At-Issue State Absolutism and Moral Agency in the Political Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

At-Issue State Absolutism and Moral Agency in the Political Philosophy African Studies Quarterly | Volume 18, Issue 3| May 2019 At-Issue State Absolutism and Moral Agency in the Political Philosophy of Thomas Hobbes and Niccolò Machiavelli: Implications for Eritrea PETROS B. OGBAZGHI Abstract: In the progression of Western political philosophy from Aristotle to the Enlightenment, even the most statist thinkers such as Hobbes and Machiavelli, who saw organized society as a necessary evil, never accepted the notion of absolutism that sucks man's free development. Central to Hobbes' conceptualization of the state is that an artificially created sovereign is owed the total submission of his subjects who are faced with an immanent existential threat. Subjects, nonetheless, exist as individual moral agents whose values of justice and liberty—the products of social thought and common conviction—are realized in civil society of the Commonwealth. With Machiavelli’s principality, by contrast, while the success and survival of the state is closely tied together with that of the prince and his subjects, the political community could still be judged in terms of moral committal to the civic virtues of prudence, legitimacy, and order, constituting a venerated political and social force contributing consequentially to individual development. This article entails a comparative study of moral agency in light of Hobbes' Leviathan and Machiavelli's The Prince and examines its implications for Eritrea against the backdrop of its downward spiral into totalitarianism. It argues that both proponents of absolutism offer a critique of the state particularly pertinent to Eritrea where individual development is embedded on a single supreme moral authority. While notions of real or imagined existential threats, which affords regimes to roll state-society into one, enabled Eritrea to maintain a semblance of national unity, its flip side, the exercise and preservation of personal power through sheer repression, has subjected the state to idiosyncratic political attributes that militate against free agency: a nihilistic image to which neither Hobbes’ sovereign nor Machiavelli's prince would wish to subscribe. Key words: state-society relations; state absolutism; free agency Introduction This study seeks to examine the relationship between state absolutism and individual moral agency against the backdrop of Eritrea's downward spiral into totalitarianism. By drawing inspiration from Hobbes' Leviathan and Machiavelli's The Prince, the paper argues that even the most statist thinkers such as Hobbes and Machiavelli—who saw organized society as a necessary evil—would offer a critique of the state particularly pertinent to Eritrea, where the singularity and ultimacy of the morality of the state has resulted in the stunting of free agency. Specifically, while notions of real and/or imagined existential threat, which affords regimes the opportunity to lump together the state and the national society into one monolithic political entity, seems to have helped Petros B. Ogbazghi is a former lecturer in the Department of Public Administration, University of Asmara, Eritrea. He holds a PhD in Politics & Administration from Tilburg University and a Master's Degree in Public Policy & Administration. His research interests include; state-society relations in Eritrea; politics and governance in the developing world; urban regimes and local government in Western Europe. http://www.africa.ufl.edu/asq/v18/v18i3a4.pdf © University of Florida Board of Trustees, a public corporation of the State of Florida; permission is hereby granted for individuals to download articles for their own personal use. Published by the Center for African Studies, University of Florida. ISSN: 2152-2448 State Absolutism and Moral Agency| 48 the Eritrean regime maintain a sense of national unity, its anti-thesis, the exercise and preservation of personal power merely through repression and violence rather than the rule of law, has subjected the state to idiosyncratic political attributes that militate against individual moral agency: a nihilistic image to which neither Hobbes’ sovereign nor Machiavelli's prince would wish to subscribe. By way of introduction, the common analytical threads that cut across Hobbes and Machiavelli are comparatively addressed. These pertain not just to their extreme iconoclastic and pessimistic views of human nature and the concept of the “political” that lent itself to dislocate classical and medieval beliefs and intellectual paradigms: philosophical views which marked them out as the pioneers of modern political thought. But perhaps one of the most important aspect of their political theory or at least valuable in the analysis of moral agency is their recognition, albeit understood and analysed in their separate ways, of the political and social space that is needed for individual agency and civil society. Thus, for example, Hobbes, who took individual members as his unit of analysis, saw subjects as a polity of equals endowed with liberty and freedom, albeit liberty is construed as a negative right and a necessary evil, opening, nonetheless, the possibilities for the realization of “unbounded and disparate desires of individuals.”1 Further, despite Hobbes' pessimistic and egoistic view of human nature, individuals can discover irrefutable universal principles by exercising the right reason as the ultimate guide and basis—over passion—for making binding covenants and contracts out of which the Leviathan or the Commonwealth is constituted.2 Although the will of the collectives