Averroes, Kant and the Origins of the Enlightenment: Reason and Revelation in Arab Thought by Saud M

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Averroes, Kant and the Origins of the Enlightenment: Reason and Revelation in Arab Thought by Saud M book reviews 219 while universities in Muslim contexts are not yet ‘great contributors to the socio- cultural and civilisational advance of societ[y]’ (p. 36) as universities are in the European/Western world, they certainly represent a diverse array of attempts to weave Islam into modern pedagogic discourse. As evidenced by a conscious reflection on the part of Pakistani academics interviewed about the presence of Islam or Islamic principles as part of a Pakistani Higher Education ethos—whether successfully executed or not— Muslims are cognizant of their rich heritage of learning. Facing a number of Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jis/article/27/2/219/2458813 by guest on 27 September 2021 socio-economic, political, cultural and linguistic challenges, some overlapping with other Muslim countries, others peculiar to Pakistan’s South Asian post- colonial nature, where Pakistani academics (exemplifying one Muslim context) are shown to be wondering where they should place themselves in space and time with respect to not just a rich past of Muslim empires, but Indian Muslims specifically. Therein, argues Muborakshoeva, lies the opportunity aptly referred to in the book’s title: able to critique themselves and their system, academics have the potential to harness the knowledge and creativity with which to revive and reform higher learning and make it in Muslim contexts so as to ‘open debates ...and critically approach the study of, the past and present heritage of their [respective] countries’ (p. 152). Soufia A. Siddiqi St. Anne’s College, Oxford E-mail: soufi[email protected] doi:10.1093/jis/etw001 Published online 23 February 2016 Averroes, Kant and the Origins of the Enlightenment: Reason and Revelation in Arab Thought By Saud M. S. Al Tamamy (London and New York: I.B. Tauris, 2014, Library of Middle East History, 46), 280 pp. Price HB £56.00. EAN 978–1780765709. There is much to praise in this book, especially the light Professor Al Tamamy casts upon contemporary Arab thought. It is all too neglected by most Western scholars, even though the attempts of those living and writing in the Arabic-Islamic world to explain the dilemmas it faces today deserve all of our attention. Though not as commendable, Al Tamamy’s analysis of the European Enlightenment and its origins, is interesting—mainly for his focus on Kant as its major proponent. Of special interest here, at least to me, is Al Tamamy’s agreement with my argument that Averroes is not a precursor of that or any other Enlightenment, coupled with his refusal of any other common ground on how to read this most important thinker. The work’s fundamental question, why an Arab Enlightenment did not occur, is not and—truth be told—cannot be answered. So Al Tamamy replaces it by that of why the Western Enlightenment occurred. His answer focuses on Immanuel 220 book reviews Kant, above all on his time and locale. That is insufficient and, moreover, too beholden to a never examined premise identifying ideas as necessarily rooted in their historical epochs. A much simpler and more direct way to answer the question is to focus on the authors of the movement that came to be known as the Enlightenment, namely, Jean le Rond d’Alembert, De´nis Diderot, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, and even Franc¸ois-Marie Arouet, also known as Voltaire. For them, the recovery of the major writings of the past and the new emancipation from servile acceptance of Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jis/article/27/2/219/2458813 by guest on 27 September 2021 religious dogma allowed citizens—all citizens—to aspire to understand things for themselves. This new freedom held much promise ...and many dangers. Rousseau was perhaps the only one to address those dangers, something he accomplished with rare eloquence. Simply put, appealing as recourse to reason and to the pursuit of science or humanistic knowledge might be, not all individuals have the capacity to pursue such avenues. Many will be led astray by such investigations, just as many will gracelessly abandon themselves to frivolous imitations of greater poetic and literary masters. As a result, the work necessary to the well-being of a nation will be neglected. Such at least was the dismal prognosis offered by the ever cantankerous Citizen of Geneva. Cantankerous, yes, but honest. In place of enlightened—perhaps better placed in quotations marks as ‘enlightened’—pursuits, Rousseau offered something more basic: dedication to civic duty and reliance upon conscience rather than reason. No one has answered Rousseau, though many have tried. Most important, Kant never made the attempt. That, I submit, is where the analysis of the Enlighenment and its relationship to the Arabic-Islamic world today ought to begin. This has escaped not only Al Tamamy, but also any number of contemporary