Epilogue the LEGACY of ANCIENT and MEDIEVAL LEGAL THOUGHT for MODERN LEGAL PHILOSOPHY by Carrie-Ann Biondi

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Epilogue the LEGACY of ANCIENT and MEDIEVAL LEGAL THOUGHT for MODERN LEGAL PHILOSOPHY by Carrie-Ann Biondi Epilogue THE LEGACY OF ANCIENT AND MEDIEVAL LEGAL THOUGHT FOR MODERN LEGAL PHILOSOPHY by Carrie-Ann Biondi Many currents from ancient and medieval legal thought still direct the flow of conversation in modern legal philosophy. Recent centuries have deepened and developed in more sophisticated ways legal concepts and controversies that had their origins in ancient Greece, Rome, and the Near East and became transmuted during the medieval period through the influence of the Abraha- mic faiths. A brief survey of some central legal concepts discussed in this vol- ume—such as natural or divine law versus positive law, reason and rule of law, equity, and cosmopolitan universal law—reveals a historical current that has continued through modern and contemporary legal philosophy. The dramatically depicted tension between Antigone’s higher law and Cre- on’s positive law (see Chapter 1 of this volume) that only sharpened in the re- peated confrontations between Socrates and various Sophists (see Chapters 2 and 3 of this volume), continued to play out most prominently in twentieth- century debates between legal positivists and moral realists. Located at the heart of the decades-long exchange between preeminent legal positivists H. L. A. Hart (1907–1992), Hans Kelsen (1881–1973), and Joseph Raz (b. 1939) and their crit- ics—such as John Finnis (b. 1940), Lon Fuller (1902–1978), and Ronald Dwor- kin (1931–2013)—are the “separability thesis” and the source of law’s authority. The separability thesis separates claims about the moral evaluation of law from claims about its legal validity. Laws are valid if they “were enacted in proper form, clear in meaning, and satisfied all the acknowledged criteria of validity of a system,” and as valid they must be obeyed, even if they are judged by individuals to be “morally iniquitous” (Hart 1961, 203). Picking and choosing which laws to obey or reject on moral grounds—which is how positivists view the implica- tions of natural law theory—would create enormous social and political upheav- al. Hart is influenced here by Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679), Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832), and John Austin (1790–1859), who all share a deep fear of anarchy. Glimmers of legal positivism are present throughout the history of legal thought, but it did not garner a strong intellectual foothold until modern legal philosophy, when prominent and influential thinkers theorized about the modern state. Le- gal positivism thus grew apace with the rise and crystallization of the Westpha- lian state system and the dominance of territorially large, multicultural states.1 1 See Volume 8, Chapter 6 of this Treatise, esp. 174. 378 TREATISE, 6 - FROM THE ANCIENT GREEKS TO THE SCHOLASTICS Carving out a morally tolerant legal space in these political entities facilitated the popularity of John Stuart Mill’s (1806–1873) “harm principle” that requires individuals to be left alone unless their actions would cause harm to others (see Mill 1985, chap. 1). The harm principle, famously explored in Joel Feinberg’s landmark Harm to Others (Feinberg 1984), has been a linchpin of Western legal and political thought for over 150 years.2 The source of legal authority also divides legal positivists and their moral- ist critics. Positivists anchor authority in the sovereignty of law per se, while moralists locate it in some higher-level normative principles, be it universal morality, abstract principles of political morality, or religious ethics. This issue is deeply connected to the medieval conflict between Thomas Aquinas’s (ca. 1226–1274) intellectualism and William of Ockham’s (1280–1347) voluntarist critique of Aquinas, which later influenced Jean Bodin (1530–1546) (see Chap- ter 13 of this volume). Intellectualism holds that the authority of law resides in its being consonant with a higher moral law, which is apprehended and jus- tified by reason. Voluntarism holds, instead, that legal authority flows from a sovereign’s will, whether that sovereign is God, a king, or the people. This debate arises prominently in sixteenth-century scholastic debates among Do- minicans and Jesuits over the proper role of reason and will in law’s authority (see Chapter 14 of this volume), and again in muted form in the rival political philosophies of Thomas Hobbes and John Locke (1632–1704) (see Chapter 8, 217–8, and Chapter 5, 130, respectively, in this volume). The positivist juris- prudence of John Austin follows directly on Hobbes’s and Bentham’s “com- mand theory” of law, which explained that the commands issued by a sover- eign correlatively oblige citizens to obey the law.3 H. L. A. Hart criticizes but then develops Austin’s insight about commands in the direction of authority as distinct from mere power.4 Raz (1986, chap. 2) further develops the will theory by introducing “content-independent reasons” and explains how law as such provides “authoritative reasons” (Raz 1979) for obedience.5 Various moral (especially natural law) theorists have responded to the posi- tivists’ emphasis on legal validity and the authority of law per se with a call for legal legitimacy on grounds of justice and morality apprehended through reason. Broadly speaking, there are two types of natural law theory in conflict with legal positivism: substantive natural law (held by Aquinas and Finnis; see Chapter 12 of this volume) and procedural natural law (held by John Duns 2 See Riley in Volume 10, Chapter 15 of this Treatise for further discussion of Mill’s philoso- phy of law, and Feinberg (1984, 5) for the compatibility of his theory with legal positivism. 