<<

EIDE

Ê Foundations of

Series Editors Otávio Bueno, Javier Cumpa, John Heil, Peter Simons, Erwin Tegtmeier, Amie L. Thomasson Volume 9 Francesco F. Calemi (Ed.) and Scientic Realism

Ê Essays in Honour of

Edited by Francesco F. Calemi Copyright-Text

ISBN 978-3-11-045461-1 e-ISBN (PDF) 978-3-11-045591-5

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A CIP catalog record for this book has been applied for at the Library of Congress.

Bibliographic published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliograe; detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de.

© 2015 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Munich/Boston Cover image: Cover-Firma Typesetting: le-tex publishing services GmbH, Leipzig Printing and binding: Druckerei XYZ ♾ Printed on acid-free paper Printed in Germany www.degruyter.com Tuomas E. Tahko Armstrong on Truthmaking and Realism

1 Introduction

The title of this paper reects the fact truthmaking is quite frequently considered to be expressive of realism. What this means, exactly, will become clearer in the course of our discussion, but since we are interested in Armstrong’s work on - making in particular, it is natural to start from a brief discussion of how truth- making and realism appear to be associated in his work. Armstrong’s interest in truthmaking and the integration of the truthmaker to his overall system happened only later in his career, especially in his 1997 book A World of States of Aairs and of course the 2004 Truth and Truthmakers. Since the 2004 book is the most complete account of Armstrong’s thinking with regard to truthmak- ing, that book will be our primary source (especially given that he changed his about a few issues between the 1997 and the 2004 books). The theme is cer- tainly present in his earlier work as well, but the of truthmaking, which Armstrong got from C. B. Martin, was not as well formulated in the literature. The seminal paper by Mulligan, Simons and Smith (1984) had not yet popularised the notion. In the introduction to his Truth and Truthmakers, Armstrong outlines the origins of the notion in : Martin used the of truthmaking in his work against counterfactual accounts of material objects due to the phenomenalists. Armstrong himself rst took advantage of the truthmaker principle in his attempt to resist dispositional/subjunctive accounts of mental states due to behaviourists such as (Armstrong 1973, 11.). The now famous slogan, according to which the truthmaker ‘prevents the metaphysician from letting disposi- tions “hang on air”’ originates in Armstrong’s criticism of Ryle (Armstrong 2004, 3). It is thus partly because of this historical usage of the ‘truthmaker insight’ that truthmaking is often associated with realism. But the situation is certainly more complicated than that when we look into the details. One reason for the complica- tions regarding truthmaking and its potential ability to capture realist intuitions is that many of the best known theories of truthmaking are very closely tied to certain ontological views that already make realist commitments. Among these is Armstrong’s own version of truthmaking, which is integrated with his ontology of states of aairs. Naturally, the states of aairs ontology has some important impli- cations for his conception of truthmaking. The most obvious of these implications

