The Dialectic of Might and Right: Power and Justice in Realism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Dialectic of Might and Right: Power and Justice in Realism Copyright is owned by the Author of the thesis. Permission is given for a copy to be downloaded by an individual for the purpose of research and private study only. The thesis may not be reproduced elsewhere without the permission of the Author. THE DIALECTIC OF MIGHT AND RIGHT A thesis presented in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS IN POLITICS at Massey University, Palmerston North, New Zealand MARCEL JON ZENTVELD-WALE 2010-2011 Abstract The question of ‘might versus right’, as to whether might makes right or is subject to it, is one of the overarching questions of Western moral and political thought from the ancient Greeks to today. This is an exploration of that question, the debate between the proponents of might (‘Realists’), the proponents of right (‘Idealists’), and the opponents of both (‘Relativists’). It is particularly concerned with the sources of this debate, in the founding figures of these schools of thought and the foundational thought of the tradition as a whole. This debate forms a dialectic that spans much of the history of Western ancient and modern moral and political philosophy, crossing over to a number of related fields. This study is therefore concerned with both the traditional spheres of moral and political philosophy (the theory of nature and the theory of law) and certain related fields (theology, mythology and metaphysics). It provides an overview of this dialectic, its sources, and the relationship between its theoretical and practical aspects. t h e D I A L E C T I C o f M I G H T a n d R I G H T Power and Justice in Realism, Idealism and Relativism M a r c e l J o n Z e n t v e l d - W a l e Contents Acknowledgements p. iii § 0 Introduction: A Model of Might and Right 1 0.1 Triad, Dyad and Dialectic 3 0.2 Traditional and Alternative 4 0.3 Ethics and Politics 8 0.3.1 Traditional and Alternative 11 0.4 Realism, Idealism and Relativism 13 0.4.1 Conservatism and Radicalism 17 0.4.2 Triad, Dyad and Dialectic 21 0.5 A Model of Might and Right 22 I Part One: Power and Justice in Nature and Law 24 1 Chapter One: The Nature of Might and Right 26 1.1 Nature and Nurture 26 1.2 Naturalism versus Conventionalism 27 1.3 Nature, Might and Right 30 1.3.1 “Intellect versus Instinct” 30 1.3.2 “Competition versus Cooperation” 31 1.3.3 Security versus Sustenance 31 1.4 Realism, Idealism and Relativism on Nature 32 1.4.1 Conservatism and Radicalism 42 1.4.3 Triad, Dyad and Dialectic 44 1.5 The Nature of Might and Right 44 2 Chapter Two: The Laws of Might and Right 46 2.1 Natural and Positive Law 46 2.2 Legal Naturalism versus Positivism 47 2.3 Law, Might and Right 49 2.3.1 State versus Society 50 2.3.2 Edict versus Custom 51 2.4 Realism, Idealism and Relativism on Law 51 2.4.1 Conservatism and Radicalism 59 2.4.3 Triad, Dyad and Dialectic 63 2.5 The Laws of Might and Right 63 i II Part Two: Power and Justice in Religion, Myth and Reality 66 3 Chapter Three: The Theology of Might and Right 68 3.1 Theory and Theology 68 3.2 Theism versus Atheism 71 3.3 God, Might and Right 73 3.3.1 Orthodoxy versus Revision 75 3.3.2 Particular versus General Will 77 3.3.3 Political versus Liberation Theology 78 3.4 Realist, Idealist and Relativist Theology 80 3.4.1 Conservatism and Radicalism 83 3.4.3 Triad, Dyad and Dialectic 85 3.5 The Theology of Might and Right 86 4 Chapter Four: The Mythology of Might and Right 87 4.1 “Myth and Antimyth” 87 4.2 Traditional and Alternative Approaches to Myth 90 4.3 Myth, Might and Right 92 4.3.1 Ascent versus Descent 93 4.3.2 Old versus New 93 4.3.3 Ideological versus Utopian Myth 95 4.4 Realist, Idealist and Relativist Mythology 96 4.4.1 Conservatism and Radicalism 100 4.4.3 Triad, Dyad and Dialectic 101 4.5 The Mythology of Might and Right 102 5 Chapter Five: The Metaphysics of Might and Right 104 5.1 Theory and Reality 104 5.2 Being versus Becoming 105 5.3 Metaphysics, Might and Right 108 5.3.1 “The Real and the Ideal” 109 5.3.2 Empiricism versus Rationalism 110 5.4 Realism, Idealism and Relativism on Metaphysics 111 5.4.1 Conservatism and Radicalism 116 5.4.3 Triad, Dyad and Dialectic 118 5.5 The Metaphysics of Might and Right 119 Ω Conclusion: The Dialectic of Might and Right 120 Bibliography 124 ii Acknowledgements I would like to take this opportunity to thank my supervisor, Dr Beth Greener, for her support and assistance with this project. I would also like to thank Dr Suzy Killimister for her helpful comments on an early draft. In addition, I would like to acknowledge others who, while not directly involved in this particular project, were nonetheless instrumental to its inception, in aiding in my studies leading up to it: Dr William Fish and Dr Glen Petagrove, who supported my foray into philosophy, and Dr Stuart Lawrence, whose excellent courses in Greek political philosophy and mythology were the starting-point for my studies in classics. I would also like to thank my parents for their support and assistance throughout my time at university. Finally, special thanks go to Renée Manu for her love and patience these last few years. M. Z. W. iii WAGNER Excuse me sir!