The Piety of Thought in Plato's Republic, Book 1 Author(S): Darrell Dobbs Source: the American Political Science Review, Vol

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Piety of Thought in Plato's Republic, Book 1 Author(S): Darrell Dobbs Source: the American Political Science Review, Vol The Piety of Thought in Plato's Republic, Book 1 Author(s): Darrell Dobbs Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 88, No. 3 (Sep., 1994), pp. 668-683 Published by: American Political Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2944802 Accessed: 10/12/2010 23:53 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=apsa. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Political Science Review. http://www.jstor.org American Political Science Review Vol. 88, No. 3 September 1994 THEPIETY OF THOUGHT IN PLATO'SREPUBLIC, BOOK 1 DARRELL DOBBS Marquette University n the opening sentence of the Republic, Socrates recounts his intention to combine the operations of piety and theoretical speculation. Nevertheless, many readers regard Cephalus' subsequent abandonment of rational inquiry to perform certain sacred rites as a definitive indication of Plato's opinion that piety and philosophy are fundamentally incompatible. Ifind this interpretation untenable inasmuch as it depends upon the misidentification of Cephalus as the dialogue's representative of piety. I suggest that the true nature and philosophical significance of piety are indicated instead in Socrates' conversation with Cephalus' son, Polemarchus. As this conversation unfolds, Polemarchus' pious inclinations culminate in a perception of the dearness of the unknown good. Inspired by this piety, Socrates and Polemarchus defend the conventional paragon Simonides and, at the same time, launch a truly philosophical inquiry into justice. lato's Republic is reputed to be one among a in the art of dialectic, invites us to call such divisions handful of the greatest works ever written on eidetic or ponderableparts in order to distinguish them the theme of social justice and personal happi- from the mere pieces into which any whole may be ness. Yet if we should wish to verify this judgment, thoughtlessly-or even methodically-broken (States- and to derive the benefit of its insight for ourselves, man 262c8-263bll). we would confront an extraordinary challenge in the In such passages Plato encourages the practice of complexity and sheer size of the work. This challenge dialectical analysis upon his own writings. But on might seem to outrun every endeavor, for the better what basis may we undertake the dialectical task of acquainted one becomes with the Republic, the more dividing Plato's Republic into ponderable parts? time-consuming becomes the consideration of any Clearly, some grasp of the dialogue as a whole is given section of it. The pace of successive readings required before one can reasonably venture upon such tends to slow. Eventually one opens the text only to a division. But whence comes this division-initiating ponder at length the significance of a single phrase or understanding of the whole? Surely, it cannot origi- dramatic event. Such a meditation can be exquisitely nate in a concentrated study of ponderable parts, for pleasant. But what is there to prevent so closely this begs the question of which parts are correctly focused a study from losing its bearings? How might identified as ponderable. Neither can it derive from the student keep from losing sight of the forest for the blind trust in the judgment of more experienced trees? students, for this begs the question of the basis of the It would be incongruous, to say the least, were a more experienced student's understanding. The only professional academic to deny the relevance of this escape from this impasse lies in the possibility that dilemma to the study of Plato's Republic. For it is the the understanding needed to guide the division of achievement of synopsis (the capacity to see simulta- the dialogue into ponderable parts is somehow acces- neously both the forest and the trees) that the Republic sible even to the novice upon an initial reading of the submits as evidence of a dialectical nature and thus as entire work.2 The contours of the very surface of the testimony of one's being qualified to undertake ad- work might then be said to reveal its natural articu- vanced studies in the first place (537b8-c7).' So it is lations. Leo Strauss put it well when he declared in incumbent upon every reader, when approaching the case of such a work that "the problem inherent in this dialogue, to consider how the forester's dilemma the surface of things, and only in the surface of things, might be resolved. Now, Socrates himself offers a key is the heart of things" (1958, 13). to the resolution of this dilemma in his remarks on Plato employs his luminous poetic talent accord- the art of writing (Phaedrus264c2-266cl). In a properly ingly, to epitomize the profoundest themes of his constructed composition, he maintains, one finds philosophical compositions. One of his customary something like the integrity of a living body. Where devices in this undertaking is the ethological mime, such integrity obtains, the natural articulations or the representation of an action in which all pretense joints of a composition mark off segments that are is stripped away and an interlocutor reveals himself intelligible