Tuomas E. Tahko: University of Helsinki, email: tuomas.tahko@helsinki. 208 Ë Tuomas E. Tahko is that, according to Armstrong, truthmakers are facts – albeit he prefers to call them states of aairs: ‘entities having such forms as a’s F and a’s having R to b’ (Armstrong 2004, 18). Of course, as Armstrong (2004, 4) readily admits, the idea of truthmaking can be separated from the question of what truthmakers in fact are. In any case, for Armstrong the truthbearers are true propositions – although there are some caveats, e.g., he considers propositions to be ‘possible intentional objects’ and takes it that a ‘naturalist’ cannot accept a realm of propositions (ibid., 16; 1997, 131). Moving on to the truthmaking relation, there are a couple of things that, I believe, can be said without much controversy. One of these is that whatever we take the actual truthmakers to be, and, I suppose, even regardless of the of the supposed truthmaking relation between propositions and , we can in any case say that the (possible) correspondence between a proposition and the reality, i.e., between the proposition and the truthmaker, is not, in general, a one-one correspondence.¹ This is the view that Armstrong (2004, 16) takes and, in , seems to be what many other proponents of truthmaking would go for as well (see for example Lowe 2006, 182). The reason for opting for a many-many relation is simple enough: a single truthmaker can quite clearly be a truthmaker for several truthbearers and correspondingly there might be several truthmakers which serve as a sucient truthmaker for a given proposition. Perhaps it could be argued that there is always some minimal truthmaker for each truth, but as Arm- strong points out, many do also have several minimal truthmakers, such as the proposition (Armstrong 2004, 21).² Another aspect that appears to be fairly uncontroversial is that truthmaking is some kind of an asymmetrical relation between propositions and something in the world. This something in the world could be facts or states of aairs, as in Arm- strong’s case, or tropes, or something quite dierent, depending on your account of truthmakers. Another way to put this is to say that a truthmaker for a particular truth is some portion of reality in virtue of which the truth is true. This ‘in virtue of’ relation is generally to be cross-categorical, the portion of reality be- ing some entity or entities and the other being truth (which is not an entity!) (see Armstrong 2004, 5). The exact nature of the truthmaking relation is not uncontroversial though: one possibility is that it is an entailment relation between the truthmaker and the truth of the proposition, but it has also been argued that we are dealing with a

1 Note that ‘propositions’ could be considered merely as a placeholder here, depending on one’s take on what the truthbearers are. 2 Where the angled brackets describe a proposition, following Horwich 1998. For discussion on minimal truthmakers, see Tahko and O’Conaill forthcoming. Armstrong on Truthmaking and Realism Ë 209 grounding relation here, in which case truth would be grounded in entities (cf. Rodriguez-Pereyra 2005). There is also the question of whether truthmaking is an internal or an external relation (Armstrong 1997, 115-116). Armstrong favours the rst alternative, and it does perhaps seem initially more plausible that truthmak- ing is an internal relation, but there are various problems with this idea as well (cf. David 2005). Each of these issues would require a paper of its own, but we will mostly set them aside here, focusing instead on the more general question regarding truthmaking and realism. However, we will need at least an initial for- mulation of the truthmaking relation to get started. Take one formulated in terms of the ‘in virtue of’ locution, which produces a familiar truthmaker principle:

(TM) Necessarily, if a proposition

is true and has a truthmaker, then there is some entity in virtue of which it is true.

This formulation of (TM) entails (though is not the same as) Truthmaker Necessi- tarianism: the of a truthmaker is sucient for the truth of those proposi- tions it makes true. Armstrong (2004, 5–7) defends Truthmaker Necessitarianism, appealing to the slogan mentioned above, i.e., if a given truth (a true proposition) would lack a truthmaker, then its truth would ‘hang on air’ quite like Ryle’s dispo- sitional truths. Indeed Truthmaker Necessitarianism is a widely shared assump- tion amongst truthmaker theorists, even though it is dicult to come up with a conclusive argument in favour of it:

I do not have any direct argument [for Truthmaker Necessitarianism]. My hope is that of realist inclinations will be immediately attracted to the idea that a truth, any truth, should depend for its truth for something ‘outside’ it, in virtue of which it is true. (Armstrong 2004, 7.)

We will not discuss Truthmaker Necessitarianism in much more detail than this, nor the other one of Armstrong’s controversial theses, Truthmaker Maximalism, i.e., the thesis that every truth must have a truthmaker.³ (TM) does not, of course, entail Truthmaker Maximalism.

