Subjectivity and Paul Ricoeur and the Question of Naturalizing Personhood Rosfort, René

Publication date: 2008

Document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record

Document license: CC BY-NC-ND

Citation for published version (APA): Rosfort, R. (2008). Subjectivity and Ethics: Paul Ricoeur and the Question of Naturalizing Personhood. Det Teologiske Fakultet. Publikationer fra Det Teologiske Fakultet No. 2

Download date: 01. okt.. 2021 RENÉ ROSFORT ISBN 978-87-91838-09-05

RENÉ ROSFORT Subjectivity and Ethics Ricoeur and the Qustion of Naturalizing Personhood Ricoeur and the Question of Naturalizing Personhood Subjectivity and Ethics RENÉ ROSFORT

Subjectivity and Ethics Ricoeur and the Question of Naturalizing Personhood

Publikationer fra Det Teologiske Fakultet 2 RENÉ ROSFORT ISBN 978-87-91838-09-05

RENÉ ROSFORT Subjectivity and Ethics Ricoeur and the Qustion of Naturalizing Personhood Ricoeur and the Question of Naturalizing Personhood Subjectivity and Ethics RENÉ ROSFORT

Subjectivity and Ethics Ricoeur and the Question of Naturalizing Personhood

Publikationer fra Det Teologiske Fakultet 2

Subjectivity and Ethics Ricoeur and the Question of Naturalizing Personhood

Ph.D.-Thesis by René Rosfort Funded by Copenhagen University's Research Priority Area Body and Mind Submitted for defence at the Faculty of Theology University of Copenhagen 1 February 2008

Subjectivity and Ethics Ricoeur and the Question of Naturalizing Personhood Publikationer fra Det Teologiske Fakultet 2

Licensed under CreativeCommons René Rosfort

ISBN: 978-87-91838-09-05 (trykt) ISBN: 978-87-91838-98-9 (pdf) Københavns Universitet 2008

Udgivet af Det Teologiske Fakultet Københavns Universitet Købmagergade 44-46 1150 København K

Contents

Introduction 1 Subjectivity, Ethics, and Naturalization 3 Structure of the Analyses 6

Part One Ricoeur's Theory of Subjectivity

Chapter One: The Stripped Notion of Subjectivity 9

Basic Methodological Concepts 9 Transcendental Synthesis 10 Intentionality 12 The Originating Affirmation 14 Experience: Between Reason and Sensibility 18 Transcendental Imagination 20 Action: The Practical Space of Reason 26 Decision 28 Motivation and Value 29 The Practical Space of Reason 32 The Subject as a Person in Front of Other Persons 35 The Person in between Character and Happiness 39 Affectivity: The Conflict of Feelings 43 Disproportion and Fallibility 43 The Nature of Feeling 45 Outline for an Ontology 50

Chapter Two: The Redressed Notion of Subjectivity

Basic Methodological Concepts 55 Hermeneutical Phenomenology 56 Narrative Identity 65 The Affected Subject: Body and Alterity 70 Non-immediacy and Ambivalence of the Body 71 Passivity and an Ontology of the Flesh 73 Action: Selfhood and Identity 78 Motives and Causes 81 The Narrating Subject: Personhood and Identity 82 Ethical Experience: The Practical Space of Reason 91 The Configuration of Experience 93 The Self and Other Selves: 'The Good Life' 98 Subjectivity in an Ontology of Care 101

Part Two Feeling Ethical

Chapter One: Human Affectivity

Conceptual Background 111 The Feeling Theory 111 The Cognitive Theory 114 The Narrative Theory 115 Neurophysiological Dimension of Emotions 117 Antonio Damasio: Objective Emotions and Subjective Feelings 118 Jaak Panksepp: Subjective Affectivity 123 Some Considerations on Evolution, Neurophysiology, and Intentionality 129 Conatus: Spinoza, Ricoeur, and Neuroscience 132 Emotions and Personhood: Moods and Affects 138 Personhood 138 Feelings of Being-in-the-World 141 Feelings and Emotions 142 Moods and Affects 145 The Person in between Moods and Affects 147 Human Affectivity: Feelings and Embodied Normativity 160

Chapter Two: Ethical Experience and Ontology

A Preamble: Kant, Hume on Emotions, Subjectivity, and Ethics 166 The Practical Space of Reason: Values, Concern, and the Other 170 Blackburn's Quasi-Realism and the Experience of Values 172 Experience as Structured by the Value of the Other's Concerns 178 An Ontology of Care: Personhood and the Conflictual Nature of Subjectivity 184 The Moral Space and Strong Evaluations 185 Ontology and Personhood 191 Conclusion: Subjectivity and Ethics 194

Part Three The Brain and Human Values

Chapter One: Neuroethics and Subjectivity

The Case of Casebeer and Some of his Allies: Impersonal Ethical Facts 202 The Disobeying Subject: Subjective Values and Personhood 207

Chapter Two: Personhood in Nature and Culture

Which Sort of Naturalism? 218 Not a Plea for Relativism 224 Conclusion: Naturally the Subject is a Person 231

References 236

Abstracts (English/Danish) 247 Introduction Subjectivityandethicsarebothdifficulttopicstoreconcilewithaempiricalscientificoutlookon the world and the creatures living in it. They are somewhat impalpable subjectmatters in a discourse that enhances and applauds local, observable, and experimentalproved research and whichis,toputitmildly,skepticalofattemptstoexplainhumanbehaviorinthelightoffirstperson perspectiveorgeneralprinciplesofmorality.Theoriesofethicsandsubjectivityhavetraditionally included such nonobservable perspectives and have, indeed, regarded them as fundamental for ethical debate or more general investigations into human nature. We cannot observe a rational principleoramoralsentimentinthesamemannerasweobservethemovementofthecochleaof theinnerearinresponsetosoundwaves;nonetheless,principlesandsentimentsseemtohavesome kindofinfluenceonhowwe,ashumanbeings,respondtoourenvironment.Empiricalsciencesand theoreticalinvestigationsintosubjectivityandethicshavethereforealwaysfaced(andcontinueto face)theproblemofintegratingtheirdifferentmethods,analyses,andresults. Thisproblemhasexistedthroughoutthehistoryof western thought, stressed with the scientific revolutionintheseventeenthcenturyandreemergedasadominantissueoverthelastfortyyears. Confrontedwiththeprodigiousgrowthoftechnologicaldevelopmentsandscientificrevelationsin thetwentiethcentury,philosophersandempiricalscientistshavedevelopedvariousattitudestoward theproblemofintegration,frommutualdialoguetoreductionorevencompleteeliminationofthe positionoftheother.Althoughmutualdialoguemightseemthemostsensibleanswer,thedebate hasoftenoptedfortheradicalpoleofcompleteelimination.Togetafeelingofthis,wecanlookat whattwoveryinfluentialthinkershadtosayabouttheproblemsofintegrationinthelastcentury. In1929thephilosopherMartinHeideggerlaunchesapolemicattackonthescientificenthusiasm bloominginhistime:‘Notimehasknownsomuchandsuchavarietyaboutmankindasisthecase today[…]Butalso,notimehasknownlessaboutwhatmanisthantoday.Innoothertimehasman becomeasquestionableasinours’(Heidegger1998:143/209).Theempiricalsciencescanperhaps inform us with all sorts of interesting things about mankind, but it can never solve the general problemsofbeinghuman. Almostfortyyearslater,thepaleontologistGeorgeG.Simpsonwrote,inanolesspolemicaltone, against the metaphysically (i.e. not based on scientific methods and the theory of evolution) dreamingphilosopher:‘Thequestion“WhatisMan”isprobablythemostprofoundthatcanbe askedbyman.[…]ThepointIwanttomakenowisthatallattemptstoanswerthatquestionbefore

1 1859[thepublicationofDarwin’s The Origin of Species ]areworthlessandthatwewillbebetter offifweignorethemcompletely’(Simpson1966,472). Although Simpson later in the article tends to give some kind of credit to ‘[t]he other, older approaches through , theology, art, and other nonbiological, nonscientific fields’, he persists in considering them ‘merely fictional fantasies or falsities’ (op.cit., 473) if they do not acceptthathumannatureisbiologicalorganism. Thisconvictionofanabidingnecessitytogroundallinvestigationsofhumannatureinbiologyhas becomeevenmoreprevailingtoday.Theexplosivedevelopmentinneurosciencehasinfusednew hopeintotheoldideaofanentirelynaturalizedconception of man. New techniques, intriguing results, and consequently large fundings have paved the way for the socalled neuroscientific revolutionthatinthelastthirty yearsorsohas prophesized the arrival of a new, more sincere, conceptionofhumannature(Edelman2003:5520;Metzinger2005:54;Pinker1999:563;Pinker 2003:xi;Gazzaniga2006:xviii).Togetherwiththegrowthofcognitivescience,sociobiology,and lately evolutionary psychology, neuroscience is expanding its field of interest (and presumed expertise)fromneurophysiologicalinvestigationsintospecificneuronalnetworksandbrainareasto moregeneraltheoriesabouthumannature. So,thissaid,whataretheproblemswiththeattempttonaturalizehumannature?Theproblemsare spread all over the philosophical spectrum, but the main debate has always taken place in ofmind.Withourgrowingempiricalknowledgeofthestructureanddynamicsofthe brain,wecannotjustdisposeofthatknowledgewhenwethinkaboutthemind.Themindbody problemhas,onceagain,becomethebattlefieldofempiricalsciencesandphilosophy–thistimein theshapeofamindbrainproblem.Thedebatehasbeen,andstillis,averytenseandemotionally loadedaffaire,sinceitisourveryconceptionofhumannaturethatisatstake.Often,philosophyis ridiculedasmeredaydreamingandscienceaccusedofshortsightedsuperficiality.Butthedivide existsvividlywithinthedisciplinesthemselves.Therearemanyneuroscientistswhocautionagainst the holistic tendencies within their own discipline, whereas some prominent philosophers emphasizethenecessityofdoingphilosophyonthetermsoftheempiricalsciences(e.g.Dennett, Metzinger,PaulandPatricaChurchland). As mentioned, one major point of conflict is how to integrate the scientific methods with the supposedly nonscientific ones regarding, among many others, the exploration of subjective experiencesandfeelingssuchasmoralprinciples,ideasofhappinessandgoodeducation,sadness, despair,love,redness,shame,joy,anger,inshort,ourfirstperson(orperhapsitisbettertosay

2 personal) perspective on ourselves and the world. This is the question of what philosophers traditionallyhavenamed“qualia”,i.e.,thedistinctivesubjectivecharacterofexperience.Nobody woulddenythat“qualia”exists,butmanyquestiontheirontologicalstatus.Theyhavebeenthought ofasmereepiphenomenaandfolkfantasies,orasoneoftheirmostacerbateantagonists,Daniel Dennett,puts it: ‘Qualitativeproperties that are intrinsicallyconsciousareamyth,anartefactof misguided theorizing’ (Dennett 1991: 40). Now, such a denial of these qualitative features of experience is problematic, because it often leads to the denial of the subjects that have the experiences.Andthisdenialhascriticalimplicationsforthewayweunderstandanddealwiththe natureofhumanbeings.Ontheotherside,wehavephilosophers(togetherwiththeologiansand otherbranchesofthehumanities)thatquestionthelegitimacyoftheprojectofnaturalization.They arguethatwecannotacceptexplanationsofhumannature that does not account for the specific natureofsubjectiveexperiencebutmerelyreducethemtodisturbingbyproductsorepiphenomenal illusionsofamoretrueandsolidphysicalworld.Thesubjectivefeaturesofexperiencepossessa legitimateclaimoninvestigation,becausetheyrevealthenatureofaself,whichisanindispensable partofbeinghuman.AsthephilosopherDanZahaviwritesinanswertoDennett’sharshdismissal ofsubjectivity:‘ascienceofshoulddrawonboththefirst,secondandthethird person point of view, just like all of us do when we engage in the everyday practice of understandingourselvesandothers’(Zahavi2007:38;seealsoNagel1986:15;Searle2000:423; Taylor1977b:37). ThisleadsmetotheissuethatIshalltreatinthefollowingchapters,namelytherelationbetween subjectivityandethicswithregardtotheproblemsofnaturalization. Subjectivity,Ethics,andNaturalization Subjectivityandethicsbothhavealonghistory,andtheyhaveoftencrossedeachotherupthrough thecenturies.Thecentralquestionthatformsthebackgroundfortheanalysesinthepresentworkis thefollowing:canweunderstandsubjectivitywithoutdealingwithethics,andviceversa?Ishall arguethatwecannot.This,however,isbynomeansanintuitivefact;onthecontrary,thebattlehas been going on since Socrates first attacked the sophists and their immoral selfcontradictions regarding the subjectivity of good action. Aristotle went for a subtle middleposition that emphasizedtheimportanceofhumannatureindealingwithethics,andyethestillworkedwitha certainobjectivityregardinghumancapacitiesandbehavior.HumeandAdamSmitharguedforthe subjectivenatureofmorality,whereasKantandMooreshowedthatgoodandbadaresomehow

