Voting Issues: a Brief History of Preference Aggregation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Voting Issues: a Brief History of Preference Aggregation NOVEMBER 26, 2019 Voting Issues: A Brief History of Preference Aggregation Given the surprising results of recent elections, voting methods have drawn lots of attention. Research in social choice theory reveals the underlying complexity — and flaws — of different methods of expressing preferences. By Marton Farkas and Dusan Timotity WorldQuant, LLC 1700 East Putnam Ave. Third Floor Old Greenwich, CT 06870 www.weareworldquant.com 11.26.19 VOTING ISSUES: A BRIEF HISTORY OF PREFERENCE AGGREGATION PERSPECTIVES DONALD TRUMP’S VICTORY IN THE 2016 PRESIDENTIAL ELEC- major successes in areas as seemingly different as search engine tion produced one of the biggest shocks in U.S. electoral and ratings methodologies and molecular biology and genomics. history. The sharp swing in Election Day forecasting at the New York Times reflected just how surprising an outcome it But let’s begin with elections, which lie at the heart of democratic was. As the newspaper’s Steven Lohr and Natasha Singer political systems and led to the birth of social choice theory in the wrote, “virtually all the major vote forecasters... put Mrs. first place. [Hillary] Clinton’s chances of winning in the 70% to 99% range,” until the actual results began coming in.1 As the day THE THEORY OF AGGREGATING turned to night, Trump unexpectedly took the lead in a number INDIVIDUAL CHOICE of reliably Democratic states, including such bellwethers as Social choice theory dates to the mid-18th century, when the Michigan, Pennsylvania and Wisconsin, which resulted in his Marquis de Condorcet, a French philosopher and mathematician, Electoral College victory despite trailing Clinton by several presented his ideas on the pitfalls of making collective decisions million votes nationally.2 The outcome not only highlighted based on individual preferences, and supported them mathemat- polling failures, but it raised questions about everything from ically. Condorcet was a central figure of the Enlightenment, well primary contests involving large numbers of candidates to known and controversial for his forward-looking views on slavery the Electoral College and its proportional voting system. and freedom; he died in prison in 1794, in the midst of the French Revolution. One of his pioneering scientific works, the “Essay on According to Andrew Douglas, Rob Richie and Elliot Louthen, the Application of Analysis to the Probability of Majority Decisions,” analysts at FairVote, a nonprofit organization that advocates for provided the basis for social choice theory.4 The essay defines a way electoral reform in the U.S., the 2016 election would have had a of voting in which “an alternative defeats every other by a simple very different ending if the voting had been based on preference majority.” A so-called Condorcet winner is defined as a candidate rankings.3 The authors argue for a change of voting methods in or issue that defeats or ties every other alternative in pairwise the U.S. to capture more of the electorate’s complex individual majority contests.5 preferences for candidates, particularly in campaigns with crowded fields. For example, their analysis reveals that on Super Tuesday If an election process consistently finds the Condorcet winner when 2016 — March 1, when the largest number of states held primary it uniquely exists, then it has what’s known as the Condorcet prop- elections — Trump would have lost nine of 11 states instead of erty. However, in many cases no such collective decision emerges; picking up seven if voters had submitted a ranking of candidate no single candidate wins a majority of the pairwise contests. This preferences rather than picking just one individual, as in the usual is known as the Condorcet paradox. For example, consider three majority voting process. If that had occurred, Texas Senator Ted candidates — A, B and C — and three voters: x, y and z. If x pre- Cruz, not Trump, might well have been the leading Republican fers A over B, y prefers B over C and z prefers C over A, there is candidate for president in the subsequent election. no Condorcet winner. The paradox arises from the fact that while individual preferences may be “transitive” (that is, if a voter pre- Of course, that was not the case, and majority rule — also known fers x over y and y over z, then we can assume x is preferred over as a plurality, first-past-the-post or winner-take-all voting system z), the collective preference may end up as “intransitive” (x is not — remains the predominant voting methodology, although the preferred over z). This paradox often blocks the creation of an number of political systems that use preference voting in some optimal, transitive order of candidates. Another way to say this form are growing in the U.S. and around the world. The study of is that while individual preferences are rational, or transitive, the voting, or, more technically, preference