The Logical Analysis of Psychology

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Logical Analysis of Psychology A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind Readings With Commentary NOTICE This material may be Peter A. Morton protected by ropyright Jaw (llUe 17 U.S. Code.) broadview press CHAPTER 7 164 A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy uf Mind CHAPTER 7 r Cart G. Hempel 165 ' which makes use of rigorous logical tools, and marter of psychology by means of physical which has made possible decisive advances to­ methods. The subject matter of physics includes Carl G. Hempel ward the solution of the above problem. 1 This such concepts as mass, wave length, tempera­ 1'rhe Logical Analysis of Psychology" analysis was carried our by the "Vienna Circle" ture, field intensity, etc. In dealing with these, (Wiener Kreis), the members of which (M. physics employs its distinctive method which Author's prefatory note, 1977. The original Dr. Block's plea that it offers a concise account Schlick, R. Carnap, P. Frank, 0. Neurath, F. makes a co.mbined use of description and causal French version of this article was published in of an early version of logical behaviorism and Waismann, H. Feigl, etc.) have, during the past explanation. Psychology, on the other hand, has 1935. By the time it appeared in English, I had would thus be a useful contribution to this an­ ten years, developed an extremely fruitful fur its subject matter notions which are, in a abandoned the narrow translationist form of thology. method fur the epistemological examination and broad sense, mental. They are toto gmere dif­ physicalism here set forth for a more liberal In an effort to enhance the closeness of critique of the various sciences, based in part on ferent from the concepts of physics, and the 2 reductionist one, referred to in note 1, which translation and the simplicity of formulation, I the work ofL. Wittgenstein. We shall limit our­ appropriate method fur dealing with them sci­ presents psychological properties and states as have made a number of small changes in the selves essentially to the examination of psychol­ entifically is that of empathetic insight, called partially characterized, but not defined, by bun­ text of the original English version; none of ogy as carried out by Carnap and Neurath. "introspection," a method which is peculiar to dles of behavioral dispositions. Since then, I these affects the substance of the article. The method characteristic of the studies of psychology. have come to think that this conception re­ the Vienna Circle can be briefly defined as a One of the principal differences between logical ttnaf)>sis of the language of siimct. This quires still further broadening, and that the in­ I the two kinds of subject matter is generally be­ troduction and application of psychological method became possible only with the devel­ lieved to consist in the fact that the objects in­ terms and hypotheses is logically and methodo­ One of the most important and most discussed opment of a subtle logical apparatus which vestigated by psychology-in contradistinction logically analogous to the introduction and ap­ problems of contemporary philosophy is that of makes usc, in particular, of all the formal pro­ to those of physics-are specifically endowed plication of the terms and hypotheses of a determining how psychology should be charac­ cedures of modern symbolic logic.3 However, in with meaning. Indeed, several proponents of physical theory.* The considerations that terized in the theory of science. This problem, the following account, which does not pretend this idea state that the distinctive method of prompted those changes also led me long ago which reaches beyond the limits of epistemo­ ro give mqre than a broad orientation, we shall psychology consists in "understanding the sense to abandon as untenable the verificationist logical analysis and has engendered heated con­ limit ourselves to setting out the general prin­ of meaningful structures" (sinnvolk Gebilde construal of the "empirical meaning" of a sen­ troversy in metaphysics itself, is brought to a ciples of this new method, without making use verstehmd zu eifassm). Take, for example, the tence-a construal which plays such a central focus by the familiar alternative, "Is psychology of strictly formal procedures. case of a man who speaks. Within the frame­ tole in the arguments set forth in this article. a natural science, or is it one of the sciences of work of physics, this process is considered to Since the atricle is so far from representing mind and culture ( Geisteswissmschaftm) ?" II be completely explained once the movements my present views, I was disinclined to consent The present article attempts to sketch the which make up the utterance have been traced to yet another republication, but I yielded to general lines of a new analysis of psychology, one Perhaps the best way to characterize the posi­ to their causes, that is to say, to certain physi­ tion of the Vienna Circle as it relates to psy­ ological processes in the organism, and, in par­ chology, is to say that it is the exact antithesis