3 independent of our subjective experience of emotions, inclinations, and . And further, the contemporarydebateshowsthatthequestionisstillarelevantonetoask.Now,thequestioncanbe askedfromatleasttwoperspectives,namelyfromethicaltheoryandfromtheoriesofsubjectivity. With regard to ethical theory, few, and perhaps no, moral philosophers would question the importanceofhumannatureinethicaldebate;therealissuewhatweunderstandbyhumannature. Howmuchofwhatitistobeahumanbeingdependsonsubjectiveexperience?Doesoursubjective coloring of the world have anything to do with how we should behave? Are moral principles somehow detached from the baser workings of desire and feeling? These questions might be answered with the claim that only firm principles are valid; or, for example, that morality is groundedinatranscendentwhohasrevealedtheinfalliblerulesforhumanconduct,whichhave nothing to do with the wretched and sinful nature of the individual subjects; or that human experienceofgoodandbadisalwaystaintedwithselfishandfutilemotivesthatdonotpromise anythingbuttotalchaos,somoralitycannotbutbegroundedinsomethingraisedabovesubjective experience;orthatthemorallygoodtranscends,insomeparticularway,oursubjectiveexperience of certain qualities, desires and inclinations and is completely different from other nonmoral propertiesintheworld.Others,however,retainthatsubjectiveexperiencehasalottosayaboutthe natureofmoralnormsandvalues;infact,theybelievethatwecannotsayanythingaboutethics without an attentive analysis of our subjective experience of the world, the other subjects and ourselves. Subjective experience matters because it is part of who we are and what we do, and dismissingitasirrelevanttoethicsis,asthemoralphilosopherSimonBlackburnwrites,thesame astodiscredit‘anytheorythatseekstoexplainourmoralcapacitiesintermsof contingentand potentially variable facets of human nature: language, culture, upbringing, acquired “second nature”,andsoon’(Blackburn2006:145).Ishalldefendthelatterpositionandtrytoarguethata thorough investigation into the nature of subjectivity will benefit the contemporary metaethical debateconcerningtherelationbetweenhumannatureandmorality. Fromthepointofviewofsubjectivitytheory,ethicalquestionshavehadaquiteambiguousstatus. Subjectivitybecameanexplicitthemewiththecoiningofphenomenology.Ofcourse,subjectivity hasbeendiscussedsinceantiquity(especiallywiththesophistsandtheskeptics),andinmodern times Locke and Leibniz took the notion under serious consideration, whereas Hume, Kant and Kierkegaard paved the way for a systematic treatment. Nevertheless, it was with the prodigious writing of the philosopher Edmund Husserl in the beginning of the last century that the notion becameadistinctfieldofinvestigation.Husserlconstitutedphenomenologyasaclarificationofthe

4 structuresanddynamicsofsubjectiveexperienceinrelationtohumanperception,knowledge,and action. His works influenced generations of philosophers afterwards, which among the most influential include Scheler, Heidegger, MerleauPonty, Ricoeur, Sartre, Lévinas, and Derrida. Today,phenomenologystilldefendstheimportanceofthenotionofsubjectivityandfirstperson perspective in disciplines such as philosophy of mind, sociology, psychiatry, and neuroscience (Zahavi 2005; Gallagher and Zahavi 2008). Ethics, however, has not been a frequent theme in phenomenology. Apart from the works of Scheler, Ricoeur, and Lévinas, subjectivity has been investigatedwithoutexplicitlyconsideringthesubject’sethicaldispositions.Thefocushasbeenon perception,knowledgeandtheoryofaction,andeventhoughthequestionoftheotherhasbeen recenttopicintheliterature,theproblemofvalueandmoralityhasneverreally gainedaproper articulationinsidethephenomenologicaldebate.When contemporary phenomenologists discuss ethics it is normally in form of kind of ‘protoethics’ that describes the subject’s openness and structural relationship with (and infinite responsibility to) the other subject (Overgaard 2007: 143ff). The systematic treatment of the subject’s valuesandnormstendstobeconsideredasan extra dimension that can be left out of the structural analyses of subjectivity. On the following pages,Iwillarguethatitcannot.Wemightsuspendtheexplicitnormativeaspectofethicaltheory, thatis,whichsetofnormsarethemostadequate,justorright,inacertainsociety,agivensituation, orwithrespecttodifferentculturesetc.,butwecannotdismiss(meta)ethicalproblemssuchashow thesubjectexperiences,respondsto,andactuponvalues.Whydoesperceptionofasupposedly nonnormative world become faceted with normative aspects? How are values generated in subjectiveexperience? Thecentralpartsofthisworkarededicatedtotherelationbetweensubjectivityandethics.Itisnot aboutwhichkindofethicssuchanemphasisonthenotionofsubjectivitywouldeventuallyleadto. Theanalysesofsubjectivitywillbeheldonadescriptive level, since they aim at showing that ethical key concepts such as values, normativity, the other, and practices are part of the factual ofthehumansubject.Theanalysesfocusonsuchkeyconceptsanddonotdealexplicitly withethics.Itmightbesaidtobeametaethicalinvestigationofthesubjectivenatureofethical conceptsandaninvestigationintotheethicaldimension of subjectivity. There willbe no formal distinctionbetweenthesetwoaspectsofthedissertation,sincebothareclarifiedsimultaneouslyin theprogressoftheanalyses.Infact,itisthecentralaimofthedissertationtoshowthatthesetwo aspectscannotbedealtwithinisolation,butonlythroughanattentiveanalysisoftherelationthat bindthemtogether.

5 StructuresoftheAnalyses ThefirstpartisdedicatedtoareformulationofPaulRicoeur’stheoryofsubjectivity,sincehiswork is an important contribution to the discussion of subjectivity and ethics. He argues for an inseparablerelationbetweenthetwoandformulatesargumentsthatwithbenefitcanbeusedinthe contemporary debate. The second part develops some aspects Ricoeur’s theory with further analyseshumanaffectivityandethicalexperience.Ricoeur’sanalysesandargumentsareusedasthe frameworkinwhichthesedevelopmentsaredone.Ibringintheneurophysiologicaldimensionof affectivity, contemporary theories of emotions, and contemporary metaethical analyses of the relationbetweenfeelings,values,andpractices.Iargueforanaturalisticconceptionofsubjectivity thatunderstandsethicsasanaturalpartofthesubjectivebeingofthehumanperson.Thethirdpart deals with the attempt to naturalize human personhood and ethics. I hope clarify my own naturalisticpositionbycriticizingboththenewborndisciplineneuroethicsandarecentargument for moral relativism. This part is shorter than the other two, but although I only approach the questionofnaturalizationdirectlyinthelastthirtysomepages,thequestionispresentinallthe analysis,ifonlyinthesenseofpreparingananswer.Inparticularthesecondpartpavesthewayfor atreatmentofthequestionaboutnaturalizationinregardtosubjectivityandethics,sinceitlooks uponneurophysiologicaldimensionofaffectivityandvaluesinrelationtohumanpractices. Thus,tosummarizeandanticipatetheproblemsthatwillbedealtwithinthefollowingchapters: ● A Reformulation of Ricoeur’s Theory of Subjectivity 1. TheSchematicNotionofSubjectivity 2. TheRedressedNotionofSubjectivity ● Feeling Ethical: The Relation between Subjectivity and Ethics 1. HumanAffectivity 2. EthicalExperience ● Naturalized Personhood: The Brain and Human Values 1. Neuroethics:SubjectivityandNature 2. PersonhoodinNatureandCulture IthankfromtheheartmycollegesatCenterforSubjectivityResearch,mysupervisorsArneGrøn, HansHultborn,andfurtherGiovanniStanghellini,RobertaLanfredini,ilDipartimentodiFilosofia aFirenze,JacobSimonsen,andIbenDamgaardforinestimablycompetenthelpandwarmsupport.

6 Partone Ricoeur’sTheoryofSubjectivity

ThecentralpurposeofthispartistoclarifyPaulRicoeur’stheoryofsubjectivity.Thenotionofthe subjectisofprimaryimportanceinnearlyallofRicoeur’s writings, and I believe that the basic structures and constitution of subjectivity can be analyzed systematically without necessarily coveringhisphilosophyingeneral.Infact,Ibelievethatatheoreticreformulationofthenotionof subjectivitymightbeahelpifonewantstoapproachhisworksasadevelopmentofsinglebasic ideas.Anenormous,lifelong,quantityofwritingsinphenomenology,semeiotics,hermeneutics, socialsciences,historicaltheory,theology,andethicscanmakeitdifficulttofindatheoreticalcore inhiswork.Somemightdisagree,butIthinkthatthenotionofsubjectivityisagoodplacetostart insuchanattempttoemphasizeimportanceofhistheoreticalgroundwork.Thefollowingpartswill showhowhistheoryofsubjectivitycanbeusedwithgoodprofitindebateswhereonerarelyfinds hisname. ContrarytoRicoeur’sownmethod,Ishallmakeanefforttoreformulatehistheoryofsubjectivity without taking into account the vast number of dialog partners that Ricoeur himself uses as a vehicle for his thinking. Furthermore, the interpretation will not deal explicitly with the chronologicaldevelopmentofthesingleconceptsnorofhisphilosophyingeneral.Apartfromthe factthattheinterpretationisdividedintwochaptersthatdealwithtwodifferentperiodsofhis production(andthereforetheanalysesaredonewith reference to the works from the respective period),hisworkswillbeused,forthemostpart,withoutexplainingtheargumentativetransitions betweenthedifferentworks.ThischoiceisnotonlyduetothelimitedspaceavailablebutbecauseI believethathistheoryhasitsowntheoreticalgrounding which deserves to be clarified. Besides that,severalvaluablestudieshavepreviouslydealtwithhissocalled voie longue seekingtopinout theimplicationsofhisvariousdialogueswithpastandcontemporarythinkers 1.Thischoiceisnot, inanyway,adisprovalofneitherthehermeneuticalnorthecomparativemethodasanapproachto Ricoeur’sphilosophy,buttheconsequenceofastrictlysystematicinterest.Ishallusehistheoryas atheoreticalframeworkforabetterunderstandingoftherelationbetweensubjectivityandethics and in a concluding discussion of the naturalization of human personhood. Once again, the following interpretation is neither concerned with Ricoeur’s philosophy in general nor with his muchdiscussedstandpointincontemporaryphilosophy,literarytheory,socialsciencesortheology. 1Amongmanyothers:Greisch(2000,2001),Mongin(1996),Jervolino(1993,1995),Brezzi(2006).

7 Itisanattempttoclarifythebasicstructuresintheconstitutionofthesubjectastheyareconceived byRicoeuranddevelopedthroughouthiswritingsin the last fifty years. The reformulation will necessarilyappearunsatisfactoryandperhapsevenpoorintheeyesofpeoplethatknowRicoeur’s workbetterthanIdo,buttheymustkeepinmindthegeneralthemesofthework,whilereadingthe followingpages.ItrytouseRicoeur’sanalysesandideasinacontextthatisdifferentfromhisown methodsandconceptualbackground. Ihavethereforeconfinedmyselftoalimitedselectionsamonghisworks.Idealexplicitlywithsix major works: 1) Freedom and Nature , 2) Fallible Man , 3) Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on Interpretation , 4) Time and Narrative vol. 3 , 5) Oneself as Another , and 6) The Course of Recognition 2.Theseworksarechosenaccordingtotwocriteria.First,theyarethemosttheoretical treatmentsofthenotionofsubjectivity.Andsecondly,theycovertheearliestwritingsandthelatest, andtherebyaccountforthedevelopmentofhistheory.Ishall,nevertheless,makecontinuouslyuse ofseveralofthearticlesandminoressaysthataccountforasignificantpartofRicœur’sthinking. Theyoftencontainexplanativevalueinthesensethattheyelucidatethenatureofsingularconcepts andintricateargumentsinthemajorworks. Theanalysesaredividedintotwochaptersthatdealwithtwosignificantlydifferentapproachesin histheoryofthesubject.Thisdifferenceismainduetothehermeneuticalturnthattakesplaceafter thetwoearlyworks.ChapteroneisananalysisofthetwoearlywritingsFN andFM.HereIdeal withwhatIhavenamedthe stripped notionofthesubject.Iusethetermstrippedbecauseofthe schematic analysis of the structures of the subject that takes place in these two works. In this approach,Ricoeurproceedsfromexperienceoftheworldtotheselfexperienceofthesubjectat threelevels:fromexperienceoveractiontoaffectivity.ThesecondchapterexamineswhatIhave namedthe redressed notionofthesubject.ThisisdonethroughananalysisofFP,TN3,OSA,and CR.IntheselateworksRicoeurexpandshisnotion of the subject in the sense that he relates it explicitlytotheconcrete,historicworldand,notleast,toethicsandthequestionoftheother.Thus, he redresses the human subject with the features thathedepriveditof intheearlyworks.The arrangementoftheanalysesistheoppositeoftheformerinthesensethattheyproceedfromthe subject’sselfexperiencetotheexperienceoftheworld,andthatonceagainatthreelevels:from affectivityoveractiontoethicalexperience. 2Henceforth,Iwillmainlyusetheabbreviationslistedonpp.2367.ThequotationsrefertoboththeEnglishtranslation andtheFrenchoriginaltext.ThefirstnumberindicatestheEnglishandthesecondtheFrench,separatedbyaslanted stroke.IhavemodifiedthetranslationwhereIheldthattheexistingtranslationwasbadordirectlymisleading.

8 Chapterone TheStrippedNotionofSubjectivity This chapter deals with the schematic notion of subjectivity, that is, the basic structures of the humansubject,throughananalysisofRicoeur’sfirsttwomajorworks, Freedom and Nature and Fallible Man . FN (1950) is a phenomenological exploration of the possibilities and limits the concept of volition. His studies on Husserl find their application in this work, in particular the conceptofintentionality.Theanalysesconfinethemselvestoaneideticenquiry,i.e.,focusingonly onthehumancapacitytowillandbracketingthequestionabouttheontologicalstatusofthehuman subject,itsrelationshiptotheworldandtheothersubjects. Ten yearslater,in1960,thenextmajorworkFMappearsasasequeltoFN.Inthisworkthe bracketsareremovedandtheontologicalquestioncomesintoquestion.Bydoingso,Ricoeurseeks toplacethehumanbeingintheworldandlookcloselyonhowthewillingsubjectinteractswiththe world and other subjects. Still, this is not a fullblown ontology, but an introduction of basic conceptsforafurtherunderstandingofthehumanbeingintheworld.ItisinthisworkthatRicoeur bringsKantintohisphilosophy,andalthoughheusesKantinalmosteveryaspectofhisthinking,I believethattheKantianconceptoftranscendentalsynthesiscanbesingledoutasthefundamental conceptforthesefirstanalysesofsubjectivity. Beforeturningtotheexplicitanalysisofthestrippednotionofsubjectivity,itmightbeusefulto clarifythreebasicmethodologicalconceptsthatRicoeurusesintheseearlyworks.Althoughthey areintroducedintheearlyworks,theseconceptsremain,however,inallhiswriting.