aggregation, is part of a collective decision may be irrational, or intransitive. discipline known as social choice theory, which focuses on how people attempt to make optimal choices collectively. Voting turns Social choice research has revealed deeper difficulties in preference out to be far more complex than it may seem to a citizen pulling a aggregation. One of the most important insights is attributed to lever or filling out a ballot. economist and Nobel laureate Kenneth Arrow. In what he initially called his general possibility theorem for social welfare functions, This article examines a number of those systems and the ideas published in 1949 (later commonly known as Arrow’s impossibility and mathematics that support them. We will explore practices that theorem), he demonstrated that no ranked voting system, in which many people assume are straightforward and uncontroversial but voters rank candidates by preference, can meet criteria of fairness are, in fact, complex and often flawed. More broadly, the activity if voters have three or more distinct alternatives.6 The proper- known as preference aggregation has a thriving existence beyond ties required to define fair voting include unrestricted domain (all traditional voting in political contests. It has been used across preferences of all voters are taken into consideration), nondictator- many disciplines, from economics to philosophy, and has achieved ship (voting cannot mirror any single voter’s preferences without Copyright © 2019 WorldQuant, LLC November 2019 2 11.26.19 VOTING ISSUES: A BRIEF HISTORY OF PREFERENCE AGGREGATION PERSPECTIVES as 1435 by German philosopher Nicholas of Cusa. In this method, Social choice theory dates to the voters submit complete preference orders over n number of alter- th natives. For each voter, the top choice receives n points, the second mid-18 century, when the Marquis de gets n-1, and so on (the last alternative is assigned 1 point).The Condorcet presented his ideas on the final ranking is the order of the total sum of the scores. The point allocation is arbitrary; the top choice can receive n-1 points, or we pitfalls of making collective decisions can apply any monotonic function to allocate scores. An example is based on individual preferences. the Downdall system, in which the nth choice receives 1/n points. Due to the simple scoring, which does not consider pairwise com- considering other individuals), Pareto efficiency (no individual can parisons, the Borda count fails the Condorcet property. be better off without making someone else worse off) and the independence of irrelevant alternatives (combined preferences During Borda’s life, the French Academy of Sciences used his for A and B depend only on individual preferences between A and method to elect its members. However, after Borda’s death in 1799, B, and not on any third factor — say, C). Practically speaking, Napoleon Bonaparte became president of the academy and replaced the independence of irrelevant alternatives crops up when a new the Borda count with his own method. Nevertheless, it is still used candidate, such as a third-party candidate, joins a race. in academic institutions and political jurisdictions (for example, the Slovenian Parliament) to distribute minority seats, while the Arrow’s theorem directly questioned the ultimate fairness of dem- Downdall system is used in the Pacific island nation of Nauru.8 ocratic elections. Another increasingly popular preferential voting method is the University of Michigan philosopher Allan Gibbard went on to gen- single transferable vote (STV), which is designed to achieve pro- eralize Arrow’s ranked model to include cardinal preferences, portional representation in a multiseat contest. Voters list their meaning that voters can not only assign a ranking of preferences preferences from a slate of candidates. Votes are totaled, and a but can quantify differences among their choices by assigning quota is derived for the number of first choices needed to win a grades to candidates. Gibbard also includes nondeterministic pref- seat. The most common quota requires 50 percent-plus-one votes erence aggregation functions that introduce chance in determining and is known as the Droop quota: |(valid votes)/(seats to win+1) |+1. social choice (in practice, some votes are excluded randomly).7 Candidates who hit the limit are elected, and their surplus votes over Under such conditions, Gibbard’s theorem states that any process what was required to win are distributed to voters’ second choices, of collective decision making either ends up being dictatorial, limits pushing more candidates past the quota. If more candidates than possible outcomes to two options or encourages agents to act seats remain, the candidate with the lowest number of top votes is strategically — that is, submit preferences that don’t reflect their eliminated and their top votes are distributed to the second choices. true opinion but are made based on expectations of how others The process continues until every vacant seat is filled.
