Economical Unification As a Method of Philosophical Analysis

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Economical Unification As a Method of Philosophical Analysis The Department of Philosophy, History, Culture and Art Studies University of Helsinki Finland Economical Unification as a Method of Philosophical Analysis Avril Styrman ACADEMIC DISSERTATION To be presented, with the permission of the Faculty of Arts of the University of Helsinki, for public examination in lecture room 13, University main building, on 17 December 2016, at 10 noon. Helsinki 2016 i Thesis Supervisor Professor Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen, Tallinn University of Technology Pre-Examiners Professor Simo Knuuttila, University of Helsinki Professor Sami Pihlström, University of Helsinki Custos Professor Gabriel Sandu, University of Helsinki Opponent Professor Sami Pihlström, University of Helsinki ISBN 978-951-51-2696-2 (paperback) ISBN 978-951-51-2697-9 (PDF) Unigrafia Helsinki 2016 ii 1 Introduction The method of economical unification resembles a production line with three inseparable elements that are interconnected in two stages: Economy → Economically unified ontology → Applications In the first stage an economically unified ontology is explicated by applying the principle of economy. In the second stage concepts are defined and disambiguated and problems are resolved in terms of the ontology. The central argument that is defended in this doctoral dissertation is that the method is more progressive than plain conceptual analysis that proceeds in the absence of an economically unified ontology and in the absence of the principle of economy as an evaluation criterion of alternative ontologies. Its progressiveness results from having a stable economically unified ontology that is the same for all derivative topics, and which enables defining and disambiguating meanings of concepts, thereby facilitating their gen- uine understanding and resolving problems around them, more efficiently than in plain conceptual analysis. This argument is substantiated by applying the method in defining and disambiguating some of the central concepts that are dealt with in contemporary philosophy and in resolving problems around them. The scope of this thesis is on con- cepts which are directly relevant and applicable in the domains of empirical science and human social behaviour, i.e., the scope is not on language or linguistic philosophy, and not on logic as such, as characterized in §3.5. The key concepts around the method, the central topics that will be handled in terms of it and some important sources are introduced in the following. The sources behind the method are all authors who have formulated versions of the principle of economy or expressed the preference for unified science, including Aristotle, Isaac Newton, Ernst Mach and many more, as cited in §3. theory as fusion of ontology and concepts defined in terms of it. An ontology is a system of interrelated ontological commitments or a world-view of a human being.1 An ontological commitment is a commitment to the existence of something, i.e., an ontology can be seen as a system of interrelated beliefs of a person about what exists. According to Quine [323, p. 11], ontological commitments of a theory are those entities 1The term ‘ontology’ denotes sometimes also a branch of philosophy. Ontology derives from the Greek logos peri ta onta. Logos stands for word, speech, reason; peri for around, about; ta onta for the beings. Ontology can thus be translated as the study of being and as the study of the things that exist. Aristotle used the term first philosophy in the book Metaphysics 1004a4. Metaphysics derives from the Greek ta meta ta fysika, which means what comes after physics/nature, which in turn derives from the cataloguing order of Aristotle’s works: “When Aristotle’s works were collected and catalogued by Andronicus of Rhodes in the first century BC, the collection of writings dealing with substance, causation, and other topics was placed after the book now known as the Physics” (Crane and Farkas [95, p. vii]). I used originally the Finnish translations of Aristotle’s Metaphysics [11], Physics [12], and Of The Heavens [13]. The English citations are from Ross [10], from Perseus Digital Library http://www.perseus.tufts.edu, and from The Internet Classics Archive http://classics.mit.edu. ‘Ontology’ and ‘metaphysics’ are used in this thesis with exactly the same meaning when these denote a branch of philosophy. ‘Ontology’ and ‘metaphysics’ have also been used with slightly different meanings when these denote a branch of philosophy. In Wolff’s [415] distinction of general metaphysics and special metaphysics, ontology denotes general metaphysics. According to Juti [192, p. 15], ontology as general metaphysics is the heart of metaphysics that precedes the questions of special metaphysics. However, as it is in many senses difficult to cleanly separate general and special metaphysics, this dichotomy is not used. 1 that the theory requires to exist in order for the theory to be true.2 As even a single ontological commitment can be called a theory, it is often indifferent whether ‘ontology’ or ‘theory’ is used.3 However, theory as a fusion of ontology and concepts defined in terms of it, is not exactly the same as ontology only. To illustrate, consider a theory of the Solar System. Its ontology covers all that exists according to the theory, including stellar objects such as the Sun and the planets, their orbits and the supposed interactions between the objects which are characterized by mathematical formulas. One may define e.g. the concept of one year in terms of the ontology of the theory of Solar System, as the period in which the Earth orbits once around the Sun. The ontology of a theory is thus not exactly the same as the theory, i.e., the ontology with the defined concepts. Figure 1: Theory as fusion of ontology and concepts defined in terms of it. Perceptions yield verified commitments. Metaphysics explains the verified commitments. Ontology consists of verified and metaphysical (unverified and unfalsified) commitments, which are classified in two on the right. As depicted on the bottom left of figure 1, perceptions yield verified commitments, i.e., verified beliefs in the existence of something. For instance, direct perception (§8.1) has yielded the commitments in the existence of trees, houses, people, the Moon, the Sun and the Earth. Beliefs yielded by direct perception are understood as not involved with interpretation in any significant sense, i.e., they are understood as not theory-laden. When you perceive a tree in front of you and thereby believe in its existence, this is not theory-laden, or it is theory-laden only on a very insignificant level. Likewise, perceiving the outside temperature indirectly by perceiving a thermometer reading of 5 Celsius and thereby believing that the temperature outside near the thermometer is about 5 Celsius is not theory-laden, or only on an insignificant level. In the end, not much can be said to hold with absolute certainty, but direct and indirect perceptions are accepted as certain- enough points of departure, for otherwise it would be practically impossible to proceed.4 As perceptions yield verified commitments, ‘verified commitment’ and ‘perception’ do 2According to Bricker [58]: “The ontological commitments of a theory are, roughly, what the theory says exists; a theory is ontologically committed to electrons, for example, if the truth of the theory requires that there be electrons.” According to Cameron [72, p. 250] “the ontological commitments of a theory are what must exist if it is true; the ontological commitments of a theory are what counts against it when judging it for ontological parsimony; the ontological commitments of a theory are those things whose existence its truth entails that have real being.” Cameron refers to parsimony which is central to the principle of economy, and which is applied in evaluating metaphysical complexities of theories. 3The theory-ontology dichotomy vanishes e.g. in the cases of the axioms of EUO, which are unfal- sifiable and unverifiable ontological commitments: presentism is a theory of temporal existence and a metaphysical commitment; ontological realism is a theory of mind-independence and a metaphysical commitment; finite divisibility is a theory of divisibility and a metaphysical commitment; causality is as a theory of interactions and a metaphysical commitment. 4What has been taken as certain-enough can always be scrutinised in the search for a higher degree of certainty. For instance, if a physicist says that dark energy is an ‘empirical fact,’ we are dealing with a fully theory-laden metaphysical commitment, not with a direct or indirect observation. See §§3.3,5.4. 2 not have the same meaning. However, for the sake of convenience ‘verified commitment’ is often replaced by ‘perception.’ This convention is analogous to the notion that seeing is believing and allows saying that metaphysics explains perceptions. While the verified commitments are not involved with interpretations, metaphysical com- mitments especially are interpretations of the verified commitments. The function of theories or the function of metaphysical commitments of a theory is to explain the veri- fied commitments, i.e., to explain perceptions, to save phenomena, to answer questions that result from perceptions, and to function as generalisations which are induced from perceptions. The structure of the ontology of a theory thus appears as a fusion of veri- fied commitments and metaphysical commitments, where the verified commitments are explained by metaphysical commitments which are themselves unfalsified and unveri- fied by perception. Metaphysical commitments have been called by many names such as unobservables, brute facts, primitives, axioms, first principles, premisses, postulates, hypothetical entities and unexplained explainers. Although metaphysical commitments have especially been deduced by reasoning from perceptions and in this sense could be seen as verified, they are best seen as unverified and unfalsified interpretations of per- ceptions. For, different people interpret the existence of different metaphysical entities from the same perceptions: the very same perceptions have been interpreted to indicate mutually incompatible answers e.g.