precisely as parts of a whole. We may say, both in character and in thought (see Klein 1965, 18). then, that the very divisions that call for detailed The first example of such a mimesis in the Republic study also summon, at the same time, a recollection reaches a climax early in book 1, with the departure of of the whole. By concentrating attention on such Cephalus. The importance of Cephalus' departure is divisions, the student is able to think and to talk further highlighted by its conspicuous reversal of the about the most minute textual details in a wholly dialogue's dramatic momentum. In the beginning, nonreductive manner. Plato's Eleatic Stranger, expert Socrates and Glaucon are together. These two are 668 American Political Science Review Vol. 88, No. 3 soon joined by Polemarchus, Adeimantus, Niceratus, Republicof a concern for the relationship of piety and and some others. This ensemble then makes its way inquiry. In the dialogue's opening sentence, Socrates to Polemarchus' house, where await Lysias, Euthy- reports his own intention of combining these diver- demus, Thrasymachus, Charmantides, Cleitophon, gent operations. To appreciate the full significance of and Cephalus, the father of Polemarchus. A conver- this remark, however, we must keep in mind that the sation is presently launched concerning the nature of Republic is, in form, a narrated dialogue-and a justice. Although this conversation continues into the particular kind of narrated dialogue at that. Plato early hours of the morning, not a single member of assigns the role of narrator in the Republicto Socrates. the congregation is said to depart, except for Ceph- In this role, Socrates reports not only what he and alus. Cephalus abandons the inquiry in its infancy. others said and did on the preceding day but also The old man departs because, as he says, "the time is what he thought then and what he thinks now, with come when I must tend to the sacred things" (331d7). the benefit of hindsight, of those words and deeds. Cephalus' departure surely stands as one of the So Plato puts Socrates forward as a uniquely author- most striking dramatic events in the dialogue. As itative commentator on the conversation reported in such, it invites comparison with the violent eruption the Republic. Nevertheless, even in his narration of Thrasymachus, who hurls himself at Socrates and Socrates leaves many things unexplained. For exam- Polemarchus "like a wild beast" (336b5-6). But the ple, the occasion of his recapitulation of the previous antagonism represented by Thrasymachus' outburst day's doings is not itself described. Nor is there any is composed in the course of the conversation. indication of the existence (much less the identity) of Socrates later states that he and Thrasymachus have any auditor or auditors. Socrates, to all appearances, become friends, though they were not even enemies is talking to himself. Of course, we readers are the before (498c6-dl). Cephalus' departure, on the other intended audience-ultimately. But within the frame hand, is final. He never returns. So if even Thrasy- of the dialogue, Socrates addresses his rehearsal to no machus (the sometime champion of might over right) one but himself. The reader evidently is witness to an can be reconciled to Socrates, it would seem that exercise in personal recollection, a soliloquy.5 Now a Cephalus' complete break with Socrates and the soliloquy is a speech spoken with a level of candor community of inquiry must portend an issue of not to be expected in the public discourse of a considerable importance.
Recommended publications
  • The Song Elite's Obsession with Death, the Underworld, and Salvation
    BIBLID 0254-4466(2002)20:1 pp. 399-440 漢學研究第 20 卷第 1 期(民國 91 年 6 月) Visualizing the Afterlife: The Song Elite’s Obsession with Death, the Underworld, and Salvation Hsien-huei Liao* Abstract This study explores the Song elite’s obsession with the afterlife and its impact on their daily lives. Through examining the ways they perceived the relations between the living and the dead, the fate of their own afterlives, and the functional roles of religious specialists, this study demonstrates that the prevailing ideas about death and the afterlife infiltrated the minds of many of the educated, deeply affecting their daily practices. While affected by contem- porary belief in the underworld and the power of the dead, the Song elite also played an important role in the formation and proliferation of those ideas through their piety and practices. Still, implicit divergences of perceptions and practices between the elite and the populace remained abiding features under- neath their universally shared beliefs. To explore the Song elite’s interactions with popular belief in the underworld, several questions are discussed, such as how and why the folk belief in the afterlife were accepted and incorporated into the elite’s own practices, and how their practices corresponded to, dif- fered from, or reinforced folk beliefs. An examination of the social, cultural, * Hsien-huei Liao is a research associate in the Department of East Asian Languages and Civilizations at Harvard University, U.S.A. 399 400 漢學研究第20卷第1期 and political impact on their conceptualization of the afterlife within the broad historical context of the Song is key to understand their beliefs and practices concerning the underworld.