Basic Methodological Concepts: AlthoughIamconvincedthatthenotionofsubjectivitycanbereformulatedwithouttakinginto account Ricoeur’s various dialogue partners, one cannot avoid dealing, at least briefly, with the KantandHusserl.Theyareeverywhereinhiswritingandhaveinfluencedhisthoughtnumerous ways,butforthepresentinterpretationtheirmaincontributiontohistheoryofsubjectivityisfound in two key concepts, namely transcendental synthesis and intentionality. The same goes for the conceptoforiginatingaffirmation.However,unlikethefirsttwo,thisonedoesnotgetadetailed systematictreatmentinanyofRicoeur’sworks.Nonetheless,itisperhapsthemostimportantofthe three.Itlurks,somehow,inthebackgroundoftheanalysesandappearsundervariousformsfrom theearliestwritingstothelatest.Itisnotusednearlyasexplicitasthetwootherconcepts,but confersacertainstyletohiswayofdoingphilosophy(NA378).Hence,onemustbeawareofhow

9 thisconceptispresentinhisanalysesandtherolethatitplaysinhismethodology.But,fornow,I willstartKantandHusserl. Ricoeur himself provides a concise description of how Kant and Husserl are combined in his philosophy:‘Husserl did phenomenology,butKant limited and founded it’(KH201/313).Heuses HusserlasamethodologicalguidetothedescriptionofthestructuresofsubjectivityandKantasthe speculativeengineinhisthinkingabouttheontologyofsubject.Thus,onemightsaythatRicoeur’s theoryofsubjectivityisdevelopedfromKant’slimitingontologyandHusserl’sphenomenological method.Butstill,hisuseofthetwophilosophersisquiteunorthodox,anditisnotasaninterpreter ofeitherKantorHusserlthathehasgainedrecognition.Hecoinshisownnotionsfromtheirforms andperformsbothminorandmajorsemanticchangesintheuseoftheirconcepts.Idonotgointo further detail about his critiques on and use of Kant and Husserl, since this has been done thoroughlyinotherstudies,butconfinemyselftothebasicconceptsbymeansofwhichheworkout histheoryofthesubject. TranscendentalSynthesis The human subject is an intermediate being constituted by sensibility and reason: ‘he is intermediatebecauseheisamixture,andamixturebecausehebringsaboutmediations’(FM3/23). Thesubjectandtheworldisunderstoodonlybyturningtheattentionawayfromtheexperienced worldandbacktothesubjectivestructuresthatmakethisexperiencepossibleinthefirstplace.This focus on subjectivity is known as Kant’s Copernican revolution and it plays a critical role in Ricoeur’s analyses (FN 32/35, 471/443). In his use of the concept of transcendental synthesis RicoeurfollowsstraightinthefootstepsofKant. The transcendental synthesis is the first step in understanding the subject as well as the world. Transcendental here means the basic structures of the subject that make experience of reality possible(FM5/25).Realityisaresultofthemediationsperformedbythesubject.Thisisnottobe misinterpretedasakindofidealisticsolipsismthatreducestherealityoftheworldtothesubjective representationoftheworld.Onthecontrary,theworldisthereandaffectsthesubjectthroughthe body:‘existenceofthebodyisthedecisivefactwhichforcesustoelucidateconcretelifeatthe limitsofintelligibility’(FN135/129).Thepresenceoftheworldiswhatcreatesasynthesis,namely thesynthesisbetweentherealexistenceoftheworldandthepeculiarnatureofthesubject. The subject is open to the world through its body: ‘What is precisely the bewildering in the mediatingroleofthebodyisthatitopensmetotheworld;inotherwords,itistheorganofan

10 intentionalrelationinwhichthebodyisnottheboundaryofmyexistencebuttheitscorrelate’(NA 307/38081;cf.FM20/38).Nevertheless,thesubjectdoesnotcoincidewithitssensibility;itdoes notbecomeonewiththeworld.Itisturnedbackuponitselfintheexperienceofthesensibleobjects (FM21/39).Thisiswhythesynthesisis objectival ,notintrospectiveorobjective(thisdistinction will be explained further in the next section). It is in this being turned back upon itself, in the separation from the world, that the subject discovers itself as an intermediate being. It is not constitutedbytheexternalworldalonebut,otherthanreceptivity,itpossessesaspontaneitycapable ofrepresentingthingsandideasdifferentfromtheperceivedpresent.Spontaneitycoincideswiththe workingsofpurereasonwithouttheinputfromsensibledata.Buthowdothesetwoseemingly heterogeneouscapacitiescometogetherintheunitythatweknowasthehumansubject? Thehumansubjectisneithermeresensibilitynorpurereason,butasynthesisofthetwo.Atthis point, we encounter another fundamental capacity of the human subject, namely transcendental imagination. Imagination is the third capacity that unifies the synthesis by mediating between sensibilityandreason. Imaginationmustbehomogeneouswithbothsensibilityandreasontobe abletomediatebetweenthetwo.Itsnatureishiddenfromourfullcomprehensionandremainsan enigma.Ricoeur,likeKanthimself,doesnotpretendtodecideonthenatureofimagination(FM 412/59). He is satisfied with defining its function as generating a synthesis between the two fundamentalcapacitiesinthehumansubject,sensibilityandreason. Thetranscendentalsynthesisthenisdefinedasconsciousness,butaformalconsciousnessthatis notyetselfconscious,because‘[t]heconsciousnessphilosophyspeaksofinitstranscendentalstage constitutesitsownunityonlyoutsideitself,ontheobject’(FM45/63;cf.FM18/367,37/55;LS 327). I shall give a more detailed description of transcendental imagination later on. For now, sufficeittosaythatthroughtheexperiencedobjectthesubjectunderstanditselfasconstitutedby sensibilityandreason(receptivityandspontaneity),butnothingmore.Itisanemptyconsciousness thathasnoideaofhoworwhyitexists.However,thetranscendentalsynthesisprovidesabasic scheme for the analyses of human subjectivity and is therefore the necessary first step in understandingofthenatureofthesubject(FM5/25,456/63). Atthispoint,though,thequestionishowwediscoverthesubjectasbeingasynthesisofsensibility andreasoninthefirstplace.Ifthesubjectisa beingconstitutedneitherbymerephysicalinput received through the senses nor pure spontaneity of reason, we need a concept explaining consciousnessasmorethanjustacollectionofimpressionsorintramentalideas.Ricoeurfindsthis explanationinHusserl’sanalysesoftheconceptofintentionality(FN8/12,423/42;SP1567).

11 Intentionality Theconceptofintentionalitycoversagroupofexperiencesthatarealldeterminedbytheirobject directedness.Tobedirectedtowardsanobjectisaconstitutivefeature ofhuman consciousness. Consciousnessisalwaysconsciousnessofsomething,apsychicalobjectaswellasapsychological one.Whenweperceivewealwaysperceivesomethingandwhenwelovewealwayslovesomebody orsomething.Consciousnesscanbeunderstoodonlyifwetakeintoaccounttheobjectivecorrelate, that is, the perceived, the beloved etc. The multifarious variety of real and possible objects of consciousnesstellssomethingaboutthespecificnatureofhumanconsciousness.Anobjectcanbe experiencedasphysicalsuchasraindropsonmyhandorasbeingofanonphysicalnaturelikethe hopeforlibertyandequality.Theyarebothintentionalobjectsandthereforepartofthestructures ofsubjectiveexperience.Andagain,thesestructuresrevealthecomplexnatureofconsciousnessto be both physical and nonphysical. Employing the Husserlian concept of intentionality in his analyses,Ricoeurimmediatelyrejectstwoothertheoriesofsubjectivity:naturalismandsubjective idealism(FN910/1314). Thenaturalisticinterpretationofsubjectivityfindsitsexpressioninthemethodologyadoptedby theempiricalsciences.Onlythatwhichinfluencesmecausallyissaidtobepartoftheexplanation ofconsciousexperience,e.g.raindropsonmyhand.Theintramentalexperience,suchasthehope forlibertyandequality,isexcludedfromthiskindofapproachtosubjectivity.Thesubjecthastobe treatedinthesamewayaseveryotherlivingbeinginnature.Bycontrast,thesubjectiveidealismis animmanentconceptionofrealitywheretheexternal,mindindependentworldisconsideredifnot irrelevant then at least as secondary for an analysis of subjectivity. There is no ontological differencebetweenphysicalandnonphysicalentities,sincebothofthemarepartofmyintentional consciousness.Thus,ahopeforlibertyandequalityexistsinthesamemannerasraindropsonmy hands.Alackofdifferentiationbetweenthephysicalandnonphysicalcan,inthisway,easilylead totheideaofanomnipotentsubjectwhonotonlyexperiencestheexternalworldbutcreatesitatthe sametime(FN54/53,4856/456). Ricoeurdistanceshimselffromsuchtheoriesbyindicatingthat‘[t]heCogitoisinternallyshattered’ (FN 14/17. Translation modified). The subject is made up by both physical and nonphysical entities and therefore it has to be analyzed with a methodology different from the one used in empiricalscienceswithout,however,slidingintoanintrospectivemysticism:‘Inversely,knowledge ofsubjectivitycannotbereducedtointrospection[…]Itsessenceistorespecttheoriginalityofthe Cogito as a cluster of the subject’s intentional acts’ (FN 10/14). The concept of intentionality

12 revealstheconscioussubjectasapeculiarbeinginthenaturalorder.Itbelongstonatureandyetit transcendstheimmediatepresenceofsensedata.Toapproachacomplexnatureasthatofhuman beings,wemustfindamethodthatincludesasmanyaspectsaspossibleofthisparticularbeing. RicoeurfindssuchamethodologyinadevelopmentofthetwoconceptsinheritedfromKantand Husserl. In the concept of intentionality he discovers an argument for the twofold nature of subjectivity,quotingMainedeBrian’sfamousdictuminbothworks‘Homosimplexinvitalitate duplexinhumanitate’(FN228/213;FM91/107).Thistwofoldnatureexcludesamethodthatis basedonlyoncausality,andbyusingtheHusserlianconceptinhisanalysisheis,atthesametime, able to curb a subjective idealism. Once this is settled, he takes on the Kantian concept of transcendentalsynthesisinordertodevelopabasicnotionofsubjectivity. Intentionalityrevealsthenatureofsubjectivitybyturningthesubjectbackuponitself.Ricoeur’s favoriteexampletoclarifythismovementisthenatureofperception(FM267/4445;NA307 311/38185;LS2567).Whenweperceiveanobjectwearealwaysboundtoacertainperspective. The object is always seen from a certain perspective, from the front or the back; we are never capable of seeing the object in its totality. Perspectivity accounts for the limits and general narrownessofhumanperception.Theconceptionoftheperceivedobjectpointsbacktothenature oftheperceivingsubjectasconfinedtoacertainperspective.However,ourunderstandingofthe objectisnotcompletedintheactofperception.Theawarenessofourconfinedvisionoftheobject is a result of the idea of other possible perspectives on the object. This knowledge somehow transcendsourownperspectiveandrevealsanunderstandingofthetotalityofperspectivesonthe object.Thistotalityisthemeaningoftheperceivedobject.IfI,forexample,lookataplasticchair attheendofalongtable,Ionlyseeasmallpartofit,saythetopofthechairback.Nevertheless,I immediatelyformanideaofthatpieceofmatterasbeingpartofathingthatwenameachair.This capacitytoformanideaoftotalityfromafragmentaryperceptioniswhatRicoeurcallsour‘power toexpressameaning’or‘intentiontosignify’(FM26/44).Thesubjectiscapableoftalkingabout theobjectinitstotality,andthatsoeveninitsabsence.Inthisway,theunderstandingoftheobject asathingrevealsnotonlytherestrictednatureofhumanperception,butalsotothehumancapacity totranscendthatrestrictionintheactofexpressingameaning. Thesubjectisopentotheobjectthroughitsbodily senses, but in theact of understanding the objectasathing,itisturnedbackuponitselfandrevealedasmorethanjustrestrictedperception. Thus,thesubjectisconstitutedbybothreceptivity(body)andspontaneity(reason),andanyattempt to explain subjectivity must take into consideration both these aspects. Hence, the descriptive

13 analyses of intentionality in FN emphasize the necessity of a further analysis into this complex natureofsubjectivity,whichisthendoneinFM. Assaidabove,thetwoconceptshavetheirspecificdevelopmentinthesingleworks,intentionality isappliedtothewillinFNandthetranscendentalsynthesisisusedtoanalyzereason,sensibility andaffectivityFM.Todrawasystematicpictureofthesonamedstrippednotionofsubjectivity,I use the transcendental synthesis developed in FM as the basic structure by means of which the differentconstitutivestructuresofthesubjectshallbe analyzed. The analyses of these structures drawonbothworksinterchangeably.FM,however,isfundamentalbecauseoftheefforttodescribe thestructuresofabasichumanontologyinformofaphilosophicalanthropology.Herewefindthe matureRicoeurarguingforacoherentnotionofsubjectivity.Theworkis,inmanyways,thefinest theoreticalargumentforhistheoryofsubjectivity.Itis,however,averydenseanalysis,sometimes onthevergeofobscurity,andinordertofollowhisargumentsandtransitions,wehavetoturnto the analyses in FN and, at times, the minor articles from the period. The intentional analyses uncoverthepeculiarstructuresandcapacitiesofsubjectivity(FN8/12;PW61);nevertheless,itis bymeansofthetranscendentalsynthesisthatthesestructuresareputtogethertoformunitywe knowasthehumansubject. TheOriginatingAffirmation Now, we come to the last of the three fundamental methodological concepts, the originating affirmation. This concept plays a strange inarticulate role in the analyses. It is only dealt with explicitlyinconcludingpagesofFMandintwominorarticles,andstillitseemsappearwhenever Ricoeurtakesastandonwhatiscruciallyhuman.Itisemployedmorelikeastylethanaworking conceptinhisanalyses.Inallitsactions,thehumansubjectischaracterizedbyanoriginalwillto exist:‘Thiswillisnolongertheobjectofstatisticalinquires,ofinductivegeneralization;rather,itis recapturedastheprimitiveactofconsciousness’(PW66.Translationslightlymodified;cf.TFA 2912/362).Theaffirmationisprimitiveinthesensethatitisapartofthenaturethesubject,and notaproductionofitsactivity.Itisthatwhichenablesthesubjecttoactinthefirstplace,andthus, ithastobeconsideredasaninherentfeatureofsubjectivity. Togetanideaofhowthisconceptisthemajorworks,wehavetolookontwoarticlesfromthe period in between FN and FM: True and False Anguish (1953) and Negativity and Primary