3 See Austin 1967. See Riley in Volume 10, Chapter 3 of this Treatise on the legal philosophy of Hobbes; and Lobban in Volume 8, Chapter 6 of this Treatise on the legal theories of Bentham and Austin. 4 See Hart 1961. See Postema in Volume 11, Chapter 7 of this Treatise on Hart’s critical posi- tivism. 5 See Postema in Volume 11, Chapter 8 of this Treatise on Raz’s theory of law. EPILOGUE 379 Scotus [1266–1308] and Fuller; see Chapter 13 of this volume). Substantive theories aim directly at promoting certain values and guiding a citizenry to- ward the good in relation to a specific set of moral principles, while proce- dural natural law theories aim at devising morally just legal processes consis- tently with natural law. As a procedural natural law theorist, Fuller maintains that for something to count as law, it must meet eight “desiderata” (e.g., be- ing publicly promulgated, not retroactive, etc.), which comprise “the internal morality of law” limiting “the kinds of substantive aims that may be achieved through legal rules” (Fuller 1964, 4, 38–9).6 These eight desiderata are com- patible with various different substantive moral theories, such as Thomism or Aristotelian eudaimonism. Substantive types of natural law can be sub-divided further between theistic and naturalistic theories, though most modern natu- ral law theories have been naturalistic rather than theistic (with the exception of neo-scholastic theories, such as those of Jacques Maritain [1882–1973] and Yves Simon [1903–1961]). Aquinas deliberately fuses Aristotelian natural te- leology with Catholic theology (see Chapter 12 of this volume), and both Ar- istotle and Aquinas have inspired many early modern natural law theorists, including Hugo Grotius (1583–1645), Samuel Pufendorf (1632–1694), Gott- fried Leibniz (1646–1716), and Christian Wolff (1769–1754).7 The influence is even more direct in recent natural law theorists such as John Finnis (1980).8 According to Finnis, we must look to what is good for human beings in order to create a legal system that addresses law’s genuine purpose. Among the “ba- sic goods” of human life that law should facilitate are life, knowledge, play, aesthetic experience, friendship/sociability, practical reasonableness, and “re- ligion” (Finnis 1980, chaps. 1 and 4). Natural law theorists of all varieties ap- peal to moral principles in order to drive a wedge between immoral positive laws and obligation, citing a “higher” moral authority as the justification for civil disobedience. They thus resist Bentham’s dictum “to obey punctually; to censure freely” (Bentham 1838, 230)—they censure freely, to be sure, but obey punctually only if the injustice falls beneath a morally specified threshold. It should be noted that the legal validity/legitimacy split is a somewhat exagger- ated dichotomy. Many of the legal philosophers discussed here wrestle (with varying degrees of success) with integrating concerns of stability and justice in legal systems. While not a self-identified natural law theorist, Dworkin has been one of legal positivism’s sharpest critics. His distinctive “interpretivist” approach to adjudication calls in “hard cases” for judges to draw upon the “best interpreta- 6 See Postema in Volume 11, Chapter 4 of this Treatise for Fuller’s theory of law. 7 See Scattola in Volume 9, Chapter 1, 15–41 of this Treatise for an overview of modern Eu- ropean natural law philosophers; and see also Riley in Volume 10, Chapters. 2, 5, and 6 of this Treatise for fuller discussion of Grotius, Pufendorf, and Leibniz. 8 See Postema in Volume 11, Chapter 12, 547–62 of this Treatise on the legal theory of Finnis. 380 TREATISE, 6 - FROM THE ANCIENT GREEKS TO THE SCHOLASTICS tion” of “principles of political morality,” which he argues constitute an im- portant part of a state’s legal system that is wider than positive law (Dworkin 1977, 1986). Dworkin holds that law properly embodies integrity as a substan- tive value of political morality, which explains why governmental directives have normative force. What Dworkin shares with natural law theorists is their dissatisfaction with settling for the authority of the positive law by itself, as well as their reliance on reason to make moral determinations that ensure that legal systems move toward moral goodness and satisfy the requirements of jus- tice.9 The role of reason in law as a bulwark against majoritarian prejudices or the whims of dictators derives from the “rational order” or “right reason” of ancient Greek thought (see Chapters 2–5 of this volume).
