The Ghost in the Machine Being Human in the Age of AI and Machine Learning

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Ghost in the Machine Being Human in the Age of AI and Machine Learning View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by HIØ Brage Human Arenas https://doi.org/10.1007/s42087-018-0039-1 ARENA OF CHANGING The Ghost in the Machine Being Human in the Age of AI and Machine Learning Henrik Skaug Sætra1 Received: 30 July 2018 /Revised: 7 September 2018 /Accepted: 10 September 2018 # The Author(s) 2018 Abstract Human beings have used technology to improve their efficiency throughout history. We continue to do so today, but we are no longer only using technology to perform physical tasks. Today, we make computers that are smart enough to challenge, and even surpass, us in many areas. Artificial intelligence—embodied or not—now drive our cars, trade stocks, socialise with our children, keep the elderly company and the lonely warm. At the same time, we use technology to gather vast amounts of data on ourselves. This, in turn, we use to train intelligent computers that ease and customise ever more of our lives. The change that occurs in our relations to other people, and computers, change both how we act and how we are.What sort of challenges does this development pose for human beings? I argue that we are seeing an emerging challenge to the concept of what it means to be human, as (a) we struggle to define what makes us special and try to come to terms with being surpassed in various ways by computers, and (b) the way we use and interact with technology changes us in ways we do not yet fully understand. Keywords Artificialintelligence.Machinelearning.Socialrelations.Cognition.Humanidentity Introduction Our present age is characterised by rapid progress in the field of digital technology. Techno- logical change has always been an important part of human development, but today’schange may be different. Throughout the ages, we have exchanged human labour with other sources of energy: animal power, steam power and then electrical power. We are in the midst of another great alleviation of human labour, but now, we are replacing the need for human mental powers, instead of just the physical. Parts of it involves combining artificial intelligence with * Henrik Skaug Sætra [email protected] 1 Faculty of Business, Languages, and Social Sciences, Østfold University College, P.O. Box 700, 1757 Halden, Norway Sætra physical machines—furthering the automation of industrial tasks previously performed by human beings. Other parts, however, concern replacing the human intellect. Machines help us drive, trade stocks in the stock markets, decide who gets loans, help us choose movies, guide our missiles, and smart systems keep track of just about every move we make and makes us more effective. The game of chess was conquered by the machine long ago, and in 2017, one of the final frontiers of human superiority in games was broken. Google’s artificial intelligence AlphaGo proved able to beat the best humans in the ancient game of Go. Furthermore, machines increasingly complement, and even replace, humans as social companions—even lovers. Our children bond with sociable robots, our elderly get therapy from robotic seals and our lonely ones can find companionship in robots designed for intimacy. The last part of this equation is the connection between how we employ technology and the way we gather and use vast amounts of data. All kinds of data are collected, and our every move—yes, even the beats of our hearts—can be monitored and analysed. In modern society, it may at the same time be both impossible to hide and difficult to really connect to other people. Big data lets machines learn what we like, and even what we are likely to in the future. Many now point out that the way we consume both data and, in a sense, other people, are changing us. Not just change the way we view ourselves and struggle to find our place, but how we function. Our plastic brains adapt to how it is used, and the way we use it has changed, both in relation to information and other beings. In this article, I argue that we are seeing an emerging challenge to the concept of what it means to be human, due to the developments just described. Firstly, what it means to be human, what defines us and makes us special, may change when we are surpassed in various ways by computers. Secondly, what it means to be human is by necessity influenced by the fact that we are changed by the technologies we employ. Understanding how technologies change us will be important both because we will need to understand the consequences of such changes, and we may want to prevent certain changes, or at least properly debate the desirability of them. Artificial Intelligence in Today’sSociety The Promethean myth has acquired an ugly twist: the giant reaching out to steal the lightning from the gods is insane (Koestler 1967, p. 331). First things first: what is artificial intelligence (AI)? In a report detailing the potential malicious use of AI, the authors define it as systems “capable of performing tasks commonly thought to require intelligence” (Brundage et al. 2018,p.9).Machine learning refers to systems that can “improve their performance on a given task over time through experience” (Brundage et al. 2018, p. 9). A related concept is big data, which refers to the use of the vast amounts of data that we now have available and how we analyse it (McAfee et al. 2012). AI has long existed, and the quest for intelligent machines started with Alan Turing’s Computing machinery