––the pleasure’s surely vast To contemplate the spirit of the past! To read the thoughts of ancient learned men, And see how wondrous far the world has moved since then! FAUST Ay, far indeed! Up to the very skies! My friend, the past, all that behind us lies, Is as a book, with seven seals made fast; And what you call the spirit of the age Is but the critic’s spirit, in whose page The age itself is darkly glassed. ––Goethe, Faust iv 0 I N T R O D U C T I O N A MODEL OF MIGHT AND RIGHT Now the two masters, theory and practise, you cannot serve. ––Charles Peirce This is a study of might and right, power and justice. It is an overview of certain overarching discourses of might and right in Western moral and political thought; a genealogy of might and right, which identifies dominant trends in thinking about power and justice and explores their origin and evolution from a critical perspective. It examines the relationship between power and justice within the major “ethical-political”1 discourses of the West: the antithesis of power and justice in the traditional discourse, its synthesis in the alternative. This is a study of that dialectic and, more specifically, of its genesis. Its first task is taxonomical: to outline the familial relations between discourses of power and justice. The second is genealogical: to trace their points of “emergence” (entstehung) and lines of “descent” (herkunft).2 The third is critical: to explore the links between theory and ideology. The scope of the study is very broad. It uses the “telescope” (to apply Proust’s metaphor) rather than the “microscope”.3 This is reflected in both the length of the intellectual history surveyed and the range of topic-areas considered. The core sources are drawn from the ancient, medieval, renaissance and modern periods, in a history spanning from before the ‘birth’ of moral and political philosophy in Socrates to its ‘death’ in Nietzsche.4 Because it is a search for the genesis of certain ideas and ways of thinking, these core sources are restricted largely to certain founding figures of the schools of thought in question. In addition, a number of precursors to the 1 The term “ethical-political” is from Bernstein, The New Constellation: The Ethical-Political Horizons of Modernity and Post-Modernity, 1991: 9 2 Foucault, ‘Nietzsche, Genealogy, History’, 2004: 75–7 3 Proust, Remembrance of Things Past, Volume Two [1932: 1118] 4 Rengger, Political Theory, Modernity and Postmodernity: Beyond Enlightenment and Critique, 1995: 138–9 1 core sources, going back to even earlier times, are also surveyed, as are various secondary sources, interpretations of the core and precursor texts, many of which date to present times. The topic-areas considered include not only the traditional fields of moral and political philosophy (nature and law) but also a number of related fields (religion, myth and metaphysics). The role of this introduction is to provide an overview of the basic concepts and categories of these discourses of might and right, and an outline of the dialectic that exists between them, the sources of which are the subject of the chapters that follow. This means beginning at the end, since the definitions and distinctions developed here at the outset are the outcome of a process, which the remainder of the study attempts to record. This is not unusual, according to Ophir: “In a philosophic treatise (perhaps in any scientific treatise), the reader always starts from the place where the writer has concluded.”5 Throughout this introduction, and in the chapters that follow, it will be necessary to quote extensively from both primary and secondary sources. The method is like that attributed by Proust to Schopenhauer, who, he says, “never advances an opinion without immediately supporting it with several quotations”.6 Such methods are necessary in cases such as these, where the opinions that are advanced concern the opinions of others.