14 Affirmation 3(1956).Ricoeurborrowstheconceptfromanotherofhismainsourcesofinspiration, theFrenchphilosopherJeanNabert.ThreequotesgiveapreliminaryideaofwhatRicoeurmeansby the concept: ‘Under the pressure of the negative, of negative experiences, we must reachieve a notion of being which is act rather than form , living affirmation, the power of existing and of makingexist’;‘philosophicalreflexionispurifyinginthis:thatitdiscernsthenucleusofaffirmation shroudedinanger,thegenerosityconcealedintheimplicitwillofmurder’(NA328/405;323/400); ‘Asanguishbecomesmoreradical,reflectionwillalsobecomeprofoundandwillbringintoview what I shall constantly be calling throughout the course of this meditation the “originating affirmation”, something which we shall also attempt to capture at its successive levels’ (TFA 288/358).ThefirstquoteindicatesthatRicoeur’sphilosophyisexistentialistinsensethatitaimsat understandingtheproblemsofthelivingsubject.Itisnotinterestedinthemetaphysicalformsor the essences of eternal truths, but concerned with how the human subject acts and exists in its concretepresent.Ricoeuris,indeed,interestedinmetaphysicalandontologicalquestions,butitis always with the living subject at the center of the analyses. His philosophy is a descriptive metaphysicsoftheactingsubjectwiththeintentiontodevelopaspecificontologyofsubjectivity. Thesecondandthirddisclosehisconceptionofphilosophicalreflection.Itmustbeoptimisticand therapeuticinnatureand,therefore,trytofindthe affirmative core underneath the perverse and maliciousformsofhumanexpression(ST194).Thisemphasisontheaffirmativecharacterofthe philosophicalanalysisiscrucial,sincereflectsaprephenomenologicalconceptionofhumannature. Humannatureisnotonewithitsapparentlynegativeexpressions,suchasanguish,painormalice. Ofcourse,suchexpressionsaretobeconsideredaspartofthesubject,but,asitissaidinthethird quote, the more profound the expressions of negativity are, the more reflection to search even deeperfortheoriginatingaffirmation.Inthisway,Ricoeurisglaringlyclearaboutthenature,or,as heputsithimself,the style ofhisphilosophy:‘astyleofyesandnotastyleof“no,”andperhaps evenastylecharacterizedbyjoyandnotbyanguish’(NA305/378);andfurtherinFN:‘Philosophy forusisameditationofthe yes ,andnotasurlyintensificationofthe no ’(FN446/419). Thehumansubjectischaracterizedbythisprimitivewilltolive(vouloirvivre)orpowertoexist (puissance d’exister); however, Ricœur insists that this is not to be confused with a biological instinct, but, like the indefinite anguish in front of the possibility of death, the willtolive is somethingmorethanawilltosurvive,andevenmorebasicthanrationality(TFA2901/361362). 3Theoriginaltitleofthisessayis Negativité et affirmation originaire .Theterm affirmation originaire istranslated differently by the different translators (originating affirmation, original affirmation or primary affirmation). I will constantlyuse originating affirmation ,since,inmyopinion,thistranslationcapturestheoriginalmeaningbest.

15 Beingintheworld,asmentionedabove,ischaracterizedby a disharmonybetween the twofold natureofthesubject(receptivityandspontaneity).Thecogitoisshattered,andsubjectivityisina state of conflict (FM 141/157). The original affirmation is a presupposition in his analyses, a convictionabouthumannature,and,asweshallselateron,itremainsthefundamentuponwhich hedevelopshistheoryofthehumansubject.Somehow,Ibelieve,hisentiretheoryofsubjectivityis an attempt to argue for the existence of the affirmative character of humanity. That is why he repeatedlycharacterizesthenatureofhisphilosophyasarecovery,restorationorreconciliationof theconflictwithinthesubject(FN1720/2023,4689/4401;NA306/379,404;TFA303/375). Thisrelationshipbetweentheoriginatingaffirmationandthenatureofhisphilosophyiscriticalfor understanding his analyses, because if we take the original affirmation to be an expression of somethingfundamentalinthenatureofthesubject,otherconceptssuchasverbeinfini,conatus, appetitus,powertosayanddo,andattestationfindacommonpointofreference.Theyallreferto anoriginalwilltosayyes,anaffirmation,apropensitytoloveandrespectthatgobeyondthemere affectivityofthepresent.Theoriginatingaffirmation,however,isincontinuousconflictwiththe ‘existentialdifferenceorexistentialnegation’inherentinembodiednatureofsubjectivity(FM135 8/1524).Thebodytendstodimandpervertthefundamentalwilltobemorethanthepresent,more thanthegivenreality(NA327/404).Otherthanapropensitytobemorethansituatedinagiven present,togobeyondreceptivity,thesubjectisfragileinthesensethatitalsotendstodisposeofits affirmativecharacterandhideitselfinasortofpassivity.Insteadofreflectingandactingonthe immediate present, it tends to suffer the present. Giving into the overwhelming presence of the world,itispossibleforthesubjecttoblendintotheworld andbecomeparalyzedin astateof passivity.Ashewritesaboutthenatureofhumanhabits,itis‘asifhabitwereaweekpointoffered towhatisperhapsthemostperfidiousofpassions,thepassiontobecomeathing’(FN297/280). Thispassiontobecomeathingisaneverpresentdangerinthehumansynthesis.Itisawayof disposing of spontaneity and becoming one with receptivity in order to relieve oneself of the responsibilitythatcharacterizesthehumancapacitytoact. However,thisisnottosuggestthatRicoeuroperateswithadichotomywhere,ontheonehand, spontaneity, originating affirmation and reason are that which is essentially human, and on the other,receptivity,negativityandsensibilityarecharacterizedasantagoniststothehumanityofthe subject. The body, the experience of negativity and the concepts of habit and character are fundamentaltosubjectivity.Infact,theyareallessentiallyaspectsofthehumansubject,buttheir interplay in forming the subject is fragile and can very easily lead to a disproportion. This

16 disproportionisnotonly onthesideofreceptivityorsensibility,itisjustascommontotryto disregardone’sbodyandrelysolelyonthepowersofthemind.Suchanattitudeforcesthesubject intoanequallydangerousstateofdisproportion,sinceitignoresthenecessitytointeractwiththe surroundingworld.Thesubjectisopentotheworldthoughthebody,whichremainsanessential featureofitsnature.Theoriginatingaffirmationisembodied,asisthesubjectitself,andanaccount of subjectivity has to start from this fact of human nature. This is why philosophy has to be therapeuticinnature.Itmustsetthesubjectrightwhenitgoesastrayandfallsintoadisproportion, andinordertodealwithnegativity,immediateaswellasreflected,ithastohaveanidea(l)ofhow thesubjectshouldbe.Ricoeur’sphilosophyhassuchanidea(l),aprephilosophicalpresupposition ifonewill.Theprimordialnatureofsubjectivityisaffirmative,andthisaffirmativecoreismore basicthannegativityinallitsformssuchasbodilylimitedperspective,characterandvitalfeelings (FM1356/152).Thepositivestyleofhisphilosophyandtheaffirmativecoreofsubjectivityare inseparablylinkedtogetherthroughouttheentiredevelopmentofhistheoryofsubjectivity.They aretheproductof a convictionabouthumannature, andonecouldsurmisethatthe aimofhis philosophymightverywellbetoarguefortheplausibilityforthisconviction. Theoriginatingaffirmationisthedynamicfeaturethatdrivesthesubjecttoengageitselfwiththe worldandtheotherhumanbeing.Thisinteractionwithalterity,theencounterwith,reflectionupon, anddialoguingwiththeworldandtheotherhumanbeing,ismadepossiblebythisbasicfeaturein subjectivity.Inthisway,weshallfollowthedevelopmentoftheoriginatingaffirmationfromits manifestationintheverb(vouloirdire)overthenotionofhappinesstoitsmostintimateexpression inthefeelingofhappinessintheheartofthesubject. First,Iwilllookonhowconsciousnessisconstitutedbythetranscendentalsynthesisofreasonand sensibility.Then,thissynthesisisputinrelationtotheworld.Theembodiedsubjectisanalyzedin itsbeingembeddedintheworldandconstitutedbytheinteractionwiththisworldandtheother subjectsinit.Finally,followingRicoeur’sownemphasisonaffectivityandemotionascrucialin subjectivity,Itrytounravelthenotionofemotionsintheconstitutionofthesubjectandtherole that they play in the subject’s relation to itself, the world and the other subjects. This structure reflectsRicoeur’sownstructureinFM,butitreformulatestheargumentsbyusingtheanalysesof FN;thereby,inmyopinion,thestructuralnotionofsubjectivityisclarifiedandenrichedinaway notpossible,oratleastverydifficult,byareadingofonlyoneoftheworks.

17 Experience: Between Reason and Sensibility The human subject is a complex being made up of reason and sensibility. This is a common intuitionabouthumannature.Throughourfivesensesweexperiencetheworldinwhichwelive andwithreasonwecanproduceideasandimageswithouthavingtorelyonimmediatestimulifrom the external world. How do these two basic capacities of the subject interact? Throughout the philosophicaltraditiontherehavebeeninnumerousanswerstoquestionsofthissort,butbyand largewecangathertheseanswersintothreegenericgroups: dualism , materialism ,and idealism 4. AnextensiveandcentralpartofRicoeur’swritingsdealswithproblemsconcerningthecomplexity ofhumannature,andoneofhisprimaryaims,fromtheearliesttothelatestwritings,istogivean accountoftherelationbetweenbodyandreasonintheconstitutionofsubjectivity. Ricoeur is very clear about his methodology. The methodology of scientific objectivity cannot explain the nature of the human subject: ‘The body of a subject and the body as anonymous empiricalobjectdoesnotcoincide.Wecansuperimposetwoobjects,butnotadimensionofthe Cogitoandanobject.Thelivedbodycorrespondstoa“behavior”ofthewill […]Thedependence ofmy bodyonmy selfwhichwillsinit andthrough it has nothing corresponding to it in the universeofempiricalscienceexceptabodyexplainedintermsofother’(FN12/15.Translation slightlymodified;cf.2078/1934).Ricoeurisobviouslynotamaterialist.Thebody,aslivedand experienced subjectively, does not coincide with the physical body of the empirical sciences. However, what makes this statement particularly interestingisnottherejectionofapurecausal explanationofsubjectivity,butthefocusonthebodyandnotonthemindinthisrejection.Itis characteristicofRicoeur’swritingsthateventhoughhisphilosophydismissesmaterialism,itnever becomesneitheridealisticnordualistic. Whatisinquestionhereisnotthenatureofhumanreasonorbody,buttherelationbetweenthe twoaspectsofsubjectivity,embodiedreason.Thehumanbodyisnottobeconsideredasanobject

4Dualism isthephilosophicalpositionthatholdsthatthehumansubjectismadeupbytwoontologicaldifferentparts ofwhichoneisspiritualandtheotherphysical.Thesepartsareheterogeneousentitiesthatmaycommunicatewithone anotherbutcanneverbeexploredbyoneandthesamemethodology.Thephilosophersthatadvocate materialism are certainthateverything,whenanalyzedproperly,turnsouttobeofphysicalnature.Theexperienceofsomethingnon physicalisaphenomenologicalresultofhidden,oratlestunknown,physicalmechanisms.Thereareseveraldegreesof materialism, giong from strong materialism (e.g. disappearancetheory/eliminative materialism that bans all psychological experience as illusionary or epiphenomena without any effect on the physical constitution) to weak materialism (e.g. translationtheory that defends the reality of the mental and the possibility of translating this into physicalterm,withoutdisregardingtherealityofneitherofthem).Finally, idealism claimsthatwecanbesureonlyof thesubjectiveexperiencesgoingoninourhead.Theexistenceoftheexternalworldisnotacertainfactbutmayvery wellbeaproductofourmentaloperations.Theworldandthephenomenologicalexperienceofourselvesmayonlybea shadowofourrealidealisticessence(Plato),or, asacontemporaryphilosopherputsit,wemaybebrains in a vat (Putnam).