ticular, in the central nervous system. But, it is An earlier version of this paper appeared in and S.F. Barker, eds., The Legacy ofLegal Posi­ of the eutrent epistemological thesis that there said, this does not even broach the psychologi­ Ausonio Marras, ed., Intentionality, Mind. and tivism (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University is a fundamental difference between experimen­ cal problem. The latter begins with understand­ lAnguage (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, Press, 1969); "Reduction: Ontological and tal psychology, a natural science, and introspec­ ing the sense of what was said, and proceeds to · 1972), pp. 115-131, and in Herbert Feigl and Lingustic Facets," in S. Morgenbesser, P. tive psychology; and in general, berween the integrate it into a wider context of meaning. Wilfrid Sellars, eds., Readings in Philosophical Suppes, and M. White, eds., Philosophy. Scien«, natural sciences on the one hand, and the sci­ It is usually this latter idea which serves as a Analysis (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, and Mtthod: Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel ences of mind and culture on the other.4 The principle for the fundamental dichotomy that is 1949), pp. 373-384, translated from the (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1969); common content of the widely different fOrmu­ introduced into the classification of the sciences. French by W. Sellars. Reprinted, with revisions "Dispositional Explanation and the Covering· lations used to express this contention, which There is taken to be an absolutely impassable gulf by the author, with permission of the author, Law Model: Response to Laird Addis," in A. C. we reject, can be set down as follows. Apart between the natural sciences which have a sub­ Herbert Feigl, Wilfrid Sellars, and the editors Michalos and R.S. Cohen, eds., PSA 1974: Pro­ from certain aspects clearly related to physiol­ ject matter devoid of meaning and the sciences of of &vut de Synthtst. ceedingrofthe 1974 Bimnia/MeetingofthePhi­ ogy, psychology is radically different, both in mind and culture, which have an intrinsically *My reasons are suggested in some of my losophy ofScimu Association (Dordrecht: Reidel, subject matter and in method, from physics in meaningful subject matter, the appropriate more recent articles, among them "Logical Posi­ 1976), pp. 369-376. the broad sense of the term. In particular, it is methodological instrument for the scientific tivism and the Social Sciences," in P. Achinstein impossible to deal adequately with the subject study of which is "comprehension of meaning." l66 A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind CHAf'TfR 7 CHAPTER 7 r Carl G. Hempel 167 III subject matter of a science. The theoretical con­ "retranslated" without change of meaning into a. Paul weeps and makes gestures of such and tent of a science is to be found in statements. another statement-doubtless longer-in such kinds. The position in the theory of science which we It is necessary, therefore, to determine whether which the word "temperature" no longer ap­ b. At the question "What is the matter?," have just sketched has been attacked from sev­ there is a fundamental difference betWeen the pears. That term functions solely as an abbre­ Paul utters the words "I have a toothache." 5 eral different points ofview. As far as psychol­ statements of psychology and those of physics. viation, making pnssible the concise and c. Ooser examination reveals a decayed tooth ogy is concerned, one of the principal Let us therefore ask what it is that determines complete description of a state of affairs the ex­ with exposed pulp. countertheses is that formulated by behavior­ the content--<>ne can equally well say the pression of which would otherwise be very d. Paul's blood pressure, digestive processes, ism, a theory born in America shortly before "meaning"--<>f a statement. When, for exam­ complicated. the speed of his reactions, show such and the war. (In Russia, Pavlov has developed simi­ ple, do we know the meaning of the following 2. The example equally shows that two such changes. lar ideas.) Its principal methodological postu­ statement: "Today at one o'clock, the tempera­ statements which diffir in formulation can nev­ e. Such and such processes occur in Paul's late is that a scientific psychology should limit ture of such and such a place in the physics ertheless have the same meaning. A trivial ex­ central nervous system. itself to the study of the bodily behavior with laboratory was 23.4° centigrade"? Oearly when, ample of a statement having the same meaning This list could be expanded considerably, but which man and the animals respond to changes and only when, we know under what condi­ as the above would be: "Today at one o'clock, it is already sufficient to bring out the funda­ in their physical environment, and should pro­ tions we would call the statement true, and at such and such a location in the laboratory, mental and essential point, namely, that all the scribe as nonscientific any descriptive or ex­ under what circumstances we would call it false.
