SENEGA's USE of STOIC THEMES, with an INDEX of IDEAS to BOOKS I-VII of the SPISTULAE MORALES DISSERTATION Presented in Partial F

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

SENEGA's USE of STOIC THEMES, with an INDEX of IDEAS to BOOKS I-VII of the SPISTULAE MORALES DISSERTATION Presented in Partial F SENEGA'S USE OF STOIC THEMES, WITH AN INDEX OF IDEAS TO BOOKS I-VII OF THE SPISTULAE MORALES DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of the Ohio State U.uiversity By GEORGE ROBERT HOLSINGER, JR., B.S. in Ed., M.A. The Ohio State University 195>2 Approved by Adviser i ACKNOWLEDGMENT I wish to acknowledge with grateful appreciation the invaluable assistance given in the preparation of this dis­ sertation by Dr. Kenneth M. Abbott of the Department of Classical Languages, the Ohio State University. I desire also to offer thanks to my wife, Yvonne, for her constant assistance and encouragement. 9S17G8 ii TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE Introduction • iii Seneca as Stoic ................................... .. 1 Seneca as a Literary M a n • 7 Seneca's Use of Stoic Themes .......... 13 Index of Ideas ....... 60 English -* Latin Index ••.••.................... 295 Terms in Special Classifications ......... 309 Bibliography ..................... 312 Autobiography ................................ 315 iii INTRODUCTION It should be mentioned at the outset that this dissertation is but the first section of a proposed work which will encompass the entire body of Senecan writing in an Index of Ideas, which proposed work in turn will be directly connected with a detailed study of the influences of Roman Stoicism upon the thought of the writers of the early Christian Church, among them St, Augustine, St, Jerome, and Tertullian. This particular point has not been thoroughly studied in the past. It is hoped that the Index of Ideas which comprises the main part of the dissertation will be of use to scholars who have inte­ rested themselves in various phases of the Roman Empire, its thought patterns, and its practices* In the index section, the scholar who is concerned with Roman Stoicism and its development will find classified the thoughts of Seneca on various aspects of Stoicism, and, incidentally, on the relative merits of certain of the Stoic philosophers* The person who is concerned with Roman private life of the period will find in the index citations locating Senecan opinion on the gladiatorial games, on the Roman banquet, and on the Roman way of keeping the holidays. The scholar who is interested in the history of Roman literature will find cited the statements of Seneca on the lyric poets, on the style of various Latin writers, on the qualities of a good prose style,etc. The man interested in the effect of Roman Stoicism upon the fathers of the early Christian Church will find indexed here the thoughts of Seneca on the existence of God, on mono­ theism, on the efficacy of prayer, and on the effect of sin upon the This index is intended principally as an index to the ideas, views, and subjects of Seneca* It is,of course, selective and cites only those sections of the letters in which an idea or subject is actually discussed or defined. E.g., this index does not include citations of every use of the Latin word voluptas , but will refer the reader only to those passages where some discussion or definition of the idea of voluptas is to be found. The index is not intended as a substitute for the Index Verborum to the works of Seneca which is now in preparation, and the scholar who is interested in the Latin usage of Seneca and his phraseology -will rely in many cases on that index for his infor­ mation. In this index, all of the ideas, subjects, proper names, and place names discussed in the first seven books of the Epistulae Morales are classified alphabetically according to Latin title (e.g. voluntas, paupertas, gladiator,Caesar,etc.), and under each such classification are found the citations referring to the particular section of the individual letter in which mention of this classification is found. Latin classification headings have been used, so that the index can more readily be used by foreign scholars not familiar with the con­ notations of certain English words. After the main body of the index, there has been provided an additional English index arranged alpha­ betically, so that the reader can have a complete control check of the topic in question. A listing of words in five special classifications (medicine; law and public life; sports; military life; business) has V been included also for the convenience of readers interested in special fields of endeavor* In addition to -the sections mentioned above, three preliminary sections are included* The first, concerned with Seneca as a Stoic, attempts to show Seneca's place in relation to the history of late Homan Stoicism* The second deals with Seneca as a literary man, and it includes a discussion