2 Truthmaking and realism

It is well-known that Armstrong postulates an intimate connection between truth- making and realism. The mediator here is correspondence, or more precisely, the

3 For a brief defence of Truthmaker Maximalism, see Rodriguez-Pereyra 2006. 210 Ë Tuomas E. Tahko correspondence theory of truth. It appears that, for Armstrong, truthmaker the- ory could be understood simply as a more sophisticated version of the correspon- dence theory. There are several passages in Armstrong’s work that explicitly sug- gest this:

[T]he Correspondence theory tells us that, since truths require a truthmaker, there is some- thing in the world that corresponds to a true proposition. The correspondent and the truthmaker are the same thing. (1997, 128)

Propositions correspond or fail to correspond to reality. [If Armstrong’s view of propositions is correct], then it becomes pretty clear that the correspondence theory of truth can and should be upheld. (2004, 16)

The terms of the correspondence relation are truthmakers and truths. Truthmakers entail truths. Our favoured truthmakers are states of aairs or their constituents. (1997, 131)

Note however that especially in A World of States of Aairs, Armstrong empha- sises that is not only compatible with (the idea of) the corre- spondence theory of truth, but also with the redundancy theory of truth (if it is to be called a theory of truth at all) (1997, 128).⁴ Be that as it may, in the secondary literature Armstrong’s appeal to the correspondence theory in his formulation of the truthmaker theory has been received with some hostility. Typically, this is be- cause the motivation seems to be exactly to argue in favour of realism. Consider how Helen Beebee and Julian Dodd put it in their inuential volume on truthmak- ing:

Suppose that some formulation of truthmaker theory does indeed succeed in capturing real- ist intuitions. The question arises, how can truthmaker theory now legitimately be put to use in an argument for realism (about a particular domain) and against anti-realism? If truth- maker theory itself enshrines a commitment to realism, then presumably the appropriate anti-realist reaction to such an argument is simply to deny whatever truthmaker principle is being used as a premise in that argument. If a given truthmaker principle is to pull its weight in arguments against anti-realism, then we had better have reasons, independently of our commitment to realism, for believing that the principle is true. We wonder whether such reasons are to be had. (Beebee and Dodd 2005, 16.)

4 Incidentally, one might also ask whether the truthmaker theory is a theory of truth. Certainly, if we have merely a stripped down truthmaker principle, then we are not dealing with a complete theory of truth. But once the truthmaker principle is combined with an appropriate ontology, then I would be inclined to say that we do indeed have a complete theory of truth, as we can give a full account of the truthbearers and the truthmakers. But the core of truthmaking is the truthmaker principle, and if it turns out to be compatible with dierent (as will be proposed below), then it is at least a promising starting point for a complete theory of truth. Armstrong on Truthmaking and Realism Ë 211

So if Armstrong’s postulated connection between truthmaker theory and realism truly holds, then Beebee and Dodd insist that we should be able to put forward a truthmaker principle that would be able to capture our realist intuitions while not being compatible with anti-realism. Even if we were to succeed, we would still have to show that there are reasons, independently of our realist intuitions, to believe that our truthmaker principle is the correct one, as otherwise the use of truthmaking in arguments against anti-realism will just be question-begging. Perhaps this can be done, but as we have seen, Armstrong’s own project seems to postulate a very intimate connection between truthmaking and realism. However, if we were to concede that truthmaker theory fails to cash out our re- alist intuitions, at least without leaving room for other interpretations, then what would the cost be, precisely? Well, provided that truthmaker theory is at least compatible with realism – which it surely is – then the possibility that it might be able to accommodate other than realist intuitions might not be so harmful. In other words, if truthmaking turned out to be an ontologically neutral way of talking about truth we could of course still combine it with a realist ontology. Now, this is of course not an answer to the challenge posed by Beebee and Dodd. Rather, the proposal is that the price that Armstrong might have to pay is not all that high. But this line of argument is only feasible once it is clear that truthmaker theory can be presented in an ontologically neutral way and if realism itself can stand on its own. So let us now move to a discussion of truthmaker theory combined with various alternatives to realism.

3 Truthmaking as ontologically neutral

If we wish to nd an ontologically neutral formulation of the truthmaker princi- ple, then this is likely to impose some constraints on the theory. For that reason, certain usual formulations are unlikely to work. Consider one typical formulation, as presented by Beebee and Dodd:

(TM-E) Necessarily, if

is true, then there exists at least one entity α such that <α exists> entails <

is true>. (Beebee and Dodd 2005, 2.)

