Florida State University Libraries

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Florida State University Libraries )ORULGD6WDWH8QLYHUVLW\/LEUDULHV 2020 Not a Tale of Alcinous: A Reading of the Myth of Er Jacob Dvorak Follow this and additional works at DigiNole: FSU's Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected] THE FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF ARTS & SCIENCES NOT A TALE OF ALCINOUS: A READING OF THE MYTH OF ER By JACOB DVORAK A Thesis submitted to the Department of Classics in partial fulfillment of the requirements for graduation with Honors in the Major Degree Awarded: Spring, 2020 Dvorak 2 The members of the Defense Committee approve the thesis of Jacob Dvorak defended on March 30th, 2020. ______________________________ Associate Professor Svetla Slaveva-Griffin Thesis Director ______________________________ Associate Professor Nathanael Stein Outside Committee Member ______________________________ Assistant Professor Virginia Lewis Committee Member *Signatures on file with the Honors Program Office* Dvorak 3 Table of Contents Iὀtὄὁἶuἵtiὁὀμ “ἦhἷ ἦalἷ ὁf a Stὄὁὀg εaὀ” ...................................................................................... 4 I. Reading the Myth of Er: Political, Mythological, and Allegorical ............................................... 8 IIέ ἦhἷ Juἶgmἷὀt ὁf Sὁulὅμ ἑἷὂhaluὅ’ ἔἷaὄ, ἕlauἵὁὀ’ὅ ἑhallἷὀgἷ, aὀἶ χἶἷimaὀtuὅ’ ἤἷὃuἷὅt ........16 Cephalus’ Fear and the Non-Philosopher’s View of Justice ......................................................16 Glaucon’s Challenge and Adeimantus’ Request ........................................................................20 What Should a Soul Fear?: Punishment in the Myth of Er .........................................................31 III. The Spindle of Necessity: The Philosophical Myth and its Messenger .....................................38 The Allegorical Interpretation of Myth in the Phaedrus .............................................................38 How Can a Platonic Myth have Meaning? ................................................................................41 Everyman and ϊaimὀ: Er as Interpretive Lens ........................................................................44 “Binder of the Heavens”: the Spindle of Necessity and an Ordered Cosmos .............................51 IV. The Lottery of Lives: Day-Dwelling Souls and the Choice of Odysseus ..................................60 “The Divine is Blameless”: Human Choice in the Lottery of Lives ............................................61 The Search for Philosophy and the Choices of Heroes ..............................................................65 The Choice of Odysseus: Katabasis as Allegory for Moral Thought ..........................................72 ἑὁὀἵluὅiὁὀμ “ἦhἷ εyth Waὅ ἠὁt δὁὅt”.........................................................................................81 Bibliography .................................................................................................................................85 Dvorak 4 Introduction: “ἦhἷ ἦalἷ ὁf a Stὄὁὀg εaὀ” Slain in battle, a warrior awakes in a place between the human world and the world of the gods. He approaches four openings in the ground and the sky. Through the chasms pass streams of souls, some headed to be rewarded, some to be punished, and some returning their journeys in heaven and the underworld. Souls are usually judged and sent on their way, but when the warrior approaches the chasms, he is told that he will not be judged, but that he will be a messenger of what he sees in this afterlife. The warrior walks with the souls to see a massive beam of light binding the heavens together. Around the beam turn spheres, like the whorls of a spindle, and atop the spheres sit Sirens singing in harmony. The spheres are turned by the three Fates and sitting silent above them is the goddess Necessity. The souls gather and are given lots. They will choose their next lives and will then return to Earth to live them. Some souls choose well, and some poorly. Some souls choose the lives of animals, some the lives of humans. The last soul to choose is the soul of the hero Odysseus, who chooses a peaceful private life. The souls then drink from the River of Forgetfulness and lie down to sleep. They shoot off into the sky like stars, and the warrior awakes on a funeral pyre, days after he died. He tells his story, and it survives. This myth is how Plato ends his Republic. Why does a dialogue