son.8 My aim here is not to offer an overall reading of the dialogue in the context of antique funeral oration, political events, or even Plato’s other works. Rather I want to address the question of why Plato has chosen to make Aspasia the central figure of the dialogue. Though this question has not always been taken seriously,9 I am certainly not the first to pose it. Charles Kahn identified it as the first of five central puzzles raised by the Menexenus.10 There can be little doubt that Aspasia’s involvement serves to tie the dialogue closely to the figure of Pericles. As we know from other sources, notably Plutarch’s Life of Pericles, Aspasia was romantically linked to the great Athenian statesman, presumably as his “concubine (παλλακίς)” since as a metic she could not have married him.11 She was known for her intelligence and skill as a rhetorician, credited with (or blamed for) shaping Pericles’ speeches and even his political policies. After his death, she married Lysicles and helped to make him a successful orator and politician.12 Plutarch also conveys (without necessarily accepting these charg- es) that she was a notorious and divisive figure, accused of running prostitutes, 5 This would fit with the remark of Philostratus that Aspasia “sharpened up Pericles’ speak- ing style in the manner of Gorgias.” See the report at Boys-Stones and Rowe 2013, §8.6. 6 For Kahn 1963, 229, it is “a kind of political pamphlet, written out of deep loyalty to the noblest traditions of Athens, but out of heartbreak, shame, and fury at the present policy of the city” (229). He emphasizes its plea for pan-Hellenic unity. For Haskins 2005, 26, the target of Plato’s critique is the Peace of Antalkidas, agreed by Athens in 287. 7 Huby 1957. 8 Dean-Jones 1995, Rosenstock 1994. 9 Huby 1957, 109-10: “It is difficult to know what to make of the statement that the speech is the work of Aspasia, but as the pretence wears very thin at the end of the dialogue [she cites 248d], we should probably not attach too much importance to this point.” 10 Kahn 1963, 220. 11 Henry 1994, 13-14. 12 A scholium to the Menexenus itself claims that she trained Pericles, Plato, and Callias in oratory, as well as Lysicles. See Boys-Stones and Rowe 2013, §8.7..
Recommended publications
  • Marathon 2,500 Years Edited by Christopher Carey & Michael Edwards
    MARATHON 2,500 YEARS EDITED BY CHRISTOPHER CAREY & MICHAEL EDWARDS INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SCHOOL OF ADVANCED STUDY UNIVERSITY OF LONDON MARATHON – 2,500 YEARS BULLETIN OF THE INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SUPPLEMENT 124 DIRECTOR & GENERAL EDITOR: JOHN NORTH DIRECTOR OF PUBLICATIONS: RICHARD SIMPSON MARATHON – 2,500 YEARS PROCEEDINGS OF THE MARATHON CONFERENCE 2010 EDITED BY CHRISTOPHER CAREY & MICHAEL EDWARDS INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SCHOOL OF ADVANCED STUDY UNIVERSITY OF LONDON 2013 The cover image shows Persian warriors at Ishtar Gate, from before the fourth century BC. Pergamon Museum/Vorderasiatisches Museum, Berlin. Photo Mohammed Shamma (2003). Used under CC‐BY terms. All rights reserved. This PDF edition published in 2019 First published in print in 2013 This book is published under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial- NoDerivatives (CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0) license. More information regarding CC licenses is available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Available to download free at http://www.humanities-digital-library.org ISBN: 978-1-905670-81-9 (2019 PDF edition) DOI: 10.14296/1019.9781905670819 ISBN: 978-1-905670-52-9 (2013 paperback edition) ©2013 Institute of Classical Studies, University of London The right of contributors to be identified as the authors of the work published here has been asserted by them in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. Designed and typeset at the Institute of Classical Studies TABLE OF CONTENTS Introductory note 1 P. J. Rhodes The battle of Marathon and modern scholarship 3 Christopher Pelling Herodotus’ Marathon 23 Peter Krentz Marathon and the development of the exclusive hoplite phalanx 35 Andrej Petrovic The battle of Marathon in pre-Herodotean sources: on Marathon verse-inscriptions (IG I3 503/504; Seg Lvi 430) 45 V.