is subsumed in the artificially created person—the sovereign—in Hobbes' absolutist state, subjects exist as individual free agents and their values of justice and freedom—the effects of positive law and social discipline—are only produced or realized in civil society of the commonwealth.3 The Commonwealth thus provides the intersection point at which the rational aims of the individual—his capacity for volition and autonomy—and the collectives encapsulating “that which they desire to attain, namely their own good, which is the work of reason” are harmonized.4 On the one hand, is individual desire to escape from what Hobbes called “the fear of death and wounds’” which epitomises the 'state of nature' where self-preservation becomes of surpassing interest. Self-preservation is partly informed, legitimated and propelled by divine reason, although largely governed by passionately selfish and inexorable existentialist human nature.5 On the other hand, is the desire of the collectives to live “in peace and security” by ceding their individual natural rights for self-preservation, and hence, instituting, in exchange, over them an artificially created sovereign through collective agreements that are founded on naturalist and externalist law-based moral conduct as opposed to humanist-internalist moral order.6 Once at the helm, the sovereign, who holds, in a manner of speech, a metonymic sceptre with one hand, and a sword with the other commences “to keep them all in awe.”7 Brought forth by the midwifery of the social contract, the state of nature metaphorically gives birth to a political society, producing at one and the same time, the office and the person occupying it—the sovereign; he symbolizes the ultimate embodiment of the state itself without which: “there is no place for Industry; because the fruit thereof is uncertain...no Society; which is worst of all, continuall feare, and danger of violent death; And the life of man, solitary, poore, nasty, brutish, and short.”8 Of course, subjects are tied to kings and princes who justify their authority by the moral principle of property-rights, where “continuous use has given them something more than the exercise of authority: it has given them ownership of authority; and their subjects are thus tied to them, and to the authority which they own, by the necessity of respecting ownership and all the African Studies Quarterly | Volume 18, Issue 3|May 2019 http://www.africa.ufl.edu/asq/v18/v18i3a3.pdf 49 | Ogbazghi rights which it carries.”9 And yet, Hobbes' early modern state was also characterised by an immense economic, social, and moral space in which individuals live in an atmosphere of liberty, where free agency and personal capacity is cherished and developed. In other words, the state maintains, at least in principle, a degree of political distance from private social life of subjects in such areas as the economic market, family life and religious sphere, if not in ecclesiastical matters.10 Indeed, Hobbes’ concept of the state was formulated against the backdrop of liberty and free agency where the state of nature has endowed individuals with natural rights and powers that enabled them to preserve their lives and properties. Hobbes contention that the collective will of individuals is subsumed in the office of an artificially created sovereign can indeed be considered ground-breaking in so far as Hobbes' “collectivization” allows society “a private sphere, which is regulated by the common law, and which escapes the direct power of the state.”11 This is true, especially when weighed against the ramifications of the exercise of absolute power both in early modern England and France, where kings claimed to be the state itself, but also in contemporary totalitarian systems, albeit differently, where the state has come to be conceived as an organic entity or a corporation sole, where the private sphere has shrunk to form a single Hegelian “ethical totality” rather than Hobbesian “persona civilis.”12 After all, the values of
Recommended publications
  • Homage to Political Philosophy
    Homage to Political Philosophy Also by James R. Flynn Philosophy Humanism and Ideology: An Aristotelian View (1973) How to Defend Humane Ideals: Substitutes for Objectivity (2000) Fate and Philosophy: A Journey through Life’s Great Questions (2012) The modern world The Torchlight List: Around the World in 200 Books (2010) How to Improve Your Mind: Twenty Keys to Unlock the Modern World (2012) The New Torchlight List: In Search of the Best Modern Authors (2016) No Place to Hide: Climate change-- A Short Introduction for New Zealanders (2nd Printing 2017) Intelligence What Is Intelligence? Beyond the Flynn Effect (2007) Are We Getting Smarter? Rising IQ in the Twenty-first Century (2012) Intelligence and Human Progress: The Story of What Was Hidden in Our Genes (2013) Does Your Family Make You Smarter? Nature, Nurture, and Human Autonomy (2016) Group differences Race, IQ, and Jensen (1980) Asian Americans: Achievement beyond IQ (1991) American politics and foreign policy American Politics: A Radical View (1967) Where Have All the Liberals Gone? Race, Class, and Ideals in America (2008) Beyond Patriotism: From Truman to Obama (2012) Belles lettres O God Who Has a Russian Soul: Poems about New Zealand and Its people (2010) Homage to Political Philosophy: The Good Society from Plato to the Present By James R. Flynn Homage to Political Philosophy: The Good Society from Plato to the Present By James R. Flynn This book first published 2018 Cambridge Scholars Publishing Lady Stephenson Library, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2PA, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2018 by James R.