rooted in a historical place, at a historical time, and populated by historical figures, end with this vision of the afterlife, attributed to a fictional character? Does the story have a philosophical meaning, or is it just a poetic flourish at the end of a philosophical work? And why does Plato appropriate characters and imagery from the poets he criticizes? Is he simply reacting to previous authors, or is his relationship to his predecessors more complicated? These are all questions one faces when reading the Myth of Er. Readings that answer them too quickly or dismissively can miss important elements of the Republic, from the dynamics Dvorak 5 between its characters to indications that politics cannot address ethics to a demonstration of the importance of imagination and literature for moral thinking. My thesis will not attempt to discover all of the implications of the Myth of Er, nor will it ἵlaim tὁ uὀἵὁvἷὄ itὅ “tὄuἷ mἷaὀiὀgέ” ἤathἷὄ, I will, by analyzing the literary elements of Platὁ’ὅ wὄitiὀg, aὀἶ ἴy ἷxamiὀiὀg thἷ myth with a fὁἵuὅ on its allegorical meaning, argue that it cannot be dismissed as inconsistent with the Republic, incoherent philosophically, or bluntly anti-Homeric. Rather, the myth complements the dialogue it ends; has a philosophical meaning expressed, not through argument, but through character and setting; and responds to a central moral theme of the poetry before Plato. I do not argue these points for their own sakes, but rather to show the rewards of taking Platὁ’ὅ mythὅ ὅἷὄiὁuὅlyέ I will begin with a chapter on previous reading of the Myth of Er. Chapter I will discuss a political reading of the myth, which argues that its purpose is only rhetorical, as well as a mythological reading of the myth, which analyzes thἷ myth iὀ thἷ ἵὁὀtἷxt ὁf ἢlatὁ’ὅ hὁὅtilἷ criticism of past authors. I argue that these readings miss important elements of the myth, and I propose that an allegorical reading would better reveal the meaning intended for philosophical readers, rather than the reductive reading meant for the non-philosopher. I also note that an allegorical reading would still allow for literary analysis and other methods of criticism which ἵὁulἶ lἷaἶ tὁ thἷ myth’ὅ mἷaὀiὀgέ In Chapter II, I turn to a major set-piece of the Myth of Er, the Judgment of Souls. I will argue that the myth, in showing the punishment of souls who are vicious and the rewards for souls who are just, does not contradict earlier points of the Republic, but rather complements and completes those points. The myth answers concerns raised by Cephalus, Glaucon, and Adeimantus in Books 1 and 2; it responds to the fear Cephalus has of punishment in the underworld, the challenge Glaucon issues to provide an account of justice as desirable in itself, the Adeimantuὅ’ request to find a way of talking about vice in a way that does not encourage listeners to be vicious. Dvorak 6 Chapter III turns to another set-piece, the Spindle of Necessity. Here, I will address the philosophical coherence of the myth. This will require me to address the criticism of allegory presented in the Phaedrus. I will argue that this criticism applies to Homeric myth, but not to Platonic myth. Because the cosmos Plato portrays in the myth is ordered, open to human reason, and impactful on human life, it can be allegorized and can have a philosophical meaning. This mἷaὀiὀg iὅ ὅymἴὁliὐἷἶ ἴy thἷ Sὂiὀἶlἷ ὁf ἠἷἵἷὅὅity, whiἵh, aὅ a thiὀg whiἵh “ἴiὀἶὅ thἷ hἷavἷὀὅ,” also connects the divine to the human. The character of Er is constructed to facilitate the conceptualization of such a cosmos, and is key to understanding how the myth has philosophical meaning. Chapter IV, on the Lottery of Lives, continues the analyὅiὅ ὁf thἷ myth’ὅ ὂhilὁὅὁὂhiἵal meaning, but also introduces the problem of inspiration, in my chapter on the Lottery of Lives. I will analyze how the Homeric heroes that appear in this part of the myth represent different character types based on their roles in the poetic tradition. I will finally focus on the choice of Odysseus, which places ἢlatὁ’ὅ ἶἷὂiἵtiὁὀ ὁf ἵhὁiἵἷ ὁf lifἷ iὀ ἵὁὀtἷxt with ώὁmἷὄ’ὅ tὄἷatmἷὀt ὁf thἷ same theme. Plato is responding to Homer, not solely as a critic, but also as a literary writer who ἶἷὂἷὀἶὅ ὁὀ ώὁmἷὄ’ὅ thὁught tὁ ἷxὂὄἷὅὅ hiὅ ὁwὀέ Iὀ faἵt, if ώὁmἷὄiἵ myth wἷὄἷ ἷntirely banished fὄὁm thἷ ὄἷaἶἷὄ’ὅ miὀἶ, thἷ εyth ὁf Eὄ wὁulἶ ἴἷ lἷὅὅ ἵὁhἷὄἷὀt, aὀἶ thἷ ἵhὁiἵἷὅ ὁf thἷ hἷὄὁἷὅ iὀ particular would mean much less. My reading highlightὅ thἷ ὄὁlἷ ὁf litἷὄaὄy ἷlἷmἷὀtὅ ὁf ἢlatὁ’ὅ wὄitiὀg, iὀἵluἶiὀg ἵhaὄaἵtἷὄ, setting, and myths. These ἷlἷmἷὀtὅ fὄamἷ thἷ aὄgumἷὀtὅ ἢlatὁ’ὅ ἵhaὄaἵtἷὄὅ makἷ aὀἶ at timἷὅ introduce myths as responses to philosophical discourse. That this happens at all necessitates a consideration for the poetic and literary parts of Plato. If a reading discounts the myths of Plato as rhetorical, reactionary, or superfluous to the arguments of the dialogues, it misses out on the roles Dvorak 7 those myths play, not only in the philosophical meanings they provide, but also in the way they ὄἷὅὂὁὀἶ tὁ ἢlatὁ’ὅ ἵhaὄaἵtἷὄὅ aὀἶ ὂὁἷtic predecessors. This reading places the myth in its context as part of the Republic,