    [Show full text]
  • Questions: the Story of Ancient Greece and Rome
    Questions: The Story of Ancient Greece and Rome Name ______________________________________________ Class _____ Using Vocabulary democracy citizens Golden Age peninsula colonies 1. The main part of Greece is on a ______________, or land that has water on most sides. 2. The Greek ____________________ were far-off places that were ruled by Greece. 3. The first class of people in Sparta were the ____________________. 4. In a ____________________ the government is run by the people. 5. The people of Athens enjoyed peace, art, and good government during Greece’s ____________________________. Who Am I? Read each sentence then look at the words in the word bank for the name of the person who might have said it. Write the name on the blank beside the quote. Pericles Socrates Aristotle Alexander the Great Aspasia 6. “I lived in Athens where I wrote about science, art, and law.” _____________________ 7. “I opened a school in Athens so that girls could learn to read and write.” ___________ 8. “The Parthenon was built while I was leader of Athens.” __________________________ 9. “My empire became a mixture of many cultures.” _______________________________ 10.“I taught people that there were right ways and wrong ways to behave.” ___________ Think and Apply: Understanding different points of view The people of Sparta and Athens had different points of view about their ways of life. Read each sentence below. Write Sparta next to the sentences that might show the point of view of a person from Sparta. Write Athens next to the sentences that might show the point of view of a person from Athens.
    [Show full text]
  • Feminist Revisionary Histories of Rhetoric: Aspasia's Story
    University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Supervised Undergraduate Student Research Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects and Creative Work Spring 5-1999 Feminist Revisionary Histories of Rhetoric: Aspasia's Story Amy Suzanne Lawless University of Tennessee - Knoxville Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_chanhonoproj Recommended Citation Lawless, Amy Suzanne, "Feminist Revisionary Histories of Rhetoric: Aspasia's Story" (1999). Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_chanhonoproj/322 This is brought to you for free and open access by the Supervised Undergraduate Student Research and Creative Work at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. UNIVERSITY HONORS PROGRAM SENIOR PROJECT - APPROVAL N a me: _ dm~ - .l..4ul ~ ___________ ---------------------------- College: ___ M..5...~-~_ Department: ___(gI1~~~ -$!7;.h2j~~ ----- Faculty Mentor: ___lIs ...!_)Au~! _ ..A±~:JJ-------------------------- PROJECT TITLE: - __:fum~tU'it __ .&~\'?lP.0.:-L.!T __W-~~ · SS__ ~T__ Eb:b?L(k.!_ A; ' I -------------- ~~Jl~3-- -2b~1------------------------------ --------------------------------------------. _------------- I have reviewed this completed senior honors thesis with this student and certify that it is a project commensurate with honors
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Foreigners As Liberators: Education and Cultural Diversity in Plato's
    1 Foreigners as Liberators: Education and Cultural Diversity in Plato’s Menexenus Rebecca LeMoine Assistant Professor of Political Science Florida Atlantic University NOTE: Use of this document is for private research and study only; the document may not be distributed further. The final manuscript has been accepted for publication and will appear in a revised form in The American Political Science Review 111.3 (August 2017). It is available for a FirstView online here: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055417000016 Abstract: Though recent scholarship challenges the traditional interpretation of Plato as anti- democratic, his antipathy to cultural diversity is still generally assumed. The Menexenus appears to offer some of the most striking evidence of Platonic xenophobia, as it features Socrates delivering a mock funeral oration that glorifies Athens’ exclusion of foreigners. Yet when readers play along with Socrates’ exhortation to imagine the oration through the voice of its alleged author Aspasia, Pericles’ foreign mistress, the oration becomes ironic or dissonant. Through this, Plato shows that foreigners can act as gadflies, liberating citizens from the intellectual hubris that occasions democracy’s fall into tyranny. In reminding readers of Socrates’ death, the dialogue warns, however, that fear of education may prevent democratic citizens from appreciating the role of cultural diversity in cultivating the virtue of Socratic wisdom. Keywords: Menexenus; Aspasia; cultural diversity; Socratic wisdom; Platonic irony Acknowledgments: An earlier version of this paper was presented at the 2012 annual meeting of the Association for Political Theory, where it benefitted greatly from Susan Bickford’s insightful commentary. Thanks to Ethan Alexander-Davey, Andreas Avgousti, Richard Avramenko, Brendan Irons, Daniel Kapust, Michelle Schwarze, the APSR editorial team (both present and former), and four anonymous referees for their invaluable feedback on earlier drafts.