Arab thinkers who might have addressed it: Muhammad al-Jabiri above all, but also Hasan Hanafi, Aziz al-Azmeh, Sadiq al-Azm, and the multitude of other thinkers whose writings Al Tamamy reviews in his first chapter. To state the issue more boldly: none of these thinkers, Al Tamamy included, has even addressed the question. Al Tamamy’s stated conviction that reason completes faith, another way of saying that reason is consonant with revelation, may well keep him from pursuing the task—one that cannot ignore the attack upon religion by the proponents of Enlightenment. No such reticence can account for the silence of at least two of these other thinkers. What turns them away from this pursuit or prompts them to raise other questions must be desire that a shackled reason—one promising technological, political, and economic advances—become the lodestar of Arabic–Islamic thought, not a reason that accepts no binding ropes. Alas, once loosed, reason is as recalcitrant to control as the many beings kept shut within Pandora’s chest. Consequently, Al Tamamy, ignoring Bacon and Machiavelli, begins his account of the European Enlightenment with Jean Bodin, then moves on to the natural law teaching of Grotius, Pufendorf, and Wolff and also to the moral and natural science inquiries of Descartes, Locke, and Hume. These, for Al Tamamy, are the thinkers most important for discovering Kant’s practical teaching. Because metaphysics rather than politics provides the ground for Kant’s embrace book reviews 221 of freedom, Rousseau is accorded only a passing reference. But perhaps one need not reach so far. Kant does not, at least not in his essay on Enlightenment. Rather, freedom is what characterizes human fulfillment. Enlightenment allows human beings to claim maturity, that is, to rely on their own judgment. Voicing that claim, daring to be mature, is an act of courage—one that has become possible only because his fellow citizens, like himself, enjoy the rule of an enlightenment monarch—even, at least in Al Tamamy’s judgment, a despot. Kant immediately puts strictures on such an expression of freedom, Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jis/article/27/2/219/2458813 by guest on 27 September 2021 distinguishing between its permissible public expression in scholarly discourse and impermissible private voicing. The clergyman, public servant, or other citizen representing a higher authority may not speak his own mind, that is, act maturely. The limits are important and were not observed by the French proponents of the movement. Indeed, the claim of ability to reason for oneself in an orderly manner, rooted in a rejection of the received tradition—philosophic and ecclesiastic—led to a questioning of all authority, political as well as intellectual, and to the revolution that transformed European society. Whether adherence to the doctrines of Kant would be sufficient safeguard against such consequences remains to be seen, and Al Tamamy does not address the question. More must be said about Averroes, not least because Al Tamamy and I understand his teaching so differently. For reasons never explained, Al Tamamy favours George F. Hourani’s edition (London, 1959) and translation (On the Harmony of Religion and Philosophy, London, 1969) of Averroes’s Book of the Decisive Treatise (Kita¯bFaBl al-Maqa¯l) over mine and rejects—not refutes—my characterization of Averroes, replacing it by his own. Here is the issue: while we agree that Averroes is not a proponent of Enlightenment, we disagree about whether he is in favour of rationalism. I think he is, Al Tamamy does not (pp. 3 and 203). For Al Tamamy, those who hold views contrary to his are said to ‘cherry-pick’ among Averroes’s ideas. For me, the error stems, rather, from failing to understand the basic arguments Averroes expounds in his multiple writings and especially in the trilogy of which the FaBl is the centre-piece, literally and figuratively. (It seems, incidentally, that Al Tamamy ignores the relationship between the FaBl and its sequel, Kita¯b al-Kashf 6an mana¯hij al-adilla fı¯ 6aqa¯8id al- milla.) One reason Al Tamamy eschews such analysis is that he believes he alone understands how Averroes understood his relationship with his rulers, this even though Averroes never says anything about such an entente. That prejudgment must be contested along with the one that prompts Al Tamamy to assert a belief in progress in history and thus to reject—again, not refute—the approach of Leo Strauss (and also my own). Fundamental as these differences are, this is not the place to contest them. But they do merit notice. There are other, much more important questions, that deserve answers. Why, for example, do nineteenth- and twentieth-century thinkers writing in Arabic focus on Kant? Is it because he offers a version of enlightenment as freedom, albeit—as noted—one that depends upon Frederick? And, subsequent to Kant, who can deserve such attention? Curiously, with rare exceptions—6Abd al-RaAma¯n Badawı¯’s flirtation with Heidegger in al-Zama¯n al-wuju¯ dı¯ comes readily to mind—there are no major contenders.