Recommended publications
  • Resemblance and Camouflage in Graeco-Roman Antiquity 169
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Institutional Research Information System University of Turin Sign Systems Studies 38(1/4), 2010 1 2 3 4 5 6 Resemblance and camouflage 7 in Graeco-Roman antiquity 8 Massimo Leone 9 Department of Philosophy, University of Turin 10 Via S. Ottavio 20, 10124, Torino, Italy 11 e-mail: [email protected] 12 13 Abstract. In the twenty-eighth book of the Naturalis Historia Pliny the Elder 14 claims that, if a chameleon’s left leg is roasted together with a herb bearing the 15 same name, and everything is mixed with ointment, cut in lozenges, and stored in 16 a wooden little box, this will bestow on those who own it a perfect camouflage. 17 The ring of Gyges (Plato, etc.), that of Midas (Pliny), the heliotropium (Pliny), the 18 dracontitis (Philostratus): ancient cultures abound with references to objects, 19 recipes, and techniques able to bestow different kinds of invisibility, meant as a 20 perfect resemblance with the environment. At the same time, these same cultures 21 also teem with references to how to avert the perfect camouflage: for instance, by 22 being endowed with a pupula duplex, a double pupil (Ovid). 23 The paper explores such vast corpus of texts from the point of view of a 24 semiotics of cultures, in order to track the roots of a conception of camouflage 25 that, from these ancient cultures on, develops through intricate paths into the 26 contemporary imaginaires (and practices) of invisibility.
    [Show full text]
  • Mythological Magic Items
    MY T H O LO G I C A L MAGIC ITEMS Sample file MYTHOLOGICAL MAGIC ITEMS Introduction: The magical creations herein hail from classical antiquity. Whether they be in the hands of friend or foe, they are certain to infuse your game with a certain mythological flavor straight from the epic poems of old! In addition to 30 magic items, there is also a bonus creature from the gates of hell. Author: Eugene Marshall Layout: Amy Bliss Marshall Cover: Figure Inks by Bien Flores, Figure Colors by Basith Ibrahim, Background Image by Yusef Dundar Interior Art: art made available under the Community Content Agreement for the DMs Guild by Wizards of the Coast and from Edouard Dognin, Mateus Campos, Mike Gorrell, & Milada Vigerova Sample file DUNGEONS & DRAGONS, D&D, Wizards of the Coast, Forgotten Realms, Ravenloft, Eberron, the dragon ampersand, Ravnica and all other Wizards of the Coast product names, and their respective logos are trademarks of Wizards of the Coast in the USA and other countries. This work contains material that is copyright Wizards of the Coast and/or other authors. Such material is used with permission under the Community Content Agreement for Dungeon Masters Guild. All other original material in this work is copyright 2019 by Eugene Marshall & Arcanist Press and published under the Community Content Agreement for Dungeon Masters Guild. Table of Contents Magic Items Aegis of Zeus 4 Hercules’ Club 7 Aeolus’ Bag of Gales 4 Lantern of Diogenes 7 Ambrosia 4 Lyre of Apollo 7 Archimedes’ Mirror 4 Odysseus’ Bow 7 Artemis’ Longbow of the
    [Show full text]
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Nuclear Disarmament Is a Utopia