    [Show full text]
  • Russian Orthodoxy and Women's Spirituality In
    RUSSIAN ORTHODOXY AND WOMEN’S SPIRITUALITY IN IMPERIAL RUSSIA* Christine D. Worobec On 8 November 1885, the feast day of Archangel Michael, the Abbess Taisiia had a mystical experience in the midst of a church service dedicated to the tonsuring of sisters at Leushino. The women’s religious community of Leushino had recently been ele­ vated to the status of a monastery.1 Conducting an all-women’s choir on that special day, the abbess became exhilarated by the beautiful refrain of the Cherubikon hymn, “Let us lay aside all earthly cares,” and envisioned Christ surrounded by angels above the iconostasis. She later wrote, “Something was happening, but what it was I am unable to tell, although I saw and heard every­ thing. It was not something of this world. From the beginning of the vision, I seemed to fall into ecstatic rapture Tears were stream­ ing down my face. I realized that everyone was looking at me in astonishment, and even fear....”2 Five years later, a newspaper columnistwitnessedasceneinachurch in the Smolensk village of Egor'-Bunakovo in which a woman began to scream in the midst of the singing of the Cherubikon. He described “a horrible in­ *This book chapter is dedicated to the memory of Brenda Meehan, who pioneered the study of Russian Orthodox women religious in the modern period. 1 The Russian language does not have a separate word such as “convent” or nunnery” to distinguish women’s from men’s monastic institutions. 2 Abbess Thaisia, 194; quoted in Meehan, Holy Women o f Russia, 126. Tapestry of Russian Christianity: Studies in History and Culture.
    [Show full text]
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Homage to Political Philosophy
    Homage to Political Philosophy Also by James R. Flynn Philosophy Humanism and Ideology: An Aristotelian View (1973) How to Defend Humane Ideals: Substitutes for Objectivity (2000) Fate and Philosophy: A Journey through Life’s Great Questions (2012) The modern world The Torchlight List: Around the World in 200 Books (2010) How to Improve Your Mind: Twenty Keys to Unlock the Modern World (2012) The New Torchlight List: In Search of the Best Modern Authors (2016) No Place to Hide: Climate change-- A Short Introduction for New Zealanders (2nd Printing 2017) Intelligence What Is Intelligence? Beyond the Flynn Effect (2007) Are We Getting Smarter? Rising IQ in the Twenty-first Century (2012) Intelligence and Human Progress: The Story of What Was Hidden in Our Genes (2013) Does Your Family Make You Smarter? Nature, Nurture, and Human Autonomy (2016) Group differences Race, IQ, and Jensen (1980) Asian Americans: Achievement beyond IQ (1991) American politics and foreign policy American Politics: A Radical View (1967) Where Have All the Liberals Gone? Race, Class, and Ideals in America (2008) Beyond Patriotism: From Truman to Obama (2012) Belles lettres O God Who Has a Russian Soul: Poems about New Zealand and Its people (2010) Homage to Political Philosophy: The Good Society from Plato to the Present By James R. Flynn Homage to Political Philosophy: The Good Society from Plato to the Present By James R. Flynn This book first published 2018 Cambridge Scholars Publishing Lady Stephenson Library, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2PA, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2018 by James R.
    [Show full text]
  • Pilgrimage Processions, Religious Sensibilities and Piety in the City Of
    Pilgrimage Processions, Religious Sensibilities and Piety in the City of Acre in the Latin Kingdom of Jerusalem Peregrinaciones, sensibilidades religiosas y piedad en la ciudad de Acre del Reino latino de Jerusalén Peregrinações, sensibilidades religiosas e piedade na cidade de Acre do Reino Latino de Jerusalém Shlomo LOTAN1 Resumen: Después de la caída de Jerusalén en 1187, Acre se convirtió en la capital formal de la cruzada de la cristiandad. Durante el siglo XIII, se convirtió en lugar de peregrinaje para los cristianos, quienes, a su vez, enriquecieron la ciudad con las ceremonias religiosas que aportaron. Esta procesión se ha denominado Perdón de Acre y ha contribuido notablemente al entendimiento que hoy tenemos de los lugares religiosos y de los grupos militares situados en la Acre franca. Es por ello que en este ensayo pretendo revisitar estos eventos para aportar nueva luz a la comprensión de los lugares religiosos, peregrinaciones y grupos militares que participaron en tan señalado momento. Palabras clave: Cruzadas – Reino latino de Jerusalén – Acre – Peregrinación – Órdenes militares – Hospitalarios – Templarios – Orden Teutónica. Abstract: After the fall of Jerusalem in 1187, Acre became the formal capital of the Crusader Kingdom. During the 13th century, it became a pilgrimage site for many Christian pilgrims, who enriched the city with their religious ceremonies. Such as a procession called the Pardon d'Acre, which contributed greatly to our understanding of the religious places and military compounds in Frankish Acre. In this essay, I link the religious ceremonies that took place in Acre with the passages among the locations mentioned therein. All these contributed to the revival of the historical and religious space in medieval Acre.