Recommended publications
  • St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death
    The University of Akron IdeaExchange@UAkron Williams Honors College, Honors Research The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors Projects College Spring 2020 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death Christopher Choma [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects Part of the Christianity Commons, Epistemology Commons, European History Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, History of Religion Commons, Metaphysics Commons, Philosophy of Mind Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Please take a moment to share how this work helps you through this survey. Your feedback will be important as we plan further development of our repository. Recommended Citation Choma, Christopher, "St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death" (2020). Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects. 1048. https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects/1048 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors College at IdeaExchange@UAkron, the institutional repository of The University of Akron in Akron, Ohio, USA. It has been accepted for inclusion in Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects by an authorized administrator of IdeaExchange@UAkron. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. 1 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death By: Christopher Choma Sponsored by: Dr. Joseph Li Vecchi Readers: Dr. Howard Ducharme Dr. Nathan Blackerby 2 Table of Contents Introduction p. 4 Section One: Three General Views of Human Nature p.
    [Show full text]
  • Jewish Averroists Between Two Expulsions (1306-1492): from Conflict to Reconciliation
    JEWISH AVERROISTS BETWEEN TWO EXPULSIONS (1306-1492): FROM CONFLICT TO RECONCILIATION Basem Mahmud Freie Universität Berlin ABSTRACT This article investigates the intellectual production of Jewish authors influenced by Averroes in the 14th and 15th Centuries in northern Spain and southern France. The primary objective is to determine the main features of Jewish Averroism in this period, and to understand it within its socio-historical context. The outcomes suggest that there was a relationship between the new social and political trends toward democratization and reconciliation in the heart of Jewish communities on one hand, and the growing interest in Averroes’ original works on the other. Original here means the works that are not commentaries or summaries of other works. Key words: Aristotelianism, Averroes, Averroism, Jewish philosophy, Kabbalah, Maimonides, Scripture. INTRODUCTION «There is nothing worse in social government than a policy that makes one single society into several, just as there is no greater good in communities than a policy that joins and unifies» (Averroes)1 The 14th Century was a very difficult time for Jewish communities in northern Spain and southern France, they faced great threats from outside as well as significant domestic division. The domestic conflict emerged not only because of religious and philosophical issues, but also due to economic and social matters related to the distribution of wealth and power within Jewish communities.2 In addition, these communities lived in delicate conditions due to threats from the Christians. This situation also had an effect on demographics. Since the last years of 13th Century, the Jewish community started to encounter sizeable obstacles in its demographic development.3 Under these conditions, Hebraic Averroism continued its development which had begun in XIII century.