18 amongothersintheworld;itisabodylivedbythesubjectin firstperson.Anditissomehow controlledor,atleast,influencedbythewill.However,regardlessofhisemphasisonthebody, Ricoeurisclearaboutthestatusofthesubject’stwobasiccapacities.Thebody,beingpartofthe involuntaryaspectofsubjectivityasopposedthevoluntary,alwayshastobeunderstoodfromthe perspectiveoftheconsciousmind:‘seulunêtrederaisonestaussiunêtredesentiment’(LS320). Thesubjectisacomplexbeingbecauseitconsistsofbothphysicalandnonpsychicalentities,body andreason.Itisdifferentfrombothangels(ifonebelievesinsuchcreatureofpurereason)andthe restofnature’sanimalsbecauseofthiscomplexity(FM3/23). The first, but not sufficient, step in an attempt to understand how reason and body interact in subjectivityhastodealwiththeconceptoftranscendentalsynthesis(FM5/25,17/35,46/63,49 50/67, 812/978). As we have seen, the transcendental synthesis is what enables subjective experienceinthefirstplace;itisthatwhichbringstogethertheheterogeneouscapacitiesofthe subject in what we know as consciousness. Although he quite faithfully adopts the concept of transcendentalsynthesisfromKant,Ricoeurhimselfbelievesthathemakesaslight,butimportant, modification.WhereasKantworksouttheconceptinordertojustifytheobjectivityofsubjective experienceandtherebyemphasizesthescientificaspectofexperience,Ricoeurismoreinterestedin thesubjectivedimensionofexperience:‘namelythatpropertyofbeingthrownbeforeme,atonce giventomypointofview and capableofbeingcommunicated,inalanguagecomprehensibleby anyrationalbeing’(FM39/56) 5.Hedescribesthissubjectivefeatureoftheobjectfor‘thething’s objectivalcharacter’.By objectival ,hereferstosomethingthatismoreobjective,oratleastmore fundamental,thanscientificobjectivitybecauseitisthatonwhichsciencesbuilds,namelythepre conceptual giveness of the world. The world as it is conferred to us through the senses and elaboratedbyreason:‘hereconsciousnessisnothingelsethanthatwhichstipulatesthatathingisa thingonlyifitisinaccordancewiththissyntheticconstitution,ifitcanappear and beexpressed,if itcanaffectmeinmyfinitude and lenditselftothediscourseofanyrationalbeing’(idem).Itis importanttonoticethattheexperiencemadepossiblebythetranscendentalsynthesismustbethe

5Thesentencedeservestobequotedinitsfulllength,sinceit,albeitthedenseandobscureformulations,presentsa conciseexpressionofakeypointinhistheoryofsubjectivity.Heisconcernedwiththewaythesubjectrelatesitselfto the worldaroundit,inshort,thesubjectiveexperience.Thisexplorationofsubjectivity mustbegin,however,inthe object,andnotbymeansofsomekindofintrospectiveanalysis.Thesentencegoesasfollows:‘Kantreducedthescope ofhisdiscoverytotherestricteddimensionsofanepistemology.Theobjectivityoftheobjectisreducedtothescientific aspect of objects belonging to a domain carved out by the history of the sciences. But criticism is more than epistemology,transcendentalreflectionismorethananexplorationofthescientificnatureoftheobjectsofnature.The real a priori synthesisdoesnotappeareveninthefirstprinciples;itconsistsinthething’sobjectivalcharacter(rather thanobjective,ifobjectivemeansscientific),namelythatpropertyofbeingthrownbeforeme,atoncegiventomypoint ofview and capableofbeingcommunicated,inalanguagecomprehensiblebyanyrationalbeing’(FM389/56).

19 samefor any rationalbeing.Thisconditioniswhatmakesthesynthesistranscendentalinthesense that,eventhoughitiswhatmakessubjectivitypossible,itisnotasolipsistickindofsubjectivity, butthebasicstructuresofsubjectiveexperienceineveryrationalsubject. Therefore, besides distinguishing it from scientific analyses, the objectal character of the transcendentalsynthesis(effectiveexperienceoftheworld)isalsoarejectionoftheintrospective approach.Subjectivitymustbeexaminedbymeansofananalysisofitsopennesstotheworld(FM 1920/378)andnotbyplungingintothehiddenstructuresofindividualsubjectivity.Thestructures thatRicœurislookingforarethecommonstructuresinvolvedinthewayeveryreasonablesubject isopentotheworld.Subjectivityisconstitutedintheencounterofreasonandthatwhichisnot reason(thatbeingtheexternalworldaswellasthesubject’sownbody).Neitherreasonnorbody canaccountforsubjectivity.Subjectivityhastobesoughtforintheinteractionofthetwo.Inorder tounderstandhowreasonandbodyinteractinthesynthesisthatformsconsciousness,wehaveto turntotheconceptoftranscendentalimagination(FM5/25). TranscendentalImagination 6 TIisthecardinalconceptinthesynthesisbecauseitisthatwhichmakesanintegralunionofbody and reason. Ricoeur deals with two aspects of imagination, the transcendental and the empirical (FM 45/62). This distinction was first made by Kant in the Critique of Pure Reason where he assignsthetranscendentalimaginationtothegenerationofthepossibility(i.e.thebasicstructures) ofexperience,andtheempiricalimaginationtotheworkingsofactualexperience(Kant1997:267 85/131169).However,thisdistinctionisnotasrigidinRicoeurasinKant.Asmentionedearlier, Heisnotinterestedinjustifyingtheobjectiveaspectofsubjectiveexperience,butconcernedwith theexperienceoflivedsubjectivity.Hethereforecontinuouslyemphasizesthatthetranscendental isonlythefirststepintheanalysis.Then,beforegoingtothenextstep,Ishalltakeacloserlookon theworkingsofTI. TIisthe‘blindpointofknowledge’(FM82/98)and‘remainsobscure,hidden,andblind’(FM 45/62),andyet,wehavetobeginwiththisobscureconceptinouranalysisofthehumansubject (FM 5/25). It is in our encounter with the world that we first notice the function of TI. In the previous section, we saw that subjectivity is both receptive and spontaneous. Our bodily constitutionpermitsonlyalimitedperceptionofanobject,acertainperspective. Oursensescan neverconveyacompleteperception,orwhatRicoeurcalls‘zeropoint’(FM31/49).Andstill,we

6Intheremainingofthissection,IshallusetheabbreviationTIforthetranscendentalimagination.

20 cantransgressthelimitsofourpointofviewand,sotosay,gobeyondourperceptiveabilities.We dothisbyjudgingaboutthefragmentary presence oftheobjectinordertoreachthe meaning ofthe object.Ricoeurcallsthishumancapacityfor‘theintentiontosignify’,andthenadds‘tosignifyis tointend,thetransgressionofthepointofviewwhichisnothingelsethanspeechasthepossibility ofexpressing,andofexpressingthepointofviewitself’(FM26/4445).Herelatesthis‘intentional transgression’ (idem) of our point of view with our will to say something about the perceived object, to give the object a significance. In this way, we discover two distinct capacities of the subject:thecapacitytobecomeaffectedbytheworldthroughourbodilysenses,andthecapacity, bymeansofreason,toconferameaningtothatwhichaffectsus. TosumupwhatRicoeursaysaboutthesetwocapacitiesofsubjectivity,wecannamethem–as Ricoeurdoeshimself–the finite perspective andthe infinite verb .Thefiniteperspectiveiswhatthe bodilysensestellusabouttheobjectsintheworld.Ourbodilyperceptionisalwayscharacterized byafragmentaryandsporadicregistrationofobjectschangingandmovinginfrontofus.Thus,this registrationisnevercomplete,butlinkedtoacertainperspectiveduetoourbodilyconstitution.The infiniteverb,however,iswhatpermitsustoformameaningofthisregistration.Weareabletosay something about the object and categorize it as this or that, i.e., a specific thing loaded with a certain meaning. This capacity to categorize originates in our willtosaysomething about the object.Itisaninherentfeatureofhumansubjectivitythatdistinguishesthehumansubjectinthe world:‘Thistranscendenceofsignificationoverperception,ofspeakingoverperspective,iswhat makesthereflectiononpointofviewassuchpossible:Iamnotimmersedintheworldtosuchan extentthatIloosethealoofnessofsignifying,ofintending,aloofnessthatistheprincipleofspeech’ (FM 31/4849). The capacity to saysomethingabout the perceived object is rooted in the spontaneityofhumanreason,theinfinitepossibilityofmeaningcontainedintheverbalaffirmation ornegationofacertainobject.Inaccordancewiththepreviousexample,wecanaffirmordenythat theobjectinfrontofusisactuallyachairornot.Thisindicatessomethingotherthanthebodily senses.However,neitheroftheseheterogeneousaspectsofsubjectivityisinitselfahumansubject. They are heterogeneous in that senses are receptive and reason is spontaneous, but both are constitutionalofsubjectivity.Reasonwithoutthebodyanditssensesisnotahumanreason.Anda bodywithoutthemindisonlyacongregationofmeaninglesslimbsandblindsenses.Wearemade upofbothmindandbody,andinordertogetthemtointeractinthesingleunitythatwecallthe subject,weneedathirdconcept,namelyTI(FM37/55).

21 TIisnotgiveninitselfand,therefore,itcannotbeunderstoodbyscrutinizinginthesubject,but mustbeinferredfromtheobjectencounteredintheworldthroughthesensesandunderstoodby reason(idem).Theobjecttellsussomethingaboutthewaysubjectivityisstructured.Theobjectis bothregisteredsensiblyandcomprehendedaspossessingameaning;itisnotjustanobjectbuta certainthing.Theobjectbecomesathingthroughthecooperationofbodyandreason;withoutthis cooperation we only sense an undefined object without being able to determine and, thereby, understandthatwhichmovesinfrontofusorsmellsinthevicinity.ThatiswhyRicoeurdefines consciousnessasanaprioritranscendentalsynthesisandspecifiesthatthenatureofthissynthesisis objectival(FM389/56).Itisaprioriandtranscendentalbecauseitisthatwhichenablesconscious experienceoftheobjectsintheworld,anditisobjectivalsinceitisonlyunderstoodthroughthe perceived object, and not in itself (e.g. by introspection). But how does TI bring the two heterogeneous capacities of subjectivity together in the synthesis that we understand as consciousness?Ricoeurdoesnotgiveaclearanswertothisquestion,butjoinsKantinstatingthatit remainsanenigma(FM41/59).Nevertheless,herelentlesslyemphasizesthatitisafundamental conceptinhistheoryofsubjectivitybecauseitremainsthefirststepinanunderstandingofthe subject(FM5/25,46/63).Andalthoughhedoesnotgiveaclearanswer,heattemptstocloseinon anapproximateunderstandingoftheconcept. Itmustbehomogeneouswithbothsensibilityandreasoninordertomediatebetweenthosetwo capacitiesofthesubject.Furthermore,ithastoconferanidentitytothesubjectthroughitsdifferent experiences.AsKant,heemphasizesthatTIisthe‘commonroot’ofreasonandsensibility(FM 43/61).Whatcansatisfythesecriteria?RicoeursuggeststhatKanthimselfpointedtowardstimeas apossibleclarificationofTI(FM42/59;cf.Kant1997:27375/181187)andthenhefollowsthat directionhimself.Timeisproducedthroughmybodilysenses,inmyapprehensionofthechanging objectsinfrontofmeandthechangingofmyownbody.Moreover,Iusetimetodeterminethe differentobjectsinrelationtooneanotherandtomyself.Thereby,timeisbothsensible(forever changing)andrational(therelationtoanonchangingidentity).Timeisnotpossiblewithoutafirm pointthatisnotchanging.Thisfirmpointisreason,e.g.ourcapacitytodetermineobjectasthisor that,beforeorafter,bigorsmall,growingordecreasing;inshort,ourcapacitytocategorize.Our reasonisthe‘zeropoint’thatwecannotperceive,butonlyreflecton(FM31/49).Thereby,time mediatesbetweensensibilityandreasonandprocuresuswithconsciousnessofanidenticalsubject andeverchangingobjects.Time,however,doesnotexplaintheenigmaofTI:‘Strictlyspeaking, wehaveonlysharpenedtheparadoxbyamoresubtleapproximation […]Tosaythattimeisthe

22 unityofthatdualityistonamethedifficultyaswellastosituateit–whichisnotnothing–butit does not solve it’ (FM 43/60). This point of convergence between TI and time cannot be underestimatedinRicoeur’stheory.TimeitselfremainsanenigmalikeTI.ForKant,TIproduces thetranscendentalschemes(Kant1997:2734/180)whichareinthemselvesnothingelsethana prioritimedeterminationsaccordingtocertainrules(Kant1997:2756/1801).TItherebydiscloses theworldasweknowit.Thetranscendentalschemesaretheconditionsonwhichtheworldappears forus.Wedonotperceiveachaosofeverchanging,undefinedobjectswithoutabeginning,anend or an observable cause. On the contrary, the world appears to obey certain definable rules and followthediscrete,continuoussuccessionoftime.Theworldisbothincontinuouschangeand identicaltoitself.This,ourunderstandingoftheworld,revealsourown,transcendentalconstitution (FM201/39). Whatisimportantforthepresentanalysisisnottoinsistontheobscureconceptualarchitecture presentinKantandfollowedbyRicœur,inpagesnolessdenseandinconclusive,buttoconcentrate ontheconvergenceitself.WhydoestimesharpentheparadoxinherentinTI? IfTIisthehidden,but‘commonroot’insubjectivity,i.e.,thatwhichprocurestheidentityofthe subject,andiftimeconvergesonthisroot,thenthistellsussomethingfundamentalaboutthenature ofsubjectivity:subjectivityisinitscoremarkedbytemporality,thisis,‘[m]ylifeistemporality’ (FN 425/399400). Our understanding of the world and, thereby, of ourselves is temporal (an insightthatremainsandisfurtherdevelopedinthelaterwritings). Inordertounderstandthisbasictemporality,wehavetoturntotheanalysesofimaginationinFN. AsIsaidearlier,thedistinctionbetweentranscendentalandempiricisnotasclearcutinRicoeuras itisinKant,sinceRicoeurisconcernedwiththe structures of experience in the living subject. Then, we may clarify the relationship between TI and time by looking at the workings of the empirical(i.e.concrete)useofimagination. A central passage sums up the analyses of imagination in FN: ‘But the core of meaning of imaginationremainsknowledge […]Itisasknowledgethatimaginationwhichswellsourdesiresis susceptibletocomingunderthecontrolofthewillandthatourlifeitselfcanbeevaluated’(FN 99/95. Translation slightly modified). Imagination procures knowledge about the world and the subjectbycreatinganevaluativespaceofreason.Ricoeurcomparesittolight:‘Lightisthusthe spaceofappearance,butlightisalsoaspaceofintelligibility.Light,asopenness,isamediumof appearance and expressibility’ (FM 40/58). We are immediately aware of the workings of imagination in our understanding of the world and our self. Imagination is reproductive: a