    [Show full text]
  • Mark Twain's Writing During His Last Twenty Years: the Conflicts of A
    Mark Twain’s Writing During his Last Twenty Years: The Conflicts of a Moralist Senior Paper Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For a Degree Bachelor of Arts with A Major in Literature at The University of North Carolina at Asheville Fall 2009 By BRYCE ARGHIERE ____________________ Thesis Director Dr. Blake Hobby ____________________ Thesis Advisor Dr. Gary Ettari Arghiere 2 Unlike much of his earlier writing, most of Mark Twain’s later work presents a grim view of the human race. From roughly 1895 onwards, Twain’s writing contains few of the features for which it first gained recognition: frontier humor, as in “The Celebrated Jumping Frog of Calaveras County” (1867); commentary on rural American life, as in The Adventures of Tom Sawyer (1876) and The Adventures of Huckleberry Finn (1884); and satirical social criticism, as in The Innocents Abroad (1869) and The Prince and the Pauper (1881). Rather, many of his later works deal with philosophical concerns: psychological egoism (the theory that all acts are primarily self-interested), determinism, and solipsism. These concerns appear in Twain’s later correspondences; in The Mysterious Stranger Manuscripts (published posthumously in 1969), a collection of three unfinished narratives; and in What Is Man? (1906), a Socratic dialogue which Twain called his “Bible” (“535. Clemens To Howells” 689). By reviewing the philosophical ideas in these works we can gain insights into several conflicts in Twain’s writing which brought about a dramatic shift in style and a radically different depiction of the human race. Despite the wealth of criticism on Twain’s later works and views and on the conflicts inherent in them, few critics have explored in depth the significance of Twain’s passionate interest in several eighteenth- and nineteenth-century ideas and movements for his later thought, writing, and response to injustice and personal tragedy.
    [Show full text]
  • Morality and the Ring Fall 2018
    Welcome to your life! Now What? The Question: How should I live? “Free at Last!” • You’re adults! – Cool, huh? • You no longer have to do what others tell you to do …. – Your parents – Your teachers – Your religion • What Now? --What should you do? What to do? • How should you live? • How should you choose? • What do you want to do? • What do you get to do? • What makes you happy? • Is being happy all that matters? • What is the “good life?” • What is “justice?” Moral Philosophy • How should I live? – How should we live? • And why? • Is there such a thing a moral obligation? – Are there things that, morally speaking, you should do, even if you don’t want to? • Is there some general principle that makes things “morally right” or “morally wrong?” Moral Philosophy What is morality? Why should we act morally? Is there an objective “moral code?” What is “justice?” Is it morally OK to do whatever I want to do? How do I decide what I want to do? What makes things “moral?” • Is morality subjective? Is it simply a matter of personal preference or personal “taste?” • Is morality culturally relative? Does what’s right or wrong depend upon society? • Is morality “God’s will?” Is something right because God allows it and wrong because God forbids it? • Is morality “absolute?” Are there “objective” moral truths? Well? What do YOU think? If you have no opinion, then I guess that means it would be alright for me to assign your grades at random, … …right? A Thought Experiment What would you do If you knew You’d never get caught? If you could be INVISIBLE? Plato and Socrates Plato: 428-327 BC uBorn in Athens, to upper-class family uGave up a life in politics to study with another Athenian, named Socrates uWas present when Socrates died in 399 BC uFounded the “Academy,” the first university in the western world.