    [Show full text]
  • Albert Schweitzer: a Man Between Two Cultures
    , .' UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I LIBRARY ALBERT SCHWEITZER: A MAN BETWEEN TWO CULTURES A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN LANGUAGES AND LITERATURES OF • EUROPE AND THE AMERICAS (GERMAN) MAY 2007 By Marie-Therese, Lawen Thesis Committee: Niklaus Schweizer Maryann Overstreet David Stampe We certify that we have read this thesis and that, in our opinion, it is satisfactory in scope and quality as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts in Languages and Literatures of Europe and the Americas (German). THESIS COMMITIEE --~ \ Ii \ n\.llm~~~il\I~lmll:i~~~10 004226205 ~. , L U::;~F H~' _'\ CB5 .H3 II no. 3Y 35 -- ,. Copyright 2007 by Marie-Therese Lawen 1II "..-. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS T I would like to express my deepest gratitude to a great number of people, without whose assistance, advice, and friendship this thesis w0l!'d not have been completed: Prof. Niklaus Schweizer has been an invaluable mentor and his constant support have contributed to the completion of this work; Prof. Maryann Overstreet made important suggestions about the form of the text and gave constructive criticism; Prof. David Stampe read the manuscript at different stages of its development and provided corrective feedback. 'My sincere gratitude to Prof. Jean-Paul Sorg for the the most interesting • conversations and the warmest welcome each time I visited him in Strasbourg. His advice and encouragement were highly appreciated. Further, I am deeply grateful for the help and advice of all who were of assistance along the way: Miriam Rappolt lent her editorial talents to finalize the text; Lynne Johnson made helpful suggestions about the chapter on Bach; John Holzman suggested beneficial clarifications.
    [Show full text]
  • The Agent Intellect As" Form for Us" and Averroes's. Critique of Al-Farabi
    Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía ISSN: 0188-6649 [email protected] Universidad Panamericana México Taylor, Richard C. The Agent Intellect as "form for us" and Averroes's. Critique of al-Farabi Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía, núm. 29, 2005, pp. 29-51 Universidad Panamericana Distrito Federal, México Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=323027318003 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative The Agent Intellect as "form for us" and Averroes's Critique of al-FarabT Richard C. Taylor Marquette University This article explicates Averroes's understanding of human knowing and abstraction in this three commentaries on Aristotle's De Anima. While Averroes's views on the nature of the human material intellect changes through the three commentaries until he reaches is famous view of the unity of the material intellect as one for all human beings, his view of the agent intellect as 'form for us' is sustained throughout these works. In his Long Commentary on the De Anima he reveals his dependence on al-Farabi for this notion and provides a detailed critique of the Farabian notion that the agent intellect is 'form for us' only as agent cause, not as our true formal cause. Although Averroes argues that the agent intellect must somehow be intrinsic to us as our form since humans 2tieper se rational and undertake acts of knowing by will, his view is shown to rest on an equivocal use of the notion of formal cause.
    [Show full text]
  • Agrippa Von Nettesheim, Heinrich Cornelius, 61, 62, 70, 91 Albert of Saxony, 44 Alberti, Leon Battista, 51 Albertus Magnus, 44
    INDEX Agrippa von Nettesheim, Heinrich Blumenberg, Hans, 114 Cornelius, 61, 62, 70, 91 Böhme, Jakob, 113 Albert of Saxony, 44 Botero, Giovanni, 72 Alberti, Leon Battista, 51 Brahe, Tycho, 89 Albertus Magnus, 44, 45 Brucker, Johann Jakob, 111 Alciato, Andrea, 64 Bruno, Giovanni, 1 Alexander of Aphrodisias, 2 Alsted, Johann Heinrich, 79, 110 Calvin, John, 10 Alvinczi, Peter, 109 Calvinism, Calvinists, 3, 10, 11, 26, Analogy, 17, 18, 23, 38, 40, 41, 83, 57, 79, 80, 106, 107, 109, 93 117, 118 Antitrinitarianism, 3, 10, 26 Campanella, Tommaso, 94, 96 Antonino of Fiesole, 5 Carrière, Moritz, 113 Aquarius, Matthias, 4, 45 Cassirer, Ernst, 114 Aquilecchia, Giovanni, 110 Castelnau, Michel de, 25, 26, 28, 29, Aquinas, Thomas, 4, 6, 7, 13, 16, 39, 69, 72, 117, 118 41, 46, 47, 50, 56, 57, 117 Catherine de’ Medici, 11 Aratus, 52 Catherine of Siena, 5 Arian heresy, 7, 8, 117 Cavalca, Domenico, 5 Ariosto, Ludovico, 3, 85, 103 Celestino da Verona, 101 Aristotle, Aristotelianism, Center, 1, 31, 33, 43, 50, 68, 97 Aristotelian, 2, 4, 6, 10, 11, Chambéry, 9, 117 15, 16, 19, 21, 22, 25, 27–29, Chaos, 38 36–38, 39, 41, 43, 44–47, 51, Christ, 3, 5, 8, 54, 55 59, 60, 61, 63, 64, 67, 71–79, Christian I of Saxony, 80 83, 86, 88, 89, 110, 117 Church Fathers, 7 Astronomy, 9, 11, 27, 32, 34, 38, 52, Cicala, 1 70, 117 Cicero, 13, 84 Atomism, 3, 50, 69, 71, 72, 96, 99, Clemens, Franz Jacob, 112 102, 110 Clement VIII, Pope, 102, 103 Augustine, 5, 7, 35, 38, 55, 66 Colle, Giovanni Vincenzo (Sarnese), Augustinians, 2 2 Augustus I of Saxony, 80 Combinatorics, 15, 20,