23 representation of an absent thing or situation, representing the thing or the situation that was previous the object of our conscious awareness (memory of the past). On the other hand, it is productive:animageofapossible,orimpossible,thingorsituationthathasnotyettakenplace.We canimagineascenarioandworktowardsit(apossiblefuture).Putlikethis,wenowbegintosee howtimeandimaginationcanhelptoexplainoneanother.Onecansay,inaverysimplifiedway, thatourcapacitytocategorizeanobjectisfoundedonourcapacitytorepresentpastperceptions, comparethemtooneanother,and,then,makeajudgmentaboutwhatisgoingtohappeninthe future.Thus,itisthroughourimaginativepowersthatwecometounderstandabouttheworldand ourselves,inshort:imaginationisthebasisforknowledge(FN99/95).Andthewayimagination procuresknowledgeshowsthatthisknowledgeisalwaystemporal.Wecometoanunderstanding oftheworkingsoftheworldthroughourcapacitytorepresentthepastandprojectthefutureinour imagination. InoticedthatRicoeurmaintained,althoughinalessstrictsense,theobscureKantiandivisionof thetranscendentalandempiricalaspectofimaginationbecauseittellsussomethingimportantabout hisnotionofsubjectivity.Imaginationisnotjustsomethingweuseinourdealingswithapregiven, objectivereality.Asiffirstwehavetherealityasitisinitself(objective,firm,inescapable)and then,inasecondstep, wehaveourowninterpretation of that reality. This can be a firsthand, intuitive understanding of the relation between world and the perceiving subject. But often the ‘everyday forms’ of knowledge tend to hide or complicate ‘man’s structures or fundamental possibilities ’(FN3/7).Therefore,humanrealitymightmorecomplexthanassumedbysuchanaïve realism. Theempiricalaspectofimaginationissubjectiveinthesensethateverysubjectusesitinitsown way. How we employ it depends on our personal and social history, individual needs, private dreamsandideas.Thisweallknow.Thetranscendentalaspect,however,worksinthesamewayin everysubject.Andthisisfarlessintuitive.Itisthatwhichbringstogetherreasonandsensibilityin what we know as consciousness. The most basic structure of subjectivity is a synthesis of our receptive capacities, the bodily senses, which let us become affected by the world, and our spontaneouscapacities,ourinfiniteverb,ourwilltosay,ourreasonwhichenableustoaffirmor deny and, thereby, confer a meaning to the object. This synthesis (i.e. consciousness) is made possiblebyTIinthatitmediatesbetweenthetwoheterogeneousaspectsofsubjectivity.Aswith theworkingsoftheempiricalimagination,TI createstheevaluativespaceofreasonthatwecall reality. Human reality is a product of the external stimuli received through the senses and the

24 affirmativepowersofreason.Now,thismaysoundlikesubjectiveidealisminwhichrealityisa productofthesubjectivemind.This,however,isnotthecase.Humanrealityisnotaproductof mindalone.Asstatedrepeatedlythroughouttheanalysis,realitymadeupofbothbodyandmind. Intuitively,weseetheexternalwordassomethingseparatedfromtheperceivingsubject.Andthe world is indeed external and accessible only through the senses. Our body is the organ for our actions and recipient for (some of) our sufferings. Thus, subjectivity is only understood as embodiedreason.AndasRicoeurputsit:‘Tosucceedherewehavetoreintroducethebodyintothe cogitoasawholeandtorecoverthefundamentalcertitudeofbeingincarnate,ofbeinginacorporal situation’(FN217/203;878/845).WhatRicoeurattemptstoshowisthateveninitsmostbasic experiences,suchasexperiencingtimeandtheexternalworld,thesubjectis,somehow,activein thatitconfersameaningtothatwhichaffectsit.Thesubjectisactiveinexperiencingtheworldand itselfbecauseitisjudgingaboutwhataffectsit.Humanrealityisloadedwithmeaning,andthe subjectis,somehow,acoproducerofthismeaningfulreality.ThisiswhyTIissoimportantin Ricoeur’stheoryofsubjectivity.Itshowsthatameaningfulrealitycannotrisefromreasonalone. OurconsciousexperienceismadepossiblebythemediationproducedbyTI,sinceitprocuresthe unityofour experience oftheworld.TI shows how reality is both mental and physical in that reason’sabilitytodetermineandcomprehendisalwaysconditionedbytheexternalstimuli.Weare affectedbyawrongdeterminationofacertainobject.Thiscanbeillustratedbyanoversimplified example.Sayweaffirmthattheobjectmovingtowardusisaleafandnotabaseball,andwego about, undisturbed, with whatever we were doing. Less than a second later, we are definitely affectedbyourwrongaffirmation.Thisisnottrueofonlyleavesandbaseballs,butofanyobjectof ourexperience,fromthehardphysicalobjectstothemostfeeblepassionmovinginourbreast. Surely,Ricoeurwouldnotdenythepresenceofanindependentphysicaluniverseinwhichthe subjectisbutasmallactorinatiny,fragileatmosphere.This,however,isnotthesubjectmatterof hisanalyses.Whatheistryingtodemonstrate ishow we can access the peculiar nature of the humansubjectandunderstandhowthissubjectperceives,feels,actsandsuffers.Thissectionhas beenananalysisofhowreasonandsensibilityareinterconnectedinthetranscendental(i.e.validfor every rational human subject) synthesis that we apprehend as conscious experience. This is a necessary,butnotsufficient,firststepinhistheoryofsubjectivity:‘Consciousnessisnotyetthe unity of a person in itself and for itself; it is not one person; it is not a person’ (FM 456/63. Translationslightlymodified).Ihavearguedthateventhemostbasicexperience,asthatofreality, isacomplexmatter.Thesubjectisexperiencingtheworldarounditbymeansofacapacitytojudge

25 aboutthatwhichaffectsit(externalstimuliaswellastimeandthesubjectitself).Ricoeurnames this capacity ‘the infinite verb’, ‘willtosay’, ‘powertoaffirm’. Affirmation, however, is closely linkedtothepossibilityoffailure(FM32/50).Wecanmakewrongjudgmentsabouttheworldand ourselves. Thus, Ricoeur introduces two notions that have large impact on his further analysis, namelytheconceptofdisproportionandtheconceptofhumanfrailty.Ireturntothesenotionsin thelastsection.Inthefollowingsection,Ishalllookonhowthesubjectisabletoactintheworld disclosedbyreasonandsensibility. Action: The Practical Space of Reason In the previous section, we saw how sensibility and reason are related in the making of consciousness.This,however,isonlyanabstractconceptionofconsciousness;thesearethebasic structuresofsubjectiveexperience,butnotsufficientforselfconsciousnessand,therefore,notyeta person(FM456/63).How,then,doesthesubjectbecomeconsciousofitselfandtherebyaperson? Inordertoanswerthatquestion,wehavetogobeyondthetranscendentalsynthesisandlookat whatIhavenamedthepracticalspaceofreason.Thetranscendentalanalysisisnecessarybecauseit discloses the most basic structures of conscious experience and, further, explains the integrate workingsofthetwofundamentalaspectsofthispeculiarexperience,namelybodyandreason.But still,thisapproachhasitslimit‘becausetheuniverseofthingsisstillonlytheabstractframeworkof ourlifeworld’(FM47/65;1067/123).Thelivingsubjectdoesnotonlyexperiencetheworld,butis interactingwiththatreality.Thetranscendentalanalysisclarifiedthebasicstructuresthatenablethe objectalexperiencethatweknowastheworld.Theanalysisofthepracticalspaceofreasongoesa stepfurtherandattemptstodisclosethestructuresbymeansofwhichthesubjectcopeswiththat world.Iftheformeranalysesenquiredintohowthesubjectperceivesandunderstandsthatwhichit experiencesasreality,thissectiondealswithhowthesubjectinteractswiththisrealityintermsof decision,motivation,andvalue, andhowthese cometogetherinwhat weunderstandashuman actionintheworld. Thetransitionfromthetranscendentaltothepracticalismarkedbytheconceptofvolition.The reasonwhythesubjectanalyzedbymeansoftheconceptoftranscendentalsynthesiswasnotyet conscious of itself is because those analyses focused only on the structures of the experiencing subject.However,itis onlyby interactingwiththe experienced world that the subject becomes consciousofitselfasanindividualsubject,anagent;orasRicoeurputsit:‘theselfisinitsacts’ (FN58/56;cf.FM51/68),andfurther,‘Iaffirmmyselfasthesubjectpreciselyintheobjectofmy

26 willing’ (FN 60/58). By acting, the subject thickens the concept of identity found in the transcendentalanalysis.Theconceptofidentitythroughchangespertainstobothanimateaswellas unanimatedbeings,whereastheconceptofsubjectivityrequiressomethingmorethanmerenumeric identitytodifferentiateitselffromotherentitiesintheworld.Ricoeurfindsthisintheconceptof volition:apeculiarhumancapacitytocauseachangeintheexternalworldwithoutbeingdirectly inducedtothisactionbyapriorexternalcause.Iftheprevioussectionshowedthatthescientific methodofcauseandeffectcouldnotexplainsubjectiveexperienceofreality,thisbecomeseven clearerinthepresentanalysis.Thefunctionofhumanwillisdifferentfromthephysicalexplanation ofcauseand effectbecause‘[c]onsciousnessisnotanaturalphenomenon’(FN67;cf.12/156, 187/1778,379/3723).Thewillisoneofthecriticalcapacitiesthatdifferentiatehumansubjects from other beings in the world. Therefore, to understand human action, we have to clarify the conceptofvolition,andthisispossibleonlythrough an analysis of the interaction of decision, motivationandvalue. In an important chapter in FN, Ricoeur draws a poignant picture of both human will and the peculiarontologypertainingtosubjectivity:‘Athingishere,located,anddeterminedbywhatisnot itself,whilefreedomisnotlocated,doesnotbecome aware of itself, does not discover itself as beingalreadyhereuntilIobserveit.Itcreatesitselfindoingandaffirmsitselftotheextenttowhich itdoes–itisabeingwhichdeterminesitself.Itspotentialbeingisnotatallagaspingabyss,itis theactualtaskwhichfreedomisforitselfinthemoment in which it constitutes itself bythedecision itmakes’(FN65/63).Whereasotherphysicalobjectsintheworldaredeterminedbytheirpresence, theirbeingthereasaneffectofapriorphysicalcause(andarethemselvesacauseforaposterior effect),thesamecannotbesaidofthesubject.Thesubjecthasawillthatisnotaneffectofaprior physicalcause,oratleastnotentirelyaneffectofaphysicalcause.Thereissomethingmorethan externalstimulitothebeingthereofsubject.It isnotjustalinkinthegreatchainofcausality. Whenthesubjectreactstoexternalstimuli,thentheeffectsescapetheschemedrawnbycausality. Inshort,theoutputcannotbeexplainedbyacausaldeductionoftheinput(FN945/91).Theinput passesthroughthepracticalspaceofreasonoftheindividualsubjectbeforeitgivesrisetocertain effect.Itisatthispointthatthewillappears. Consciousexperienceisaresultofouraffirmationandcategorizationoftheperceivedobjectsas specificthings.Itisinthisactualexperiencethatwecometonoticetheworkingsofthewill.The willisnotpresentassomethingwecanunderstandandthenuse.Onthecontrary,wecometoknow thewillthroughitsworks,i.e.,thedecisiontoact.Throughareflection onourdecision,wecan

27 cometoknowwhatmade me (I myself ,thisindividualsubjectinacertainsituationatagiventime inthecontextoftheworld)chosethatparticulardecisionandnotanother.Butreflectioncomes afterwards.Therefore,itis‘theawarenessofthatpracticalreferenceto myselfwhichisthevery rootofreflection.Explicitreflection,inthedistendedformofthejudgment“itisIwho…,”only raisesamoreprimitiveaffirmationofmyselftothedignityofdiscourse,ajudgmentwhichprojects itselfintheplanofaction’(FN61/59).Onceagain,weencountertheconceptofaffirmation.There exists an affirmation more primitive than the subject itself, and every conscious choice that the subjectmakesoriginatesinthisprimitiveaffirmationinherentinsubjectivity.Ishallcomebackto thisinthelastsection. Inthepresentcontext,wemustconcentrateontherelationbetweenreflectionandthepracticalself. Before its capacity to reflect, the subject is characterized by its capacity to act. And although reflectionandactionareinseparableineveryaspectoftheactualvoluntaryact,thedistinctionis interestingbecauseitemphasizesthatthesubjectisonlyasubjectthroughitsactions.Thesubjectis notonlya res cogitans ,butfirstofalla cogito agens .Reflectionmaybethehallmarkofhumanity. Nevertheless, reflection is always rooted in sensibility and action. The subject senses, thinks, suffers,andacts.Thus,Ricoeurcoinstheterm Integral Cogito todescribethenatureofthegeneral humansubject(FN91/88).Theterm‘integral’iscuriouslyenoughomittedbythetranslator).The subjectisnotgivenbeforeitsactionsbutexistsonlyinvirtueofitsactions:‘Iaminaworldin whichthereissomethingtobedone.Ihaveembarkedintoitinordertoactinit’(FN212/1978);or simply,‘[t]oexististoact’(FN334/316). Whatisimportant,inthissection,isnotsomuchthenatureofactionitself(whichwillbedealt withinchaptertwo),but how thesubjectiscapabletoactand why itactsinacertainway.Howit actsisanalyzedbytheconceptofdecision;andwhyitactsinonethiswayandnotinanotheris approached through the concepts of motivation and value. The three concepts are obviously inseparableineffectiveaction(FN712/69,83/80,934/90),andtheyshall,therefore,beanalyzed intheirreciprocalworkings.Nevertheless,forthesakeofclarityitmightbeagoodideatostart withabriefpresentationofRicoeur’sbasicunderstandingofthethreeconcepts. Decision Ricoeurgivesaconcisedefinitionofdecision:‘ a decision signifies, that is, designates in emptiness, a future action which depends on me and which is within my power ’(FN43/42.Translationslightly modified). Decision is constituted by intentionality. It is a decision to do something (a future