Recommended publications
  • Comments on “Facts About the Slingshot” by Gregory Landini Valia Allori
    Comments on “Facts about the Slingshot” by Gregory Landini Valia Allori This paper is very technical, so I will start my comments with a reconstruction of the arguments presented. Only at the end of this I will say what I think. I apologize in advance for any misinterpretation that I might have done. If I did, it was, of course, entirely unintentional. There is an argument against the correspondence theory of truth that, because of its combined simplicity and devastation, has been named the slingshot argument. According to the correspondence theory of truth a sentence is true iff there is a fact corresponding to it. In order to make sense, it seems that this theory must be able to differentiate between facts. The slingshot arguments, if sound, establish that every true sentence corresponds to the same fact, and therefore the corresponding theory of truth is doomed to failure. In his paper, Gregory argues that the slingshot argument is unsound. Let me just recapitulate what the argument says and my understanding of Gregory's argument against it. I will talk only about Davidson’s first version, for simplicity. The comments I will make will nonetheless apply to both versions. Let [p] be a shortcut for the locution “the fact that p”. Then it seems reasonable to assume that: 1) if to sentences p and q are identical, then [p]=[q] 2) if p and q describe the same thing (are co-denoting), then [p]=[q] for example: given S= “Cicero wrote Philippicae Oratione” and R=“Tully wrote Philippicae Oratione”, then [Cicero wrote Philippicae Oratione]=[Tully wrote Philippicae Oratione] 3) if p ad q are logically equivalent sentences, then [p]=[q] for example: S'= “ Plato=x: (x=Plato & S)” is logically equivalent to S, so [S]=[S'] Assumption number 2) is what Gregory calls the assumption of “constitution”: it amounts to say that the facts containing an object do not depend on the description provided.
    [Show full text]
  • SYSTEMATIC METAPHYSICS, OXFORD 2010 (1ª Ed.), 138 Páginas: OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS
    Aporía • Revista Internacional ISSN 0718-9788 de Investigaciones Filosóficas Diego Morales Pérez Artículos /Articles Nº 5 (2013), pp. 86-89 Santiago de Chile DAVID MALET ARMSTRONG, SKETCH FOR A SYSTEMATIC METAPHYSICS, OXFORD 2010 (1ª Ed.), 138 páginas: OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Diego Morales Pérez1 Pontificia Universidad Católica de Chile Sketch for a Systematic Metaphysics, publicado por Oxford University Press en el año 2010, es una de las obras más recientes que nos ofrece el célebre profesor australiano D.M. Armstrong. En este breve libro, el lector puede encontrar un conciso resumen de las ideas y opiniones más recientes del autor sobre los temas que deben conformar, a su juicio, un programa de investigación serio en metafísica. Es así como el texto trata los siguientes temas: 1. Propiedades; 2. Relaciones; 3. Estados de Cosas; 4. Leyes de la Naturaleza; 5. Reacción contra el Disposicionalismo; 6. Particulares; 7. Truthmakers; 8. Posibilidad, Actualidad y Necesidad; 9. Límites; 10. Ausencias; 11. Las Disciplinas Racionales: Lógica y Matemática; 12. Números; 13. Clases; 14. Tiempo; 15. Mente. El sello distintivo que presenta esta obra, en comparación a otras que entregan panoramas generales sobre temas recurrentes en metafísica, es la intención del autor de articular los contenidos de manera “sistemática”. En el prefacio Armstrong nos dice que la metafísica, disciplina que se ha vuelto respetable una vez más, está siendo trabajada por pensadores muy talentosos, pero de manera inconexa y a pedazos (p. X). Sería provechoso, entonces, presentar una propuesta que articule los contenidos, aprovechando de dar su opinión en cada uno de ellos. Ahora bien, el autor no se pronuncia explícitamente sobre lo que entiende por “metafísica sistemática”.