Recommended publications
  • Homage to Political Philosophy
    Homage to Political Philosophy Also by James R. Flynn Philosophy Humanism and Ideology: An Aristotelian View (1973) How to Defend Humane Ideals: Substitutes for Objectivity (2000) Fate and Philosophy: A Journey through Life’s Great Questions (2012) The modern world The Torchlight List: Around the World in 200 Books (2010) How to Improve Your Mind: Twenty Keys to Unlock the Modern World (2012) The New Torchlight List: In Search of the Best Modern Authors (2016) No Place to Hide: Climate change-- A Short Introduction for New Zealanders (2nd Printing 2017) Intelligence What Is Intelligence? Beyond the Flynn Effect (2007) Are We Getting Smarter? Rising IQ in the Twenty-first Century (2012) Intelligence and Human Progress: The Story of What Was Hidden in Our Genes (2013) Does Your Family Make You Smarter? Nature, Nurture, and Human Autonomy (2016) Group differences Race, IQ, and Jensen (1980) Asian Americans: Achievement beyond IQ (1991) American politics and foreign policy American Politics: A Radical View (1967) Where Have All the Liberals Gone? Race, Class, and Ideals in America (2008) Beyond Patriotism: From Truman to Obama (2012) Belles lettres O God Who Has a Russian Soul: Poems about New Zealand and Its people (2010) Homage to Political Philosophy: The Good Society from Plato to the Present By James R. Flynn Homage to Political Philosophy: The Good Society from Plato to the Present By James R. Flynn This book first published 2018 Cambridge Scholars Publishing Lady Stephenson Library, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2PA, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2018 by James R.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Naturalism Is a Disjunctivism Roderick T. Long Legal Positivists
    Legal Naturalism Is a Disjunctivism Roderick T. Long Auburn University aaeblog.com | [email protected] Abstract: Legal naturalism is the doctrine that a rule’s status as law depends on its moral content; or, in its strongest form, that “an unjust law is not a law.” By drawing an analogy between legal naturalism and perceptual disjunctivism, I argue that this doctrine is more defensible than is generally thought, and in particular that it entails no conflict with ordinary usage. Legal positivists hold that a rule’s status as law never depends on its moral content. In Austin’s famous formulation: “The existence of law is one thing; its merit or demerit is another. Whether a law be is one enquiry; whether it ought to be, or whether it agree with a given or assumed test, is another and different inquiry.”1 There seems to be no generally accepted term for the opposed view, that a rule’s status as law does (sometimes or always) depend on its moral content. Legal moralism would be the natural choice, but that name is already taken to mean the view that the law should impose social standards of morality on private conduct. Legal normativisim, another natural choice, is, somewhat perversely, already in use to denote a species of legal positivism.2 The position in question is sometimes referred to as “the natural law view,” but this is not really accurate; although the view has been held by many natural law theorists, it has not been held by all of them, and is not strictly implied by the natural law position.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of International Law H