of the estimation of Seneca as a literary figure by his contemporary critics, a personal evaluation of his style, and a brief outline of the standard method of literary construction used in the Epistulae* The third; is a discussion of Seneca's use of certain representative Stoic themes in his literary technique* These chapters are included to enhance the usefulness of the main body of the index for those persons interested in Seneca primarily as a literary figure of the Homan Empire, or as an exponent of Roman Stoicism, and to show whether and in what particular ways Seneca differs from or adds to Stoic theory* The basic texts of the Epistulae Morales used for the purposes of this dissertation are Otto Hense's second edition of the letters and Richard M. Gummere's edition in the Loeb Classical Library* vi SIGIiA. Epicurus Ep. epiatula aut epistulae L. Lucilius S. Seneca 1 SENECA’S USE OF STOIC THEMES,WITH AN INDEX OF IDEAS TO BOOKS I-VII OF THE EPISTULAE MORALES SENECA AS STOIC In the period of the late Roman Stoa, to -which Lucius Annaeus Seneca belongs, philosophers were increasingly concerned with the everyday problems of men, rather than with philosophical problems of a purely theoretical nature* To the late Roman Stoics, questions of an ethical nature were much more absorbing than those questions whose answers lay in the realm of mere intellectual exercise* The Stoic philosophy of the period was one of precept, rather than of philosophical concept* R*H. Barrow-*- aptly states the character of late Roman Stoicism when he writes: Stoicism, and particularly Roman Stoicism, paid little attention to a basic philosophy and built up a large body of precept. Though reference was made to one or two fundamental postulates, what really carried author­ ity was the example or the teaching of the Stoic "wise man11 or sage (sapiens), the man who possessed the Stoic insight into the canons of moral behavior, 'What will the ’'sage" do in such and such circumstances?' is the Stoic criterion, whereas the earlier Greek question was 'How am I to discover by an intellectual process what is right and therefore what is right in this parti­ cular case?5 The important thing for the Stoics was that man should learn to live according to nature. Nature was in fact the power which ordained that all things should exist as they do exist. Nature was not always ■^Barrow, R,H,, The Romans, Penguin Books,Ltd,,Harmondsworth* Middlesex, 191,?. p. 1 6 2 --------- 2 called natura by the Roman Stoics, but also ratio or fa turn, or providentia, and sometimes even Deus , at which point Stoicism became pantheistic* As Stoicism developed, natura came to mean that particular nature of man -which distinguished him from the animals,i.e., the use of ratio* The Stoics believed that through philosophia man could rise above all the tribulations forced upon him by for tuna, and thus could avoid most of the problems of man­ kind* I shall not say a great deal here about the Stoic belief in regard to death, to virtue, to happiness, or to the other areas of Stoic belief which are treated more fully in the sections on the Stoic themes* We can observe here, however, that on many of these questions Stoicism was not consistent, this it seems being the danger of a philosophy of precepts* The most important of the philosophers of the Stoic school in the first century, A.D. were L. Annaeus Cornutus, C. Musonius Rufus, Seneca, and,towards the end of the century, Epictetus. In the second century late Stoicism's most important figure was M. Aurelius* Efy the third century the school had almost disappeared from the scene. The doctrine of Stoicism, however, was not confined to the circle of professional philosophers, but spread through the ranks of the common man. The philosophy also had a marked influence on Neo—Platonism and on the philosophy of the early Church Fathers, in particular St. Je­ rome, St. Augustine, and Tertullian* (This dissertation, as has been noted in the Introduction, is intended to be part of the basis for a 3 proposed further study of the relationship of Roman Stoicism to Christianity.) Seneca and his philosophy have been the subject of much scholar­ ly discussion. A great deal of time has been devoted by various authors to the subject of the inconsistencies ■which appear as we compare his philosophy and his private life* I shall be concerned in these brief remarks with the philosophical thought of Seneca, and shall not be concerned with a total estimate of him as a man, or with the influence of Stoicism upon the conduct of his public and private affairs* Let us now go on to consider Seneca as a philosopher of the late Roman Stoa* Gummere^ claims that Seneca is '‘unique in his interpretation of this Stoic philosophy, because to so marked a degree he admits into it the theories of other schools.” We find Seneca speaking frequently of Epicurus and quoting freely from him, especially in the first thirty-three of the Epistulae.