    [Show full text]
  • The Seven Deadly Sins
    THE SEVEN DEADLY SINS "The lesson writ in red since first time ran, A hunter hunting down the beast in man; That till the chasing out of its last vice, The flesh was fashioned but for sacrifice." GEORGE MEREDITH xenrht IDas h<mtmi(# Snjferbta, /mJ/i S—^5^T\ ~t{?H placcOjjfltKeo dmti mmtsi^/a mi/'i. s* / PRIDE. (After Goltziits.) [Frontispiece. THE SEVEN DEADLY SINS BY FREDERICK ROGERS A. H. BULLEN 47, GREAT RUSSELL STREET, LONDON, W.C. I907 TO ARTHUR C. HAYWARD WITH WHOM I HAVE READ MANY BOOKS AND FROM WHOM I HAVE HAD MUCH FRIENDSHIP I DEDICATE THESE PAGES CONTENTS INTRODUCTION LIST OF SINS AND VIRTUES WORKS OF MERCY, SPIRITUAL GIFTS, AND PENITENTIAL PSALMS PAGE CHAPTER I. THE SINS AND THE CHURCH 1 CHAPTER II. THE SINS AND RELIGIOUS DRAMA - 11 CHAPTER III. THE SINS AND SOCIAL REVOLT - r 29 CHAPTER IV. THE SINS IN COMMON LIFE - 44 CHAPTER V. THE SINS AND THE REFORMATION - - 62 CHAPTER VI. THE SINS AND THE ELIZABETHANS - - 74 CHAPTER VII. EXEUNT THE SINS ----- - 98 ILLUSTRATIONS PRIDE (after Goltzws) . FRONTISPIECE TO FACE PAGE PRIDE (after De Vos) . 8 LECHERY „ . 18 ENVY „ • 32 WRATH „ . 42 COVETOUSNESS „ . 58 GLUTTONY „ .70 SLOTH „ . 80 WRATH (after Peter Brueghil) . : . 88 AVARICE „ . IOO INTRODUCTION HE business of literature is the presentation Tof life, all true literature resolves itself into that. No presentation of life is complete without its sins, and every master of literary art has known it, from the poet King of Israel to Robert Browning. The imagination of the Middle Ages, in many ways more virile and expansive than our own, had a strong grasp of this fact, and realised that it is the sense of fault or error that lies at the root of every forward movement, that there is no real progress unless it is accompanied by a sense of sin.