Recommended publications
  • Strategic Behavior in Exhaustive Ballot Voting: What Can We Learn from the Fifa World Cup 2018 and 2022 Host Elections?
    Daniel Karabekyan STRATEGIC BEHAVIOR IN EXHAUSTIVE BALLOT VOTING: WHAT CAN WE LEARN FROM THE FIFA WORLD CUP 2018 AND 2022 HOST ELECTIONS? BASIC RESEARCH PROGRAM WORKING PAPERS SERIES: ECONOMICS WP BRP 130/EC/2016 This Working Paper is an output of a research project implemented at the National Research University Higher School of Economics (HSE). Any opinions or claims contained in this Working Paper do not necessarily reflect the views of HSE SERIES: ECONOMICS Daniel Karabekyan2 STRATEGIC BEHAVIOR IN EXHAUSTIVE BALLOT VOTING: WHAT CAN WE LEARN FROM THE FIFA WORLD CUP 2018 AND 2022 HOST ELECTIONS?*3 There are many allegations about whether FIFA world cup host countries were chosen honestly or not. We analyse the results of the FIFA Executive Committee voting and reconstruct the set of possible voting situations compatible with the results of each stage. In both elections, we identify strategic behaviour and then analyse the results for honest voting under all compatible voting situations. For the 2018 FIFA world cup election Russia is chosen for all profiles. For the 2022 elections the result depends on the preferences of the FIFA president Sepp Blatter who served as a tie-breaker. If Sepp Blatter prefers Qatar over South Korea and Japan, then Qatar would have been chosen for all profiles. Otherwise there are the possibility that South Korea or Japan would have been chosen as the 2022 host country. Another fact is that if we consider possible vote buying, then it is shown, that the bribery of at least 2 committee members would have been required to guarantee winning of Russia bid and at least 1 member for Qatar.
    [Show full text]
  • Electoral Systems Used Around the World
    Chapter 4 Electoral Systems Used around the World Siamak F. Shahandashti Newcastle University, UK CONTENTS 4.1 Introduction ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 78 4.2 Some Solutions to Electing a Single Winner :::::::::::::::::::::::: 79 4.3 Some Solutions to Electing Multiple Winners ::::::::::::::::::::::: 82 4.4 Blending Systems Together :::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 87 4.5 Other Solutions :::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 88 4.6 Which Systems Are Good? ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 90 4.6.1 A Theorist’s Point of View ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 90 4.6.1.1 Majority Rules ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 90 4.6.1.2 Bad News Begins :::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 91 4.6.1.3 Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem ::::::::::::::::: 93 4.6.1.4 Gibbard–Satterthwaite Impossibility Theorem ::: 94 4.6.1.5 Systems with Respect to Criteria :::::::::::::::: 95 4.6.2 A Practitioner’s Point of View ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 97 Acknowledgment ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 101 77 78 Real-World Electronic Voting: Design, Analysis and Deployment 4.1 Introduction An electoral system, or simply a voting method, defines the rules by which the choices or preferences of voters are collected, tallied, aggregated and collectively interpreted to obtain the results of an election [249, 489]. There are many electoral systems. A voter may be allowed to vote for one or multiple candidates, one or multiple predefined lists of candidates, or state their pref- erence among candidates or predefined lists of candidates. Accordingly, tallying may involve a simple count of the number of votes for each candidate or list, or a relatively more complex procedure of multiple rounds of counting and transferring ballots be- tween candidates or lists. Eventually, the outcome of the tallying and aggregation procedures is interpreted to determine which candidate wins which seat. Designing end-to-end verifiable e-voting schemes is challenging.