    [Show full text]
  • The Piety of Thought in Plato's Republic, Book 1 Author(S): Darrell Dobbs Source: the American Political Science Review, Vol
    The Piety of Thought in Plato's Republic, Book 1 Author(s): Darrell Dobbs Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 88, No. 3 (Sep., 1994), pp. 668-683 Published by: American Political Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2944802 Accessed: 10/12/2010 23:53 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=apsa. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Political Science Review. http://www.jstor.org American Political Science Review Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Contents Humanities Notes
    Humanities Notes Humanities Seminar Notes - this draft dated 24 May 2021 - more recent drafts will be found online Contents 1 2007 11 1.1 October . 11 1.1.1 Thucydides (2007-10-01 12:29) ........................ 11 1.1.2 Aristotle’s Politics (2007-10-16 14:36) ..................... 11 1.2 November . 12 1.2.1 Polybius (2007-11-03 09:23) .......................... 12 1.2.2 Cicero and Natural Rights (2007-11-05 14:30) . 12 1.2.3 Pliny and Trajan (2007-11-20 16:30) ...................... 12 1.2.4 Variety is the Spice of Life! (2007-11-21 14:27) . 12 1.2.5 Marcus - or Not (2007-11-25 06:18) ...................... 13 1.2.6 Semitic? (2007-11-26 20:29) .......................... 13 1.2.7 The Empire’s Last Chance (2007-11-26 20:45) . 14 1.3 December . 15 1.3.1 The Effect of the Crusades on European Civilization (2007-12-04 12:21) 15 1.3.2 The Plague (2007-12-04 14:25) ......................... 15 2 2008 17 2.1 January . 17 2.1.1 The Greatest Goth (2008-01-06 19:39) .................... 17 2.1.2 Just Justinian (2008-01-06 19:59) ........................ 17 2.2 February . 18 2.2.1 How Faith Contributes to Society (2008-02-05 09:46) . 18 2.3 March . 18 2.3.1 Adam Smith - Then and Now (2008-03-03 20:04) . 18 2.3.2 William Blake and the Doors (2008-03-27 08:50) . 19 2.3.3 It Must Be True - I Saw It On The History Channel! (2008-03-27 09:33) .
    [Show full text]
  • The Wisdom of Noble Simplicity
    The Εὐηθέστεροι Myth: the Wisdom of Noble Simplicity L. M. J. Coulson A Thesis Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Classics and Ancient History School of Philosophical and Historical Inquiry Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences The University of Sydney November 2016 Statement of Originality This is to certify that to the best of my knowledge, the content of this thesis is my own work. This thesis has not been submitted for any degree or other purposes. I certify that the intellectual content of this thesis is the product of my own work and that all the assistance received in preparing this thesis and sources have been acknowledged. L. M. J. Coulson November 2016 i Acknowledgements Throughout this undertaking it has been my great good fortune and privilege to have the gracious and generous support of my family, supervisors and colleagues. On November 5, 2012 Professor Eric Csapo and I met for the first time. At that meeting Eric suggested the apparently paradoxical use of εὐήθεια in Ancient Greece as a postgraduate research topic. This thesis is a direct consequence of his suggestion, encouragement and forbearance. Eric’s erudition in the Classics’ disciplines is extraordinary and gives constant cause for admiration. Professor Rick Benitez is officially designated as my auxiliary supervisor. However, he has been far more that that, especially in the last year of this project when the depth of his Platonic scholarship and generous support made an invaluable contribution to the completion of this thesis. I am grateful for the opportunity to have worked closely with these exceptional scholars.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 3. the Power of the Sophist
    David Kolb, Postmodern Sophistications 1 A belated Introduction These pages contain a typescript of my 1990 book, Postmodern Sophistications, slightly different from the published version. While writing some recent essays, I have been both delighted and worried to see how much had been foreshadowed 26 years ago. I have obtained the rights to the essays and will make them available separately for current discussions, but there may be some interest in seeing them in their original context. The architectural examples are the most dated, and the word postmodern has gone out of fashion in architecture. But the earlier use of the term for an attempt to bring substantive content into formal modernity retains interest. My conclusions about inability of postmodern architecture