    [Show full text]
  • 8 Nickolas Pappas and Mark Zelcer What Might Philosophy Say At
    ��8 Book Reviews Nickolas Pappas and Mark Zelcer Politics and Philosophy in Plato’s Menexenus: Education and Rhetoric, Myth and History (London; New York: Routledge, 2015), vii + 236 pp. $140.00. ISBN 9781844658206 (hbk). What might philosophy say at the burial of citizens who died in war? No sooner is this timely question raised that we must acknowledge that it is far from obvious what the philosopher would say. Civic funerals are moments in political life where the philosopher is confronted by contingency, by a blow to the body politic of which she is part, where she must either speak or keep silent. The confrontation is the subject of Pappas and Zelcer’s book, Politics and Philosophy in Plato’s ‘Menexenus’. The couplings in its subtitle reveal the main ingredients of philosophic speech: Education and Rhetoric, Myth and History. The Menexenus, the authors write, ‘show[s] philosophy bringing a pedagogical impulse to funeral rhetoric that the Republic says philosophical rulers would bring to all aspects of governing a city’ (p. 99). Plato acknowledges the ‘magic of rhetoric’ (p. 136), and the relationship between philosophy and rhetoric is analogous to the relationship between philosophy and politics: in both cases philosophy is the superior partner and the driving force. For Plato, Pappas and Zelcer conclude, the dead are to be ‘buried in philosophy’ (p. 220). Since one cannot assume a ready familiarity with the Menexenus, here is a brief summary. Plato raises Socrates from the dead to converse with the young Menexenus, as the city is poised to commemorate those who died in Athens’ defeat at the end of the Corinthian War in 386 BC.
    [Show full text]
  • PYTHAGORAS-The-Story-Of-A-Child
    1 Title: Pitagora – Storia di un bambino diventato immortale © 2019 Nuova Scuola Pitagorica – all rights reserved Editing by Marco Tricoli Cover by Giuseppe Santoro Translation by Gabriella Mongiardo www.nuovascuolapitagorica.org 2 Pythagoras The story of a child that became immortal Nuova Scuola Pitagorica 3 Foreword This publication was born with the intention of stimulating awareness of the Pythagorean phenomenon and of opening a debate in society and particularly in the world of school edu- cation. It represents a starting point for a series of activities in various fields to schedule over the years. The contents of this text are the result of studies and analyses conducted within the New Pythagorean School, thanks to the contribution of its members spread around the world. The New Pythagorean School is an organization open to eve- ryone, without any preclusion and without precepts or pre- conceived truths to give: a school of free thought. It conducts activities in various cultural sectors, from the artistic to the lit- erary one, giving particular emphasis to ethical philosophy as a universal guide to righteous behavior in order to create a bet- ter world. 4 Pythagoras The story of a child that became immortal There once was a beautiful and intelligent child, with long flowing hair that sometimes took on a blond shade and at other times a copper one. Thus, he was called the long-haired. His eyes were a sea green and light blue sky color and his body was thin and in shape. He was also very curious and continu- ously asked questions about everything.
    [Show full text]
  • Porphyry on Pythagoras V
    Porphyry on The Life of Pythagoras Porphyry on Pythagoras v. 12.11, www.philaletheians.co.uk, 3 April 2018 Page 1 of 15 BUDDHAS AND INITIATES SERIES PORPHYRY ON PYTHAGORAS From Porphyrius, Vita Pythagorae, 17. Translated by Kenneth Sylvan Guthrie. Alpine, New Jer- sey: Platonist Press, c. 1919. This biography should not to confused with the another work bear- ing the same title by Iamblichus, thought to be Porphyry’s disciple. ANY THINK THAT PYTHAGORAS WAS THE SON OF MNESARCHUS, but they differ as to the latter’s race; some thinking him a Samian, while Neanthes, M in the fifth book of his Fables states he was a Syrian, from the city of Tyre. As a famine had arisen in Samos, Mnesarchus went thither to trade, and was natu- ralized there. There also was born his son Pythagoras, who early manifested studi- ousness, but was later taken to Tyre, and there entrusted to the Chaldeans, whose doctrines he imbibed. Thence he returned to Ionia, where he first studied under the Syrian Pherecydes, then also under Hermodamas the Creophylian who at that time was an old man residing in Samos. 2. Neanthes says that others hold that his father was a Tyrrhenian, of those who in- habit Lemnos, and that while on a trading trip to Samos was there naturalized. On sailing to Italy, Mnesarchus took the youth Pythagoras with him. Just at this time this country was greatly flourishing. Neanthes adds that Pythagoras had two older brothers, Eunostus and Tyrrhenus. But Apollonius, in his book about Pythagoras, affirms that his mother was Pythais, a descendant, of Ancaeus, the founder of Sa- mos.