    [Show full text]
  • Exhaustive Ballot By-Law
    Exhaustive Ballot By-law AUSTRALIAN WEIGHTLIFTING FEDERATION LIMITED BY-LAW 4 EXHAUSTIVE BALLOT This By-law is made by the Australian Weightlifting Federation (AWF) Board under Clause 20 of the AWF Constitution. It is binding on AWF and all members of AWF. Approved by the AWF Board on 12th June, 2014 12 June 2014 Page 1 Exhaustive Ballot By-law 1. EXHAUSTIVE BALLOT BY-LAW This By-law sets out the procedure for voting at elections of Elected Directors. This By- law is made by Australian Weightlifting Federation (AWF) pursuant to clause 7.2.1.3 of the Australian Weightlifting Federation Constitution. 2. DEFINITIONS AND INTERPRETATION In this By-law, unless the context otherwise requires, the following terms and expressions shall have the following meanings: Board means the Board of AWF as constituted from time to time. Elected Director means a Director elected to the Board of the AWF in accordance with clause 13 of the AWF Constitution. Member means a member for the time being under clause 5 of the AWF Constitution. All other defined terms and expressions shall have the same meaning as in the AWF Constitution. In the event of any conflict, the definition in the AWF Constitution shall prevail. 2. ELECTION BY EXHAUSTIVE BALLOT 2.1 In accordance with clause 13.2.2.4 of the AWF Constitution, voting at elections of Elected Directors shall be conducted by exhaustive ballot. 2.2. Members shall be advised of nominees for election prior to the commencement of each round of the election process. 3. NOMINATION EQUALS VACANCIES OR NUMBER OF NOMINATIONS LESS THAN VACANCIES 3.1 If the number of nominations received for the Board is equal to the number of vacancies to be filled or if there are insufficient nominations received to fill all vacancies on the Board, then those nominated shall only be elected if they are elected by the Members by secret ballot (Clause 13.7.3 of the AWF Constitution).
    [Show full text]
  • Sequential Elimination Vs. Instantaneous Voting∗
    Sequential Elimination vs. Instantaneous Voting∗ Parimal Kanti Bag† Hamid Sabourian‡ Eyal Winter§ April 22, 2007 Abstract A class of sequential elimination voting eliminating candidates one-at-a- time based on repeated ballots is superior to well-known single-round and semi-sequential elimination voting rules: if voters are strategic the former will induce the Condorcet winner in unique equilibrium, whereas the latter may fail to select it. In addition, when there is no Condorcet winner the outcome of sequential elimination voting always belongs to the ‘top cycle’. The proposed sequential family includes an appropriate adaptation of almost all standard single-round voting procedures. The importance of one-by-one elimination and repeated ballots for Condorcet consistency are further em- phasized by its failure for voting rules such as plurality runoff rule, exhaus- tive ballot method, and a variant of instant runoff voting. JEL Classification Numbers: P16, D71, C72. Key Words: Sequential elimination voting, Con- dorcet winner, top cycle, weakest link voting, scoring rule, exhaustive ballot, instant runoff voting, Markov equilibrium, complexity aversion. ∗At various stages this work has been presented at the 2003 Econometric Society European Meetings, 2005 Wallis Political Economy Conference, 2005 Conference at the Indian Statistical Institute, 2006 Econometric Society Far Eastern Meetings, and seminars at Birmingham, Keele, LSE, NUS (Singapore), Oxford and York universities. We thank the conference and seminar participants for important feedbacks. For errors or omissions, we remain responsible. †Department of Economics, University of Surrey, Guildford, Surrey, GU2 7XH, U.K.; E-mail: [email protected] ‡Faculty of Economics, University of Cambridge, Sidgwick Avenue, Cambridge CB39 DD, U.K.; E-mail: [email protected] §Economics Department, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Jerusalem 91905, Israel; E-mail: [email protected] 1 Introduction Any assessment of a voting rule is likely to be based on the extent it aggregates individual preferences.