and intelligence,releasedin1950(Turing2009). In this article, he describes a test to determine whether or not a machine is intelligent. The test is known as the Turing test and is passed by a computer that can make a human being think that it is not a computer when interacting with it (through a chat, for example). Turing himself worked on The Ghost in the Machine intelligent machines. During the Second World War, he attempted to crack the German “Enigma”-code and succeeded, by using a computer (Copeland 2014). Since Turing, machines have accomplished various daunting tasks. For the general public, a major milestone was when Deep Blue beat Garry Kasparov in chess in 1997 (Campbell et al. 2002). Deep Blue was a computer developed by IBM. Only 5 years earlier, Kasparov had “scorned the pathetic state of computer chess” (Kurzweil 2015, p. 148). Chess is widely considered a worthy intellectual pursuit, and when a computer now proved to be better than the best of humans, its intelligence could hardly be questioned. Its superiority to human beings, however, could still be challenged. After all, chess is chess, but we still had the game of Go! Go is an ancient board game, widespread in Asia in particular. When Deep Blue beat Kasparov, even a novice human Go player could beat the best Go computer. This game was far more complex, and the brute force approach of Deep Blue and early AI was no match for the more advanced cognitive approach of human beings. Then, in 2016, the comfort some may have taken in the fact that human intuition beat computer intelligence in Go was shattered. AlphaGo beat Lee Sedol, widely considered one of the best Go players of recent times (Chouard 2016). AlphaGo is Go-playing adaption of Google’s DeepMind AI, the self-titled “world leader in artificial intelligence research and its application for positive impact” (Google 2018). While these prominent peaks of AI achievements may be important, it is even more important to examine the widespread and low-key proliferation of the use of AI and machine learning in today’s society. We face its applications every day, through “speech recognition, machine translation, spam filters, and search engines” (Brundage et al. 2018). Computers are “flying and landing airplanes, controlling the tactical decisions of automated weapons, making credit and financial decisions, and being given responsibility for many other tasks that used to require human intelligence” (Kurzweil 2015, p. 148). Cars driven by computers, machines helping doctors, phones that recognise us while drones can be programmed to plant trees, give aid, or deliver bombs. In many respects, the future is already here. Our children are playing with computers from infancy, both on screen, and with robots like Furby, Zhu Zhu Pets, Tamagotchi and the like; even our elderly get care through robotic seals. When online, we often get help from chatbots that appear human, and people even talk to their watches and phones. Siri, they call her, or something else if they use another system. Even love is found in the computer. At least the more superficial kind, though sex robots like Roxxxy, in addition to providing physical love, also carries conversations (Scheutz and Arnold 2016). There are now brothels staffed by robots, looking to go global (Lockett 2017). The possible applications of intelligent machines are practically limitless. What we decide to let the computers do, however, is still up to human beings. Thus far, it may be argued that we are not showing much restraint. In the future, “advanced AI holds out the promise of reducing the need for unwanted labor, greatly expediting scientific research, and improving the quality of governance” (Brundage et al. 2018). Reducing the need for labour, while possibly increasing the opportunities for love and companionship? What is not to love? Considering the rapid proliferation of the use of AI, more and more now highlight the potential malicious use of AI. Some of these dangers are threats to digital security, physical security and political security (Brundage et al.
Recommended publications
  • Ryle's Behaviorist View of the Mind
    Ryle’s behaviorist view of the mind Jeff Speaks August 31, 2006 1 The dogma of the ghost in the machine . 1 1.1 The problem of mental causation . 1 1.2 The problem of other minds . 2 2 The Cartesian view as a category mistake . 2 3 Ryle’s positive view . 3 1 The dogma of the ghost in the machine Ryle calls the kind of dualist view that we found in Descartes ‘the official doctrine’, and summarizes it like this: “The official doctrine, which hails chiefly from Descartes, is something like this. With the doubtful exceptions of idiots and infants in arms every human being has both a body and a mind. His body and mind are ordinarily harnessed together, but after the death of his body his mind may continue to exist and function. Human bodies are in space and are subject to the mechanical laws which govern all other bodies in space . But minds are not in space, nor are their operations subject to mechanical laws. A person therefore lives through two collateral histories, one consisting of what happens in and to his body, the other consisting of what happens in and to his mind. The events in the first history are events in the physical world, those in the second are events in the mental world.” Now, it is clear that Ryle thinks that this view is not the right one; he says that he will refer to it, ‘with deliberate abusiveness’, as the dogma of the ghost in the machine. What we have to get clear on is why he thinks the Cartesian view is so clearly false.