    Anthony Carty is Professor of Public Law at the Philosophy of University of Aberdeen. P Philosophy of International Law h i ANTHONY CARTY l o s A fundamental challenge to the foundations o International Law of the discipline of international law. p This book offers an internal critique of the h discipline of international law whilst showing y the necessary place for philosophy within this o ANTHONY CARTY subject area. By reintroducing philosophy into f the heart of the study of international law, I Anthony Carty explains how traditionally n philosophy has always been an integral part of t the discipline. However, this has been driven e out by legal positivism, which has, in turn, r n become a pure technique of law. He explores the extent of the disintegration and confusion a in the discipline and offers various ways of t i renewing philosophical practice. o n A range of approaches are covered – post- Jacket design: River Design, Edinburgh a structuralism, neo-Marxist geopolitics, social- Jacket image: Kurt Hutton/Hulton Archive/ l democratic constitutional theory and Getty Images L existential phenomenology – encouraging the Shawcross at the Hague Court in 1948: ‘[ . ] a reader to think afresh about how far to bring Parties to litigation are not entitled to use w order to, or find order in, contemporary merely those documents which they think will international society. assist their case and to suppress others which Key Features are inimical to it. [ . ] As it is, we retain great A misgivings about the propriety of what is being N • Offers a broad survey of possible done, which we can only justify on the T philosophical approaches to international principle “my country [ .
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE July 2007
    CURRICULUM VITAE January 2013 FRANK CUNNINGHAM Date of Birth: 5 August, 1940. Cities Centre 130 Carlton St. University of Toronto unit 905 455 Spadina Ave. Toronto, Ontario Toronto, Ontario Canada M5A 4K3 Canada M5S 2G8 416-962-9788 416-978-5590 E-mail: [email protected] web: http://individual.utoronto.ca/frankcunningham ACADEMIC HISTORY Ph.D. University of Toronto 1970 M.A. University of Chicago 1965 B.A. Indiana University 1962 University of Toronto Appointments Philosophy Department: Lecturer 1967; Assistant Professor, 1970; Associate Professor, 1974; Professor, 1986. Department of Political Science: Cross Appointment, 2000. Associate Instructor of History and Philosophy of Education, OISE, University of Toronto, 2007 - . Cities Centre, University of Toronto, 2007 - . Emeritus Professor of Philosophy and Political Science, University of Toronto, 2009 - . Visiting Positions University of Amsterdam, Fall 1990 Lanzhou University (PRC), Spring, 199l Ritsumeikan University (Kyoto), Fall 1994, Fall 1997, Spring 2007 University of Rome (I), Spring 1999 Posts Interim Director, Centre for Ethics, University of Toronto, 2011. Principal, Innis College, University of Toronto, 2000- 2005 President, Canadian Philosophical Association, 1997-98 (Vice President, 1996-97) Chair, Department of Philosophy, University of Toronto, 1982- 88 (Associate Chair, 1977-8; Acting Chair, 1991-92) HONOURS Recipient, SAC/APUS Undergraduate Teaching Award, 2005 Recipient, Queen’s Golden Jubilee Medal, 2002 Senior Fellow, Massey College, University of Toronto, 1999 - Fellow of the Royal Society of Canada, 1995 - Faculty Teaching Fellow, University of Toronto, 1974-75 Mary Beatty Fellowship, University of Toronto, 1965-66 School of Letters Fellowship, Indiana University, 1964-5 Woodrow Wilson Fellowship, 1962-63 Phi Beta Kappa, 1962 Ford Foundation Fellowship, 1961-62 2 TEACHING Introductory Courses: Introduction to Philosophy, Political Philosophy, Science and Society (in the Faculty of Applied Science and Engineering), Environmental Ethics.