    [Show full text]
  • The ('('Orthodox" View of Theories: Remarks in Defense As Well As Critique
    -----HERBERT FEIGL----- The ('('Orthodox" View of Theories: Remarks in Defense as well as Critique The purpose of the following remarks is to present in outline some of the more important features of scientific theories. I shall discuss the "standard" or "orthodox" view, mainly in order to set up a target for criticisms, some of which I shall briefly sketch by way of anticipation. The standard account of the structure of scientific theories was given quite explicitly by Norman R. Campbell [7], as well as independently in a little-known article by R. Carnap [12]. A large part of the voluminous literature in the philosophy of science of the logical empiricists and re­ lated thinkers contains, though with a great many variations, develop­ ments, modifications, and terminological diversities, essentially similar analyses of the logical structure and the empirical foundations of the theories of physics, biology, psychology, and some of the social sciences. Anticipating to some extent Campbell and Carnap, Moritz Schlick, in his epoch-making AIIgemeine Erkenntnisiehre [38], championed the doc­ trine of "implicit definition." In this he was influenced by David Hil­ bert's axiomatization of geometry, as well as by Henri Poincare's and Albert Einstein's conceptions of theoretical physics and the role of ge­ ometry in physics. These matters were then developed more fully and precisely in the work of H. Reichenbach, R. Carnap, C. G. Hempel, R. B. Braithwaite, E. Nagel, and many other logicians and methodolo­ gists of science. In order to understand the aim of this important approach in the philosophy of science it is essential to distinguish it from historical, so­ ciological, or psychological studies of scientific theories.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Major Issues and Developments in the Philosophy Ofscience Oflogical Empiricism
    -----HERBERT FEIGL----- Some Major Issues and Developments in the Philosophy ofScience ofLogical Empiricism AsouT twenty-five years ago a small group of philosophically minded scientists and scientifically trained philosophers in Vienna formulated their declaration of independence from traditional philosophy. The pamphlet Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der Wiener Kreis (1929) contained the first succinct statement of the outlook which soon after became known as "logical positivism." In the first flush of enthusiasm we Viennese felt we had attained a philosophy to end all philosophies. Schlick spoke of a "Wende der Philosophie" (a decisive turning point of philosophy). Neurath and Frank declared "school philosophy" as obsolete and even suggested that our outlook drop the word "philoso­ phy" altogether, and replace it by "Einheitswissenschaft" or by "scien· tific empiricism." The notable impact of Alfred Ayer's first book in England, and my own efforts ~oward a propagation of Logical Positiv­ ism in the United States during the early thirties, and then the immi· gration of Carnap, Frank, von Mises, Reichenbach, Hempel and Berg­ mann created a powerful movement, but it elicited also sharp opposition nncl criticism. Through the discussions within the movement and its own production and progressive work, as well as in response to the NO'l'F.: This essay is a revised and considerably expanded .version of a lecture given in plenary session at the International Congress for Philosophy of Science, Zurich, /\ngust 25, 1954. It was first- published in Proceedi11gs of the Secono International Congress of the International Union for tl1e Philosophy ot Science (Neuchatel, Switzerland, 19 55). In the cordial letter of invitation I received from Professor Ferdinand Gonseth, president of the Congress, he asked me to discuss "I'empirisme logi<\ue,-ce qu'il fut, et ce qu'il est clevenu." Much as I appreciated the honor of t 1is ambitious assignment, I realized of course that the limitations of time would permit me to deal onJy with some selected topics within this larger frame.