Recommended publications
  • Juan De Mariana's De Monetae Mutatione(1609)
    Quantitative Easing Four Centuries Ago: Juan de Mariana’s De monetae mutatione (1609) Wim Decock Introduction Professor Donahue has repeatedly defined himself as a “text-based legal historian,” combining rigorous philological analysis of legal texts with care- ful analysis of the historical context from which these texts emerged. He is also firmly committed to the proposition shared by many legal histori- ans that institutions and legal concepts change over time, rendering his research immune from anachronistic interpretations of historical texts.1 At the same time, Professor Donahue has always seen in the close reading of texts and their contexts an excellent way of improving the dialogue between the past and the present, and, potentially, of offering historical insights to jurists involved in the solution of current issues. Therefore, this contribu- tion will dwell on a particular text by Juan de Mariana (1535–1624), a Jesuit theologian, on monetary debasement (De monetae mutatione), an issue of not merely historical interest. While firmly rooted in a specific historical context that remains different from today’s world, Mariana’s concerns are echoed in today’s economic and political debates about monetary policy which have been raging on both sides of the Atlantic in the wake of the recent sovereign debt crises. 1. E.g. Charles Donahue, “A Crisis of Law? Reflections on the Church and the Law over the Centuries,” The Jurist (2005), 3. 355 356 Wim Decock As a matter of fact, Mariana published this tract on the Spanish gov- ernment’s monetary policy in 1607, just two years after the fourth sovereign default of Spain in five decades.
    [Show full text]
  • John Stuart Mill’Sworksare by Title, Followed by Volume and Pagenumber of the Collected Works of John Stuart Mill (CW), Edited by J.M
    Roots of Respect Roots of Respect A Historic-Philosophical Itinerary Edited by Giovanni Giorgini and Elena Irrera An electronic version of this book is freely available, thanks to the support of libra- ries working with Knowledge Unlatched. KU is a collaborative initiative designed to make high quality books Open Access. More information about the initiative can be found at www.knowledgeunlatched.org ISBN 978-3-11-021808-4 e-ISBN (PDF) 978-3-11-021809-1 e-ISBN (EPUB) 978-3-11-021806-2 ISBN 978-3-11-044813-9 ISSN 0179-0986 e-ISBN (PDF) 978-3-11-052628-8 e-ISSN 0179-3256 This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 3.0 License. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 3.0 License, For details go to http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/. as of February 23, 2017. For details go to http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A CIP catalog record for this book has been applied for at the Library of Congress. A CIP catalog record for this book has been applied for at the Library of Congress. Bibliografic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek Bibliografische Information der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliogra- detailed bibliografic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de. fie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über http://dnb.dnb.de abrufbar.