    [Show full text]
  • Women and Property in Ancient Athens: a Discussion of the Private Orations and Menander Cheryl Cox University of Memphis
    Women and Property in Ancient Athens: A Discussion of the Private Orations and Menander Cheryl Cox University of Memphis There has been a great deal of discussion in the past two decades or so among social historians and anthropologists of the proposition that women in European societies, both in the past and in the present, have informal power at the private level of the household. Women’s interests were reflected and expressed in succession practices and in the management of the household economy. Central to the status of women was the dowry because of its place in the conjugal household and the negotiations over its use and transmission. A large dowry ensured the woman’s important role in the decisions of the marital household and thus helped to stabilize the marriage. Because the dowry, as the property of the woman’s natal kin, would ideally be transmitted to the man’s children, the man could become involved in the property interests of his wife’s family of origin.1 In a material sense, in classical Athens the wife’s dowry allowed for the cohesion of two households (oikoi): the oikos of her marriage and that of her natal family. The dowry in legal terms belonged to the woman’s natal family, as it had to be returned to her family of origin either on divorce or on the death of her husband and her remarriage. Much of the information we have for dowries pertains to elite families. Because the woman’s dowry could be inherited by the children, it was worth fighting for, especially if she had not received her full share (Dem.
    [Show full text]
  • Status of Women in Ancient Greece
    Center for Open Access in Science ▪ https://www.centerprode.com/ojas.html Open Journal for Anthropological Studies, 2019, 3(2), 49-54. ISSN (Online) 2560-5348 ▪ https://doi.org/10.32591/coas.ojas.0302.03049s _________________________________________________________________________ Status of Women in Ancient Greece Zhulduz Amangelidyevna Seitkasimova M. Auezov South Kazakhstan State University, KAZAKHSTAN Faculty of Pedagogy and Culture, Shymkent Received 18 October 2019 ▪ Revised 12 December 2019 ▪ Accepted 21 December 2019 Abstract This paper examines the status, position and roles of women in ancient Greece. Based on available historical sources, it can be clearly established that women in ancient Greece had an inferior position to men. They were primarily viewed as “species-extending beings”. In none of the Greek city-states did women have political rights and were not considered as citizens. The status of women in ancient Greece, in terms of role, position, opportunity etc., varied from one city-state to another. This status is well known for ancient Athens, based on the large number of historical sources that can document the basic characteristics of the status of women in ancient Athens. Keywords: women’ status, ancient Greece, society, family, gender discrimination. 1. Introduction What was the status and positions of women in ancient Greece, and what was the main characteristics of that status? Women in the ancient Greek world had no possess all rights as men possessed and had few rights in comparison to male citizens. The key restrictions that women had was that they could not vote in different public affairs, and also could not own or inherit land.