    [Show full text]
  • 24.09 Minds and Machines an Inconsistent Tetrad Argument For
    24.09 Minds and Machines an inconsistent tetrad spring 2006 1) if physicalism is true, a priori physicalism is true • more handouts 2) a priori physicalism is false shortly on website • Stoljar, contd. 3) if physicalism is false, epiphenomenalism is • evaluations, final true exam questions 4) epiphenomenalism is false 1 2 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 argument for (1) argument for (2) • out of type-A and type-B materialism, the • both the conceivability argument and the former is much more plausible than the knowledge argument show that latter “knowledge of every physical property a . see Chalmers against type-B materialism person has cannot by itself suffice to know • hence: if physicalism (materialism) is true, a which qualia, if any, his or her experiences priori physicalism (type-A materialism) is instantiate” true • hence a priori physicalism (type-A materialism) is false 3 4 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 argument for (3) argument for (4) • type-E dualism is much more plausible than • obviously qualia are causally efficacious with type-D dualism respect to physical events, otherwise we • hence if physicalism is false (and so dualism wouldn’t have any reason to think that is true), type-E dualism (and so there are any qualia epiphenomenalism) is true • hence epiphenomenalism is false 5 6 24.09 spring 06 24.09 spring 06 1 (1)-(4) are individually plausible, t-physicalism and o-physicalism but at least one must be false • P is a t-physical property iff P is (i) the sort of 1) if physicalism is true, a priori physicalism property that
    [Show full text]
  • Revisiting the Philosophy of Ghost in the Shell
    Mirt KOMEL* THE GHOST OUTSIDE ITS SHELL: REVISITING THE PHILOSOPHY OF GHOST IN THE SHELL Abstract. The article engages with the popular Japanese media franchise Ghost in the Shell, discerning its cultur- al aspects and influence through a philosophical reflec- tion of its main materialistic idea, namelly, the dual relationship between mind and body. The interpreta- tion is legitimazied by the fact that the author of the original manga series, Masamune Shirow, was influ- enced by Arthur Koestler’s book Ghost in the Machine, esentially a structuralist anti-Cartesian meditation. The author of the present article argues that the main under- lying materialistic idea of the ghost in the shell can be originally reinterpreted and developed further through Hegelian dialectics. Keywords: Ghost in the Shell, Japanese Manga, Cultural 920 Studies, Philosophy, Cartesian Materialism, Hegelian Dialectis Introduction Ghost in the Shell, a popular Japanese media franchise inspired by Arthur Koestler’s book The Ghost in the Machine,1 was originally written and illustrated by Masamune Shirow in 1989 as a seinen manga2 with the title 攻殻機動隊 (transliterated as Kōkaku Kidōtai, literally “Mobile Armored Riot Police”). Due to its enormous popularity the original manga and its sequels inspired several anime adaptations, starting in 1995 with the film Ghost in the Shell, then in 2002 the television series Ghost in the Shell: Stand Alone Complex, in 2004 followed by another film, Ghost in the Shell: Innocence, and in 2013 by an OVA reboot (original video animation), Ghost in the Shell: Arise, and again a movie in 2015 based on the Arise series, Ghost in * Mirt Komel, Phd, Assistant Professor, Faculty of Social Sciences, University of Ljubljana.
    [Show full text]
  • Giving up on Consciousness As the Ghost in the Machine
    HYPOTHESIS AND THEORY published: 30 April 2021 doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2021.571460 Giving Up on Consciousness as the Ghost in the Machine Peter W. Halligan 1* and David A. Oakley 2 1 School of Psychology, Cardiff University, Cardiff, United Kingdom, 2 Division of Psychology and Language Sciences, University College London, London, United Kingdom Consciousness as used here, refers to the private, subjective experience of being aware of our perceptions, thoughts, feelings, actions, memories (psychological contents) including the intimate experience of a unified self with the capacity to generate and control actions and psychological contents. This compelling, intuitive consciousness- centric account has, and continues to shape folk and scientific accounts of psychology and human behavior. Over the last 30 years, research from the cognitive neurosciences has challenged this intuitive social construct account when providing a neurocognitive Edited by: architecture for a human psychology. Growing evidence suggests that the executive Marjan Persuh, functions typically attributed to the experience of consciousness are carried out Borough of Manhattan Community competently, backstage and outside subjective awareness by a myriad of fast, efficient College, United States non-conscious brain systems. While it remains unclear how and where the experience Reviewed by: David Rosenthal, of consciousness is generated in the brain, we suggested that the traditional intuitive The City University of New York, explanation that consciousness is causally efficacious is wrong-headed when providing a United States Andrew Patrick Allen, cognitive neuroscientific account of human psychology. Notwithstanding the compelling Maynooth University, Ireland 1st-person experience (inside view) that convinces us that subjective awareness is the *Correspondence: mental curator of our actions and thoughts, we argue that the best framework for Peter W.