    [Show full text]
  • Mark Twain's Writing During His Last Twenty Years: the Conflicts of A
    Mark Twain’s Writing During his Last Twenty Years: The Conflicts of a Moralist Senior Paper Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For a Degree Bachelor of Arts with A Major in Literature at The University of North Carolina at Asheville Fall 2009 By BRYCE ARGHIERE ____________________ Thesis Director Dr. Blake Hobby ____________________ Thesis Advisor Dr. Gary Ettari Arghiere 2 Unlike much of his earlier writing, most of Mark Twain’s later work presents a grim view of the human race. From roughly 1895 onwards, Twain’s writing contains few of the features for which it first gained recognition: frontier humor, as in “The Celebrated Jumping Frog of Calaveras County” (1867); commentary on rural American life, as in The Adventures of Tom Sawyer (1876) and The Adventures of Huckleberry Finn (1884); and satirical social criticism, as in The Innocents Abroad (1869) and The Prince and the Pauper (1881). Rather, many of his later works deal with philosophical concerns: psychological egoism (the theory that all acts are primarily self-interested), determinism, and solipsism. These concerns appear in Twain’s later correspondences; in The Mysterious Stranger Manuscripts (published posthumously in 1969), a collection of three unfinished narratives; and in What Is Man? (1906), a Socratic dialogue which Twain called his “Bible” (“535. Clemens To Howells” 689). By reviewing the philosophical ideas in these works we can gain insights into several conflicts in Twain’s writing which brought about a dramatic shift in style and a radically different depiction of the human race. Despite the wealth of criticism on Twain’s later works and views and on the conflicts inherent in them, few critics have explored in depth the significance of Twain’s passionate interest in several eighteenth- and nineteenth-century ideas and movements for his later thought, writing, and response to injustice and personal tragedy.
    [Show full text]
  • Morality and the Ring Fall 2018
    Welcome to your life! Now What? The Question: How should I live? “Free at Last!” • You’re adults! – Cool, huh? • You no longer have to do what others tell you to do …. – Your parents – Your teachers – Your religion • What Now? --What should you do? What to do? • How should you live? • How should you choose? • What do you want to do? • What do you get to do? • What makes you happy? • Is being happy all that matters? • What is the “good life?” • What is “justice?” Moral Philosophy • How should I live? – How should we live? • And why? • Is there such a thing a moral obligation? – Are there things that, morally speaking, you should do, even if you don’t want to? • Is there some general principle that makes things “morally right” or “morally wrong?” Moral Philosophy What is morality? Why should we act morally? Is there an objective “moral code?” What is “justice?” Is it morally OK to do whatever I want to do? How do I decide what I want to do? What makes things “moral?” • Is morality subjective? Is it simply a matter of personal preference or personal “taste?” • Is morality culturally relative? Does what’s right or wrong depend upon society? • Is morality “God’s will?” Is something right because God allows it and wrong because God forbids it? • Is morality “absolute?” Are there “objective” moral truths? Well? What do YOU think? If you have no opinion, then I guess that means it would be alright for me to assign your grades at random, … …right? A Thought Experiment What would you do If you knew You’d never get caught? If you could be INVISIBLE? Plato and Socrates Plato: 428-327 BC uBorn in Athens, to upper-class family uGave up a life in politics to study with another Athenian, named Socrates uWas present when Socrates died in 399 BC uFounded the “Academy,” the first university in the western world.