Recommended publications
  • The ('('Orthodox" View of Theories: Remarks in Defense As Well As Critique
    -----HERBERT FEIGL----- The ('('Orthodox" View of Theories: Remarks in Defense as well as Critique The purpose of the following remarks is to present in outline some of the more important features of scientific theories. I shall discuss the "standard" or "orthodox" view, mainly in order to set up a target for criticisms, some of which I shall briefly sketch by way of anticipation. The standard account of the structure of scientific theories was given quite explicitly by Norman R. Campbell [7], as well as independently in a little-known article by R. Carnap [12]. A large part of the voluminous literature in the philosophy of science of the logical empiricists and re­ lated thinkers contains, though with a great many variations, develop­ ments, modifications, and terminological diversities, essentially similar analyses of the logical structure and the empirical foundations of the theories of physics, biology, psychology, and some of the social sciences. Anticipating to some extent Campbell and Carnap, Moritz Schlick, in his epoch-making AIIgemeine Erkenntnisiehre [38], championed the doc­ trine of "implicit definition." In this he was influenced by David Hil­ bert's axiomatization of geometry, as well as by Henri Poincare's and Albert Einstein's conceptions of theoretical physics and the role of ge­ ometry in physics. These matters were then developed more fully and precisely in the work of H. Reichenbach, R. Carnap, C. G. Hempel, R. B. Braithwaite, E. Nagel, and many other logicians and methodolo­ gists of science. In order to understand the aim of this important approach in the philosophy of science it is essential to distinguish it from historical, so­ ciological, or psychological studies of scientific theories.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Major Issues and Developments in the Philosophy Ofscience Oflogical Empiricism
    -----HERBERT FEIGL----- Some Major Issues and Developments in the Philosophy ofScience ofLogical Empiricism AsouT twenty-five years ago a small group of philosophically minded scientists and scientifically trained philosophers in Vienna formulated their declaration of independence from traditional philosophy. The pamphlet Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der Wiener Kreis (1929) contained the first succinct statement of the outlook which soon after became known as "logical positivism." In the first flush of enthusiasm we Viennese felt we had attained a philosophy to end all philosophies. Schlick spoke of a "Wende der Philosophie" (a decisive turning point of philosophy). Neurath and Frank declared "school philosophy" as obsolete and even suggested that our outlook drop the word "philoso­ phy" altogether, and replace it by "Einheitswissenschaft" or by "scien· tific empiricism." The notable impact of Alfred Ayer's first book in England, and my own efforts ~oward a propagation of Logical Positiv­ ism in the United States during the early thirties, and then the immi· gration of Carnap, Frank, von Mises, Reichenbach, Hempel and Berg­ mann created a powerful movement, but it elicited also sharp opposition nncl criticism. Through the discussions within the movement and its own production and progressive work, as well as in response to the NO'l'F.: This essay is a revised and considerably expanded .version of a lecture given in plenary session at the International Congress for Philosophy of Science, Zurich, /\ngust 25, 1954. It was first- published in Proceedi11gs of the Secono International Congress of the International Union for tl1e Philosophy ot Science (Neuchatel, Switzerland, 19 55). In the cordial letter of invitation I received from Professor Ferdinand Gonseth, president of the Congress, he asked me to discuss "I'empirisme logi<\ue,-ce qu'il fut, et ce qu'il est clevenu." Much as I appreciated the honor of t 1is ambitious assignment, I realized of course that the limitations of time would permit me to deal onJy with some selected topics within this larger frame.