The nature of the truthmaking relation, here suggested to be an entailment rela- tion, is perhaps the most controversial part of (TM-E). Of course, other problems may emerge when certain truths, such as necessary truths or negative truths are considered. There have been numerous attempts to deal with these problems, but the details of each solution depend, often heavily, on the details of the ontology that one wishes to combine with truthmaking, and accordingly these problems 212 Ë Tuomas E. Tahko are not something that we should focus on here. However, a somewhat neutral way to address the problems involved with entailment is to replace entailment with (metaphysical) necessitation: in every where a truthmaker for a certain proposition exists, that proposition is true. This is the line that was taken in the initial formulation given in this paper (TM) and it would seem to be preferable to Armstrong (1997, 115) as well (see also Lowe 2006, 185). Some key features of the truthmaker principle were listed earlier and at least some of them would also seem to hold in regard to the general principle that we are now looking for. So, we can for example without much risk of controversy say that truthmaking is an asymmetrical many-many relation. Also, as Rodriguez-Pereyra (2005, 20-1) suggests, we seem to have the intuition that truth is asymmetrical, and the truthmaker principle ts this intuition perfectly. The way that Rodriguez- Pereyra puts it is that truth is grounded: the truth of a proposition depends on what reality is like, and the relationship between truth and reality is of course asymmetrical, for reality does not depend on the truth of the proposition. As he points out, this by itself does not commit us to realism, for an idealist (for instance) could just add that reality or world and the entities in it are not mind-independent (ibid.). Moreover, Chris Daly (2005) has suggested that there is one issue that advo- cates of dierent truthmaker theories always agree upon: truthmaking does some explanatory work. This is of course a rather natural source for motivation to adopt truthmaker theory in the rst place. Ultimately, this motivation concerns the na- ture of the truthmaking relation, for whatever explanatory work the truthmaker principle might do, it must surely have something to do with the relationship be- tween propositions and truthmakers. So what are our options for motivating truth- making? According to Daly (2005, 102), there are three options. The rst one is what he calls the ‘Canadian mountie’ theory of truthmakers, the idea of which is to argue from examples and to show that we can, in fact, always nd a truthmaker for any given truth. Daly accuses this theory of being ad hoc, in that it assumes the truthmaker principle without giving any justication for it. Presumably the point is that we need more than a working theory of truthmaking to motivate the idea in the rst place. This would appear to be a valid request. The second strategy suggests that truthmaker theory could help in nding ex- planations to further ontological problems, such as the theory of universals. Daly (2005, 98-102) argues against Rodriguez-Pereyra’s suggestion, namely that truth- makers could explain universals by entailing that it is true that there are some properties which are shared by several distinct particulars. There are other alter- natives as well though, one of them being Josh Parsons’s (2005) rather plausible idea that truthmaking could be used to motivate arguments concerning propo- sitions about the past and the future and thus might provide some explanatory Armstrong on Truthmaking and Realism Ë 213 power when discussing theories of , such as presentism. However, while I am not against the idea of granting the possibility that truthmaking could help motivate arguments concerning other ontological problems, I do not believe that this by itself is a sucient condition for adopting the truthmaker principle; and neither, of course, does Daly. The third strategy that Daly (2005, 94–8) considers, namely inference to the best explanation, is perhaps the most common. According to this strategy, truth- making explains our pro-realism intuitions and grasps the core idea of the corre- spondence theory of truth. This is of course the core motivation that we are now interested in. Daly considers Armstrong’s and Bigelow’s theories in this connec- tion. Here we are faced with the central question: could truthmaking oer a way to characterise a theory of truth compatible with realism? But we have to be careful here, for even if truthmaking is compatible with realism, it does not mean that it would explain why realism is any better than other alternatives. Indeed, it seems that the truthmaker principle is in no way connected with any necessarily realist premises, especially if it is compatible with, say, pragmatism and as well (which is a suggestion we will consider briey below). There is one further complication. Recall that Armstrong seems to consider truthmaking to be eectively a more sophisticated version of the correspondence theory – and this is in fact a major reason for the claim that it captures realist intuitions. If this were indeed the case, then it would seem dicult to combine truthmaking with anything but realism. But this is where things get interesting, for Daly argues that the same ontological neutrality thesis applies to the Correspon- dence Intuition (CI) as well, formulated in the following way:

(CI)

is true if and only if things are as

says they are. (Daly 2005: 96.)