to escape modern distance from history remain true, as does my argument that modern distance from history is an illusion, that we are more embedded in history than we moderns have wanted to think, though that embodiment is not as total and restrictive as we have imagined in our image of our ancestors. The opposition between postmodern and modern views on knowledge, in the persons of Lyotard and Habermas, remains relevant although later developments in deconstruction and critical theory have widened and deepened the debate. I think the points made in these older essays remain useful, if not complete. The underlying aim of my book was to get away from the duality between the Sophists and Plato. That classic dispute has been the model for many interpretations of the tensions within our society today. On the one hand you have the clever manipulative salesmen who care nothing about truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Friedrich Nietzsche's Superman and Its Religious Implications
    Journal of Philosophy, Culture and Religion www.iiste.org ISSN 2422-8443 An International Peer-reviewed Journal Vol.45, 2019 Friedrich Nietzsche’s Superman and Its Religious Implications Anthony C. Ojimba (Ph.D) 1* Bruno Yammeluan Ikuli (Ph.D) 2 1.Department of Philosophy, University of Nigeria, Nsukka, Enugu State, Nigeria 2.Institute of Foundation Studies, Federal University, Otuoke, Bayalsa State, Nigeria Abstract This paper examines Nietzsche’s idea of the superman and its religious implications, with a view to showing that despite Nietzsche’s rejection of Christian religion and his attack on religious moral ideals, using his concept of the superman, Nietzsche fails in stripping humanity/man of his religious nature. Nietzsche’s superman represents the highest principle of the development of humanity and the affirmation of man’s full potentialities. He posits the superman as a critique on Christian religion and the crisis of modernity. This is because, according to him, the Christian morality stifles the development, freedom and creativity of humanity/man, as well as making him dependent on faith. Consequently, he advocates for the total rejection and abolition of the Christian moral ideals in order to make way for the freedom of humanity/man and consequently the emergence of super-humanity. Attempts are made to articulate Nietzsche’s concept of the superman and to highlight its link with his entire philosophic system. This will be examined critically, in each segment of the paper, to show its implications for religion. The paper employs the method of historical hermeneutics and textual analysis/exposition. Keywords: superman, religion, morality, reevaluation of values, Christianity, nihilism and modernity.
    [Show full text]
  • PLATO Context Soctrates Taught Systematic Dialogical Inquiry Into Knowledge to Plato, with the Goal of Illuminating Human Affairs
    PLATO Context Soctrates taught systematic dialogical inquiry into knowledge to Plato, with the goal of illuminating human affairs. However, the dialogues of Socrates are aporetic – they lead to systematic doubt, paralysis, no strategic recommendations. History: 504 BCE Democracy comes to Athens 469 Socrates born 431 Peloponnesian War begins 428 Plato born 404 Athens surrenders; Oligarchs take over 399 Trial and Death of Socrates 385 Plato founds the Academy 380 The Republic written The deliberative virtues of political life: To listen to contrary views/ to have the courage to follow their insight/ to see the partiality of one’s own views/ to have the humility to recognize the faults of one’s own logic/ to embrace your communicative need for others/ to require the input of others This leads to critical interrogation and is a necessary condition for wise politics. Plato was affected by the death of his mentor, when a 501-person jury put Socrates to death by 30 votes. Plato wanted to renew Athenian power, but questioned if the deliberative virtues and wisdom (philosophical/critical interrogation) were compatible with democracy. Random Thoughts about The Republic Not aporetic, a dialogue of construction. Plato believes that for Socrates to live, philosophers must rule. The art of ruling is the most important and difficult of all the human arts. This requires a type of political science, “the knowledge by which we are to make men good.” The philosopher has a vision of the good, the immutable forms of the good, the pattern, harmony, and music of life. The project of the philosopher-king is to establish the right influences and best environment so that the soul will be attracted to the right things.
