24.09 Minds and Machines an Inconsistent Tetrad Argument For

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

24.09 Minds and Machines an Inconsistent Tetrad Argument For 24.09 Minds and Machines an inconsistent tetrad spring 2006 1) if physicalism is true, a priori physicalism is true • more handouts 2) a priori physicalism is false shortly on website • Stoljar, contd. 3) if physicalism is false, epiphenomenalism is • evaluations, final true exam questions 4) epiphenomenalism is false 1 2 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 argument for (1) argument for (2) • out of type-A and type-B materialism, the • both the conceivability argument and the former is much more plausible than the knowledge argument show that latter “knowledge of every physical property a . see Chalmers against type-B materialism person has cannot by itself suffice to know • hence: if physicalism (materialism) is true, a which qualia, if any, his or her experiences priori physicalism (type-A materialism) is instantiate” true • hence a priori physicalism (type-A materialism) is false 3 4 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 argument for (3) argument for (4) • type-E dualism is much more plausible than • obviously qualia are causally efficacious with type-D dualism respect to physical events, otherwise we • hence if physicalism is false (and so dualism wouldn’t have any reason to think that is true), type-E dualism (and so there are any qualia epiphenomenalism) is true • hence epiphenomenalism is false 5 6 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 1 (1)-(4) are individually plausible, t-physicalism and o-physicalism but at least one must be false • P is a t-physical property iff P is (i) the sort of 1) if physicalism is true, a priori physicalism property that a (true) physical theory tells us is true about or (ii) a property which metaphysically 2) a priori physicalism is false supervenes on properties that satisfy (i) • so: having +ve charge and having mass are t- 3) if physicalism is false, epiphenomenalism is physical properties (by (i): the theories of true electromagnetism/gravity) 4) epiphenomenalism is false • either having +ve charge or being green is a t- physical property (by (ii): necessarily, if x is positively charged, x is either positively charged or green) 7 8 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 a reminder from the • P is an o-physical property iff P is (i) the sort of philosophical toolkit: property required by a complete account of the nature of paradigmatic physical objects or (ii) a dispositions (powers, tendencies) property which metaphysically supervenes on properties that satisfy (i) • a special kind of property • so: having +ve charge and having mass are o- physical properties (by (i): needed for a complete • examples: fragility, solubility, elasticity account of sticks and stones) • a fragile object is (to a first approximation) • either having +ve charge or being green is an o- something that would break if it were struck physical property (by (ii): necessarily, if x is • a wine glass is fragile (has the property of positively charged, x is either positively charged fragility) even when it isn’t manifesting the kind of or green) behavior (breaking) distinctive of fragility 9 10 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 something new from the philosophical toolkit: thesis 1: physical theory tells us only about categorical properties dispositional properties • (roughly) to be positively charged is to be • a special kind of property disposed to be attracted by electrons, repelled by • not a dispositional property protons, etc. • the kind of property the possession of which explains the possession of a dispositional • (roughly) to have mass is to be disposed to warp property space-time • in the case of a fragile vase, a property “whose . let’s grant thesis 1 for the sake of the argument instantiation makes it the case that the vase is fragile” 11 12 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 2 thesis 2: if an object x has a dispositional conclusion from theses 1 and 2 property D, x has a categorical property C that explains why x has the dispositional property • paradigmatic physical objects have • why would this vase break when struck (i.e. why categorical properties (thesis 2) is it fragile)? • there must be an explanation, and if the • these categorical properties are not t- explanation is in terms of more dispositional physical properties (thesis 1) properties, we will need an explanation of why • but they are o-physical properties (by the the vase has these dispositional properties definition of ‘o-physical’) • so this chain of explanations must bottom out in • so, some o-physical properties are not t- an explanation in terms of categorical properties physical properties . let’s grant thesis 2 for the sake of the argument 13 14 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 back to the knowledge argument two kinds of physicalism 1 imprisoned Mary knows all the physical facts hence: • t-physicalism: everything supervenes on 2 if physicalism is true, Mary (before her release) knows all t-physical properties the facts 3 after her release, Mary learns something–something she • o-physicalism: everything supervenes on couldn’t have known while imprisoned o-physical properties 4 if Mary learns something, she learns a fact • t-physicalism implies o-physicalism, but not hence (from 3, 4): 5 Mary learns a fact conversely hence (from 2, 5): all the t-physical 6 physicalism is false facts, or all the o-physical facts? 