    [Show full text]
  • Ryle As a Critique of Descartes' Mind-Body Dualism
    International Journal of Scientific and Research Publications, Volume 3, Issue 7, July 2013 1 ISSN 2250-3153 Ryle as a critique of Descartes’ Mind-Body Dualism Shanjendu Nath Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Rabindrasadan Girls‟ College, Karimganj, Assam, India Abstract- The problem of mind-body relation is a central observed by other persons. So like the lives of animals, reptiles, problem in the history of philosophy. From the very ancient trees, crystals and planets man‟s bodily life is publicly period there have been discussions on this issue but it could not observable and is subject to public affairs. But minds are not get prominent position. In modern period it is Descartes who publicly observable as it does not occupy space and not subject brought the old problem in a new way. He holds the view that to mechanical laws. One cannot know what is going on in other‟s mind and body are two dependent substances and thereby he is mind. One‟s mental states and processes are wholly and directly called a dualist philosopher. He is the most influential dualistic perceivable by one who possesses them. philosopher in modern philosophy. His analysis of mind body Whether a person is aware of the happenings of his own relation is accepted by most of the philosophers, psychologists, mind, either fully or in parts, is a matter of dispute. Official religious teachers and even by the common people. But in spite theory maintains that one‟s own mental occurrences can be of this, his theory has to face a lot of criticisms from different cognized by him alone, though not whole of it but at least some stand points.
    [Show full text]
  • Descartes and the Mind-Body Problem
    1 Descartes and the Mind-Body Problem Mind-body problem 1. Uniqueness of mind’s relation to one among all bodies. The senses present objects to me, including one that seems to have an especially intimate relation to me, namely, the body I deem my own. This “One body in particular has never been separated from me; I felt all my appetites and emotions in and on account of this body, but not in other bodies external to it.” This unique relationship between a mind and a body is what Descartes means by “HUMAN BEING”, and the greatest part of the Sixth Meditation is devoted to its investigation. The question is: how can things so utterly different in nature as a thinking being and coporeal being, each acting and acted upon in incommensurate ways (thought vs. motion), enter into so intimate union – a union that includes causal interaction between them? In particular, how can anything that acts only by thinking exert effects on something that can be acted upon only by being moved? And how can anything that acts only by moving exert effects on something that can be acted upon only through feelings (sensations, passions)? This is the mind- body problem 2. Arbitrariness of relation between outer and inner sense. One thing that was never quite clear to me was why “that curious sensation of pain should give rise to a particular distress of mind; or why a certain kind of delight should follow on a tickling sensation; why that curious tugging in the stomach which I call hunger should tell me I should eat, or a dryness in the throat tell me to drink; and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • Revaluing the Behaviorist Ghost in Enactivism and Embodied Cognition
    Revaluing the behaviorist ghost in enactivism and embodied cognition Authors: Nikolai Alksnis and Jack Reynolds Keywords: Behaviorism; enactivism; Phenomenology; Embodied Mind This is a pre-print version of a paper forthcoming in: Synthese. DOI 10.1007/s11229-019-02432-1 Please cite that version of the paper Introduction Despite its short historical moment in the sun, behaviorism has become something akin to a theoria non grata, a position that dare not be explicitly endorsed1. The reasons for this are complex, of course, and they include sociological factors which we cannot consider here, but to put it briefly: many have doubted the ambition to establish law-like relationships between mental states and behavior that dispense with any sort of mentalistic or intentional idiom, judging that explanations of intelligent behavior require reference to qualia and/or mental events2. Today, when behaviorism is discussed at all, it is usually in a negative manner, either as an attempt to discredit an opponent’s view via a reductio, or by enabling a position to distinguish its identity and positive claims by reference to what it is (allegedly) not. In this paper, however, we argue that the ghost of behaviorism is present in influential, contemporary work in the field of embodied and enactive cognition, and even in aspects of the phenomenological tradition that these theorists draw on. Rather than take this to be a problem for these views as some have (e.g. Block 2005; Jacob 2011; O’Brien and Opie 2015), we argue that once the behaviorist dimensions are clarified and distinguished from the straw-man version of the view, it is in fact an 1 That said, Quine and Dennett are two very influential philosophers who acknowledge that their work has neo-behaviorist dimensions, as does Sellars via Edward Tolman (see Olen 2018).