    [Show full text]
  • Passmore, J. (1967). Logical Positivism. in P. Edwards (Ed.). the Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Vol. 5, 52- 57). New York: Macmillan
    Passmore, J. (1967). Logical Positivism. In P. Edwards (Ed.). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Vol. 5, 52- 57). New York: Macmillan. LOGICAL POSITIVISM is the name given in 1931 by A. E. Blumberg and Herbert Feigl to a set of philosophical ideas put forward by the Vienna circle. Synonymous expressions include "consistent empiricism," "logical empiricism," "scientific empiricism," and "logical neo-positivism." The name logical positivism is often, but misleadingly, used more broadly to include the "analytical" or "ordinary language philosophies developed at Cambridge and Oxford. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND The logical positivists thought of themselves as continuing a nineteenth-century Viennese empirical tradition, closely linked with British empiricism and culminating in the antimetaphysical, scientifically oriented teaching of Ernst Mach. In 1907 the mathematician Hans Hahn, the economist Otto Neurath, and the physicist Philipp Frank, all of whom were later to be prominent members of the Vienna circle, came together as an informal group to discuss the philosophy of science. They hoped to give an account of science which would do justice -as, they thought, Mach did not- to the central importance of mathematics, logic, and theoretical physics, without abandoning Mach's general doctrine that science is, fundamentally, the description of experience. As a solution to their problems, they looked to the "new positivism" of Poincare; in attempting to reconcile Mach and Poincare; they anticipated the main themes of logical positivism. In 1922, at the instigation of members of the "Vienna group," Moritz Schlick was invited to Vienna as professor, like Mach before him (1895-1901), in the philosophy of the inductive sciences. Schlick had been trained as a scientist under Max Planck and had won a name for himself as an interpreter of Einstein's theory of relativity.
    [Show full text]
  • Introductory Lectures: the Nature and History of Cognitive Science Chapter 4: Philosophy’S Convergence Towards Cognitive Science by Dr
    Introductory Lectures: The Nature and History of Cognitive Science Chapter 4: Philosophy’s Convergence Towards Cognitive Science By Dr. Charles Wallis Last revision: 9/24/2018 Chapter Outline 4.1 Introduction 4.2 The Scientific Explosion of the Early 20th Century 4.3 The Logical and Mathematical Explosion of the Early 20th Century 4.4 The Rise Logical Empiricism 4.5 Logical Behaviorism 4.6 Three Problems for Logical Behaviorism 4.7 Identity Theories: Reduction Through Reference Equivalence Rather Than Meaning Equivalence 4.8 Identity Theories: Type-Type Identity 4.9 Two Arguments For Type-Type Identity Theory 4.10 Identity Theories: Token-Token Identity 4.11 Functionalism 4.12 Computationalism 4.13 Property Dualism 4.14 Eliminative Materialism 4.15 Glossary of Key Terms 4.16 Bibliography The 20th Century and the Semantic Twist 4.1 Introduction Recall that ontological frameworks provide a general framework within which theorists specify domains of inquiry and construct theories to predict, manipulate, and explain phenomena within the domain. Once researchers articulate an ontological framework with sufficient clarity they begin to formulate and test theories. Chapter two ends with the suggestion that oppositional substance dualists face two major challenges in their attempt to transition from the articulation of an ontological framework to the formulation and testing of theories purporting to predict, manipulate, and explain mental phenomena. On the one hand, oppositional substance dualists have problems formulating theories providing explanations, predictions, and manipulations of the continual, seamless interaction between the mental and the physical. Philosophers often call this the interaction problem. On the other hand, the very nature of a mental substance--substance defined so as to share no properties with physical substance--gives rise to additional challenges.