The apparent problem with (CI), however, is that it appears to be vacuous: (CI) is compatible with just about any theory of truth, and hence its explanatory cannot be particularly high. So, if truthmaker theory is supposed to be explana- tory, it better capture something more than just (CI). Armstrong himself (2004: Ch. 4) certainly claims that the truthmaker principle could say something more than (CI) does – this will be done by combining the correspondence relation with the truthmaker principle and his states of aairs ontology – but consider Daly’s analysis of (CI):

Consider the coherence theorist. He may consistently say ‘If

is true, it has a truthmaker.

corresponds to a state of aairs, namely the state of aairs which consists of a relation of coherence holding between

and the other members of a maximal set of propositions’. Consider the pragmatist. He may consistently say, ‘If

is true, it has a truthmaker.

corresponds to a state of aairs, namely the state of aairs of

’s having the of 214 Ë Tuomas E. Tahko

being useful to believe’. It is controversial whether there exist states of aairs. Let that pass. My point here is that the coherence theory and the pragmatic theory are each compatible with the admission of states of aairs. Furthermore, each of these theories is compatible with the admission of states of aairs standing in a correspondence relation to truths. (Daly 2005, 97)

So Daly’s case against the third strategy (to guarantee the explanatory value of truthmaker theory and hence motivate it) is based on the claim that the truth- maker principle does not restrict our in terms of ontology in any way and thus truthmaking understood in the lines of Armstrong and Bigelow is just as vac- uous as (CI). This is indeed a valid concern, for if truthmaking is understood as a special case of the correspondence theory, then it seems to inherit all of its original problems. However, it seems trivial that the truthmaker principle could be combined with dierent ontologies once we acknowledge the idea that truthmaking is quite separate from the varying answers concerning the actual truthmakers and truth- bearers. Furthermore, as already noted, Armstrong (2004: 4) seems to have no quarrel with the idea that truthmaking may be compatible with very dierent ac- counts of truthmakers and truthbearers. This is really the only thing that counts: it ought to be one’s account of truthmakers and truthbearers that introduces the (important) ontological commitments, not the truthmaker principle itself. Accord- ingly, I think that Armstrong and other advocates of realist truthmaker theories could very well be content with a somewhat weakened condition when it comes to the truthmaker principle, namely, that the truthmaker principle is the best way to characterise the correspondence relation understood in a realist sense. When put like this, the details of our ontology are still open, but the motivation for truth- making is still clear: it is the best way to formulate the realist understanding of the correspondence relation. This hints towards a fourth strategy for motivating truthmaking in addition to the three suggested by Daly, and in fact I think that the fourth strategy is closer to how most truthmaker theorists would like to motivate their theories.