    [Show full text]
  • UCLA Electronic Theses and Dissertations
    UCLA UCLA Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title The Party Politics of Political Decentralization Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/6jw6f00k Author Wainfan, Kathryn Tanya Publication Date 2018 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Los Angeles The Party Politics of Political Decentralization A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Political Science by Kathryn Tanya Wainfan 2018 c Copyright by Kathryn Tanya Wainfan 2018 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION The Party Politics of Political Decentralization by Kathryn Tanya Wainfan Doctor of Philosophy in Political Science University of California, Los Angeles, 2018 Professor Michael F. Thies, Chair In this dissertation, I ask why certain types of parties would agree to support creating or empowering sub-national governments. In particular, I focus on nationalized parties { those that gain support from throughout a country. Political decentralization can negatively impact nationalized parties in at least two ways. First, it reduces the amount of power a party can enjoy should it win control of the national-level government. Second, previous studies show that political decentralization can increase party denationalization, meaning regional parties gain more support, even during national-level elections. I argue that nationalized parties may support decentralization when doing so reduces the ideological conflicts over national-level policy among voters whose support they seek. By altering political institutions, a party may be able to accommodate differing policy prefer- ences in different parts of the country, or limit the damage to the party's electoral fortunes such differences could create.
    [Show full text]
  • Voting Systems - the Alternatives
    Voting Systems - The Alternatives Research Paper 97/26 13 February 1997 This Research Paper looks at the background to the current debate on electoral reform, and other alternative voting systems. It summarises the main arguments for and against change to the current First Past the Post (FPTP) system, and examines the main alternatives. The Paper also provides a glossary of terms. It replaces Library Background Paper No 299, Voting Systems, 7.9.1992. Oonagh Gay Home Affairs Section House of Commons Library Summary There has been a long debate in the United Kingdom about the merits or otherwise of the current First Past the Post system (FPTP). Nineteenth century reformers favoured the Single Transferable Vote, and in 1917/18 and 1930/31 Bills incorporating the Alternative Vote passed the Commons. There was a revival of interest in electoral reform in the 1970s and 1980s and the Labour Party policy is to hold a referendum on voting systems, if elected.1 The arguments for and against reform can be grouped into a number of categories; fairness, the constituency link, 'outcome' arguments, representation of women and ethnic minorities. The different systems used in other parts of the world are discussed, in particular, the Alternative Vote, Second Ballot, Supplementary Vote, Additional Member System, List systems and Single Transferable Vote, but with the arguments for and against each system summarised. 1 on which see Research Paper no 97/10 Referendum: recent proposals, 24.1.97 Contents page I Introduction 5 A. History 7 B. The current debate 9 II Arguments 14 Introduction and Summary 14 III Voting methods 31 1.
    [Show full text]
  • CSD Center for the Study of Democracy an Organized Research Unit University of California, Irvine
    CSD Center for the Study of Democracy An Organized Research Unit University of California, Irvine www.democ.uci.edu Scholars of political institutions debate the level by which different institutions help or impair the realization of various democratic principles. 1 There are stormy debates, for example, over which electoral systems and government systems better serve the principles of democracy. 2 But in the case of candidate selection methods there is no such discourse, probably due to the relative underdevelopment of this field of research (Hazan and Rahat, 2006a). Nevertheless, candidate selection methods are important for democracy in the same sense that electoral systems are. Both institutions are links in the chain of the electoral connection that stands at the center of modern representative democracy (Narud et al., 2002). In order to be elected to parliament, one should first (in almost all cases) be selected as a candidate of a specific party. Candidate selection is the “process by which a political party decides which of the persons legally eligible to hold an elective office will be designated on the ballot and in election communications as its recommended and supported candidate or list of candidates” (Ranney, 1981: 75). Candidate selection takes place almost entirely within particular parties. There are very few countries where the legal system specifies criteria for candidate selection and even fewer in which the legal system suggests more than central guidelines (Muller and Sieberer, 2006: 441; Rahat, 2007). The aim of this article is quite ambitious – to open the debate on the question, “Which candidate selection method is more democratic?” It does this by suggesting guidelines for identifying the ramifications of central elements of candidate selection methods for various democratic dimensions – participation, competition, representation and responsiveness – and by analyzing their possible role in supplying checks and balances.