    [Show full text]
  • Socrates and Democratic Athens: the Story of the Trial in Its Historical and Legal Contexts
    Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics Socrates and democratic Athens: The story of the trial in its historical and legal contexts. Version 1.0 July 2006 Josiah Ober Princeton University Abstract: Socrates was both a loyal citizen (by his own lights) and a critic of the democratic community’s way of doing things. This led to a crisis in 339 B.C. In order to understand Socrates’ and the Athenian community’s actions (as reported by Plato and Xenophon) it is necessary to understand the historical and legal contexts, the democratic state’s commitment to the notion that citizens are resonsible for the effects of their actions, and Socrates’ reasons for preferring to live in Athens rather than in states that might (by his lights) have had substantively better legal systems. Written for the Cambridge Companion to Socrates. © Josiah Ober. [email protected] Socrates and democratic Athens: The story of the trial in its historical and legal contexts. (for Cambridge Companion to Socrates) Josiah Ober, Princeton University Draft of August 2004 In 399 B.C. the Athenian citizen Socrates, son of Sophroniscus of the deme (township) Alopece, was tried by an Athenian court on the charge of impiety (asebeia). He was found guilty by a narrow majority of the empanelled judges and executed in the public prison a few days later. The trial and execution constitute the best documented events in Socrates’ life and a defining moment in the relationship between Greek philosophy and Athenian democracy. Ever since, philosophers and historians have sought to
    [Show full text]
  • Mark Twain's Writing During His Last Twenty Years: the Conflicts of A
    Mark Twain’s Writing During his Last Twenty Years: The Conflicts of a Moralist Senior Paper Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For a Degree Bachelor of Arts with A Major in Literature at The University of North Carolina at Asheville Fall 2009 By BRYCE ARGHIERE ____________________ Thesis Director Dr. Blake Hobby ____________________ Thesis Advisor Dr. Gary Ettari Arghiere 2 Unlike much of his earlier writing, most of Mark Twain’s later work presents a grim view of the human race. From roughly 1895 onwards, Twain’s writing contains few of the features for which it first gained recognition: frontier humor, as in “The Celebrated Jumping Frog of Calaveras County” (1867); commentary on rural American life, as in The Adventures of Tom Sawyer (1876) and The Adventures of Huckleberry Finn (1884); and satirical social criticism, as in The Innocents Abroad (1869) and The Prince and the Pauper (1881). Rather, many of his later works deal with philosophical concerns: psychological egoism (the theory that all acts are primarily self-interested), determinism, and solipsism. These concerns appear in Twain’s later correspondences; in The Mysterious Stranger Manuscripts (published posthumously in 1969), a collection of three unfinished narratives; and in What Is Man? (1906), a Socratic dialogue which Twain called his “Bible” (“535. Clemens To Howells” 689). By reviewing the philosophical ideas in these works we can gain insights into several conflicts in Twain’s writing which brought about a dramatic shift in style and a radically different depiction of the human race. Despite the wealth of criticism on Twain’s later works and views and on the conflicts inherent in them, few critics have explored in depth the significance of Twain’s passionate interest in several eighteenth- and nineteenth-century ideas and movements for his later thought, writing, and response to injustice and personal tragedy.
    [Show full text]
  • Killing of Eratosthenes Between Reality and Mime (Or, Was Lysias 1 Really Pronounced?)
    GRAECO-LATINA BRUNENSIA 18, 2013, 1 PAVEL NÝVLT (CHARLES UNIVERSITY, PRAGUE) KILLING OF ERATOSTHENES BETWEEN REALITY AND MIME (OR, WAS LYSIAS 1 REALLY PRONOUNCED?) Lysias’ speech On the Murder of Eratosthenes deals with a case of a husband (named Euphiletus) who caught an adulterer (called Eratosthenes) in flagrante delicto with his wife, killed him and pleaded before a court that what he had done was in keeping with law. In a stimulating article written in 1997, J. R. Porter pointed out many parallels with plots of mimes and adduced some additional arguments from comparison with other Athenian court speeches, which led him to suggest that the speech has never been pronounced and is actu‑ ally a rhetorical exhibition, made by Lysias in order to advertise his skill. The main purpose of this paper is to challenge this assumption. Further, a tentative suggestion concerning the date of the speech’s composition is made. A problem of a familiarity of average Athenian with mimic productions is raised, too. Key words: Lysias, ancient Greek oratory, ancient Greek mime, Athens. Lysias, son of Cephalus, an elder contemporary of Plato, was ranked among the ten canonical Attic orators by the Alexandrine scholars and was famous for lucidity of his style and vividness of his characterisation (etho‑ poiia).1 It is commonly held2 that he began his literary career in 403 BCE, after his family’s prospering weaponry manufacture had been confiscat- ed by an oligarchic régime of Thirty tyrants. Lysias then became a log‑ ographos, that is, a man who was writing court speeches for others.3 Of 1 For the precise meaning of the term which implies rather an active creation of char- acter than its precise description, see, e.