4 Realism can stand on its own

The strategy for motivating truthmaking that is now emerging rests on this very simple point: realism can stand on its own. In other words, we do not need truth- making (or the correspondence theory, for that ) to motivate realism. This reects Michael Devitt’s (1997) classic work on the topic of realism and truth. Com- pared to Daly’s third strategy, this changes the direction of explanation. It could Armstrong on Truthmaking and Realism Ë 215 be said that the fourth strategy does not so much try to provide an explanation, but a justication, although in another sense it can be thought to provide an ex- planation as well, as we will shortly see. In any case, what is important is that because realism can stand on its own, those of us who are realists can motivate truthmaking with realism – not the other way around. While this type of strat- egy is not clearly present in Armstrong’s writings, I do believe that he might have welcomed it. If we start with a realist ontology and if truthmaking increases the plausibility of the overall theory, then it seems rather straightforward to choose the way to go: realism plus truthmaking is the best theory available. But in order for this strategy to be plausible, we ought to see some more evidence to the eect that, say, ideal- ists or pragmatists would also be happy with the proposed truthmaker principle. To this eect, the principle would have to be such that an idealist or pragmatist could insert their desired truthmakers and truthbearers into the principle. There may be some limitations here. For one thing, on all the usual formulations, the truthmakers are taken to be entities of some kind. It is certainly a matter of de- bate what kind of entities they are, but it might be objected that, say, a pragmatist would not be happy about the commitment to ‘entities’ in any form whatsoever. So how could pragmatism be compatible with truthmaking? Positive accounts ar- guing to this eect are scarce, but Sami Pihlström (2005) has outlined some op- tions. Pihlström suggests that pragmatists such as (at ) and could very well be considered as taking advantage of a version of truthmaking, whereby the truthbearers and the ‘world’ that makes them true (i.e., the truthmakers) are human constructions, ‘made’ by us in the process of representing and acting. Now, whether this constitutes a commitment to entities or not is perhaps debatable – maybe ‘human constructions’ are to be considered as entities. But there appears to be no reason why this type of picture couldn’t be represented with a truthmaker principle not unlike the ones we have been dis- cussing. A more general point to note is the following. If we take truthmakers to be en- tities, there are several alternatives available, such as Armstrong’s states of aairs or tropes, as suggested in Mulligan, Simons and Smith (1984). There is not much that can be said about the nature of the truthmakers without a commitment to a particular ontology. However, personally I would be inclined to part ways with Armstrong here, for it seems to me that the apparent complexity of truth suggests that truthmakers must be spread out in several dierent categories rather than just one. This complexity manifests itself in the variety of things we consider to be true: mathematical theorems, laws of physics, that Hesperus and Phosphorus are identical, and so on. Introducing a further category of facts or states of aairs to account for all truthmakers is not ontologically parsimonious; why not say that 216 Ë Tuomas E. Tahko the truthmakers are just the very entities that a given true proposition concerns? This line of thought has also been noted by Beebee and Dodd (2005, 9) and it is exactly what Lowe (2005, 182 .) argues for as well. Returning to the issue concerning a commitment to entities, we might note that one could attempt to formulate truthmaking in a manner that does not entail a commitment to entities at all, perhaps in the lines of McFetridge’s (1990) sug- gestion that every true sentence must have an explanation of why it is true. This would seem to release us from the commitment to entities, but it also distances us from the original idea of truthmaking. In fact, it appears that this would take us back towards a vacuous principle. McFetridge’s proposal is another attempt to combine truthmaking and our realist intuitions so that we would have an argu- ment against anti-realism (see Liggins 2005 for details of how this might be done). This is a line of thought that we have already distanced ourselves from. Of course, we can easily modify the truthmaker principle in such a way that an explicit com- mitment to entities is removed, but it is questionable whether this really does the trick. Consider (TM*):

(TM*) Necessarily, if a proposition

is true and has a truthmaker, then there is some α in virtue of which it is true.

Here the entailment relation has been replaced with metaphysical necessitation, as in the original (TM). In fact, you’ll notice that (TM*) diers from the original (TM) only in replacing the explicit reference to entities with a reference to the un- specied ‘α’. Have we been moving in circles? Not as such: what has changed is the order of explanation. Truthmaking is now understood as a tool to help char- acterise one’s ontology, not a way to motivate the ontology itself. To that eect, all we need is that the truthmaker principle is compatible across dierent ontologies. (TM*) is obviously compatible with realist ontologies, in which case it is likely that we would want to add that what makes

true is the existence of an en- tity of some kind. A pragmatist, on the other hand, could replace α with ‘human construction’, as suggested by Pihlström. Whether or not this avoids the commit- ment to entities is another question, but one that I consider an ancillary issue. As for idealists, they could presumably interpret existence so that it does not require material existence, although I am not aware of any idealist accounts which would employ truthmaking explicitly. Naturally, we need to add something to (TM*) to give it any explanatory power, as the nature of the truthmaking relation depends on what α is – and now also on how we interpret existence. Indeed, (TM*) is just the spine of truthmaking as we need to say something about α to determine how it makes