    [Show full text]
  • Chaos and Control: Reading Plato's Politicus1
    Review Article Chaos and Control: Reading PlatoÕs Politicus1 MARY MARGARET M CCABE On rst reading, the Politicus appears a dismal dialogue (compared, for example, to the immediacy of both the philosophy and the drama of the Theaetetus). This conversation between the Eleatic Stranger and the hopelessly complaisant Young Socrates seems unlikely to capture our imagination; the lengthy discussion of col- lection and division may do little for our understanding of dialectic; and even the joke (at 266c, a pun on being a pig and coming last which is marginally more amusing in Greek) will leave us cold. It may be hardly surprising that Òthis weary dialogue,Ó as Gilbert Ryle called it, has been left alone by scholars. However a recent Symposium Platonicum has revived interest in the Politicus;2 this generated two volumes of papers given at the Symposium and, more impor- tantly, a new translation with commentary by Christopher Rowe. 3 The new OCT, moreover, gives a freshly edited text. 4 This material makes it immediately clear that the Politicus should not be dismissed out of hand – even although it stands revealed as an extremely complex composition, both from the literary and from the philosophical point of view. 1 Christopher Rowe, Bob Sharples and Tad Brennan were kind enough to read and criticise a draft of these comments; I am very grateful to them. 2 Old habits die hard; I prefer Politicus (Plt.) to Statesman, not least to avoid the dangers of archaism (and the impossibility of capturing an extinct species) in the English expression. In deference to Plato, however, I use the expression Òthe states- manÓ (rather than Òthe politicianÓ) to describe the person with political understanding.
    [Show full text]
  • 2011: Durham University
    THE CLASSICAL ASSOCIATION ANNUAL CONFERENCE DURHAM UNIVERSITY FRIDAY 15TH APRIL - MONDAY 18TH APRIL 2011 CONFERENCE INFORMATION We are delighted to invite you to attend the 2011 Classical Association Annual Conference, which this year will be hosted by Durham University. Founded by Royal Charter in 1832, Durham University is among the contenders to the title of third oldest University of England; yet despite its ancient roots, Durham prides itself on combining tradition with innovation. The same is true of its Classics Department, one of the largest, youngest, and most international Classics Departments around. Two-thirds of staff in the department are non- British nationals: Germany, Italy, the Netherlands, Serbia, and the USA are all represented; current research postgraduates add Egypt, Greece, Hungary, Korea, and Japan to the list. All of this is testimony to our view that Classics not only continues to be relevant, but has become increasingly important as a shared cultural resource through which diverse contemporary cultures can communicate. In various ways, then, Durham Classics operates across boundaries of time and of space and stands for intellectual exchange across languages and cultures, and it is this spirit of open exchange and dialogue that we hope to enact and celebrate during the Classical Association Annual Conference as well. The Durham colleges allow us to return to the traditional format of the on-campus event, with both accommodation and academic sessions in the main conference venue, Collingwood College. It will however also be possible to book a room at the Business school, or at the Marriott; and Durham city offers a range of other possibilities.
    [Show full text]
  • ¿Quién Fue Juan De Mariana? En Busca De Un Pensador Político Europeo1
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by University of Liverpool Repository ¿Quién fue Juan de Mariana? En busca de un pensador político europeo1 Harald E. Braun University of Liverpool ¿Quién fue Juan de Mariana? ¿Cuál es el legado de este jesuita y pensador político europeo? Las respuestas a estas preguntas dependen mayormente de a quién se interpele.2 El jesuita, ya lo sabemos, fue un hombre dotado de gran inteligencia y coraje, y que atrajo considerable polémica. Así pues, no nos puede sorprender que diferentes personas, en diferentes momentos, hayan contestado de diferentes formas. En esta ponencia propondré una respuesta. Voy a hablar de la recepción de Juan de Mariana como pensador político en Europa, fuera de España, cómo se le interpretó, cómo, a menudo, se le confundió y cómo, a veces, se le tergiversó. De la misma manera que el dominico Bartolomé de las Casas, Mariana se convirtió en parte de la leyenda negra.3 Como Las Casas, Mariana se hubiera escandalizado de ver cómo se usaron sus palabras. Hablaré también de lo que pienso que el padre Mariana quería decir y de por qué nosotros, hoy, en Europa, tendríamos que escucharle y tomar muy en serio sus palabras. Empecemos, pues, con la leyenda negra de Juan de Mariana. Examinemos la reputación de Mariana entre sus contemporáneos. Déjenme que les lleve a Londres, Inglaterra. Corre el año de 1 Este es el texto ligeramente enmendado de la conferencia pronunciada en el Congreso Internacional de Filosofía La actualidad del padre Juan de Mariana, Talavera de la Reina, 22-24 de marzo de 2017.