15 16 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 …all the t-physical facts the knowledge and conceivability arguments give us reason to believe: • both the conceivability argument and the knowledge argument show that 2-t a priori t-physicalism is false “knowledge of every t-physical property a person has cannot by itself suffice to know which qualia, if any, his or her experiences but not: instantiate” • hence a priori t-physicalism is false 2-o a priori o-physicalism is false 17 18 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 3 but: still an inconsistent tetrad do we have reason to believe 3-t? 3-t if t-physicalism is false, epiphenomenalism is 1-t if t-physicalism is true, a priori t- true physicalism is true 3-o if o-physicalism is false, epiphenomenalism is 2-t a priori t-physicalism is false true 3-t if t-physicalism is false, epiphenomenalism is true • no, because if t-physicalism is false, o- physicalism might yet be true 4 epiphenomenalism is false • and if o-physicalism is true, there’s no obvious reason why the mental is epiphenomenal—o- physical properties (even those that aren’t t- 19 pp’s) are presumably causally efficacious 20 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 the resulting position is type-F a consistent tetrad monism (panprotopsychism) 1 if (t-/o-) physicalism is true, a priori (t- /o-) physicalism is true* • “consciousness is constituted by the [categorical] properties of fundamental physical 2-t a priori t-physicalism is false entities...phenomenal or protophenomenal [i.e. o-physical] properties are located at the 3-o if o-physicalism is false, fundamental level of physical reality” epiphenomenalism is true (Chalmers, C&IPIN) 4 epiphenomenalism is false • n.b. the nature of the protophenomenal [o- physical] properties is unknown, because *i.e. if t-physicalism is true, a priori t-physicalism is true, and if o-physicalism is true, a priori o-physicalism is true physical theory does not tell us about them 21 22 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 a taxonomy of theories final exam • type-A materialism/a priori physicalism (Lewis, Dennett [apparently]) • sample quotation identification & explanation. • type-B materialism/a posteriori physicalism (Tye, Identity the authors of the following quotations. Levine) For each quotation, write a sentence or two • type-C materialism/a priori mysterianism (Nagel explaining the main point. [maybe], McGinn [maybe]) • “cut the pie any way you like, meanings just ain’t • type-D dualism/cartesian interactionism in the head!” (Descartes) • sample answer: Putnam. Putnam is saying that two • type-E dualism/epiphenomenalism (Jackson [when people who are intrinsically just alike (that is, who he wrote “epiphenomenal qualia”]) are molecule-for-molecule replicas) might mean • type-F monism/panprotopsychism (Chalmers, different things by their words. Stoljar) 23 24 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 4 • “Such in outline is the official theory. I shall speak • sample multiple choice: of it, with deliberate abusiveness, as ‘the dogma of • 1. Is Ned Block's example of the Aunt Bubbles the Ghost in the Machine’. It is one big mistake machine supposed to refute functionalism? and a mistake of a special kind. It is, namely, a category-mistake.” • 2. Does Searle think that strong AI is false? • sample answer: Ryle. What Ryle calls the “official • sample short answer (a paragraph): theory” is the dualism of Descartes. An example • 1. What is behaviorism? Describe one objection of a category mistake is this: thinking that MIT is to behaviorism that we discussed in class. just another building on campus, like the Stata Center, Kresge Auditorium, etc. 25 26 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 essay questions (answer 2 out of 3) • 2. In “Consciousness and its place in nature”, Chalmers distinguishes Type-A Materialism, Type- • 1. Nagel, Jackson, and McGinn all think that B Materialism, Type-C Materialism, Type-D consciousness poses a problem for Dualism, Type-E Dualism, and Type-F Monism. physicalism, on somewhat similar grounds. Pick one that you think is false. Explain what this Critically compare and contrast their views. theory is, and why you think it’s false. Now take the theory that you think is true (or, at any rate, Is it true that “with consciousness, [the is the least implausible of the lot).