    International Journal of Security Studies Volume 2 Issue 1 Article 6 2020 WHY NUCLEAR DISARMAMENT IS A UTOPIA YOVANI EDGAR CHAVEZ National Air Naval Service (Republic of Panama), [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.northgeorgia.edu/ijoss Part of the Defense and Security Studies Commons Recommended Citation CHAVEZ, YOVANI EDGAR (2020) "WHY NUCLEAR DISARMAMENT IS A UTOPIA," International Journal of Security Studies: Vol. 2 : Iss. 1 , Article 6. Available at: https://digitalcommons.northgeorgia.edu/ijoss/vol2/iss1/6 This Focus Articles is brought to you for free and open access by Nighthawks Open Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in International Journal of Security Studies by an authorized editor of Nighthawks Open Institutional Repository. WHY NUCLEAR DISARMAMENT IS A UTOPIA Introduction Centuries ago, ancient literature told the legend of the ring of Gyges, a ring capable of making its owner invisible to act with no consequences and be able to seduce both just and unjust men to commit injustice.1 It was so powerful that it transformed a mere shepherd into a mighty king. In the same way, governments around the world have been seduced to develop their own nuclear-weapon ring of Gyges to obtain maximum power and guarantee survival. Because the international community has tried to prevent wars to no avail, it is imperative for states to develop mechanisms to protect themselves. In that regard, nuclear weapons are the best guarantee of survival. During World War II, the international community saw how the United States used nuclear weapons to defeat Japan.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ring of Gyges
    The Ring of Gyges Retold by Jason Buckley Once in the ancient kingdom of Lydia, there lived a shepherd called Gyges. The sheep he looked after were not his own. They belonged to the King. One day, when Gyges was out grazing the flocks, there was a great storm. Lightning stabbed at the earth, and crashes of thunder swept the sky. Then an earthquake shook the hills, answering the thunderclaps with the crunching of stone on stone. When the storm and the earthquake were over and all was quiet again Gyges was amazed to see that a hole had opened up in the earth. When he looked into it, he saw a long tunnel. At the end, he could just make out the faint glimmer of shining metal. He took a torch and followed the tunnel, which opened into a cave. In the centre of the cave, surrounded by many other wonderful things, was an enormous horse made of bronze. Stranger still, the horse had doors, and inside them lay ... a huge body. Not just the body of a large man, but of a small giant. The body was wearing a gold ring, set with a single gem. Gyges took the ring and went back up. The king’s shepherds all met together. They talked about the storm and about whose turn it was to visit the king and report on how the flocks were doing. While Gyges was sitting with them, he happened to twist the ring so that the gem was on the inside of his hand. He was amazed to hear the other shepherds talking about him as if he was not there at all.
    [Show full text]
  • Ring of Gyges” Effect: an Ethical Critique of Lethal Remotely Piloted Aircraft by Matthew D
    The “Ring of Gyges” Effect: An Ethical Critique of Lethal Remotely Piloted Aircraft by Matthew D. Pride The U.S. Army pledges to defend the country against all enemies, foreign and domestic, in a manner that upholds national values. One such way recent presidential administrations make good on their pledge to protect the American people is by authorizing military strikes using the remotely piloted aircrafts (RPA). If RPA do act as a political deposit on the sacred oath sworn by our leaders to protect and defend the constitution, does the policy likewise uphold the traditional norms associated with justice in war (jus in bello)? In other words, does the U.S. Government violate jus in bello in its use of RPA to conduct military strikes? This article aims for two broad areas. The first, and most substantial, is the legal and moral basis for any justifiable military action. The second deals in understanding the intention behind such policy that uses RPA to achieve a desired end state. This article critiques the morality, legality, and military ethics of the United States’ RPA Policy. Introduction and Background If it remains true that “the strongest is never strong enough to be always the master, unless he transforms his strength” into virtue, we may ask ourselves the following question: what kind of right or virtue is needed by these modern Gyges? ― Grégoire Chamayou, 2015 U.S. elected officials and military professionals pledge to defend the country against all enemies, foreign and domestic, in a manner that upholds national values and principles. One such way in which the executive branch of government makes good on their pledge to protect the American people is by authorizing military strikes using remotely piloted aircrafts (RPA).
    [Show full text]
  • Killing of Eratosthenes Between Reality and Mime (Or, Was Lysias 1 Really Pronounced?)