    [Show full text]
  • 36Pm Mathews
    Michael R. Matthews 223 Rescuing Two Positivist “Babies” from the Educational Bathwater Michael R. Matthews University of New South Wales It is an understatement to say that Positivism is unpopular in education circles. “Positivist” has become for educators, what “terrorist” is for politicians. In the past two decades positivists and their bathwater have been summarily dispatched out the education window. This situation represents a dramatic turn in philosophical and educational fashion. In the 1920s, adherents of the newly formulated positivism, or the “Scien- tific Conception of the World,” were social and educational progressives in a reactionary central-European milieu. In the 1950s and 1960s the logical empiricist variant of positivism dominated philosophy of science and monopolized the “nature of science” chapters of science textbooks. Most serious educational researchers measured their work against positivist norms of rigor, clarity, objectivity, repeat- ability, and so on. The change in intellectual fashion was dramatic: from comfortable bath to defenestration in just the time it took to say “Thomas Kuhn.” But how well based is the educational rejection of positivism? What can be rescued from the bathwater? This paper will answer the question by going back to the sources and examining the philosophical and educational views of two of the founding Vienna Circle positivists — Philipp Frank and Herbert Feigl — and arguing that they at least should be rescued from the bathwater; and further that most of their orientation to science, philosophy and education should be rescued along with them. Both Frank and Feigl followed in the scientific and philosophical footsteps of Ernst Mach, who also had deep and robust educational views.1 THE MENACE OF POSITIVISM The sheer volume of positivist “bad press” in education makes a comprehensive survey impossible, but a small sampling gives an idea of the whole.
    [Show full text]
  • Realistic Claims in Logical Empiricism
    Realistic Claims in Logical Empiricism Matthias Neuber Logical empiricism is commonly seen as a counter-position to scientific realism. In the pre- sent paper it is shown that there indeed existed a realist faction within the logical empiricist movement. In particular, I shall point out that at least four types of realistic arguments can be distinguished within this faction: Reichenbach’s ‘probabilistic argument,’ Feigl’s ‘pragmatic argument,’ Hempel’s ‘indispensability argument,’ and Kaila’s ‘invariantist argument.’ All these variations of arguments are intended to prevent the logical empiricist agenda from the shortcomings of radical positivism, instrumentalism, and other forms of scientific antirealism. On the whole, it will be seen that logical empiricism and scientific realism are essentially compatible with each other. Especially Kaila’s invariantist approach to science (and nature) comes quite close to what nowadays is discussed under the label ‘structural realism.’ This, in turn, necessitates a fundamental reevaluation of Kaila’s role in the logical empiricist move- ment in particular and in twentieth-century philosophy of science in general. Keywords: logical empiricism, structural realism, semantics, invariance, Eino Kaila 1 Introduction Logical Empiricism has for a long time been conceived of as a monolithic, one-dimensional, movement within early twentieth-century philosophy. As such, it frequently served as a con- trast for later, opposing viewpoints, such as scientific realism, critical rationalism, or Kuhnian historical
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of Karl Popper
    P1: JZX 0521839467Agg.xml CY443/Keuth 0521839467 August 25, 2004 16:38 The Philosophy of Karl Popper HERBERT KEUTH Eberhard Karls Universitat,¨ Tubingen¨ iii P1: JZX 0521839467Agg.xml CY443/Keuth 0521839467 August 25, 2004 16:38 published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, ny 10011-4211, usa 477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, vic 3207, Australia Ruiz de Alarcon´ 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org Die Philosophie Karl Poppers C J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck) 2000 English translation C Herbert Keuth 2005 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published in German in 2000 English edition first published 2005 Printed in the United States of America Typeface itc New Baskerville 10/13 pt. System LATEX 2ε [tb] A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication data Keuth, Herbert, 1940– [Philosophie Karl Poppers. English] The philosophy of Karl Popper / Herbert Keuth. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and indexes. isbn 0-521-83946-7 – isbn 0-521-54830-6 (pbk.) 1. Popper, Karl Raimund, Sir, 1902–1994 I. Title. b1649.p64k4813 2004 192 – dc22 2004045179 isbn 0 521 83946 7 hardback isbn 0 521 54830 6 paperback iv P1: JZX 0521839467Agg.xml CY443/Keuth 0521839467 August 25, 2004 16:38 Contents List of Abbreviations page xiii Preface xv Introduction 1 part i.