true. However, the relative weakness of (TM*) is exactly why the principle is plausible across ontolo- Armstrong on Truthmaking and Realism Ë 217 gies: it could perhaps be interpreted as a family of that covers all possi- ble kinds of truthmakers. Of course, in (TM*) the truthbearers are still taken to be propositions, which might not satisfy everyone (or every ontology). But I would not be too concerned about this, given that Armstrong himself wishes to avoid a commitment to propositions and reinterprets them as ‘possible intentional ob- jects’, in accordance with his naturalistic agenda. Accordingly, perhaps there is room to interpret propositions as well in accordance with various ontologies. The upshot is that truthmaking is not, or does not have to be, an explana- tion for, or a case in favour of our realist intuitions. Perhaps truthmaking does increase the appeal of realism, for the explanatory power of the complete the- ory (realism plus truthmaking) is certainly greater with truthmaking than without it. In this sense, truthmaking may still make a contribution towards explanatory power. But an idealist or a pragmatist could attempt to make the same claim. In any case, there are strong reasons to think that the question of realism is inde- pendent of the question of truth. Armstrong may have wanted something more than this out of truthmaker theory, nevertheless, truthmaker theory is a plausible way to account for truth within a realist ontology. A particularly forceful reason to think so is that, in the lines of ’s (e.g. 1991) inuential work, the anti-realist’s strongest case against realism may be exactly that realism is un- able to account for truth in a satisfactory manner, given the shortcomings of the correspondence theory. If truthmaker theory can now oer an ontologically neu- tral way to account for truth, then this argument dissipates. Realism can stand on its own, and truthmaking is a way to account for truth regardless of one’s ontol- ogy. This is really all that Armstrong or any realist proponent of truthmaker theory needs: a way to account for truth within a realist ontology.

Bibliography

Armstrong, D. M. 1973. , Truth and . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Armstrong, D. M. 1997. A World of States of Aairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Armstrong, D. M. 2004. Truth and Truthmaking. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Beebee, H. and Dodd, J. (eds.) 2005. Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate. Oxford: . Daly, C. 2005. “So Where’s the Explanation?” In Beebee, H. and Dodd, J. (eds.) 2005, 85–103. David, M. 2005. “Armstrong on Truthmaking”. In Beebee, H. and Dodd, J. (eds.) 2005, 141–59. Devitt, M. 1997. Realism and Truth, 2nd edn. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Dummett, M. 1991. The Logical Basis of Metaphysics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Horwich, P. 1998. Truth, 2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 218 Ë Tuomas E. Tahko

Liggins, D. 2005. “Truthmakers and Explanation”. In Beebee, H. and Dodd, J. (eds.) 2005, 105– 15. Lowe, E. J. 2006. The Four-Category Ontology: A Metaphysical Foundation for Natural Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press. McFetridge, I. 1990. “Truth, Correspondence, Explanation and Knowledge”. In his Logical Ne- cessity and Other Essays. London: . Mulligan, K., Simons, P. and Smith, B. 1984. “Truth-Makers”. Philosophy and Phenomenologi- cal Research 44: 287–321. Parsons, J. 2005. “Truthmakers, the Past, and Future.” In Beebee, H. and Dodd, J., 161–74. Pihlström, S. 2005. “Truthmaking and Pragmatist Conceptions of Truth and Reality”. Minerva – An Internet Journal of Philosophy 9. URL = . Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. 2005. “Why Truthmakers”. In Beebee, H. and Dodd, J. (eds.), 17–31. Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. 2006. “Truthmaker Maximalism Defended”. Analysis 66 (3): 260–64. Tahko, T. E. and O’Conaill, D. forthcoming. “Minimal Truthmakers”. Pacic Philosophical Quar- terly.