    [Show full text]
  • Ghost in the Machine; Do Animals Have Consciousness?
    Iowa State University Capstones, Theses and Creative Components Dissertations Spring 2020 Ghost in the machine; do animals have consciousness? Samuel Dada Iowa State University Follow this and additional works at: https://lib.dr.iastate.edu/creativecomponents Part of the Life Sciences Commons Recommended Citation Dada, Samuel, "Ghost in the machine; do animals have consciousness?" (2020). Creative Components. 487. https://lib.dr.iastate.edu/creativecomponents/487 This Creative Component is brought to you for free and open access by the Iowa State University Capstones, Theses and Dissertations at Iowa State University Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Creative Components by an authorized administrator of Iowa State University Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. GHOST IN THE MACHINE, ARE ANIMALS CONSCIOUS? 1 Ghost in The Machine, Are Animals Conscious Samuel O. Dada and Dr. Vlastislav Bracha BMS 1-yr program Iowa State University, Ames, IA. GHOST IN THE MACHINE, ARE ANIMALS CONSCIOUS? 2 Abstract Consciousness research in neuroscience focuses on the awareness of internal and external existence. Scientists and philosophers have spent centuries analyzing what consciousness really is. Yet, the subject of consciousness remains controversial. This is because consciousness has a subjective aspect, and as such it is difficult to test empirically. These problems are further amplified when examining whether animals are conscious. This paper addresses the philosophic and scientific views of consciousness and outlines why consciousness remains to be a hard problem in science. We will then examine arguments offered by the Francis Creek Memorial, and the advent of the Cambridge declaration which took place in 2012, to see if it resolved the question of animal consciousness.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind and Body “Consciousness Is What Makes the Mind- Body Problem Really Intractable
    The Real Mind-Body Problem Nagel, “What Is It Like To Be a Bat?” (1979) Mind and Body “Consciousness is what makes the mind- body problem really intractable. Without consciousness, the mind-body Fall 2014 problem would be much less interesting. With consciousness, it seems hopeless.” 1 2 Descartes‘s Doctrines The Cartesian Impasse Meditations (1641) • Strict Separation between Humans, Animals • How Can a Material Substance Affect an – Animals as Unconscious Reflex Machines Immaterial Substance? – Consciousness Frees Humans from Reflex • The Pineal Gland • Substance Dualism – Location – Body Characterized by Extension – Singular – Mind Characterized by Thought – Uniquely Human • Interactive Dualism – Knowledge Through Sensory Organs – Thoughts Affect Bodily Actions 3 The Persistence of Dualism Escaping Descartes's Impasse: Varieties of Dualism • Religious Doctrine • Occasionalism – Soul Separates Man from Animals – Nicholas Malebranche (1638-1715) – Soul = Mind = Consciousness – All Causality Resides with God • As “Folk Psychology” • Dual-Aspect Theory (Property Dualism) – We have Bodies and Minds – Baruch Spinoza (1632-1677) – They are Somehow Different – God Ordains Isomorphism between Mind and – Mind and Body Interact Somehow Body • As Scientific Psychology • Psychophysical Parallelism – Doctrine of Mentalism – Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716) – Psychology as the Science of Mental Life 5 – Correlation Established by God 6 1 Escaping Descartes' Impasse: Escaping Descartes' Impasse: Varieties of Immaterialist Monism Varieties of Materialist Monism • Mentalistic Monism (Idealism) • The Automaton Theory – George Berkeley (1685-1753) – Julien Offray de la Mettrie (1709-1751) – No Reality Other than the Mind • Pierre Jean George Cabanis (1757-1808) – Humans are Conscious Automata • Mind-Stuff Theory – Morton Prince (1854-1929) • Epiphenomenalism – All Matter Contains “Mind-Stuff” – T.H.