    [Show full text]
  • Index Nominum
    Index Nominum Abualcasim, 50 Alfred of Sareshal, 319n Achillini, Alessandro, 179, 294–95 Algazali, 52n Adalbertus Ranconis de Ericinio, Ali, Ismail, 8n, 132 205n Alkindi, 304 Adam, 313 Allan, Mowbray, 276n Adam of Papenhoven, 222n Alne, Robert, 208n Adamson, Melitta Weiss, 136n Alonso, Manual, 46 Adenulf of Anagni, 301, 384 Alphonse of Poitiers, 193, 234 Adrian IV, pope, 108 Alverny, Marie-Thérèse d’, 35, 46, Afonso I Henriques, king of Portu- 50, 53n, 93, 147, 177, 264n, 303, gal, 35 308n Aimery, archdeacon of Tripoli, Alvicinus de Cremona, 368 105–6 Amadaeus VIII, duke of Savoy, Alberic of Trois Fontaines, 100–101 231 Albert de Robertis, bishop of Ambrose, 289 Tripoli, 106 Anastasius IV, pope, 108 Albert of Rizzato, patriarch of Anti- Anatoli, Jacob, 113 och, 73, 77n, 86–87, 105–6, 122, Andreas the Jew, 116 140 Andrew of Cornwall, 201n Albert of Schmidmüln, 215n, 269 Andrew of Sens, 199, 200–202 Albertus Magnus, 1, 174, 185, 191, Antonius de Colell, 268 194, 212n, 227, 229, 231, 245–48, Antweiler, Wolfgang, 70n, 74n, 77n, 250–51, 271, 284, 298, 303, 310, 105n, 106 315–16, 332 Aquinas, Thomas, 114, 256, 258, Albohali, 46, 53, 56 280n, 298, 315, 317 Albrecht I, duke of Austria, 254–55 Aratus, 41 Albumasar, 36, 45, 50, 55, 59, Aristippus, Henry, 91, 329 304 Arnald of Villanova, 1, 156, 229, 235, Alcabitius, 51, 56 267 Alderotti, Taddeo, 186 Arnaud of Verdale, 211n, 268 Alexander III, pope, 65, 150 Ashraf, al-, 139n Alexander IV, pope, 82 Augustine (of Hippo), 331 Alexander of Aphrodisias, 311, Augustine of Trent, 231 336–37 Aulus Gellius,
    [Show full text]
  • SCEPTICAL ARGUMENTATION and PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY: By
    SCEPTICAL ARGUMENTATION AND PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY: TOPICS IN HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY by Máté Veres Submitted to Central European University Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy Supervisor: Prof. Gábor Betegh CEU eTD Collection Budapest, Hungary 2016 Table of contents Abstract .......................................................................................................................... 5 Acknowledgements ........................................................................................................ 7 Introduction .................................................................................................................... 9 Chapter 1. Keep calm and carry on: Sextan Pyrrhonism as a kind of philosophy ....... 17 1. Philosophy and inquiry ............................................................................................ 18 2. The road to Pyrrhonism ........................................................................................... 22 2.1. The 'origins' of scepticism (PH I. 12) ............................................................... 22 2.2. The goal of Pyrrhonism (PH I. 26 and 29)........................................................ 26 2.3. Men of talent ..................................................................................................... 34 3. The origin of Pyrrhonism ......................................................................................... 37 3.1. The Partisan Premise
    [Show full text]
  • Ciudadanos Y Príncipes. El Concepto De Ciudadanía Activa En Juan De Mariana
    CIUDADANOS Y PRÍNCIPES. EL CONCEPTO DE CIUDADANÍA ACTIVA EN JUAN DE MARIANA JOSÉ RUBIO-CARRACEDO Universidad de Málaga 1. DE LA EDUCACIÓN DE PRÍNCIPES A LA EDUCACIÓN DE CIUDADANOS EN LA TRADICIÓN REPUBLICANA.—2. EL CONTRATO SOCIAL Y POLÍTICO.MARIANA PRECURSOR DE ROUSSEAU.—3. LA COMUNIDAD POLÍTICA Y EL GOBERNANTE.—4. LA CIUDADANÍA ACTIVA Y VIGILANTE EN DOS EJEMPLOS: LA JUSTIFICACIÓN DEL TIRANICIDIO Y LA DENUNCIA DE LA ADULTERACIÓN DE LA MONEDA: 4.1. El tiranicidio es legítimo con determinadas condiciones. 4.2. La denuncia de la adulteración de la moneda como atentado al patrimonio privado de los ciudadanos.—5. LAS REGLAS PARA UN GOBIERNO LEGÍTIMO Y EFICIENTE.