    [Show full text]
  • The Aristotelian Curriculum in Arabic and Hebrew
    1 The Aristotelian Curriculum (Excluding Mathematics) In Arabic and Hebrew (occasionally also Greek, Syriac, Persian, Latin) Handout for “Aristotle in the Middle Ages,” James Robinson, U. Chicago, Winter 2013 General background: Christina d’Ascona, “Greek Sources in Arabic and Islamic Philosophy,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy Online: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-greek/ M. Zonta, “The Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on Judaic Thought,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-judaic/ Dag Hasse, “The Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-influence/ Tony Street, “Arabic and Islamic Philosophy of Language and Logic,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-language/ J. McGinnis, “Arabic and Islamic Natural Philosophy and Natural Science,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-natural/ Alfred Ivry, “Arabic and Islamic Psychology and Philosophy of Mind,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-mind/ Amos Bertolacci, “Arabic and Islamic Metaphysics,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-metaphysics/ Useful Resources: Arist. semitico-latinus: http://www.brill.com/publications/aristoteles-semitico-latinus Online dictionary of Arabic philosophical terms: http://www.arabic-philosophy.com/dict Hans Daiber
    [Show full text]
  • Averroes and His Using Plato's Republic in History
    Journal of Social Sciences and Humanities Vol. 1, No. 3, 2015, pp. 229-234 http://www.aiscience.org/journal/jssh Averroes and His Using Plato's Republic in History Mohammadreza Shahidipak * Faculty of Arts and humanity and literature, Department of History Islamic Republic of Iran, Islamic Azad University Central Tehran Branch, Tehran, Iran Abstract Classical Greek Social-political philosophy belongs to Plato and Aristotle and is based on the paradigm of liberty of human wisdom in presenting values in order to manage its life. Averroes (1126) re-examined the Greece philosophy and collected and explained the works and traces of Aristotle and this resulted in the development of philosophy and emergence a new global philosophy in Spain. In Averroes’s view, philosophy does not belong to Greece, and its universal truth has no limitation of nation, time or place. Representing the mentioned paradigm destroyed the cultural unity of the medieval world. Paper investigated the basic element of political philosophy as freedom, justice, ruler’s attributions, good life, philosophical description of cities and role of education and public law, right ,emotion, reason in facing of cities ;based on a commentary of Plato’s Republic by Averroes .He used terminology of political philosophy of Plato with Aristotelian view. Interpretation of social and political philosophy of Plato by Averroes in west of Islamic world is the most important cultural phenomenon in history of philosophy have conserved still his vast influence. Averroes is famous and remarkable philosopher and jurist believed in priority of reason and philosophy .He was excommunicated in eastern and western of Islamic world and in Europe but he still has any successors of Jew, Christians and Islamic philosophers and free scholar in the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Al-Kindi, a Ninth-Century Physician, Philosopher, And
    AL-KINDI, A NINTH-CENTURY PHYSICIAN, PHILOSOPHER, AND SCHOLAR by SAMI HAMARNEH FROM 9-12 December, I962, the Ministry of Guidance in Iraq celebrated the thousandth anniversary of one of the greatest intellectual figures of ninth century Baghdad, Abui Yuisuf Ya'qiib ibn Ishaq al-Kind? (Latin Alkindus).1 However, in the aftermath ofthis commendable effort, no adequate coverage of al-Kindl as a physician-philosopher ofardent scholarship has, to my knowledge, been undertaken. This paper, therefore, is intended to shed light on his intel- lectual contributions within the framework of the environment and time in which he lived. My proposals and conclusions are mainly based upon a study of al-Kindi's extant scientific and philosophical writings, and on scattered information in the literature of the period. These historical