    [Show full text]
  • UC San Diego Electronic Theses and Dissertations
    UC San Diego UC San Diego Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Pluralism and Realism Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/2n611357 Author Evpak, Matthew Publication Date 2018 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SAN DIEGO Pluralism and Realism A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Matthew Evpak Committee in charge: Professor Gila Sher, Chair Professor Samuel Buss Professor Andrew Kehler Professor Donald Rutherford Professor Clinton Tolley 2018 The Dissertation of Matthew Evpak is approved, and it is acceptable in quality and form for publication on microfilm and electronically: _____________________________________________________________________________ _____________________________________________________________________________ _____________________________________________________________________________ _____________________________________________________________________________ _____________________________________________________________________________ Chair University of California San Diego 2018 iii TABLE OF CONTENTS Signature Page ............................................................................................................................................................................................................ iii Table of Contents ....................................................................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Armstrong.Pdf
    EIDE Ê Foundations of Ontology Series Editors Otávio Bueno, Javier Cumpa, John Heil, Peter Simons, Erwin Tegtmeier, Amie L. Thomasson Volume 9 Francesco F. Calemi (Ed.) Metaphysics and Scientic Realism Ê Essays in Honour of David Malet Armstrong Edited by Francesco F. Calemi Copyright-Text ISBN 978-3-11-045461-1 e-ISBN (PDF) 978-3-11-045591-5 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A CIP catalog record for this book has been applied for at the Library of Congress. Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliograe; detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de. © 2015 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Munich/Boston Cover image: Cover-Firma Typesetting: le-tex publishing services GmbH, Leipzig Printing and binding: Druckerei XYZ ♾ Printed on acid-free paper Printed in Germany www.degruyter.com Tuomas E. Tahko Armstrong on Truthmaking and Realism 1 Introduction The title of this paper reects the fact truthmaking is quite frequently considered to be expressive of realism. What this means, exactly, will become clearer in the course of our discussion, but since we are interested in Armstrong’s work on truth- making in particular, it is natural to start from a brief discussion of how truth- making and realism appear to be associated in his work. Armstrong’s interest in truthmaking and the integration of the truthmaker principle to his overall system happened only later in his career, especially in his 1997 book A World of States of Aairs and of course the 2004 Truth and Truthmakers.
    [Show full text]
  • The Slingshot Argument, Godel's Hesitation and Tarskian Semantics
    Arhat Virdi The slingshot argument, Godel’s hesitation and Tarskian semantics Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Virdi, Arhat (2009) The slingshot argument, Godel's hesitation and Tarskian semantics. Prolegomena, 8 (2). pp. 233-241. ISSN 1333-4395 © 2009 © 2009 Society for the Advancement of Philosophy, Zagreb This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/27063/ Available in LSE Research Online: Feb 2010 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s final manuscript accepted version of the journal article, incorporating any revisions agreed during the peer review process. Some differences between this version and the published version may remain. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. The slingshot argument, Gödel’s hesitation and Tarskian semantics ARHAT VIRDI The slingshot argument is a reductio purporting to show that if there are facts at all there is only one to which all true statements correspond. If facts are not non-trivially individuable then this presumably must render the notion of fact and, by implication, theories such as the correspondence theory of truth incoherent.