    [Show full text]
  • The Making of a Prostitute: Apollodoros's Portrait Of
    Apollodoros’s Portrait of Neaira 161 THE MAKING OF A PROSTITUTE: APOLLODOROS’S PORTRAIT OF NEAIRA1 ALLISON GLAZEBROOK Apollodoros’s account of the life of Neaira ([Demosthenes] 59.16–49) is the most extensive narrative extant on a historical woman from the classical period. The recent publication of Debra Hamel’s book, Trying Neaira: The True Story of a Courtesan’s Scandalous Life in Ancient Greece (2003), has made the famous speech against Neaira and its recent scholarship accessible to a popular audience. The strength of Hamel’s work lies in the political, legal, and social context she provides for the speech, along with her ques- tioning of the various claims Apollodoros makes about Neaira’s “children” and her conclusion that he never proves beyond a doubt that Neaira has been acting as Stephanos’s wife. But does Apollodoros offer “the true story” of Neaira’s life as a courtesan, as Hamel’s title so boldly claims?2 The narrative detail of the speech and the testimony of witnesses convince Hamel (2003.156) that Apollodoros accurately portrays the events of Neaira’s early life. While one function of such witnesses was to attest to the veracity of a speaker’s comments, as in the modern day, their second 1A version of this paper was originally presented at the APA annual meeting in San Diego (2001). I would like to thank the audience for their lively discussion and helpful response, as well as Susan Cole, for her many suggestions, and my anonymous readers whose comments proved most fruitful. 2There is an assumption that oratory is a more objective source of evidence on women than other genres (Pomeroy 1975.x–xi).
    [Show full text]
  • Download Date | 6/9/19 10:06 AM Pseudo-Pythagorean Literature 73
    Philologus 2019; 163(1): 72–94 Leonid Zhmud* What is Pythagorean in the Pseudo-Pythagorean Literature? https://doi.org/10.1515/phil-2018-0003 Abstract: This paper discusses continuity between ancient Pythagoreanism and the pseudo-Pythagorean writings, which began to appear after the end of the Pythagorean school ca. 350 BC. Relying on a combination of temporal, formal and substantial criteria, I divide Pseudopythagorica into three categories: 1) early Hellenistic writings (late fourth – late second centuries BC) ascribed to Pytha- goras and his family members; 2) philosophical treatises written mostly, yet not exclusively, in pseudo-Doric from the turn of the first century BC under the names of real or fictional Pythagoreans; 3) writings attributed to Pythagoras and his relatives that continued to appear in the late Hellenistic and Imperial periods. I will argue that all three categories of pseudepigrapha contain astonishingly little that is authentically Pythagorean. Keywords: Pythagoreanism, pseudo-Pythagorean writings, Platonism, Aristote- lianism Forgery has been widespread in time and place and varied in its goals and methods, and it can easily be confused with superficially similar activities. A. Grafton Note: An earlier version of this article was presented at the colloquium “Pseudopythagorica: stratégies du faire croire dans la philosophie antique” (Paris, 28 May 2015). I would like to thank Constantinos Macris (CNRS) for his kind invitation. The final version was written during my fellowship at the IAS of Durham University and presented at the B Club, Cambridge, in Mai 2016. I am grateful to Gábor Betegh for inviting me to give a talk and to the audience for the vivid discussion.
    [Show full text]
  • Women in Early Pythagoreanism
    Women in Early Pythagoreanism Caterina Pellò Faculty of Classics University of Cambridge Clare Hall February 2018 This dissertation is submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Alla nonna Ninni, che mi ha insegnato a leggere e scrivere Abstract Women in Early Pythagoreanism Caterina Pellò The sixth-century-BCE Pythagorean communities included both male and female members. This thesis focuses on the Pythagorean women and aims to explore what reasons lie behind the prominence of women in Pythagoreanism and what roles women played in early Pythagorean societies and thought. In the first chapter, I analyse the social conditions of women in Southern Italy, where the first Pythagorean communities were founded. In the second chapter, I compare Pythagorean societies with ancient Greek political clubs and religious sects. Compared to mainland Greece, South Italian women enjoyed higher legal and socio-political status. Similarly, religious groups included female initiates, assigning them authoritative roles. Consequently, the fact that the Pythagoreans founded their communities in Croton and further afield, and that in some respects these communities resembled ancient sects helps to explain why they opened their doors to the female gender to begin with. The third chapter discusses Pythagoras’ teachings to and about women. Pythagorean doctrines did not exclusively affect the followers’ way of thinking and public activities, but also their private way of living. Thus, they also regulated key aspects of the female everyday life, such as marriage and motherhood. I argue that the Pythagorean women entered the communities as wives, mothers and daughters. Nonetheless, some of them were able to gain authority over their fellow Pythagoreans and engage in intellectual activities, thus overcoming the female traditional domestic roles.
    [Show full text]