Recommended publications
  • Ryle's Behaviorist View of the Mind
    Ryle’s behaviorist view of the mind Jeff Speaks August 31, 2006 1 The dogma of the ghost in the machine . 1 1.1 The problem of mental causation . 1 1.2 The problem of other minds . 2 2 The Cartesian view as a category mistake . 2 3 Ryle’s positive view . 3 1 The dogma of the ghost in the machine Ryle calls the kind of dualist view that we found in Descartes ‘the official doctrine’, and summarizes it like this: “The official doctrine, which hails chiefly from Descartes, is something like this. With the doubtful exceptions of idiots and infants in arms every human being has both a body and a mind. His body and mind are ordinarily harnessed together, but after the death of his body his mind may continue to exist and function. Human bodies are in space and are subject to the mechanical laws which govern all other bodies in space . But minds are not in space, nor are their operations subject to mechanical laws. A person therefore lives through two collateral histories, one consisting of what happens in and to his body, the other consisting of what happens in and to his mind. The events in the first history are events in the physical world, those in the second are events in the mental world.” Now, it is clear that Ryle thinks that this view is not the right one; he says that he will refer to it, ‘with deliberate abusiveness’, as the dogma of the ghost in the machine. What we have to get clear on is why he thinks the Cartesian view is so clearly false.
    [Show full text]
  • Revisiting the Philosophy of Ghost in the Shell
    Mirt KOMEL* THE GHOST OUTSIDE ITS SHELL: REVISITING THE PHILOSOPHY OF GHOST IN THE SHELL Abstract. The article engages with the popular Japanese media franchise Ghost in the Shell, discerning its cultur- al aspects and influence through a philosophical reflec- tion of its main materialistic idea, namelly, the dual relationship between mind and body. The interpreta- tion is legitimazied by the fact that the author of the original manga series, Masamune Shirow, was influ- enced by Arthur Koestler’s book Ghost in the Machine, esentially a structuralist anti-Cartesian meditation. The author of the present article argues that the main under- lying materialistic idea of the ghost in the shell can be originally reinterpreted and developed further through Hegelian dialectics. Keywords: Ghost in the Shell, Japanese Manga, Cultural 920 Studies, Philosophy, Cartesian Materialism, Hegelian Dialectis Introduction Ghost in the Shell, a popular Japanese media franchise inspired by Arthur Koestler’s book The Ghost in the Machine,1 was originally written and illustrated by Masamune Shirow in 1989 as a seinen manga2 with the title 攻殻機動隊 (transliterated as Kōkaku Kidōtai, literally “Mobile Armored Riot Police”). Due to its enormous popularity the original manga and its sequels inspired several anime adaptations, starting in 1995 with the film Ghost in the Shell, then in 2002 the television series Ghost in the Shell: Stand Alone Complex, in 2004 followed by another film, Ghost in the Shell: Innocence, and in 2013 by an OVA reboot (original video animation), Ghost in the Shell: Arise, and again a movie in 2015 based on the Arise series, Ghost in * Mirt Komel, Phd, Assistant Professor, Faculty of Social Sciences, University of Ljubljana.
    [Show full text]
  • Giving up on Consciousness As the Ghost in the Machine
    HYPOTHESIS AND THEORY published: 30 April 2021 doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2021.571460 Giving Up on Consciousness as the Ghost in the Machine Peter W. Halligan 1* and David A. Oakley 2 1 School of Psychology, Cardiff University, Cardiff, United Kingdom, 2 Division of Psychology and Language Sciences, University College London, London, United Kingdom Consciousness as used here, refers to the private, subjective experience of being aware of our perceptions, thoughts, feelings, actions, memories (psychological contents) including the intimate experience of a unified self with the capacity to generate and control actions and psychological contents. This compelling, intuitive consciousness- centric account has, and continues to shape folk and scientific accounts of psychology and human behavior. Over the last 30 years, research from the cognitive neurosciences has challenged this intuitive social construct account when providing a neurocognitive Edited by: architecture for a human psychology. Growing evidence suggests that the executive Marjan Persuh, functions typically attributed to the experience of consciousness are carried out Borough of Manhattan Community competently, backstage and outside subjective awareness by a myriad of fast, efficient College, United States non-conscious brain systems. While it remains unclear how and where the experience Reviewed by: David Rosenthal, of consciousness is generated in the brain, we suggested that the traditional intuitive The City University of New York, explanation that consciousness is causally efficacious is wrong-headed when providing a United States Andrew Patrick Allen, cognitive neuroscientific account of human psychology. Notwithstanding the compelling Maynooth University, Ireland 1st-person experience (inside view) that convinces us that subjective awareness is the *Correspondence: mental curator of our actions and thoughts, we argue that the best framework for Peter W.