    [Show full text]
  • Carnap, Reichenbach and the Great Intellectual Migration. Part II: Hans Reichenbach.” Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 8(11): 24–47
    Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Coming to America: Carnap, Reichenbach and the Volume 8, Number 11 Great Intellectual Migration. Editor in Chief Part I: Rudolf Carnap Audrey Yap, University of Victoria Sander Verhaegh Editorial Board Annalisa Coliva, UC Irvine In the years before the Second World War, Rudolf Carnap and Henry Jackman, York University Hans Reichenbach emigrated to the United States, escaping the Frederique Janssen-Lauret, University of Manchester quickly deteriorating political situation on the continent. Once Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts in the U. S., the two significantly changed the American philo- Consuelo Preti, The College of New Jersey sophical climate. This two-part paper reconstructs Carnap’s and Marcus Rossberg, University of Connecticut Reichenbach’s surprisingly numerous interactions with Ameri- Anthony Skelton, Western University can academics in the decades before their move in order to explain Mark Textor, King’s College London the impact of their arrival in the late 1930s. Building on archival Richard Zach, University of Calgary material of several key players and institutions, I take some first steps toward answering the question why logical empiricism be- Editors for Special Issues came so successful in the United States after the War. This first Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University part reconstructs Carnap’s development between 1923, when he Alexander Klein, McMaster University first visited New York, and 1936, when he was offered a position Review Editors at the University of Chicago. I describe Carnap’s first substantive Sean Morris, Metropolitan State University of Denver contacts with American philosophers as well as the events lead- Sanford Shieh, Wesleyan University ing up to his decision to emigrate.
    [Show full text]
  • Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: the Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy Christopher Bailes Washington University in St
    Washington University in St. Louis Washington University Open Scholarship All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs) 5-24-2012 Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy Christopher Bailes Washington University in St. Louis Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/etd Recommended Citation Bailes, Christopher, "Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The eN ed for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy" (2012). All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs). 681. https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/etd/681 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs) by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WASHINGTON UNIVERSITY IN ST. LOUIS Department of Germanic Languages and Literatures Dissertation Examination Committee: Paul Michael Lützeler, Chair Julia Driver Matt Erlin Erin McGlothlin Gillian Russell Lynne Tatlock Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy By Christopher Wade Bailes A dissertation presented to the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Washington University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 2012 Saint Louis, Missouri Acknowledgements I would like to thank the Department of Germanic Languages and Literatures and Washington University in Saint Louis for their generous financial support. My dissertation benefited from various guest lecturers, conferences, and graduate seminars supported by the university, and would not have been financially feasible without the tuition waivers and more than adequate living stipends that kept me afloat.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of Logical Positivism ______
    The Philosophy of Logical Positivism ________________________________________________ Mauro Murzi Member of Società Filosofica Italiana [email protected] http://www.murzim.net 1 2 Table of Contents 1. Introduction.................................................................................................5 2. The Main Philosophical Tenets of Logical Positivism...............................7 a. Verifiability Principle.............................................................................7 b. Elimination of Metaphysics...................................................................7 c. The Language of Science.......................................................................8 d. Observational and Theoretical Terms..................................................10 e. Synthetic and Analytic Statements.......................................................11 