    [Show full text]
  • Circumscribing European Crusading Violence Susanna A
    Ursinus College Digital Commons @ Ursinus College History Faculty Publications History Department 2018 'Not Cruelty But Piety': Circumscribing European Crusading Violence Susanna A. Throop Ursinus College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.ursinus.edu/history_fac Part of the Christianity Commons, Ethics in Religion Commons, European History Commons, History of Christianity Commons, History of Religion Commons, Islamic Studies Commons, Islamic World and Near East History Commons, Medieval History Commons, and the Medieval Studies Commons Click here to let us know how access to this document benefits oy u. Recommended Citation Throop, Susanna A., "'Not Cruelty But Piety': Circumscribing European Crusading Violence" (2018). History Faculty Publications. 8. https://digitalcommons.ursinus.edu/history_fac/8 This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the History Department at Digital Commons @ Ursinus College. It has been accepted for inclusion in History Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Ursinus College. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1 ‘Not Cruelty but Piety’: Circumscribing European Crusading Violence Susanna A. Throop Traditionally the crusading movement has been distinguished from other forms of Christian violence motivated or justified in religious terms. In the western world, innumerable books and articles discuss ‘the crusades’ or ‘the crusading movement’ as discrete entities. The crusades, so the narrative goes, began firmly in 1096 when an armed, penitential expedition set out to Jerusalem in response to the 1095 appeal of Pope Urban II, and ended less conclusively at some point before the onset of modernity. Meanwhile, in a broader global context and across a wider range of media, some continue to invoke the crusades as explanation for ongoing geopolitical conflict.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtuous Life, Honored Afterlife and the Evolution of Confucianism
    History in the Making Volume 10 Article 7 January 2017 Virtuous Life, Honored Afterlife and the Evolution of Confucianism Jasmyn Murrell CSUSB Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.lib.csusb.edu/history-in-the-making Part of the Asian History Commons Recommended Citation Murrell, Jasmyn (2017) "Virtuous Life, Honored Afterlife and the Evolution of Confucianism," History in the Making: Vol. 10 , Article 7. Available at: https://scholarworks.lib.csusb.edu/history-in-the-making/vol10/iss1/7 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the History at CSUSB ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in History in the Making by an authorized editor of CSUSB ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Jasmyn Murrell Virtuous Life, Honored Afterlife and the Evolution of Confucianism By Jasmyn Murrell Abstract: Confucius states that we must not focus on the afterlife, because we know so little of it, and we must focus on everyday life. However, Confucianism holds a philosophy of afterlife, even if it is not outright said or depicted. This paper will aim to prove just that. First, through Confucian ideals of being a dutiful person, to grant yourself an honored afterlife, and second, through how Confucianism influenced other religions such as Buddhism and Daoism, which will show a clear depiction of afterlife by considering death rituals, festivals, commune with ancestors, prayers, tomb decor, and the ideology of Confucianism, Daoism, and Buddhism – you will begin to see the depiction of afterlife within Confucianism. But also, you will get to see how Confucianism has evolved and took on traits of both Daoism and Buddhism, which in turn is called Neo-Confucianism.
    [Show full text]
  • Morality and the Ring Fall 2018
    Welcome to your life! Now What? The Question: How should I live? “Free at Last!” • You’re adults! – Cool, huh? • You no longer have to do what others tell you to do …. – Your parents – Your teachers – Your religion • What Now? --What should you do? What to do? • How should you live? • How should you choose? • What do you want to do? • What do you get to do? • What makes you happy? • Is being happy all that matters? • What is the “good life?” • What is “justice?” Moral Philosophy • How should I live? – How should we live? • And why? • Is there such a thing a moral obligation? – Are there things that, morally speaking, you should do, even if you don’t want to? • Is there some general principle that makes things “morally right” or “morally wrong?” Moral Philosophy What is morality? Why should we act morally? Is there an objective “moral code?” What is “justice?” Is it morally OK to do whatever I want to do? How do I decide what I want to do? What makes things “moral?” • Is morality subjective? Is it simply a matter of personal preference or personal “taste?” • Is morality culturally relative? Does what’s right or wrong depend upon society? • Is morality “God’s will?” Is something right because God allows it and wrong because God forbids it? • Is morality “absolute?” Are there “objective” moral truths? Well? What do YOU think? If you have no opinion, then I guess that means it would be alright for me to assign your grades at random, … …right? A Thought Experiment What would you do If you knew You’d never get caught? If you could be INVISIBLE? Plato and Socrates Plato: 428-327 BC uBorn in Athens, to upper-class family uGave up a life in politics to study with another Athenian, named Socrates uWas present when Socrates died in 399 BC uFounded the “Academy,” the first university in the western world.
    [Show full text]