    [Show full text]
  • God and Evil: the Case for God in a World Filled with Pain
    460 PHILOSOPHIA CHRISTI relevant materials in the Christian tradition that stress the importance of con- version and transformation for the pursuit of knowledge of God. In addition, I would like to see a fuller account of the relationship be- tween Christian philosophy and spirituality, especially since Moser thinks that “a Christ-shaped philosophy should be joined with Christ-formed phi- losophers” (169ff.). Undergirding a connection of this sort is a deeper im- mersion in (perhaps dependence on) a set of spiritual practices. This kind of emphasis resembles the early Christian integration of formation and the pursuit of the relevant epistemic goods (for example, knowledge of God, discernment of divine truths, wisdom). Given the current expansion of topics in epistemology, I wonder whether Moser could relocate this project under the category of spiritual formation. The focus here would be on the practices, materials, and processes that are fundamental to the kind of Christian phi- losophy Moser has in mind. Notwithstanding these suggestions, Moser’s proposal rightly takes its place in the intersection of theology and philosophy. It creates space for at- tending more fully to epistemological issues that crop up within theology. REVIEWED BY FREDERICK D. AQUINO ABILENE CHRISTIAN UNIVERSITY God and Evil: The Case for God in a World Filled with Pain. Edited by Chad Meister and James K. Dew, Jr. Downers Grove, Illinois: InterVarsity, 2013. 360 pages. $20.00. God and Evil serves as an excellent introduction to the problem of evil. Further, it goes beyond most works on the topic by addressing related issues including divine hiddenness, original sin, evolution, and hell.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae Michael Tooley
    CURRICULUM VITAE MICHAEL TOOLEY Education University of Toronto, 1959-64. B.A., 1964. Princeton University, 1964-67. Ph.D., 1968. Personal Date of birth: 17 March 1941 Place of birth: Toronto, Canada Married to Sylvia Tooley, with daughters Sandra and Suzanne, and grandchildren Anthony, Joshua, Donald, Joseph, and Sofia. Citizenship: American and Canadian. Academic Honors and Awards President, American Philosophical Association, Pacific Division, 2010-2011. Vice President, American Philosophical Association, Pacific Division, 2009-2010. The Cecil H. and Ida Green Honors Chair Professor, Texas Christian University, Spring, 2010 The John Dewey Lecture, "A Philosophical Journey," American Philosophical Association, Central Division, Chicago, February, 2009. College Professor of Distinction, Arts and Sciences, University of Colorado at Boulder, 2006- Faculty Fellowship. University of Colorado at Boulder, 2006-2007. Boulder Faculty Assembly Excellence in Research Award, 1998-1999. JSPS Invitation Fellowship for Research in Japan. Awarded by the Japan Society for the Promotion of Science, 1999. Fellow of the Australian Academy of the Humanities. President, Australasian Association of Philosophy, 1983-1984. Woodrow Wilson Dissertation Fellow, 1966-1967. Woodrow Wilson Fellow, 1964-1965. Most Recent Position Distinguished College Professor, Arts and Sciences, University of Colorado. 2006- University of Colorado, Philosophy Department: Professor, 1992–present, now retired. Previous Positions Bowling Green State University, Adjunct Professor, 2004-09. The Australian National University, Philosophy Program, Research School of Social Sciences: Senior Research Fellow, 1988-92; Senior Fellow, 1992. University of Western Australia, Philosophy Department: Professor, 1983-88; Head of Department, 1985-88. University of Miami, Philosophy Department: Associate Professor, 1981-82; Professor, 1982-83. 2 Wichita State University, Philosophy Department: Visiting Associate Professor, 1980-81.