f. Probability and Inductive Logic...........................................................12 g. Ethics....................................................................................................14 3. History of Logical Positivism...................................................................15 a. Before Logical Positivism....................................................................15 b. Early Research in Europe.....................................................................17 c. The American Period............................................................................17 d. Influences on European Philosophy.....................................................18
    [Show full text]
  • Economical Unification As a Method of Philosophical Analysis
    The Department of Philosophy, History, Culture and Art Studies University of Helsinki Finland Economical Unification as a Method of Philosophical Analysis Avril Styrman ACADEMIC DISSERTATION To be presented, with the permission of the Faculty of Arts of the University of Helsinki, for public examination in lecture room 13, University main building, on 17 December 2016, at 10 noon. Helsinki 2016 i Thesis Supervisor Professor Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen, Tallinn University of Technology Pre-Examiners Professor Simo Knuuttila, University of Helsinki Professor Sami Pihlström, University of Helsinki Custos Professor Gabriel Sandu, University of Helsinki Opponent Professor Sami Pihlström, University of Helsinki ISBN 978-951-51-2696-2 (paperback) ISBN 978-951-51-2697-9 (PDF) Unigrafia Helsinki 2016 ii 1 Introduction The method of economical unification resembles a production line with three inseparable elements that are interconnected in two stages: Economy → Economically unified ontology → Applications In the first stage an economically unified ontology is explicated by applying the principle of economy. In the second stage concepts are defined and disambiguated and problems are resolved in terms of the ontology. The central argument that is defended in this doctoral dissertation is that the method is more progressive than plain conceptual analysis that proceeds in the absence of an economically unified ontology and in the absence of the principle of economy as an evaluation criterion of alternative ontologies. Its progressiveness results from having a stable economically unified ontology that is the same for all derivative topics, and which enables defining and disambiguating meanings of concepts, thereby facilitating their gen- uine understanding and resolving problems around them, more efficiently than in plain conceptual analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Empiricism
    Logical Empiricism HISTORICAL CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES Edited by Paolo Parrini, University ofFlorence Wesley C. Salmon, University ofPittsburgh Merrilee H. Salmon, University of Pittsburgh UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH PRESS This book is dedicated to the memory of Wesley C . Salmon 1925-2001 Published by the University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, P&, 15260 Copyright ® 2003, University of Pittsburgh Press All rights reserved Manufactured in the United States of America Printed on add-free paper 10987654321 ISBN 0 - 8n9- 4194-5 Contents Preface Introduction r Paolo Parrini and Wesley Salmon I. Turning Points and Fundamental Controversies rt A Turning Point in Philosophy : Carnap-Cassirer-Heidegger 13 Michael Friedman Carnap's "Elimination of Metaphysics through Logical Analysis of Language" : A Retrospective Consideration of the Relationship between Continental and Analytic Philosophy 30 Gottfried Gabriel Schlick and Husserl on the Essence of Knowledge 43 Roberta Lanfredini Carnap versus Gbdel on Syntax and Tolerance 57 S. Awodey and A. W Carus II. On the Origins and Development of the Vienna Circle 65 On the Austrian Roots of Logical Empiricism: The Case of the First Vienna Circle 67 Thomas Uebel On the International Encyclopedia, the Neurath-Carnap Disputes, and the Second World War 94 George Reisch Carl Gustav Hempel : Pragmatic Empiricist log Gereon Wolters III. The Riddle of Wittgenstein 123 The Methods of the Tractatus: Beyond Positivism and Metaphysics? 125 David G. Stern IV Philosophy of Physics 157 Two Roads from Kant : Cassirer, Reichenbach, and General Relativity ' 159 T A. Ryckman Vienna Indeterminism II : From Exner to Frank and von Mises 194 'Michael Stoltzner V. The Mind-Body Problem 231 The Mind-Body Problem in the Origin of Logical Empiricism : Herbert Feigl and Psychophysical Parallelism 233 Michael Heidelberger Logical Positivism and the Mind-Body Problem 263 Jaegwon Kim VI.
    [Show full text]