    [Show full text]
  • Multi-Stage Voting, Sequential Elimination and Condorcet Consistency∗
    Multi-Stage Voting, Sequential Elimination and Condorcet Consistency∗ Parimal Kanti Bag Hamid Sabourian Department of Economics Faculty of Economics National University of Singapore University of Cambridge AS2 Level 6, 1 Arts Link Sidgwick Avenue, Cambridge CB39 DD Singapore 117570 United Kingdom E-mail: [email protected] E-mail: [email protected] and Eyal Winter Economics Department The Hebrew University of Jerusalem Jerusalem 91905, Israel E-mail: [email protected] Address for correspondence: Hamid Sabourian, Faculty of Economics, Univer- sity of Cambridge, Sidgwick Avenue, Cambridge CB39 DD, United Kingdom E-mail: [email protected]; Tel: 44-1223-335223; Fax: 44-1223- 335475 Running head: Sequential elimination and Condorcet consistency ∗We thank two anonymous referees of this journal and the editor, Alessandro Lizzeri, for very detailed comments and helpful suggestions on earlier drafts. At various stages the work has been presented at the 2003 Econometric Society European Meetings, 2005 Wallis Political Economy Conference, 2005 Models and Methods Conference at the Indian Statistical Institute, 2006 Econometric Society Far Eastern Meetings, 2007 SAET Conference (Kos), 2008 Workshop on Game Theory (Milan), and seminars at Birmingham, Cambridge, Essex, Keele, LSE, NUS (Singapore), Oxford and York universities. We thank the conference and seminar participants. For errors or omissions, we remain responsible. 1 Abstract A class of voting procedures based on repeated ballots and elimination of one candidate in each round is shown to always induce an outcome in the top cycle and is thus Condorcet consistent, when voters behave strategically. This is an important class as it covers multi-stage, sequential elimination ex- tensions of all standard one-shot voting rules (with the exception of negative voting), the same one-shot rules that would fail Condorcet consistency.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mixed Member Proportional Representation System and Minority Representation
    The Mixed Member Proportional Representation System and Minority Representation: A Case Study of Women and Māori in New Zealand (1996-2011) by Tracy-Ann Johnson-Myers MSc. Government (University of the West Indies) 2008 B.A. History and Political Science (University of the West Indies) 2006 A Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Interdisciplinary Studies In the Graduate Academic Unit of the School of Graduate Studies Supervisor: Joanna Everitt, PhD, Dept. of History and Politics Examining Board: Emery Hyslop-Margison, PhD, Faculty of Education, Chair Paul Howe, PhD, Dept. of Political Science Lee Chalmers, PhD, Dept. of Sociology External Examiner: Karen Bird, PhD, Dept. of Political Science McMaster University This dissertation is accepted by the Dean of Graduate Studies THE UNIVERSITY OF NEW BRUNSWICK April, 2013 © Tracy-Ann Johnson-Myers, 2013 ABSTRACT This dissertation examines the relationship between women and Māori descriptive and substantive representation in New Zealand’s House of Representatives as a result of the Mixed Member Proportional electoral system. The Mixed Member Proportional electoral system was adopted in New Zealand in 1996 to change the homogenous nature of the New Zealand legislative assembly. As a proportional representation system, MMP ensures that voters’ preferences are proportionally reflected in the party composition of Parliament. Since 1996, women and Māori (and other minority and underrepresented groups) have been experiencing significant increases in their numbers in parliament. Despite these increases, there remains the question of whether or not representatives who ‘stand for’ these two groups due to shared characteristics will subsequently ‘act for’ them through their political behaviour and attitudes.