    GRAECO-LATINA BRUNENSIA 18, 2013, 1 PAVEL NÝVLT (CHARLES UNIVERSITY, PRAGUE) KILLING OF ERATOSTHENES BETWEEN REALITY AND MIME (OR, WAS LYSIAS 1 REALLY PRONOUNCED?) Lysias’ speech On the Murder of Eratosthenes deals with a case of a husband (named Euphiletus) who caught an adulterer (called Eratosthenes) in flagrante delicto with his wife, killed him and pleaded before a court that what he had done was in keeping with law. In a stimulating article written in 1997, J. R. Porter pointed out many parallels with plots of mimes and adduced some additional arguments from comparison with other Athenian court speeches, which led him to suggest that the speech has never been pronounced and is actu‑ ally a rhetorical exhibition, made by Lysias in order to advertise his skill. The main purpose of this paper is to challenge this assumption. Further, a tentative suggestion concerning the date of the speech’s composition is made. A problem of a familiarity of average Athenian with mimic productions is raised, too. Key words: Lysias, ancient Greek oratory, ancient Greek mime, Athens. Lysias, son of Cephalus, an elder contemporary of Plato, was ranked among the ten canonical Attic orators by the Alexandrine scholars and was famous for lucidity of his style and vividness of his characterisation (etho‑ poiia).1 It is commonly held2 that he began his literary career in 403 BCE, after his family’s prospering weaponry manufacture had been confiscat- ed by an oligarchic régime of Thirty tyrants. Lysias then became a log‑ ographos, that is, a man who was writing court speeches for others.3 Of 1 For the precise meaning of the term which implies rather an active creation of char- acter than its precise description, see, e.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato-Ring-Of-Gyges.Pdf
    ;,. With all reading assignments, I assign an un-graded one p~ge.writing exercise i.n o~der to help students begin processing the ideas.. They get credit simply for comple~lng It, and this constitytes a "class preparation" portion of their grade (about 10%). I find then that I rarely need to worry about class participation since they come much better prepared to discuss the material in class. For this piece, I would ask them to try to explain what Glaucon thinks the story of the Ring of Gyges demonstrates. The Ring of Gyg~s Plato Plato (ca. 428-348 [or 347] B.C.), considered by many to be the greatest phi­ losopher who ever lived, is the author of The Republic and other great dia­ logues. Plato's influence on Western culture is incalculable. In The Republic, Plato describes the ideal society where justice reigns supreme. It opens with a scene in which Socrates confronts powerful arguments that .dis­ parage justice. We find Glaucon summarizing the views of those who think that justice is merely a compromise between the freedom to do wrong with impunity and to sufferwrong without redress. GLAUCON (TO I have never heard from anyone the sort of defence ofjustice SOCRATES): that I want to hear, proving that it is better than injustice. I want to hear it praised for itself, and I think I am most likely Excerpt from Tilr Repliblic by Plato, pp. 31-33. Translated by G. M. A. Grube. copyright 1974 by Hackett Publishing Company. Inc., reprinted by perl11i.~sion ofHackett Publishing Company, Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • JPT 8.1 F3 3-32-Adluri.Indd
    The International Journal The International Journal of the of the Platonic Tradition 8 (2014) 3-32 Platonic Tradition brill.com/jpt Plato’s Saving Mūthos: The Language of Salvation in the Republic Vishwa Adluri [email protected] Abstract This article discusses the Homeric background of the Republic with the aim of eluci- dating Plato’s critique of Homeric nostos. It argues that the Republic unfolds as a nostos voyage, with Socrates striving to steer the soul home. Even though Segal has already argued for seeing the Republic as an Odyssean voyage, this article suggests that Plato does more than simply borrow the idea of a voyage as a metaphor for the wanderings of the soul. Rather, there is an implicit critique of Homer as the “poet of Becoming” in the dialogue. Thus, reading the Republic in the context of other Platonic dialogues such as the Cratylus and Theaetetus where Socrates identifies Homer as the source of the view that Ocean is the origin of all things (Crat. 402b, Theaet. 180d) and that everything is in flux (Theaet. 180d) allows us to better appreciate Socrates’ critique of poets in the Republic. At stake in this critique is ultimately the question of the soul’s true nostos, which Plato identifies with a vertical ascent (Rep. 521c, 532b) to Being rather than with a temporary homecoming within Becoming. This article contributes to the elucidation of the Homeric and pre-Socratic background of Platonic philosophy. It undertakes a literary reading of the Republic against the background of the hero’s journey motif. Specifically, it argues that Plato critiques and emends the Odyssean nostos in order to make space for Parmenidean ontology, thus forging a new understanding of salvation.