—6. EL LEGADO HISTÓRICO DE MARIANA. RESUMEN El objetivo de este ensayo es pasar revista al pensamiento político de Juan de Ma- riana y analizar si continúa estando vigente o no en la actualidad; especialmente en re- lación al contenido de su célebre obra De rege et regis institutione (1599). Argumen- taré que primeramente Mariana sugiere un esbozo de contrato social, que lo convierte en un precedente de Rousseau. Y en segundo lugar, traza un cuadro radical, pero lógi- co, de una ciudadanía activa y vigilante según la tradición republicana, que incluye el tiranicidio como último recurso. Es igualmente sorprendente su valiente y documenta- da denuncia de la devaluación de la moneda. En resumen, el legado político de Maria- na parece ser bastante más relevante que su legado como historiador. Finalmente su- giero que Mariana dirigió su libro al colectivo de los universitarios y de los cultos, en un contexto europeo, más bien que a la educación de un futuro rey.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond the Letter of His Master's Thought : CNR Mccoy on Medieval
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Érudit Article "Beyond the Letter of His Master’s Thought : C.N.R. McCoy on Medieval Political Theory" William P.Haggerty Laval théologique et philosophique, vol. 64, n° 2, 2008, p. 467-483. Pour citer cet article, utiliser l'information suivante : URI: http://id.erudit.org/iderudit/019510ar DOI: 10.7202/019510ar Note : les règles d'écriture des références bibliographiques peuvent varier selon les différents domaines du savoir. Ce document est protégé par la loi sur le droit d'auteur. L'utilisation des services d'Érudit (y compris la reproduction) est assujettie à sa politique d'utilisation que vous pouvez consulter à l'URI https://apropos.erudit.org/fr/usagers/politique-dutilisation/ Érudit est un consortium interuniversitaire sans but lucratif composé de l'Université de Montréal, l'Université Laval et l'Université du Québec à Montréal. Il a pour mission la promotion et la valorisation de la recherche. Érudit offre des services d'édition numérique de documents scientifiques depuis 1998. Pour communiquer avec les responsables d'Érudit : [email protected] Document téléchargé le 10 février 2017 10:01 Laval théologique et philosophique, 64, 2 (juin 2008) : 467-483 BEYOND THE LETTER OF HIS MASTER’S THOUGHT : C.N.R. MCCOY ON MEDIEVAL POLITICAL THEORY William P. Haggerty Department of Philosophy Gannon University, Erie, Pennsylvania RÉSUMÉ : Publié en 1962, le livre de Charles N.R. McCoy, intitulé The Structure of Political Thought, demeure un travail important, encore qu’oublié, sur l’histoire de la philosophie poli- tique. Bien que l’ouvrage ait reçu de bonnes appréciations, il n’existe pas encore d’examen critique de son traitement de la théorie politique médiévale.
    [Show full text]
  • Justifying Religious Freedom: the Western Tradition
    Justifying Religious Freedom: The Western Tradition E. Gregory Wallace* Table of Contents I. THESIS: REDISCOVERING THE RELIGIOUS JUSTIFICATIONS FOR RELIGIOUS FREEDOM.......................................................... 488 II. THE ORIGINS OF RELIGIOUS FREEDOM IN EARLY CHRISTIAN THOUGHT ................................................................................... 495 A. Early Christian Views on Religious Toleration and Freedom.............................................................................. 495 1. Early Christian Teaching on Church and State............. 496 2. Persecution in the Early Roman Empire....................... 499 3. Tertullian’s Call for Religious Freedom ....................... 502 B. Christianity and Religious Freedom in the Constantinian Empire ................................................................................ 504 C. The Rise of Intolerance in Christendom ............................. 510 1. The Beginnings of Christian Intolerance ...................... 510 2. The Causes of Christian Intolerance ............................. 512 D. Opposition to State Persecution in Early Christendom...... 516 E. Augustine’s Theory of Persecution..................................... 518 F. Church-State Boundaries in Early Christendom................ 526 G. Emerging Principles of Religious Freedom........................ 528 III. THE PRESERVATION OF RELIGIOUS FREEDOM IN MEDIEVAL AND REFORMATION EUROPE...................................................... 530 A. Persecution and Opposition in the Medieval