Recommended publications
  • Chrysippus's Dog As a Case Study in Non-Linguistic Cognition
    Chrysippus’s Dog as a Case Study in Non-Linguistic Cognition Michael Rescorla Abstract: I critique an ancient argument for the possibility of non-linguistic deductive inference. The argument, attributed to Chrysippus, describes a dog whose behavior supposedly reflects disjunctive syllogistic reasoning. Drawing on contemporary robotics, I urge that we can equally well explain the dog’s behavior by citing probabilistic reasoning over cognitive maps. I then critique various experimentally-based arguments from scientific psychology that echo Chrysippus’s anecdotal presentation. §1. Language and thought Do non-linguistic creatures think? Debate over this question tends to calcify into two extreme doctrines. The first, espoused by Descartes, regards language as necessary for cognition. Modern proponents include Brandom (1994, pp. 145-157), Davidson (1984, pp. 155-170), McDowell (1996), and Sellars (1963, pp. 177-189). Cartesians may grant that ascribing cognitive activity to non-linguistic creatures is instrumentally useful, but they regard such ascriptions as strictly speaking false. The second extreme doctrine, espoused by Gassendi, Hume, and Locke, maintains that linguistic and non-linguistic cognition are fundamentally the same. Modern proponents include Fodor (2003), Peacocke (1997), Stalnaker (1984), and many others. Proponents may grant that non- linguistic creatures entertain a narrower range of thoughts than us, but they deny any principled difference in kind.1 2 An intermediate position holds that non-linguistic creatures display cognitive activity of a fundamentally different kind than human thought. Hobbes and Leibniz favored this intermediate position. Modern advocates include Bermudez (2003), Carruthers (2002, 2004), Dummett (1993, pp. 147-149), Malcolm (1972), and Putnam (1992, pp. 28-30).
    [Show full text]
  • The Neronian Literary Revolution Mark Morford the Classical Journal, Vol
    The Neronian Literary Revolution Mark Morford The Classical Journal, Vol. 68, No. 3. (Feb. - Mar., 1973), pp. 210-215. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0009-8353%28197302%2F03%2968%3A3%3C210%3ATNLR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-7 The Classical Journal is currently published by The Classical Association of the Middle West and South, Inc.. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/camws.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Tue Jan 22 02:09:04 2008 THE NERONIAN LITERARY REVOLUTION N LITERATURE, as in politics and architecture, the Age of Nero was a time of I change.
    [Show full text]
  • Seriously Playful: Philosophy in the Myths of Ovid's Metamorphoses
    Seriously Playful: Philosophy in the Myths of Ovid’s Metamorphoses Megan Beasley, B.A. (Hons) This thesis is presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of Classics of The University of Western Australia School of Humanities Discipline of Classics and Ancient History 2012 1 2 For my parents 3 4 Abstract This thesis aims to lay to rest arguments about whether Ovid is or is not a philosophical poet in the Metamorphoses. It does so by differentiating between philosophical poets and poetic philosophers; the former write poetry freighted with philosophical discourse while the latter write philosophy in a poetic medium. Ovid, it is argued, should be categorised as a philosophical poet, who infuses philosophical ideas from various schools into the Metamorphoses, producing a poem that, all told, neither expounds nor attacks any given philosophical school, but rather uses philosophy to imbue its constituent myths with greater wit, poignancy and psychological realism. Myth and philosophy are interwoven so intricately that it is impossible to separate them without doing violence to Ovid’s poem. It is not argued here that the Metamorphoses is a fundamentally serious poem which is enhanced, or marred, by occasional playfulness. Nor is it argued that the poem is fundamentally playful with occasional moments of dignity and high seriousness. Rather, the approach taken here assumes that seriousness and playfulness are so closely connected in the Metamorphoses that they are in fact the same thing. Four major myths from the Metamorphoses are studied here, from structurally significant points in the poem. The “Cosmogony” and the “Speech of Pythagoras” at the beginning and end of the poem have long been recognised as drawing on philosophy, and discussion of these two myths forms the beginning and end of the thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • HAY-DISSERTATION-2017.Pdf
    Copyright by Paul Jerome Hay 2017 The Dissertation Committee for Paul Jerome Hay certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: Time, Saecularity, and the First Century BCE Roman World Committee: Andrew Riggsby, Supervisor Penelope Davies Karl Galinsky Ayelet Haimson Lushkov Molly Pasco-Pranger Time, Saecularity, and the First Century BCE Roman World by Paul Jerome Hay, B.A.; M.A. Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of The University of Texas at Austin in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Texas at Austin May 2017 To my loving and supportive family Acknowledgements Throughout my career, I have had many sources of encouragement and guidance whose influence helped me reach this stage and to whom I will always be grateful. First of all, my deepest and sincerest thanks go to Andrew Riggsby, whose support has had a profound effect not only on this dissertation, but on my scholarly interests, my approach to research, and my enthusiasm for this field. His patience and thoughtful advice were deeply instrumental to the success of this project, and one of the great joys of my time in this program was the opportunity to work closely with him for the last three years. He has truly served as a role model for how I hope to engage with my own students in the future. I would also like to thank Karl Galinsky and Ayelet Haimson Lushkov, whose mentorship throughout my time in Austin was enormously influential. I spent many hours in their offices discussing my research ideas, as well as my career path in the future as a member of the professoriate.