    [Show full text]
  • JPT 8.1 F3 3-32-Adluri.Indd
    The International Journal The International Journal of the of the Platonic Tradition 8 (2014) 3-32 Platonic Tradition brill.com/jpt Plato’s Saving Mūthos: The Language of Salvation in the Republic Vishwa Adluri [email protected] Abstract This article discusses the Homeric background of the Republic with the aim of eluci- dating Plato’s critique of Homeric nostos. It argues that the Republic unfolds as a nostos voyage, with Socrates striving to steer the soul home. Even though Segal has already argued for seeing the Republic as an Odyssean voyage, this article suggests that Plato does more than simply borrow the idea of a voyage as a metaphor for the wanderings of the soul. Rather, there is an implicit critique of Homer as the “poet of Becoming” in the dialogue. Thus, reading the Republic in the context of other Platonic dialogues such as the Cratylus and Theaetetus where Socrates identifies Homer as the source of the view that Ocean is the origin of all things (Crat. 402b, Theaet. 180d) and that everything is in flux (Theaet. 180d) allows us to better appreciate Socrates’ critique of poets in the Republic. At stake in this critique is ultimately the question of the soul’s true nostos, which Plato identifies with a vertical ascent (Rep. 521c, 532b) to Being rather than with a temporary homecoming within Becoming. This article contributes to the elucidation of the Homeric and pre-Socratic background of Platonic philosophy. It undertakes a literary reading of the Republic against the background of the hero’s journey motif. Specifically, it argues that Plato critiques and emends the Odyssean nostos in order to make space for Parmenidean ontology, thus forging a new understanding of salvation.
    [Show full text]
  • The Piety of Thought in Plato's Republic, Book 1 Author(S): Darrell Dobbs Source: the American Political Science Review, Vol
    The Piety of Thought in Plato's Republic, Book 1 Author(s): Darrell Dobbs Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 88, No. 3 (Sep., 1994), pp. 668-683 Published by: American Political Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2944802 Accessed: 10/12/2010 23:53 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=apsa. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Political Science Review. http://www.jstor.org American Political Science Review Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • 2016 Actc Proceedings
    TRADITION & RENEWAL TRADITION AND RENEWAL: CONTINUITY AND CHANGE IN CORE AND LIBERAL ARTS PROGRAMS Selected Papers from the Twenty-Second Annual Conference of the Association of Core Texts and Courses, Atlanta, April 14–17, 2016 Edited by Tuan Hoang Association for Core Texts and Courses ACTC Liberal Arts Institute 2021 Acknowledgments (Park) CREDIT LINE: Excerpt(s) from THE BIRTH OF TRAGEDY AND THE CASE OF WAGNER by Friedrich Nietzsche, translated by Walter Kaufmann, translation copyright © 1967 by Walter Kaufmann. Used by permission of Random House, an imprint and division of Penguin Random House LLC. All rights reserved. (McGrath) Excerpt(s) from THE SPIRIT OF THE LAWS by Montesquieu, translated and edited by Anne M. Cohler, Basia Carolyn Miller, and Harold Samuel Stone, translation copyright © 1989 by Anne M. Cohler, Basia Carolyn Miller, and Harold Samuel Stone. Used by permission of Cambridge University Press. All rights reserved. (Galaty) Excerpt(s) from DISCOVERIES AND OPINIONS OF GALILEO by Galileo, translated by Stillman Drake, translation copyright © 1957 by Stillman Drake. Used by permission of Doubleday, an imprint of the Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group, a division of Penguin Random House LLC. All rights reserved. Contents Introduction: Core Texts and Tradition in Atlanta Tuan Hoang ix Tradition Juxtaposed and Complicated The Oral Voice in Ancient and Contemporary Texts Jay Lutz 3 On the Unity of the Great French Triumvirate John Ray 7 Burke, MacIntyre, and Two Concepts of Tradition Wade Roberts 13 Happiness as a Moral End: On Prudence in Kant’s Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals and Austen’s Persuasion Jane Kelley Rodehoffer 19 “The Stranger God” and the “Artistic Socrates”: On Nietzsche and Plato in Thomas Mann’s Death in Venice Julie Park 27 The Human Person in Core Texts Unheroic Heroes: Ambiguous Categories in Three Core Texts Michael D.
    [Show full text]