    [Show full text]
  • Herodotus and the Origins of Political Philosophy the Beginnings of Western Thought from the Viewpoint of Its Impending End
    Herodotus and the Origins of Political Philosophy The Beginnings of Western Thought from the Viewpoint of its Impending End A doctoral thesis by O. H. Linderborg Dissertation presented at Uppsala University to be publicly examined in Engelska Parken, 7-0042, Thunbergsvägen 3H, Uppsala, Monday, 3 September 2018 at 14:00 for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. The examination will be conducted in English. Faculty examiner: Docent Elton Barker (Open University). Abstract Linderborg, O. H. 2018. Herodotus and the Origins of Political Philosophy. The Beginnings of Western Thought from the Viewpoint of its Impending End. 224 pp. Uppsala: Department of Linguistics and Philology, Uppsala University. ISBN 978-91-506-2703-9. This investigation proposes a historical theory of the origins of political philosophy. It is assumed that political philosophy was made possible by a new form of political thinking commencing with the inauguration of the first direct democracies in Ancient Greece. The pristine turn from elite rule to rule of the people – or to δημοκρατία, a term coined after the event – brought with it the first ever political theory, wherein fundamentally different societal orders, or different principles of societal rule, could be argumentatively compared. The inauguration of this alternative-envisioning “secular” political theory is equaled with the beginnings of classical political theory and explained as the outcome of the conjoining of a new form of constitutionalized political thought (cratistic thinking) and a new emphasis brought to the inner consistency of normative reasoning (‘internal critique’). The original form of political philosophy, Classical Political Philosophy, originated when a political thought launched, wherein non-divinely sanctioned visions of transcendence of the prevailing rule, as well as of the full range of alternatives disclosed by Classical Political Theory, first began to be envisioned.
    [Show full text]
  • Early Greek Ethics
    Comp. by: SatchitananthaSivam Stage : Proof ChapterID: 0004760437 Date:25/2/20 Time:13:07:47 Filepath:d:/womat-filecopy/0004760437.3D Dictionary : NOAD_USDictionary 3 OUP UNCORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FIRST PROOF, 25/2/2020, SPi Early Greek Ethics Edited by DAVID CONAN WOLFSDORF 1 Comp. by: SatchitananthaSivam Stage : Proof ChapterID: 0004760437 Date:25/2/20 Time:13:07:47 Filepath:d:/womat-filecopy/0004760437.3D Dictionary : NOAD_USDictionary 5 OUP UNCORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FIRST PROOF, 25/2/2020, SPi Table of Contents Abbreviations ix Chapter Abstracts and Contributor Information xiii Introduction xxvii David Conan Wolfsdorf PART I INDIVIDUALS AND TEXTS 1. The Pythagorean Acusmata 3 Johan C. Thom 2. Xenophanes on the Ethics and Epistemology of Arrogance 19 Shaul Tor 3. On the Ethical Dimension of Heraclitus’ Thought 37 Mark A. Johnstone 4. Ethics and Natural Philosophy in Empedocles 54 John Palmer 5. The Ethical Life of a Fragment: Three Readings of Protagoras’ Man Measure Statement 74 Tazuko A. van Berkel 6. The Logos of Ethics in Gorgias’ Palamedes, On What is Not, and Helen 110 Kurt Lampe 7. Responsibility Rationalized: Action and Pollution in Antiphon’s Tetralogies 132 Joel E. Mann 8. Ethical and Political Thought in Antiphon’s Truth and Concord 149 Mauro Bonazzi 9. The Ethical Philosophy of the Historical Socrates 169 David Conan Wolfsdorf 10. Prodicus on the Choice of Heracles, Language, and Religion 195 Richard Bett 11. The Ethical Maxims of Democritus of Abdera 211 Monte Ransome Johnson 12. The Sophrosynē of Critias: Aristocratic Ethics after the Thirty Tyrants 243 Alex Gottesman Comp. by: SatchitananthaSivam Stage : Proof ChapterID: 0004760437 Date:25/2/20 Time:13:07:48 Filepath:d:/womat-filecopy/0004760437.3D Dictionary : NOAD_USDictionary 6 OUP UNCORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FIRST PROOF, 25/2/2020, SPi vi 13.
    [Show full text]