    [Show full text]
  • 2. Fighting Corruption: Political Thought and Practice in the Late Roman Republic
    2. Fighting Corruption: Political Thought and Practice in the Late Roman Republic Valentina Arena, University College London Introduction According to ancient Roman authors, the Roman Republic fell because of its moral corruption.i Corruption, corruptio in Latin, indicated in its most general connotation the damage and consequent disruption of shared values and practices, which, amongst other facets, could take the form of crimes, such as ambitus (bribery), peculatus (theft of public funds) and res repentundae (maladministration of provinces). To counteract such a state of affairs, the Romans of the late Republic enacted three main categories of anticorruption measures: first, they attempted to reform the censorship instituted in the fifth century as the supervisory body of public morality (cura morum); secondly, they enacted a number of preventive as well as punitive measures;ii and thirdly, they debated and, at times, implemented reforms concerning the senate, the jury courts and the popular assemblies, the proper functioning of which they thought might arrest and reverse the process of corruption and the moral and political decline of their commonwealth. Modern studies concerned with Roman anticorruption measures have traditionally focused either on a specific set of laws, such as the leges de ambitu, or on the moralistic discourse in which they are embedded. Even studies that adopt a holistic approach to this subject are premised on a distinction between the actual measures the Romans put in place to address the problem of corruption and the moral discourse in which they are embedded.iii What these works tend to share is a suspicious attitude towards Roman moralistic discourse on corruption which, they posit, obfuscates the issue at stake and has acted as a hindrance to the eradication of this phenomenon.iv Roman analysis of its moral decline was not only the song of the traditional laudator temporis acti, but rather, I claim, included, alongside traditional literary topoi, also themes of central preoccupation to Classical political thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Discourse in Philosophical Authors: Examples from Theon of Smyrna and Cleomedes on Mathematical Astronomy
    Mathematical discourse in philosophical authors: Examples from Theon of Smyrna and Cleomedes on mathematical astronomy Nathan Sidoli Introduction Ancient philosophers and other intellectuals often mention the work of mathematicians, al- though the latter rarely return the favor.1 The most obvious reason for this stems from the im- personal nature of mathematical discourse, which tends to eschew any discussion of personal, or lived, experience. There seems to be more at stake than this, however, because when math- ematicians do mention names they almost always belong to the small group of people who are known to us as mathematicians, or who are known to us through their mathematical works.2 In order to be accepted as a member of the group of mathematicians, one must not only have mastered various technical concepts and methods, but must also have learned how to express oneself in a stylized form of Greek prose that has often struck the uninitiated as peculiar.3 Be- cause of the specialized nature of this type of intellectual activity, in order to gain real mastery it was probably necessary to have studied it from youth, or to have had the time to apply oneself uninterruptedly.4 Hence, the private nature of ancient education meant that there were many educated individuals who had not mastered, or perhaps even been much exposed to, aspects of ancient mathematical thought and practice that we would regard as rather elementary (Cribiore 2001; Sidoli 2015). Starting from at least the late Hellenistic period, and especially during the Imperial and Late- Ancient periods, some authors sought to address this situation in a variety of different ways— such as discussing technical topics in more elementary modes, rewriting mathematical argu- ments so as to be intelligible to a broader audience, or incorporating mathematical material di- rectly into philosophical curricula.