28 action).Andintentionalityiswhatmakesdecisionafundamentallinkbetweentheworldandthe subject(FN42/42).Byacting,thesubjectinteractswiththeworld;itplacesitselfintheworld,soto say.However,decisiondoesnotnecessarilydependontheworld.Onecandecidetodosomething not regarding or, perhaps even more significant, in spite of the world. The power to decide is essentiallyacapacitytodesignateinemptiness(désigneràvide),toconceiveaprojectaboutwhat todowithouttakinganythingintoaccountexcept oneself .Andthisis,perhaps,themostcritical feature of decision. To decide is, in the strictest sense, only dependent on the subject. And the individualsubjectisultimatelyaresultofitsdecisions:‘Itdependsonmetodecide’(FN184/175). Thisisanecessaryfirststepisunderstandingoftheconceptofresponsibility(FN57/56,81/78). So,thesubjectaffirmsitselfintheobjectofitswill,and,indecidingonwhattodowiththeobject, it characterizes itself as an agent of certain actions. These actions are done by the subject and, thereforetheirmeaningispartlycreatedbythesubject.Andviceversa,thesubjectbecomesthis particular subject who has done such actions and thus becomes a meaningful subject by these actions.Ricoeurcallsthisfeatureofdecision‘[t]heimputationofmyself:“ se decider”–makingup my mind’(FN55/54). MotivationandValue However,nodecisionhaseverbeenmadewithoutacertain motivation: ‘There are no decision withoutmotives’(FN66/64).Theconceptofdecisionasthecapacitytodesignateinemptiness,i.e., dependentonlyuponthesubjectitself,couldeasilyleadtotheerroneousconclusionthatthehuman willisarbitrary.Onthecontrary,‘[t]hehighestformofwillisthewillwhichhas its reasons,thatis, onewhichbearsatthesametimethemarkofmyinitiativeandthemarkofalegitimacy’(idem. Translationmodified).Thus,whenthesubjectmakesadecision,thenthedecisiondeterminesthe subjectasthisindividualsubjectbyreferringtosomekindoflegitimacyforthedecisionmade,and, consequently,fortheactionofthesubject.Itisbygivinganaccountofthemotivesforacertain decision that the question of legitimacy comes into the picture. A motif can be legitimate or illegitimate.So,thequestionis:howdoesthesubjectunderstandwhatisalegitimatemotifand whatisnot?Toanswerthisquestion,wemusttakeacloserlookontheconceptofvalue. Aspointedtoseveraltimesnow,thehumansubjectismadeupofbothreasonandbody,andthe twoaspectsareintrinsicallyinterlacedinsubjectiveexperience.Nevertheless,itcanbeahelpto examinetheconceptofmotivationfromthesetwoaspectsseparately,i.e.,thebodilymotivesand the motives of reason. This is, of course, a forced distinction, since motives never present

29 themselves as pure bodily motives or motive of pure reason. Anyhow, the theoretic distinction mightclarifythestructureofmotivation. Theconceptofmotivationcoversa wide andcomplex field of phenomena. But at the extreme polesoftheconcept,wefindthebodilyrootedmotivesatoneend,andthemotivesofpurereason attheother.Thisscalegoesfromtheabsoluteinvoluntary(body)totheabsolutevoluntary(reason). Thus,ourdecisionisinfluencedbyallkindsofmotivesrangingfromthosethatwearenecessarily affectedbytothosethatwedeliberatelytakeuponus.Ibeginwiththebodilymotives. Itisthebodythatevidencesthecloseconnectionbetweenmotivationandvalue:‘BeforeIwillit,a valuealreadyappealstomesolelybecauseIexistinflesh […]ThemysteryofincarnateCogitoties willingtothisfirststratumofvalueswithwhich motivation begins’ (FN 94/90). Motivation is generatedby values. Although we normally ascribe generation of values to thepower of reason, Ricoeur makes it clear that values are strictly bound to the embodied mind, i.e., our existential situationofbeingbothbodyandreason.So,thereexistnovalueswithoutbodilyexistence:‘The firstnondeducibleisthebodyasexisting,lifeasvalue’(idem).Itisthroughthebodythatwefirst feelamotivationtodosomething,toact.Ricoeurnamethisfirstlayerofvalue‘organicvalues’(FN 120/114).Theorganicvaluesarecharacterizedasneeds.Wefeelamotivationtodosomethingin ordertosatisfy a certainneed;thus,itisclear that we act not by reason alone, but are always affectedbyourexistencebeingbodilyexistence(FN86/83).Examplesofbasichumanneedsare thirst and hunger (idem). We are not in control of our needs. They present themselves as an involuntarypartofourexistenceanddemandtobesatisfied.Ifwedonotsatisfythesebasicneeds pertaining to our existence as an integral Cogito, we simply languish and die. Hence, they are immediatemotivesforcertainactions,e.g.,eatingordrinking.Thequestionishowtheybecome values?Toanswerthis,wemustturntothemotivesof(pure)reason. Thesubjectcannotcontrolitsneeds,but‘[t]houghIamnotthemasterofneedinthesenseoflack, Icanrejectitasareasonforaction.Inthisextreme experience man shows his humanity’ (FN 93/90).Thesubjectcanchoosetonotsatisfyitsneeds.And,perhapsevenmoresignificantly,this choice can be done systematically. Some of the most dramatic examples of such choices are celibacyandhungerstrike:‘Maniscapableofchoosingbetweenhishunger and somethingelse’ (idem).Itisamotivationtoactinspiteofthespontaneousmotivationgeneratedbybodilyneeds.In thisway,wecomeaboutthestrangesituationinwhichthesubjectturnsagainstitsownbody,its ownexistence,inordertofollowanothermotivationalfactor.Thishumancapacitytosacrificeits needsand,inthemostextremecase,itslifeinflatesthecomplexityofmotivesandvalues.The

30 humanwillcanbecontrolledbysomethingelsethanthebodyand‘[n]eedscanthusbeonemotive among others’(FN94/90).ThisiswhatIcallamotivationofpurereason. Theconnectionofmotivesandvaluestakesplaceinthemotivationalfielddisclosedbythetwo extremepoles,thebodilyneedsandthesacrificeoftheseneedsby(pure)reason.Asacrificeby means of pure reason is very different from suicide: ‘In contrast with suicide, which is pure negationanddestruction,sacrificeisentirelyaffirmative,affirmingvalueandbeing,albeitwithout referencetomylife’(FN121/116).Whereassuicidecanbeanexpressionofanimmanentneedin the individual subject, a sacrifice is a (extreme) way to transcend the proper needs (and proper motives)andpartakeinthepracticalspaceofvalues.Themotivationalstaircaseascendsfromthe involuntarybodilyneedstothehighestexpressionofvoluntarydecision,thesacrificeofone’sown life.Ofcourse,humandecisionisveryrarelyeitherablindfollowingofbodilyneedsoradramatic sacrificeofourownlives.Mostofourdecisionsareinamoremoderatepositionbetweenthese poles.Inthechoiceoffollowingonemotiveinsteadofanother,theconceptofvalueisintroduced intotheanalysisofmotiveanddecision. Bodilyneedsarenotcommonlyunderstoodasvaluesinthemselves,butmoreanecessarypartof humanexistence.However,theybecomevaluesbybeingonlycertainmotivesamongstothers 7.The human subject holds the possibility to decide amongst an infinite variety of different motives. Becauseofthispossibility,thesubjectisseizingthedifferentmotivesintermsoftheirvalue.It decidesononechoiceandnotanotherduetothevaluesthatitascribestodifferentmotives:‘onthe humanlevel,organiclifeisundoubtedlyaclusterof heterogeneous demands,revealing discordant values’ (FN 105/101). The possibility to choose is constituted by the practical space of reason wherethediscordantandheterogeneousvaluesareweightedagainstoneanotherinordertodecide on which to choose as a legitimate motive for a certain action. Thereby, the motives (even the spontaneousbodilyones)becomeahierarchyofvaluesfortheindividualsubject(FN1456/1389). Thequestionisnow:howdothedifferentmotivesformthehierarchyofheterogeneousvaluesthat structurethepracticalspaceofreason?

7 Even though the bodily or organic needs are only some motives amongst others, Ricoeur is well aware of their fundamentalcharacterinthataneedis‘theprimordialspontaneityofthebody;assuchitoriginallyandinitiallyreveals valueswhichsetitapartfromallothersourcesofmotives.Throughneed,values emerge withoutmyhavingposited theminmyactgeneratingrole:breadisgood,wineisgood’(FN94/90).

31 ThePracticalSpaceofReason Beforeansweringthatquestion,wehavetotakeacloserlookatwhatImeanbythepracticalspace of reason. In the previous section, we saw how the transcendental imagination made conscious experiencepossibleby thesynthesisofbody andreason. This, however, cannot account for the subjectiveexperienceasbeingapartofand,atthesametime,differentfromtheexperiencedworld, i.e.,theexperienceofbeinganautonomouspersonsomewhatdifferentfromtherestoftheworld. Thesubjectdoesnotblendintotheworld,butisitselfcapableofcausingachangeintheworld throughactions.Andactions,ontheirpart,aredonebecauseofacertainmotivation.Motivesdonot compelthesubjecttoactinacertainway,butpresentthemselvesasdifferentoptionsamongwhich thesubjectcandecideonwhichonetochoose.Theseheterogeneousmotivesoccurasoptionsfor thesubjectinwhatIhavechosentonamethepracticalspaceofreason. Whereas conscious experience is roughly the same in every normal functioning subject, the practicalspaceofreasonispersonal,inthestrictest sense of the word. Conscious experience is intersubjectivebecauseitisthatwhichenablesacommonexperienceofobjectsinandfeaturesof theworld.Thepracticalspaceispersonalbecauseitisthatthroughwhichsubjectdecidesonhowto interactwiththeworld.Bymeansofthesedecisions,thesubjectdeterminesandaffirmsitselfasan agentofcertainactionsand,thereby,itbecomesthisparticularsubject,aperson. Inthiscontext,weonceagainencountertheconceptofimagination.Thistime,though,itisnotthe transcendental,buttheempiricalaspectthatisatplay.Imaginationis‘imaginationoftheabsent thing and of action directed towards the thing – the crossroad of need and willing’ (FN 95/91. Translationmodified). Whereastranscendentalimaginationilluminatesthebasicstructuresofthe experiencedworld,theempiricalaspectisthatwhichpresentsthemotives(andthemeanstofollow thosemotives)forthesubjecttodecideon.Thequotedsentencesaysitclearly:imaginationisthe crossroads of the will and the needs. However, imagination does not only present the means to fulfillbodilyneeds,suchasthirstorhunger,butaninfinitevarietyofmotives.Aswehaveseen, thesemotivesspanfromthemostconcretebodilyneed,rootedinourbodilyconstitution,tothe mostabstractmotive,suchasthedecisionnottoeatinordertoserveamotivedifferentfromthe motivetofulfilltheneedofeating(i.e.anidea).Thesubjectcandecidetofollowonemotiveand notanother. Imagination plays a critical role in decisionmaking. The capacity to represent absent things, feelings,andpastscenariosandtoprojectimagineddecisionsintoapossiblefuturemakesitthe catalyst in the practical space of reason. Without it no decision would ever be made. It holds

32 together past, present and future in the process of decision. This is an important feature of imaginationbecauseitmakespossiblewhatweexperienceasidentitythroughtime.Inrepresenting thepastandprojectingthefuture,itconferstheexperienceofidentitythroughachangingworld.It isthesamesubjectwhohasdonesuchandsuchactionsinthepastandthesamewhowilldothese orotheractionsinthefuture:‘Iimputeafutureactiontomyselfinidentifyingtheprojected“I” withthe“I”whichprojects’(FN140/133). Anotherfeatureofimagination,closelylinked to theaspectoftime,isitscapacitytopresenta motiveasconnectedwitheitherpleasureorpain. 8Everysituationandeveryactionisexperienced bythesubjectasjoinedwithacertainfeeling.These feelings cover an infinite field of different sensations and emotions: pain, fear, tiredness, impatience, anguish, satisfaction, energy, joy, happiness etc. They are, in the first place, revealed by our bodily needs. If we do not eat, we becometired,impatientandendupbeinginpain.Therefore,Ricoeurinsiststhatbodilyneedsarea ‘primordial spontaneity’ that generates values without the subject’s consent. It is a pleasure to satisfyonesneed,andwethereforespontaneouslyascribeapositivevaluetothesatisfactionofour needs:‘prereflexivefeelingisaspontaneousbeliefconcerningthegoodofthebody’(FN104/100). Imaginationiswhatenablesthesubjecttobreakwiththisspontaneousbeliefonthebodilygood. Insteadofimmediatelysatisfyingthebodilyneeds,theseneedsareconfiguredinthepracticalspace asamotiveforanactionandnotanimmediate,necessarycause.Ofcourse,theseneedsstillremain astrongmotivationforaction,sincetheypromiseapleasurablesatisfactionandtherebygeneratea desirefordoingaspecificaction,suchaseating.However,thesubjectcandecidenottosatisfythis need.Thisispossiblebecauseimagination,inconfiguringthepracticalspaceofreason,canpresent this motive together with other motives which perhaps are capable of generating other kinds of desires,suchasnoteatingbecauseofadesiretofollowcertainprinciple,orsimplybecauseofa desiretolooseweight. Thisisaninterestingfeatureofhumansubjectivity. The feeling of pleasure or pain points to a rudimentary system of value inherent in subjectivity. A decision to follow one motive and not another in the practical space of reason is immediately joined with a certain feeling: ‘It is the affectivemediumofallvalues:avaluecanreachmeonlyasdignifyingamotive,andnomotive can incline me if it does not impress my sensibility’ (FN 122/117). The heterogeneous and discordantmotivespresentthemselvesinthepracticalspaceofreasonwherethesubjectexperience 8 This is a very clearcut distinction that does not correspond to the effective experience of pleasure and pain: ‘Affectivityformsnosystem;itillustratesdisparatevaluesindisparatepleasuresandsuffering’(FN120/115).Anyway, Ishallusethisabstractdistinctioninordertoclarifythestructuralconnectionbetweenmotivesandvalues.