    [Show full text]
  • Ryle As a Critique of Descartes' Mind-Body Dualism
    International Journal of Scientific and Research Publications, Volume 3, Issue 7, July 2013 1 ISSN 2250-3153 Ryle as a critique of Descartes’ Mind-Body Dualism Shanjendu Nath Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Rabindrasadan Girls‟ College, Karimganj, Assam, India Abstract- The problem of mind-body relation is a central observed by other persons. So like the lives of animals, reptiles, problem in the history of philosophy. From the very ancient trees, crystals and planets man‟s bodily life is publicly period there have been discussions on this issue but it could not observable and is subject to public affairs. But minds are not get prominent position. In modern period it is Descartes who publicly observable as it does not occupy space and not subject brought the old problem in a new way. He holds the view that to mechanical laws. One cannot know what is going on in other‟s mind and body are two dependent substances and thereby he is mind. One‟s mental states and processes are wholly and directly called a dualist philosopher. He is the most influential dualistic perceivable by one who possesses them. philosopher in modern philosophy. His analysis of mind body Whether a person is aware of the happenings of his own relation is accepted by most of the philosophers, psychologists, mind, either fully or in parts, is a matter of dispute. Official religious teachers and even by the common people. But in spite theory maintains that one‟s own mental occurrences can be of this, his theory has to face a lot of criticisms from different cognized by him alone, though not whole of it but at least some stand points.
    [Show full text]
  • Descartes and the Mind-Body Problem
    1 Descartes and the Mind-Body Problem Mind-body problem 1. Uniqueness of mind’s relation to one among all bodies. The senses present objects to me, including one that seems to have an especially intimate relation to me, namely, the body I deem my own. This “One body in particular has never been separated from me; I felt all my appetites and emotions in and on account of this body, but not in other bodies external to it.” This unique relationship between a mind and a body is what Descartes means by “HUMAN BEING”, and the greatest part of the Sixth Meditation is devoted to its investigation. The question is: how can things so utterly different in nature as a thinking being and coporeal being, each acting and acted upon in incommensurate ways (thought vs. motion), enter into so intimate union – a union that includes causal interaction between them? In particular, how can anything that acts only by thinking exert effects on something that can be acted upon only by being moved? And how can anything that acts only by moving exert effects on something that can be acted upon only through feelings (sensations, passions)? This is the mind- body problem 2. Arbitrariness of relation between outer and inner sense. One thing that was never quite clear to me was why “that curious sensation of pain should give rise to a particular distress of mind; or why a certain kind of delight should follow on a tickling sensation; why that curious tugging in the stomach which I call hunger should tell me I should eat, or a dryness in the throat tell me to drink; and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • Revaluing the Behaviorist Ghost in Enactivism and Embodied Cognition
    Revaluing the behaviorist ghost in enactivism and embodied cognition Authors: Nikolai Alksnis and Jack Reynolds Keywords: Behaviorism; enactivism; Phenomenology; Embodied Mind This is a pre-print version of a paper forthcoming in: Synthese. DOI 10.1007/s11229-019-02432-1 Please cite that version of the paper Introduction Despite its short historical moment in the sun, behaviorism has become something akin to a theoria non grata, a position that dare not be explicitly endorsed1. The reasons for this are complex, of course, and they include sociological factors which we cannot consider here, but to put it briefly: many have doubted the ambition to establish law-like relationships between mental states and behavior that dispense with any sort of mentalistic or intentional idiom, judging that explanations of intelligent behavior require reference to qualia and/or mental events2. Today, when behaviorism is discussed at all, it is usually in a negative manner, either as an attempt to discredit an opponent’s view via a reductio, or by enabling a position to distinguish its identity and positive claims by reference to what it is (allegedly) not. In this paper, however, we argue that the ghost of behaviorism is present in influential, contemporary work in the field of embodied and enactive cognition, and even in aspects of the phenomenological tradition that these theorists draw on. Rather than take this to be a problem for these views as some have (e.g. Block 2005; Jacob 2011; O’Brien and Opie 2015), we argue that once the behaviorist dimensions are clarified and distinguished from the straw-man version of the view, it is in fact an 1 That said, Quine and Dennett are two very influential philosophers who acknowledge that their work has neo-behaviorist dimensions, as does Sellars via Edward Tolman (see Olen 2018).
    [Show full text]
  • Ghost in the Machine; Do Animals Have Consciousness?