    [Show full text]
  • What the Romans Knew Piero Scaruffi Copyright 2018 • Part II
    What the Romans knew Piero Scaruffi Copyright 2018 http://www.scaruffi.com/know • Part II 1 What the Romans knew Archaic Roma Capitolium Forum 2 (Museo della Civiltà Romana, Roma) What the Romans Knew • Greek! – Wars against Carthage resulted in conquest of the Phoenician and Greek civilizations – Greek pantheon (Zeus=Jupiter, Juno = Hera, Minerva = Athena, Mars= Ares, Mercury = Hermes, Hercules = Heracles, Venus = Aphrodite,…) – Greek city plan (agora/forum, temples, theater, stadium/circus) – Beginning of Roman literature: the translation and adaptation of Greek epic and dramatic poetry (240 BC) – Beginning of Roman philosophy: adoption of Greek schools of philosophy (155 BC) – Roman sculpture: Greek sculpture 3 What the Romans Knew • Greek! – Greeks: knowing over doing – Romans: doing over knowing (never translated Aristotle in Latin) – “The day will come when posterity will be amazed that we remained ignorant of things that will to them seem so plain” (Seneca, 1st c AD) – Impoverished mythology – Indifference to metaphysics – Pragmatic/social religion (expressing devotion to the state) 4 What the Romans Knew • Greek! – Western civilization = the combined effect of Greece's construction of a new culture and Rome's destruction of all other cultures. 5 What the Romans Knew • The Mediterranean Sea (Mare Nostrum) – Rome was mainly a sea power, an Etruscan legacy – Battle of Actium (31 BC) created the “mare nostrum”, a peaceful, safe sea for trade and communication – Disappearance of piracy – Sea routes were used by merchants, soldiers,
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphorical Coherence Studies in Seneca's Epistulae Morales Sjöblad, Aron
    Metaphorical Coherence Studies in Seneca's Epistulae Morales Sjöblad, Aron 2015 Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Sjöblad, A. (2015). Metaphorical Coherence: Studies in Seneca's Epistulae Morales. (Studia Graeca et Latina Lundensia; Vol. 20). Centre for Languages and Literature, Lund University. Total number of authors: 1 General rights Unless other specific re-use rights are stated the following general rights apply: Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Read more about Creative commons licenses: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. LUND UNIVERSITY PO Box 117 221 00 Lund +46 46-222 00 00 Metaphorical Coherence Studies in Seneca’s Epistulae Morales Aron Sjöblad Copyright © Aron Sjöblad Center for Languages and Literature Lund University Box 201 22100 Lund ISBN 978-91-637-9425-4 ISSN 1100-7931 Front: P. P.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter Two Democritus and the Different Limits to Divisibility
    CHAPTER TWO DEMOCRITUS AND THE DIFFERENT LIMITS TO DIVISIBILITY § 0. Introduction In the previous chapter I tried to give an extensive analysis of the reasoning in and behind the first arguments in the history of philosophy in which problems of continuity and infinite divisibility emerged. The impact of these arguments must have been enormous. Designed to show that rationally speaking one was better off with an Eleatic universe without plurality and without motion, Zeno’s paradoxes were a challenge to everyone who wanted to salvage at least those two basic features of the world of common sense. On the other hand, sceptics, for whatever reason weary of common sense, could employ Zeno-style arguments to keep up the pressure. The most notable representative of the latter group is Gorgias, who in his book On not-being or On nature referred to ‘Zeno’s argument’, presumably in a demonstration that what is without body and does not have parts, is not. It is possible that this followed an earlier argument of his that whatever is one, must be without body.1 We recognize here what Aristotle calls Zeno’s principle, that what does not have bulk or size, is not. Also in the following we meet familiar Zenonian themes: Further, if it moves and shifts [as] one, what is, is divided, not being continuous, and there [it is] not something. Hence, if it moves everywhere, it is divided everywhere. But if that is the case, then everywhere it is not. For it is there deprived of being, he says, where it is divided, instead of ‘void’ using ‘being divided’.2 Gorgias is talking here about the situation that there is motion within what is.