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Miestones in the Promotion of Modern Nigerian Art Thought Oshobo Experimental Workshop
    Vol. 9(10), pp. 78-84, December 2017 DOI: 10.5897/AJHC2017.0379 Article Number: 529010367071 ISSN 2141-6672 African Journal of History and Culture Copyright © 2017 Author(s) retain the copyright of this article http://www.academicjournals.org/AJHC Review Reason of state in the philosophical works of Niccolo Machiavelli Tadie Degie Yigzaw Department of Civics and Ethical Studies, College of Social Science and Humanities, Dilla University, P.O. Box 419, Dilla, Ethiopia. Accepted 13 June, 2017; Accepted 14 September, 2017 Every state has its own reason of survival whether it is democratic or undemocratic, constitutional or unconstitutional, tyrannical or republican. Thus, the concept of reason of state depends on the nature of the state. Reason of state in a democratic order is different from that of undemocratic state. This study gave more emphasis on the philosophical works of Niccolo Machiavelli. Based on his philosophical works, the study argue that Machiavelli’s reason of state in The Prince, even though it is implicit, is tyrannical or “reason of power” in its character and not fit for human habituation. On the other hand, his thought in the Discourses promotes constitutional reason of state. As a result, different thinkers considered him as one of the advocator of constitutional reason of state. Key words: Reason of state, the prince, the discourses, reason of power. INTRODUCTION There is no common consensus among thinkers when sake of private interest in the names of the common the idea of reason of state commences. For some good. Due to this reason, many thinkers believe that thinkers, the notion of reason of state begins around the Romans were the first people who brought the theory of end of the 16th century in the writings of Machiavelli reason of state.
    [Show full text]
  • Thucydides and Hegemony: Athens and the United States
    Review of International Studies (2001), 27, 593–609 Copyright © British International Studies Association Thucydides and hegemony: Athens and the United States RICHARD NED LEBOW AND ROBERT KELLY Abstract. Fifth century Greeks distinguished between hegemonia (legitimated leadership) and arkhe (control). Thucydides employed this distinction to track the changing nature of the Athenian Empire during the Peloponnesian War, and the ways in which a diminishing concern for balancing self-interest against justice corroded Athenian authority, made survival of the empire increasingly problematic and encouraged the disastrous expedition to Sicily. The Melian Dialogue—often cited by realists to justify a power-based approach to foreign policy—is intended to symbolize this decay. Building on our analysis of Thucydides, we examine the British, Soviet and American experiences with hegemony. A striking feature of the contemporary American situation is the extent to which American leaders claim hegemonia but deny any interest in arkhe. Rightly or wrongly, much of the rest of the world has the reverse perception. This seeming contradiction has important implications for US foreign policy and world politics more generally. The success or failure of the American people’s foreign policy remains the single greatest factor shaping our own history and the future of the world. —Madeleine K. Albright1 Political scientists frequently turned to Thucydides during the Cold War for analytical insights into the causes and structure of that conflict. The post-Cold War era raises a different set of problems, and Thucydides is once again relevant to the formulation of appropriate responses. His analysis of Athens provides a cautionary tale for the United States and a useful conceptual framework for thinking about the nature of hegemony in the post-Cold War world.
    [Show full text]
  • The Straw Man of Legal Positivism, 34 Notre Dame L
    Notre Dame Law School NDLScholarship Journal Articles Publications 1959 The trS aw Man of Legal Positivism Thomas F. Broden Notre Dame Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.nd.edu/law_faculty_scholarship Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Legal History Commons Recommended Citation Thomas F. Broden, The Straw Man of Legal Positivism, 34 Notre Dame L. 530 (1958-1959). Available at: https://scholarship.law.nd.edu/law_faculty_scholarship/914 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Publications at NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STRAW MAN OF LEGAL POSITIVISM Thomas Broden, Jr.* In 1951, a distinguished U.S. Court of Appeals Judge said: John Austin, the patron saint of the modem positivists, began the law's descent to the Avernus of unfaith by proposing to distin- guish morals from law. Some of the modern but less moderate prag- matists have continued it by proposing to divorce morals from law, while the down-right radicals among them, including the fellow travelers, preferring headlong descent, propose, as Nietzsche did, to abolish morals altogether.' Two years ago a respected political scientist wrote, recently jurisprudence has been befuddled by a school, lately fashion- able in America, which, in the last resort, as Mr. Justice Holmes cynically pointed out, reduces the bases of law to the question, "who can kill whom?" 2 In 1949 an editorial in the American Bar Association Journal opined that, our difficulties have been increased by the fact that at this critical period many of our statesmen, judges, and particularly our law teachers, had abandoned natural law and had become champions of positivism or what some termed legal realism ...
    [Show full text]