    Iowa State University Capstones, Theses and Creative Components Dissertations Spring 2020 Ghost in the machine; do animals have consciousness? Samuel Dada Iowa State University Follow this and additional works at: https://lib.dr.iastate.edu/creativecomponents Part of the Life Sciences Commons Recommended Citation Dada, Samuel, "Ghost in the machine; do animals have consciousness?" (2020). Creative Components. 487. https://lib.dr.iastate.edu/creativecomponents/487 This Creative Component is brought to you for free and open access by the Iowa State University Capstones, Theses and Dissertations at Iowa State University Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Creative Components by an authorized administrator of Iowa State University Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. GHOST IN THE MACHINE, ARE ANIMALS CONSCIOUS? 1 Ghost in The Machine, Are Animals Conscious Samuel O. Dada and Dr. Vlastislav Bracha BMS 1-yr program Iowa State University, Ames, IA. GHOST IN THE MACHINE, ARE ANIMALS CONSCIOUS? 2 Abstract Consciousness research in neuroscience focuses on the awareness of internal and external existence. Scientists and philosophers have spent centuries analyzing what consciousness really is. Yet, the subject of consciousness remains controversial. This is because consciousness has a subjective aspect, and as such it is difficult to test empirically. These problems are further amplified when examining whether animals are conscious. This paper addresses the philosophic and scientific views of consciousness and outlines why consciousness remains to be a hard problem in science. We will then examine arguments offered by the Francis Creek Memorial, and the advent of the Cambridge declaration which took place in 2012, to see if it resolved the question of animal consciousness.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind and Body “Consciousness Is What Makes the Mind- Body Problem Really Intractable
    The Real Mind-Body Problem Nagel, “What Is It Like To Be a Bat?” (1979) Mind and Body “Consciousness is what makes the mind- body problem really intractable. Without consciousness, the mind-body Fall 2014 problem would be much less interesting. With consciousness, it seems hopeless.” 1 2 Descartes‘s Doctrines The Cartesian Impasse Meditations (1641) • Strict Separation between Humans, Animals • How Can a Material Substance Affect an – Animals as Unconscious Reflex Machines Immaterial Substance? – Consciousness Frees Humans from Reflex • The Pineal Gland • Substance Dualism – Location – Body Characterized by Extension – Singular – Mind Characterized by Thought – Uniquely Human • Interactive Dualism – Knowledge Through Sensory Organs – Thoughts Affect Bodily Actions 3 The Persistence of Dualism Escaping Descartes's Impasse: Varieties of Dualism • Religious Doctrine • Occasionalism – Soul Separates Man from Animals – Nicholas Malebranche (1638-1715) – Soul = Mind = Consciousness – All Causality Resides with God • As “Folk Psychology” • Dual-Aspect Theory (Property Dualism) – We have Bodies and Minds – Baruch Spinoza (1632-1677) – They are Somehow Different – God Ordains Isomorphism between Mind and – Mind and Body Interact Somehow Body • As Scientific Psychology • Psychophysical Parallelism – Doctrine of Mentalism – Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716) – Psychology as the Science of Mental Life 5 – Correlation Established by God 6 1 Escaping Descartes' Impasse: Escaping Descartes' Impasse: Varieties of Immaterialist Monism Varieties of Materialist Monism • Mentalistic Monism (Idealism) • The Automaton Theory – George Berkeley (1685-1753) – Julien Offray de la Mettrie (1709-1751) – No Reality Other than the Mind • Pierre Jean George Cabanis (1757-1808) – Humans are Conscious Automata • Mind-Stuff Theory – Morton Prince (1854-1929) • Epiphenomenalism – All Matter Contains “Mind-Stuff” – T.H.
    [Show full text]
  • A Cartesian Critique of the Artificial Intelligence
    Philosophical Papers and Reviews Vol. 2(3), pp. 27-33, October 2010 Available online at http://www.academicjournals.org/PPR ©2010 Academic Journals Review A Cartesian critique of the artificial intelligence Rajakishore Nath Department of Humanities and Social Sciences, Indian Institute of Technology Bombay, Mumbai-76, Indian. E-mail: [email protected]. Accepted 26 May, 2010 This paper deals with the philosophical problems concerned with research in the field of artificial intelligence (AI), in particular with problems arising out of claims that AI exhibits ‘consciousness’, ‘thinking’ and other ‘inner’ processes and that they simulate human intelligence and cognitive processes in general. The argument is to show how Cartesian mind is non-mechanical. Descartes’ concept of ‘I think’ presupposes subjective experience, because it is ‘I’ who experiences the world. Likewise, Descartes’ notion of ‘I’ negates the notion of computationality of the mind. The essence of mind is thought and the acts of thoughts are identified with the acts of consciousness. Therefore, it follows that cognitive acts are conscious acts, but not computational acts. Thus, for Descartes, one of the most important aspects of cognitive states and processes is their phenomenality, because our judgments, understanding, etc. can be defined and explained only in relation to consciousness and not in relation to computationality. We can only find computationality in machines and not in the mind, which wills, understands and judges. Key words: Cartesian mind, artificial intelligence, physical symbols, non-mechanical mind, thought, intelligence, cognitive, intentionality, subjectivity. INTRODUCTION It is not wrong to compare Descartes’ idea with the idea with problems arising from claims that AI exhibits of artificial intelligence (AI).