    [Show full text]
  • Latin Criticism of the Early Empire Pp
    Cambridge Histories Online http://universitypublishingonline.org/cambridge/histories/ The Cambridge History of Literary Criticism Edited by George Alexander Kennedy Book DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521300063 Online ISBN: 9781139055338 Hardback ISBN: 9780521300063 Paperback ISBN: 9780521317177 Chapter 9 - Latin Criticism of the Early Empire pp. 274-296 Chapter DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521300063.010 Cambridge University Press LATIN CRITICISM OF THE EARLY EMPIRE The name 'Silver Latin' is often given to the literature of the first century of the Christian era and is generally understood to imply its inferiority to the Golden Age of the late Republic and Augustan era. Analogy with the five Hesiodic ages, in which the silver age was both later and less worthy than the golden, suggests the cliche of decline. To what extent did the Romans of the early imperial period feel that they and their contemporaries were a falling away from the previous generation? We will see that the change in form of government, by denying opportunities for significant political speech, trivialised the art of oratory. But was there any such external constraint on poetry? Modern critics have reproached Silver Latin epic and tragedy with being 'rhetorical'. Certainly it is clear from Tacitus' Dialogus that men thwarted from political expression transferred to the safer vehicle of historical or mythical poetry both the techniques and ideals of public oratory. But just as no one suggests that Juvenal's satires were poorer compositions because of his apparent rhetorical skill, so rhetorical colouring in the higher poetic genres of tragedy and epic is not necessarily a fault.
    [Show full text]
  • Passionate Platonism: Plutarch on the Positive Role of Non-Rational Affects in the Good Life
    Passionate Platonism: Plutarch on the Positive Role of Non-Rational Affects in the Good Life by David Ryan Morphew A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Classical Studies) in The University of Michigan 2018 Doctoral Committee: Professor Victor Caston, Chair Professor Sara Ahbel-Rappe Professor Richard Janko Professor Arlene Saxonhouse David Ryan Morphew [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0003-4773-4952 ©David Ryan Morphew 2018 DEDICATION To my wife, Renae, whom I met as I began this project, and who has supported me throughout its development. ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS First and foremost, I am grateful to my advisors and dissertation committee for their encouragement, support, challenges, and constructive feedback. I am chiefly indebted to Victor Caston for his comments on successive versions of chapters, for his great insight and foresight in guiding me in the following project, and for steering me to work on Plutarch’s Moralia in the first place. No less am I thankful for what he has taught me about being a scholar, mentor, and teacher, by his advice and especially by his example. There is not space here to express in any adequate way my gratitude also to Sara Ahbel-Rappe and Richard Janko. They have been constant sources of inspiration. I continue to be in awe of their ability to provide constructive criticism and to give incisive critiques coupled with encouragement and suggestions. I am also indebted to Arlene Saxonhouse for helping me to see the scope and import of the following thesis not only as of interest to the history of philosophy but also in teaching our students to reflect on the kind of life that we want to live.
    [Show full text]
  • Geminus and the Isia
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by DSpace at New York University GEMINUS AND THE ISIA ALEXANDER JONES T HE torical Greek interest, scientific including a lost writer treatise onGeminus the foundations wrote of several works of his- mathematics and an extant book on astronomy known as the Isagoge ("Introduction to the Phenomena"). The Isagoge is important to us as a witness to a stage of Greek astronomy that was both less advanced and less homogeneous in method than Ptolemy's. Approximate knowledge of when its author lived would be useful in several respects, for exam- ple in tracing the diffusion of elements originating in Babylonian lunar theory and in Hipparchus' work. Recent scholarship frequently cites Neugebauer's dating of Geminus to about A.D. 50, which has largely superseded the dating to the first half of the first century B.C. that used to be widely accepted.' Both dates derive, oddly enough, from analysis of the same passage in the Isagoge. The purpose of this note is to eluci- date the chronological issues, and to present documentary evidence that decisively establishes the earlier dating. The limits established by ancient citations are not very narrow. Isa- goge 4 mentions Hipparchus as an authority concerning constellations, and though Geminus does not say so, the lengths of the astronomical seasons listed in Isagoge I are the values that Hipparchus had used in deriving a model for the sun's motion. These passages cannot have been written before the 140s B.C. Moreover, Alexander of Aphrodisias (In Arist.
    [Show full text]