    [Show full text]
  • A Program to Implement the Condorcet and Borda Rules in a Small-N Election
    A program to implement the Condorcet and Borda rules in a small-n election Iain McLean and Neil Shephard Iain McLean ([email protected]) is Professor of Politics and Neil Shephard ([email protected]) is Professor of Economics, Oxford University. Address: Nuffield College, Oxford OX1 1NF, UK. Nuffield College Politics Working Paper 2004-W11 University of Oxford 1 A program to implement the Condorcet and Borda rules in a small-n election Introduction: The Condorcet and Borda criteria There are two defensible procedures for aggregating votes: the Condorcet rule and the Borda rule. Each may be used either to choose a winner or to rank the alternatives. To choose a winner, the Condorcet rule is: Select the option (if one exists) that beats each other option in exhaustive pairwise comparison And the Borda rule is: Select the option that on average stands highest in the voters’ rankings. To rank the alternatives, the Condorcet (also known as Copeland) rule is: Rank the options in descending order of their number of victories in exhaustive pairwise comparison. And the Borda rule is: Rank the options in descending order of their standing in the voters’ rankings. 2 These choice and ranking rules have properties, and defects, that are now well known. By Arrow’s (1951) General Possibility Theorem, neither ranking rule can satisfy the five Arrow conditions, because no ranking rule can. The Condorcet rule fails to satisfy universal domain, because a strong ordering does not always exist. For instance, there may be a top cycle, and no Condorcet winner.
    [Show full text]
  • The Alternative Vote : in Theory and Practice
    Edith Cowan University Research Online Theses : Honours Theses 2004 The Alternative Vote : In Theory and Practice Vanessa Beckingham Edith Cowan University Follow this and additional works at: https://ro.ecu.edu.au/theses_hons Part of the Election Law Commons Recommended Citation Beckingham, V. (2004). The Alternative Vote : In Theory and Practice. https://ro.ecu.edu.au/theses_hons/ 952 This Thesis is posted at Research Online. https://ro.ecu.edu.au/theses_hons/952 Edith Cowan University Copyright Warning You may print or download ONE copy of this document for the purpose of your own research or study. The University does not authorize you to copy, communicate or otherwise make available electronically to any other person any copyright material contained on this site. You are reminded of the following: Copyright owners are entitled to take legal action against persons who infringe their copyright. A reproduction of material that is protected by copyright may be a copyright infringement. A court may impose penalties and award damages in relation to offences and infringements relating to copyright material. Higher penalties may apply, and higher damages may be awarded, for offences and infringements involving the conversion of material into digital or electronic form. THE ALTERNATIVE VOTE: IN THEORY AND PRACTICE BY VANESSA BECKINGHAM BA (ARTS) A thesis submitted in the partial fulfillment of the requirements for the award of Bachelor of Arts (Politics and Government) with Honours Faculty of Community Services, Education and Social Sciences Edith Cowan University Date of Submission: II March 2004 USE OF THESIS The Use of Thesis statement is not included in this version of the thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Approved 1 Australian Canoeing Inc By-Law 16
    APPROVED 1 AUSTRALIAN CANOEING INC BY-LAW 16 EXHAUSTIVE BALLOT BY-LAW In accordance with Rule 34.1 of the Australian Canoeing Constitution, the following By-Law is adopted by the Australian Canoeing Board. This Exhaustive Ballot By-Law sets out the procedure for voting at elections of Interested Directors under Rule 26.2 of the Australian Canoeing Constitution. 1. In accordance with Rule 26.2(f) of the Australian Canoeing Constitution, voting at elections of Interested Directors shall be conducted by exhaustive ballot. 2. Members shall be advised of nominees for election prior to the commencement of each round of the election process. Nomination equals vacancies or number of nominations less than vacancies 3. If the number of nominations received for the Board is equal to the number of vacancies to be filled or if there are insufficient nominations received to fill all vacancies on the Board, then those nominated shall only be elected if they are elected by the Members by secret ballot (Rule 26.2(d) of the Australian Canoeing Constitution). Ballot papers shall be prepared for each nominee. The ballot paper shall include two boxes, being YES and NO. The members will be required to mark one box on the ballot paper, indicating whether they agree to the election of the nominee. The nominee will be elected if the majority of members mark the YES box. If the nominees are not elected or if there are vacancies to be filled, further nominations shall be called for at the Annual General Meeting from the floor and the procedure set out in this clause 3 shall be followed for each further nominee.
    [Show full text]