    [Show full text]
  • Leading Ontologists of 19Th and 20Th Centuries
    Leading Ontologists of 19th and 20th centuries https://www.ontology.co/idx05.htm Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] INDEX OF THE SECTION: ONTOLOGISTS OF THE 19TH AND 20TH CENTURIES ONTOLOGISTS IN CHRONOLOGICAL ORDER Bernard Bolzano (1781-1848) Contributions to Logic and Ontology Critical judgments, excerpts from his works, bibliography of critical studies English Translations and Selected Bibliography on the Philosophical Work of Bernard Bolzano: Studies in English (First Part: A - C) Studies in English (Second Part: D - L) Studies in English (Third Part: M - Z) Selected Texts Ausgewählte Werke und Studien in Deutsch Traductions et Essais en Français Traduzioni e Studi in Italiano Franz Brentano (1838-1917) Ontology and His Immanent Realism Excerpts and bibliography of his works, of the English translations and of the most relevant critical studies Franz Brentano: Editions, Translations, Bibliographical Resources and Selected Texts Selected Bibliography on the Philosophical Work of Franz Brentano: Brentano: A - K Brentano: L - Z 1 di 5 09/02/2019, 13:04 Leading Ontologists of 19th and 20th centuries https://www.ontology.co/idx05.htm Charles S. Peirce (1839-1914) Ontology and Semiotics. The Theory of Categories Bibliography of his writings and about his conception of semiotics and the theory of categories Gottlob Frege (1848-1925) Ontology: Being, Existence, and Truth Excerpts from texts, studies and bibliography on his conceptions of being, existence and truth Selected Bibliography on Frege's Ontology
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics and Natural Kinds: Slingshots, Fundamentality, and Causal Structure
    METAPHYSICS AND NATURAL KINDS: SLINGSHOTS, FUNDAMENTALITY, AND CAUSAL STRUCTURE By ANDREW LEE MCFARLAND Submitted to the graduate degree program in the Department of Philosophy and the Graduate Faculty of the University of Kansas in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. ________________________________ Chair: John Symons ________________________________ John Bricke ________________________________ Armin Schulz ________________________________ Clif Pye ________________________________ Philippe Huneman Date Defended: May 16, 2014 The Dissertation Committee for Andrew Lee McFarland certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: METAPHYSICS AND NATURAL KINDS: SLINGSHOTS, FUNDAMENTALITY, AND CAUSAL STRUCTURE ________________________________ JOHN SYMONS Date approved: May 16, 2014 ii DISSERTATION ABSTRACT Metaphysics and Natural Kinds: Slingshots, Fundamentality, and Causal Structure Andrew Lee McFarland My dissertation addresses a question relevant to metaphysics, philosophy of language, and philosophy of science: What are natural kinds? I explore a view that holds that natural kinds are complex, structural properties that involve causal structure. Causal structure describes the idea that for the many properties associated with natural kinds, these properties are nomically linked – that is causally connected – in such a way that the properties of non-natural kinds are not. After criticizing arguments in favor of a nominalist theory of kinds – one that holds that a natural kind just is to be identified with its class of instances – and after defending the notion of a complex structural property from several prominent objections posed by David Lewis, I apply a causal account of natural kinds to a set of problematic cases, paying special attention to isomeric kinds from chemistry. iii Dedication I dedicate this doctoral thesis to my family and to the tireless support they have given me over the years.
    [Show full text]
  • DAVID MALET ARMSTRONG Ao 1926–2014
    26 THE AUSTRALIAN ACADEMY OF THE HUMANITIES ANNUAL REPORT 2013–14 OBITUARIES DAVID MALET ARMSTRONG ao 1926–2014 After a school career that included periods at the Dragon School in Oxford, and at Geelong Grammar, and after a short stint in the navy in the post-war occupation of Japan, he distinguished himself as a student of philosophy in John Anderson’s Department at the University of Sydney. In 1950 he married Madeleine Annette Haydon, a fellow student who was to become a librarian and theatrical critic. Soon after the marriage David was diagnosed with tuberculosis picked up in Japan, so he spent most of that year recuperating in the Concord Repatriation Hospital Having recovered, David went with Madeleine to Oxford, where he undertook the newly established and prestigious BPhil postgraduate degree. On account of his Exeter connection, that became his College, a matter perhaps a little tardily acknowledged by an Honorary Fellowship in 2006. On graduating, David held a temporary post at Birkbeck College in the University of London, and then in 1956 settled in Melbourne, where with great photo: jens maus (damato) [cc by-sa 3.0] via wikimedia commons energy he set about building a reputation and a career at the University of Melbourne, in what was at that avid Armstrong, the doyen of Australian time the premier philosophy department in Australia. Dphilosophers, and the most influential to date His first book,Berkeley’s Theory of Vision, appeared in on the international stage, has died in Sydney at the 1960. The following year he picked up a PhD, almost age of 87.
    [Show full text]