records reveal that al-Kindi was the only man in medieval Islam to be called 'the philosopher of the Arabs'.2 This honorary title was apparently conferred upon him as early as the tenth century if not during his lifetime in the ninth. He lived in the Abbasids' capital during a time of high achievement. As one of the rare intellectual geniuses of the century, he con- tributed substantially to this great literary, philosophic, and scientific activity, which included all the then known branches of human knowledge. Very little is known for certain about the personal life of al-Kind?. Several references in the literary legacy ofIslam, however, have assisted in the attempt to speculate intelligently about the man. Most historians of the period confirm the fact that al-Kindl was of pure Arab stock and a rightful descendant of Kindah (or Kindat al-Muliuk), originally a royal south-Arabian tribe3.
    [Show full text]
  • An Investigation Into a Postmodern Feminist Reading of Averroës
    Journal of Feminist Scholarship Volume 10 Issue 10 Spring 2016 Article 5 Spring 2016 Bodies and Contexts: An Investigation into a Postmodern Feminist Reading of Averroës Reed Taylor University of Arkansas at Little Rock Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.uri.edu/jfs Part of the Feminist, Gender, and Sexuality Studies Commons, Law and Gender Commons, and the Women's History Commons This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Taylor, Reed. 2018. "Bodies and Contexts: An Investigation into a Postmodern Feminist Reading of Averroës." Journal of Feminist Scholarship 10 (Spring): 48-60. https://digitalcommons.uri.edu/jfs/vol10/ iss10/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by DigitalCommons@URI. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal of Feminist Scholarship by an authorized editor of DigitalCommons@URI. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Taylor: Bodies and Contexts Bodies and Contexts: An Investigation into a Postmodern Feminist Reading of Averroës Reed Taylor, University of Arkansas at Little Rock Abstract: In this article, I contribute to the wider discourse of theorizing feminism in predominantly Muslim societies by analyzing the role of women’s political agency within the writings of the twelfth-century Islamic philosopher Averroës (Ibn Rushd, 1126–1198). I critically analyze Catarina Belo’s (2009) liberal feminist approach to political agency in Averroës by adopting a postmodern reading of Averroës’s commentary on Plato’s Republic. A postmodern feminist reading of Averroes’s political thought emphasizes contingencies and contextualization rather than employing a literal reading of the historical works.
    [Show full text]
  • 19Chronology of Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy Of
    Chronology of 19 Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art Darren Hudson Hick Notes on Selection This chronology, as with this Companion as a whole, focuses on those works that contribute to the Western tradition of aesthetics, and, beginning in the twentieth century, in the analytic current of thought within that tradition (as opposed to the Continental one). As with the history of Western philosophy in general, the study of philosophical problems in art and beauty dates back to the ancient period, and is infl uenced by the major philosophical and cultural move- ments through the centuries. Much of what survives from the ancient to the post-Hellenistic period does so in fragments or references. In cases where only fragments or references exist, and where dating these is especially problematic, the author or attributed author and (where available) his dates of birth and death are listed. Where works have not survived even as fragments, these are not listed. As well, much of what sur- vives up to the medieval period is diffi cult to date, and is at times of disputable attribution. In these cases, whatever information is available is listed. Aesthetics in the period between the ancients and the medievals tends to be dominated by adherence to Platonic, Aristotelian, and other theories rooted in the ancient period, and as such tends to be generally lacking in substantive the- oretical advancements. And while still heavily infl uenced by ancient thinking, works from the medieval period tend also to be heavily infl uenced by religious thinking, and so many issues pertaining to art and aesthetics are intertwined with issues of religion as “theological aesthetics.” Movements in art theory and aes- thetics in the Renaissance, meanwhile, were largely advanced by working artists, and so tend to be couched in observational or pedagogical approaches, rather than strictly theoretical ones.