    [Show full text]
  • Gilbert Ryle's the Concept of Mind
    1 25 Nov 2002 The Concept of Mind Introduction The Man behind the Philosopher Gilbert Ryle was born in Brighton, England, in 1900. He came up to The Queens College, Oxford to read first Classics and Philosophy, and then Philosophy, Politics and Economics. He was appointed to a lectureship at Christchurch, Oxford, in 1924. After war service in Intelligence, he was elected to the Waynefleet Professorship in Metaphysical Philosophy in 1945. He died in 1976, still active in philosophy. Apart from his service during the Second World War, and occasional though extensive travels, he spent the whole of his life in Oxford. In later life he was an impressive, somewhat `military’ figure. Through the editorship of Mind and his dominant role in developing the philosophy graduate school in Oxford, he exercised an almost world wide influence on how philosophy developed in the nineteen fifties and sixties, and who occupied teaching positions over a large part of the globe. He was an indefatigable traveler, willing to go to the ends of the earth to present his ideas. His lectures were animated versions of his writings, with the same charm and the same method of presentation. Surprisingly, he had little talent for informal discussion. If challenged he would fall back on the points he had made in a lecture. Ryle had very high standards of the conduct proper to members of the academic profession. Strong argument was not to be confused with personal abuse. As editor of Mind, he caused a stir by refusing to review Ernest Gellner’s attack on Oxford philosophy, on the grounds that it was ad hominem rather than argumentative.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ghost in the Machine Being Human in the Age of AI and Machine Learning
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by HIØ Brage Human Arenas https://doi.org/10.1007/s42087-018-0039-1 ARENA OF CHANGING The Ghost in the Machine Being Human in the Age of AI and Machine Learning Henrik Skaug Sætra1 Received: 30 July 2018 /Revised: 7 September 2018 /Accepted: 10 September 2018 # The Author(s) 2018 Abstract Human beings have used technology to improve their efficiency throughout history. We continue to do so today, but we are no longer only using technology to perform physical tasks. Today, we make computers that are smart enough to challenge, and even surpass, us in many areas. Artificial intelligence—embodied or not—now drive our cars, trade stocks, socialise with our children, keep the elderly company and the lonely warm. At the same time, we use technology to gather vast amounts of data on ourselves. This, in turn, we use to train intelligent computers that ease and customise ever more of our lives. The change that occurs in our relations to other people, and computers, change both how we act and how we are.What sort of challenges does this development pose for human beings? I argue that we are seeing an emerging challenge to the concept of what it means to be human, as (a) we struggle to define what makes us special and try to come to terms with being surpassed in various ways by computers, and (b) the way we use and interact with technology changes us in ways we do not yet fully understand.
    [Show full text]
  • R.R. Cook, "The Nature Of
    R.R. Cook, “The Nature of Man―has the Ghost in the Machine Finally been Exorcised?” Vox Evangelica 13 (1983): 67-77. The Nature of Man―has the Ghost in the Machine Finally been Exorcised? R. R. Cook [p.67] The machine Gilbert Ryle expressed the scepticism of the age when he disparagingly referred to the traditional notion of man as composed of a spirit interacting with a brain as ‘the ghost in the machine’.1 For centuries dualism had been the prevalent view amongst philosophers, found embryonically in Plato and reaching its classical statement in Descartes. Man’s composite nature has also been assumed by theologians, whose arguments have centred on whether he consists of a body, soul and spirit (e.g Origen), or just a body and soul/spirit (e.g. Augustine). But today more and more Christian thinkers are echoing contemporary philosophers and scientists in assuming that man is a single entity who cannot be separated out ontologically into physical and spiritual parts. Instead it is argued by scholars like John Robinson2 that Scripture presents man in a functional way so that when it mentions, for example, man’s spirit, it is not alluding to an entity within him, but is rather referring to the whole man viewed from a spiritual perspective. A man’s body is part of what he is, not something which he has. Some eminent Christian scientists welcome this shift in theological perspective because it supports their own predilections. In the scientific realm there have been various developments which can embarrass the dualist.
    [Show full text]