    [Show full text]
  • The Piety of Thought in Plato's Republic, Book 1 Author(S): Darrell Dobbs Source: the American Political Science Review, Vol
    The Piety of Thought in Plato's Republic, Book 1 Author(s): Darrell Dobbs Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 88, No. 3 (Sep., 1994), pp. 668-683 Published by: American Political Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2944802 Accessed: 10/12/2010 23:53 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=apsa. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Political Science Review. http://www.jstor.org American Political Science Review Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Contents Humanities Notes
    Humanities Notes Humanities Seminar Notes - this draft dated 24 May 2021 - more recent drafts will be found online Contents 1 2007 11 1.1 October . 11 1.1.1 Thucydides (2007-10-01 12:29) ........................ 11 1.1.2 Aristotle’s Politics (2007-10-16 14:36) ..................... 11 1.2 November . 12 1.2.1 Polybius (2007-11-03 09:23) .......................... 12 1.2.2 Cicero and Natural Rights (2007-11-05 14:30) . 12 1.2.3 Pliny and Trajan (2007-11-20 16:30) ...................... 12 1.2.4 Variety is the Spice of Life! (2007-11-21 14:27) . 12 1.2.5 Marcus - or Not (2007-11-25 06:18) ...................... 13 1.2.6 Semitic? (2007-11-26 20:29) .......................... 13 1.2.7 The Empire’s Last Chance (2007-11-26 20:45) . 14 1.3 December . 15 1.3.1 The Effect of the Crusades on European Civilization (2007-12-04 12:21) 15 1.3.2 The Plague (2007-12-04 14:25) ......................... 15 2 2008 17 2.1 January . 17 2.1.1 The Greatest Goth (2008-01-06 19:39) .................... 17 2.1.2 Just Justinian (2008-01-06 19:59) ........................ 17 2.2 February . 18 2.2.1 How Faith Contributes to Society (2008-02-05 09:46) . 18 2.3 March . 18 2.3.1 Adam Smith - Then and Now (2008-03-03 20:04) . 18 2.3.2 William Blake and the Doors (2008-03-27 08:50) . 19 2.3.3 It Must Be True - I Saw It On The History Channel! (2008-03-27 09:33) .
    [Show full text]
  • The Wisdom of Noble Simplicity
    The Εὐηθέστεροι Myth: the Wisdom of Noble Simplicity L. M. J. Coulson A Thesis Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Classics and Ancient History School of Philosophical and Historical Inquiry Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences The University of Sydney November 2016 Statement of Originality This is to certify that to the best of my knowledge, the content of this thesis is my own work. This thesis has not been submitted for any degree or other purposes. I certify that the intellectual content of this thesis is the product of my own work and that all the assistance received in preparing this thesis and sources have been acknowledged. L. M. J. Coulson November 2016 i Acknowledgements Throughout this undertaking it has been my great good fortune and privilege to have the gracious and generous support of my family, supervisors and colleagues. On November 5, 2012 Professor Eric Csapo and I met for the first time. At that meeting Eric suggested the apparently paradoxical use of εὐήθεια in Ancient Greece as a postgraduate research topic. This thesis is a direct consequence of his suggestion, encouragement and forbearance. Eric’s erudition in the Classics’ disciplines is extraordinary and gives constant cause for admiration. Professor Rick Benitez is officially designated as my auxiliary supervisor. However, he has been far more that that, especially in the last year of this project when the depth of his Platonic scholarship and generous support made an invaluable contribution to the completion of this thesis. I am grateful for the opportunity to have worked closely with these exceptional scholars.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Legal Naturalism and the Politics of John Marshall's Constitutional Jurisprudence, 33 J
    UIC Law Review Volume 33 Issue 4 Article 12 Summer 2000 Classical Legal Naturalism and the Politics of John Marshall's Constitutional Jurisprudence, 33 J. Marshall L. Rev. 935 (2000) Robert Lowry Clinton Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.uic.edu/lawreview Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, Judges Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, Law and Society Commons, Legal History Commons, and the Litigation Commons Recommended Citation Robert Lowry Clinton, Classical Legal Naturalism and the Politics of John Marshall's Constitutional Jurisprudence, 33 J. Marshall L. Rev. 935 (2000) https://repository.law.uic.edu/lawreview/vol33/iss4/12 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by UIC Law Open Access Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in UIC Law Review by an authorized administrator of UIC Law