    [Show full text]
  • Brief Bibliographic Guide in Medieval Islamic Philosophy and Theology
    BRIEF BIBLIOGRAPHICAL GUIDE IN MEDIEVAL ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY (2004-2006) Thérèse-Anne Druart (The Catholic University of America) Section I. Falsafa a. Collective Works or Collections of Articles Albertus Magnus und die Anfänge der Aristoteles-Rezeption im lateinischen Mittelalter von Richardus Rufus bis zu Franciscus de Maryonis. Albertus Magnus and the Beginnings of the Medieval Reception of Aristotle in the Latin West, ed. by Ludger Honnefelder, Rega Wood, Mechthild Dreyer, & Marc-Aeilko Aris (Subsidia Albertina I). Münster: Aschendorff Verlag, 2005, 862 pp., ISBN 3- 402-03993-1. L’Alchimie et ses racines philosophiques. La tradition grecque et la tradition arabe, ed. by Cristina Viano (Histoire des doctrines de l’Antiquité classique, 32). Paris: Vrin, 2005, 242 pp., ISBN 2-7116-1754-8. Averroès et l’averroïsme (XIIe-XVe siècle). Un itinéraire historique du Haut Atlas à Paris et à Padoue, ed. by André Bazzana, Nicole Bériou & Pierre Guichard (Collection d’Histoire et d’Archéologie Médiévales, 16). Lyon: Presses Universitaires de Lyon, 2005, 348 pp., ISBN 2-7297-0769-7. The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy, ed. by Peter Adamson & Richard C. Taylor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005, xviii-448 pp., ISBN 0-521-81743-9 cloth; 52069-X pb. Corpo e anima, sensi interni e intelletto dai secoli XIII-XIV ai post-cartesiani e spinoziani, ed. by Graziella Federici Vescovini, Valeria Sorge & Carlo Vinti (Fédération Internationale des Instituts d’Études Médiévales. Textes et Études du Moyen Âge, 30). Turnhout: Brepols, 2005, vi-575 pp., ISBN 2-503-51988-1. De Zénon d’Élée à Poincaré. Recueil d’études en hommage à Roshdi Rashed, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is the Summa? Who Is St Thomas Aquinas?
    What is the Summa? The Summa Theologiae (written 1265–1274 and also known as the Summa Theologica or simply the Summa) is the best‐known work of Thomas Aquinas (c. 1225–1274). Although unfinished, the Summa is "one of the classics of the history of philosophy and one of the most influential works of Western literature."[1] It was intended as an instructional guide for moderate theologians and a compendium of all of the main theological teachings of the Catholic Church. It presents the reasoning for almost all points of Christian theology in the West. The Summa's topics follow a cycle: the existence of God; Creation, Man; Man's purpose; Christ; the Sacraments; and back to God. Among non‐scholars, the Summa is perhaps most famous for its five arguments for the existence of God known as the "five ways" .The five ways occupy one‐and‐a‐half pages of the Summa's approximately three thousand, five hundred pages. Throughout the Summa, Aquinas cites Christian, Muslim, Hebrew, and Pagan sources including but not limited to Christian Sacred Scripture, Aristotle, Augustine of Hippo, Avicenna, Averroes, Al‐Ghazali, Boethius, John of Damascus, Paul the Apostle, Dionysius the Areopagite, Maimonides, Anselm, Plato, Cicero, and Eriugena. The Summa is a more structured and expanded version of Aquinas's earlier Summa contra Gentiles, though these works were written for different purposes, the Summa Theologiae to explain the Christian faith to beginning theology students, and the Summa contra Gentiles to explain the Christian faith and defend it in hostile situations, with arguments adapted to the intended circumstances of its use, each article refuting a certain belief or a specific heresy.
    [Show full text]