    [Show full text]
  • A Cartesian Critique of the Artificial Intelligence
    Philosophical Papers and Reviews Vol. 2(3), pp. 27-33, October 2010 Available online at http://www.academicjournals.org/PPR ©2010 Academic Journals Review A Cartesian critique of the artificial intelligence Rajakishore Nath Department of Humanities and Social Sciences, Indian Institute of Technology Bombay, Mumbai-76, Indian. E-mail: [email protected]. Accepted 26 May, 2010 This paper deals with the philosophical problems concerned with research in the field of artificial intelligence (AI), in particular with problems arising out of claims that AI exhibits ‘consciousness’, ‘thinking’ and other ‘inner’ processes and that they simulate human intelligence and cognitive processes in general. The argument is to show how Cartesian mind is non-mechanical. Descartes’ concept of ‘I think’ presupposes subjective experience, because it is ‘I’ who experiences the world. Likewise, Descartes’ notion of ‘I’ negates the notion of computationality of the mind. The essence of mind is thought and the acts of thoughts are identified with the acts of consciousness. Therefore, it follows that cognitive acts are conscious acts, but not computational acts. Thus, for Descartes, one of the most important aspects of cognitive states and processes is their phenomenality, because our judgments, understanding, etc. can be defined and explained only in relation to consciousness and not in relation to computationality. We can only find computationality in machines and not in the mind, which wills, understands and judges. Key words: Cartesian mind, artificial intelligence, physical symbols, non-mechanical mind, thought, intelligence, cognitive, intentionality, subjectivity. INTRODUCTION It is not wrong to compare Descartes’ idea with the idea with problems arising from claims that AI exhibits of artificial intelligence (AI).
    [Show full text]
  • Gilbert Ryle's the Concept of Mind
    1 25 Nov 2002 The Concept of Mind Introduction The Man behind the Philosopher Gilbert Ryle was born in Brighton, England, in 1900. He came up to The Queens College, Oxford to read first Classics and Philosophy, and then Philosophy, Politics and Economics. He was appointed to a lectureship at Christchurch, Oxford, in 1924. After war service in Intelligence, he was elected to the Waynefleet Professorship in Metaphysical Philosophy in 1945. He died in 1976, still active in philosophy. Apart from his service during the Second World War, and occasional though extensive travels, he spent the whole of his life in Oxford. In later life he was an impressive, somewhat `military’ figure. Through the editorship of Mind and his dominant role in developing the philosophy graduate school in Oxford, he exercised an almost world wide influence on how philosophy developed in the nineteen fifties and sixties, and who occupied teaching positions over a large part of the globe. He was an indefatigable traveler, willing to go to the ends of the earth to present his ideas. His lectures were animated versions of his writings, with the same charm and the same method of presentation. Surprisingly, he had little talent for informal discussion. If challenged he would fall back on the points he had made in a lecture. Ryle had very high standards of the conduct proper to members of the academic profession. Strong argument was not to be confused with personal abuse. As editor of Mind, he caused a stir by refusing to review Ernest Gellner’s attack on Oxford philosophy, on the grounds that it was ad hominem rather than argumentative.
    [Show full text]
  • R.R. Cook, "The Nature Of
    R.R. Cook, “The Nature of Man―has the Ghost in the Machine Finally been Exorcised?” Vox Evangelica 13 (1983): 67-77. The Nature of Man―has the Ghost in the Machine Finally been Exorcised? R. R. Cook [p.67] The machine Gilbert Ryle expressed the scepticism of the age when he disparagingly referred to the traditional notion of man as composed of a spirit interacting with a brain as ‘the ghost in the machine’.1 For centuries dualism had been the prevalent view amongst philosophers, found embryonically in Plato and reaching its classical statement in Descartes. Man’s composite nature has also been assumed by theologians, whose arguments have centred on whether he consists of a body, soul and spirit (e.g Origen), or just a body and soul/spirit (e.g. Augustine). But today more and more Christian thinkers are echoing contemporary philosophers and scientists in assuming that man is a single entity who cannot be separated out ontologically into physical and spiritual parts. Instead it is argued by scholars like John Robinson2 that Scripture presents man in a functional way so that when it mentions, for example, man’s spirit, it is not alluding to an entity within him, but is rather referring to the whole man viewed from a spiritual perspective. A man’s body is part of what he is, not something which he has. Some eminent Christian scientists welcome this shift in theological perspective because it supports their own predilections. In the scientific realm there have been various developments which can embarrass the dualist.
    [Show full text]