Open Access Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CLASSICAL LEGAL NATURALISM AND THE POLITICS OF JOHN MARSHALL'S CONSTITUTIONAL JURISPRUDENCE ROBERT LOWRY CLINTON* INTRODUCTION For many scholars, John Marshall has been a great puzzle. Although Marshall is venerated as the "Great Chief Justice" by almost everyone; his jurisprudence has not been regarded as highly, or as thoughtfully, as it ought to have been by most contemporary judges and commentators. Christopher Wolfe stated the problem bluntly almost a decade-and-a-half ago, noting that the "almost unchallenged understanding of Marshall today" is comprised in a view "which dismisses his own statements as words 'well and finely said' but not to be taken seriously."' Happily, the appearance of excellent Marshall studies by such scholars as Charles Hobson and Herbert Johnson during the past few years has ameliorated the situation somewhat.' Still, I think a fair assessment of Marshall's position today would nonetheless confirm the lingering truth of Wolfe's observation.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 3. the Power of the Sophist
    David Kolb, Postmodern Sophistications 1 A belated Introduction These pages contain a typescript of my 1990 book, Postmodern Sophistications, slightly different from the published version. While writing some recent essays, I have been both delighted and worried to see how much had been foreshadowed 26 years ago. I have obtained the rights to the essays and will make them available separately for current discussions, but there may be some interest in seeing them in their original context. The architectural examples are the most dated, and the word postmodern has gone out of fashion in architecture. But the earlier use of the term for an attempt to bring substantive content into formal modernity retains interest. My conclusions about inability of postmodern architecture to escape modern distance from history remain true, as does my argument that modern distance from history is an illusion, that we are more embedded in history than we moderns have wanted to think, though that embodiment is not as total and restrictive as we have imagined in our image of our ancestors. The opposition between postmodern and modern views on knowledge, in the persons of Lyotard and Habermas, remains relevant although later developments in deconstruction and critical theory have widened and deepened the debate. I think the points made in these older essays remain useful, if not complete. The underlying aim of my book was to get away from the duality between the Sophists and Plato. That classic dispute has been the model for many interpretations of the tensions within our society today. On the one hand you have the clever manipulative salesmen who care nothing about truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Center for the Study of Democratic Institutions Collection
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/tf3s2006vg Online items available Guide to the Center for the Study of Democratic Institutions Collection Processing Information: Arrangement and description by Deborah Kennedy, David C. Tambo, Yolanda Blue, Louisa Dennis, and Elizabeth Witherell; also student assistants Elizabeth Aburto, Julie Baron, Marisela Bautista, Liz Bittner, Michelle Bowden, Chris Caldow, Jacqueline Chau, Alison Church, Hubert Dubrulle, Sivakumar Elambooranan, Richard Frausto, Michael Fry, Joseline Garde, Joseph Gardner, Tim Hagen, Arlene Hebron, Kara Heerman, M. Pilar Herraiz, Ain Hunter, Sandra Jacobs, Derek Jaeger, Gisele Jones, Julie Kravets, Annie Leatt, Kurt Morrill, Chris Shea, Robert Simons, Kay Wamser, Leon Zimlich, and other Library and Special Collections staff and student assistants; machine-readable finding aid created by Xiuzhi Zhou. Latest revision D. Tambo. Department of Special Collections Davidson Library University of California, Santa Barbara Santa Barbara, CA 93106 Phone: (805) 893-3062 Fax: (805) 893-5749 Email: [email protected] URL: http://www.library.ucsb.edu/speccoll/speccoll.html © 2000 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Guide to the Center for the Study Mss 18 1 of Democratic Institutions Collection Guide to the Center for the Study of Democratic Institutions (CSDI) Collection, 1950-1991 [bulk dates 1961-1987] Collection number: Mss 18 Department of Special Collections Davidson Library University of California, Santa Barbara Contact Information: Department of Special Collections Davidson Library University of California, Santa Barbara Santa Barbara, CA 93106 Phone: (805) 893-3062 Fax: (805) 893-5749 Email: [email protected] URL: http://www.library.ucsb.edu/speccoll/speccoll.html Processing Information: Arrangement and description by Deborah Kennedy, David C.
    [Show full text]