33 themandmustdecidewhichonetofollow.Still,thesubjectwouldnevercometoadecisionifsome motiveswerenothighlightedandothersnot.Thisisthejoboffeelings.Theyorderthedifferent motivesintoahierarchyofvalues(FN146/139). I returntothequestionoffeelingsinthelast section. Thishierarchy,however,isnotorganizedaccordingtotheimmediatefeelingsofpleasureandpain. Theimmediateactionuponamotiveisaninstinct.Mostanimalsactaccordingtoinstincts.This couldbeaninstincttoeat,run,hide,attack,orreproduce.Andsomeanimalshavealmostperfect instincts,thatis,theyreactimmediatelyuponexternalstimuli.Thehumansubject,onthecontrary, hasmoreinstincts(invirtueofitselaboratedtimeconsciousnessandunlimitedcapacitytoinvent through knowledge), but is less instinctive in its actions (FN 945/91). Human decision is permeated by a degree of hesitation not figuring inotheranimals.Hesitationisanindicationof freedom:‘Hesitationisachoiceseekingitself’(FN137/131.Translationmodified).Itdisclosesthe fact that motives are not causes to actions, but always possible motives. The subject hesitates becauseitisuncertainaboutwhattodoinaparticularsituation:‘InindecisionIamlostamong confused motives’ (FN 142/135). Motives become values through feelings. The human subject, though,isnotonlyaffectedbythevaluespertainingtobodilyneeds.Thereissomethingotherthan bodilyneedsatplayin thehumanhierarchyof values. Other than the fulfilling of mere desire, humanactionischaracterizedbyaquestforlegitimacy.Thequestionofthelegitimacyofavalueis posedbytheintegralCogitobecauseitisbothbodyandreason.Thesubjectiscapableofopposing itsimmediatedesiretosatisfyabodilyneed. Nowwehavethenecessaryfeaturestounderstandthebasicstructuresofthepracticalspaceof reason.Intheexperienceoftheexternalworld,weaffirmourselvesasapartofand,atthesame time, as different from this world, by means of actions that are generated by certain decisions. Thesedecisionsarenotdirectlycompelledbystimulifromtheworld,butare,inthestrictestsense, only dependent on the subject (to designate in emptiness). The individual subject becomes this particular person through its decisions and actions. No decision, however, is made without a motivation.Thereexistsaninfinitevarietyofheterogeneousanddiscordantmotivesamongwhich thesubjectcandecide,frombodilyneedstoabstractideas.Motivesareintrinsicallyjoinedwitha certainfeeling,sinceallexternalstimuliandeveryactionarecharacterizedbydifferentfeelings, roughlygatheredwithinascaleofpleasureandpain.Thesefeelingsmakeuparudimentarysystem ofvalues:good=pleasurevs.bad=pain.Nevertheless,humandecisionismorecomplexthanthat. ThiscomplexityisduetowhatIcallthepracticalspaceofreason.

34 Imagination configures an experiential space wherein the different motives and their joined feelingsareweightedagainstoneanotheraccordingtoahierarchyofvalues.Theconfigurationof thatspaceisduetobothpastexperience,thepresentcontextandtheindividualconstitutionofthe subject.Theindividualconstitutionofthesubjectisdeterminedbybothbodyandreason.Notonly satisfactionofbodilyneeds,butalsoideasofreasonpresentthemselvesasvaluesinthepractical space.Theseideasaregeneratedbypastexperiences,culture,upbringing,personaldesires,bodily constitution etc. The central point is that they are formed by the individual subject and are experienced as values among other values in the practical space of reason. This can lead to a confusionofvaluesthataffectsthesubject’sdecisionsandactionsandthusthebasicidentityofthe subject.Theanalysisoftheconceptspertainingtovolition,i.e.,decision,motivationandvalue,has shownhowthesubjectbecomesanindividualsubject,aperson.Personalidentityisdeterminedby thesubject’sactions.However,wehavealsoseenthatdecidingonwhattodo,howtointeractwith theworldand,inthisway,tobecomeapersonisahighlycomplexmatter.Personalidentityisnota fact,butaproblem.Valuescansolicitconfusionandconflictinpersonalidentity.Byactingina certainway,thesubjectconsolidatesitselfasapersonwithsuchandsuchvalues:‘Iconsecratethe hierarchyofvaluespreciselyinchoosing’(FN174/165).Andyet,anactioncanbeinconflictwith thesubject’sideaofitselfasaselfandsolicitaconflictbetweenthesubjectasselfandthesubject asperson.Ireturntothisprobleminthelastpagesofthischapter. Thefirstsectiondealtwithhowthetranscendentalsynthesisconstitutesconsciousexperience.This experienceisintersubjective,i.e.,everynormalfunctioningsubjectexperiencetheworldinroughly thesameway.Inthissection,wehaveseenthatthisisnotthecasewiththesubject’sinteraction withtheworld.Thesubject’sdecisionisstrictlypersonal;infact,itbecomesthisparticularperson bymeansofitsdecisions.Thus,thepracticalspaceof reasonispersonal(contrarytoconscious experience). This raises the question of the legitimacyofthevaluesthatmotivatetheindividual subjecttomakeitsdecisionsandactinthepracticalspaceof reason. Howdo autonomousand heterogeneouspersonsinteractwithoneanotherinacommonworld?Thisquestionisthetopicthe nextsectionwhereIshalllookcloseronthequestionofidentityandlegitimacyinfrontoftheother person.

35 TheSubjectasaPersoninFrontofOtherPersons Humanbeingsperceivetheworldinfairlythesameway.Theirworld,however,isnotthesame. Althoughwepossessthesamesensesandactbymeansofsimilarrationalstructures,everysubject colorstheexperienceoftheworldinitsownpersonalway(FM61/78).Weinteractbymeansof certainmotivesthatreflectourvalues.Thesevaluesaregeneratedbyourownnature,andbythat which is different from us (the world and the other subjects). This reciprocal relation between subjectandworldtakesplaceinwhatIhavenamedthepracticalspaceofreason.Inthisspacewe form,throughourdecisionsandactions,whatweknowastheindividualsubject,aperson.Inthis way,thesubjectbecomesapersonthroughthewayitinteractswiththeworld.Buthow,ifevery subject copes with the world in its own particular way, do different persons interact with one anotherinaworldtowhichtheyallbelong?Toanswerthis,wehavetolookatthevaluesbywhich thesubjectactsand,inparticular,onthelegitimacyofthesevalues. Wesawearlierthatthehighestwillis‘onewhichbearsatthesametimethemarkofmyinitiative andthatofalegitimacy’(FN66/64.Translationmodified). These are two critical aspects of the conceptofaperson.Thesubject’sinitiative(spontaneity)iswhatmakesautonomypossibleandsets itfreeoftheimmediateresponsetostimuli.Sincethesubjectisfreeanditsactions,inthestrictest sense,onlydependuponitself,itisalsoresponsiblefortheseactions.Buttowhomorwhatisthe subjectresponsibleandhowdoesitdecideonwhichvaluestofollowandwhichtoturndown? Thesequestionspointtothesecondfeature,namelythelegitimacyofthesubject’svalues.Earlier wesawhowconsciousexperiencedevelopsintotheparticularexperienceoftheindividualsubject inthatthesubjectbecomesapersonthroughcertaindecisionsandactionsinthepracticalspaceof reason. But Ricoeur writes unambiguously that ‘[o]ne would be greatly mistaken, however in holdingthissynthesisforanaccomplishedone,giveninitselfintheimmediacyofselftoself.The personisstillaprojectedsynthesisthatseizesitselfintherepresentationofatask,ofanidealof whatthepersonshouldbe’(FM69/86;cf.LS261).Thesubjectisnotapersonsimplybythefact thatitisanautonomousandfreebeing.Tobeapersonisnota fact,butanopentaskforthe individualsubject.Butbeforegoingfurtherintototheconceptoftheperson,wefirsthavetoclarify therelationbetweenlegitimacyandresponsibility. Legitimacybecomesacriticalissuewhenthesubjectencountersanothersubjectwithahierarchy ofvaluesdifferentfromitsown.Ifthesubjectwereonlytocareaboutitsownexistenceinits decisionsandactions,legitimacywouldbeamuchlesscomplicatedmatterthanitactuallyis.The subjectwould,insuchastate,onlyhavetoorderitshierarchyofvaluesinordertopromoteitsown

36 wellbeing 9.Butthesubjectiscontinuouslyexposedtothedecisionsandactionsofothersubjects. The meaning of the movements and gestures of the other subject is not understood by laws of causality,butindicatetheworkingsofintentionality,i.e.,ameaninggivingreasonanalogoustomy own. Thus, we discover that: ‘This subject is myself, yourself, it is my fellow man. My own experience of myself and the sympathy (or better, intropathy) for the other are two living experiences which give rise to phenomenological concepts immediately valid for subjectivity in general’(FN226/212) 10 .Thus,weareinducedintothecomplexdialecticofautopathy(thefeeling of myself) and sympathy (the feeling of the other). What is important in the present context, however,isnotsomuchthecomplexityofthepresenceoftheother,butwhatthispresencedoesto thevaluesoftheindividualsubject. Whydoesasubjecthavetocareaboutthevaluesofanother?Arewenotonlyresponsibleofour own wellbeing (i.e. organize our hierarchy of values in order to promote such a state)? Such solipsistic perspective on the world would soon bring very the subject in difficulty. If only my valuesand my wellbeingcount,thenmyidentityshatterswithinafewmoments.Ilive,defacto,in ahumanworldconstitutedbyotherhumansubjects.Myidentitydependsonotherhumansubjects becauseitisanidentityinfrontof‘myfellowman’ 11 .Wearesimilarandyetnotthesame.Iam myselfandnottheother,andviceversa.Icannotpretendtoknowhowtheotherunderstandsthe world. I can try to understand how she understands the world by ways of observation and imagination.Andstill,theexistenceoftheothersurpassesmyimagination.Asimplemeetingwith the other proves this point: ‘the hand of the Other that I see “appresents to me’ the solipsistic touchingofthathandandallthatgoesalongwiththistouching.Awholeworldisborntothathand, aworldthatIcanonlypresentiate,“render”presenttomyself(vergegenwärtigen),withoutitsbeing presenttome’(APH66/122). Thepresenceoftheothersubject’shandiscriticalformyidentitybecauseoftheimplicationsof thispresence.ItisapresencethatIcannotbeindifferentof.Ifmyvaluesdonotregardthevaluesof thesubjectrevealedbythehandonmyshoulder,Iwouldnotbeabletointeractinahumanworld.I wouldendupunderminingmyownidentity.Asapersonmybeingisasocialbeing,orapolitical animal.(FM120/136).Thus,Imustbeinterestedinhowtheothersconsidermeinordertoexistin 9‘Pleasure,pain,theuseful,theagreeable,andtheeasy,inspiteoftheirheterogeneity,stillhavethefeelofafamily boundtogetherbytheterm well-being ’(FN116/111) 10 ‘ilappartientàl’apparencedelapersonnedesedonnernonseulementcommelaprésenced’unêtre,donccomme uneapparenceontique,mais,enoutre,commel’apparenced’unautresujet,l’apparencedemonsemblable.’(SR267; cf.SR269;KH1968/24748). 11 ’by formulating concepts of the subjectivity derived from perception of the self and from understanding of the behavioroftheotherassecondperson’(FN227/212.Translationslightlymodified)

37 aworldmadeupofamanifoldofdifferentsubjects.Tointeractwiththeother,Ihavetorecognize herasapersonwithherownvaluesanddesires(i.e.herownidentity).AsIstandbeforeher,she standsbeforeme.Wearebothpersons,butwithourowncharacters:‘Humanlikenessisimpliedin themutualothernessofindividualcharacters’(FM70/88).Herpresencedemandsmetoconsider herandrecognizethatshemayhavevaluesanddesiresdifferentfrommine.Ininteractionwithone another,theremustbeareciprocalrecognitionofourrespectiveidentities.Therefore,mydesireto promotemyownwellbeinghastobelimitedbythesimplefactthatothersubjectsexist:‘eneffet, je ne puis limiter mon désir en m’obligeant, sans poser le droit d’autrui à exister de quelque manière; réciproquement reconnaitre autrui, c’est m’obliger de quelque manière; obligation et existenced’autruisontdeuxpositionscorrélatives.’(SR274). Hence,theidentityofthesubjectisnotrootedonlyindecisionsandactionsconcerningitsown desires,aversions,fears,joys,inshort,itsown wellbeing.Theconceptofidentityhingesonthe recognition of other subjects. Identity is constituted by actions, and, since actions inscribe themselvesinaworldmadeupby this subject and othersubjects,theyhavetobedoneaccordingto theothersandmyself.Putinanotherway,thesubjectisnotonlyresponsibletoitself,butalsotothe othersubjectsaroundit.Infact,theconceptofresponsibilityiscoinedthroughthisbeingwiththe others.Asubjectisresponsiblebecauseitmustanswerforitsactionsanddecisionstoitself and to theothersubjectwhosemerepresenceobligatesanansweronmypart. If the subject’s identity is coined through its actions and the actions, on their behalf, are done accordingtocertainvalues,thenwecansaythatthesubject’sidentityisconstitutedbyitsvalues. Thepresenceofothersubjectschallengesmyhierarchyofvalues(andtherebymyidentity),since they condition my values. I have to take into account how my values are integrated with the existenceofothersubjectswithdifferentvalues.Otherwise,Icannotinteractinaworldmadeupby amultitudeofdifferentsubjects.Iamcontinuouslyfacedwiththeothersubjectandhavetorespond formyactions(i.e.values)tothatsubject,otherthantomyself.Wemightsaythatthepresenceof theotherdisclosesthequestionofthelegitimacyofmyvalues.Indeed,alegitimatevalueisnota valuepronetopromotemyownwellbeingateverycost,butavaluethatcontainsbothaconcern for my wellbeing and a concern for responsibility toothersubjects.Inthisway,identityofthe subjectisconstitutedbytheconstellationofvalue,legitimacy,andresponsibility.Subjectivityis,at itscore,shapedbybothitselfandtheexistenceoftheother. So,howdoestheindividualsubjectorganizeitshierarchyofvaluesinsuchawaythatitsatisfies thedemandsoflegitimacyissuedfrombothitsownwellbeingandtheresponsibilityforthewell

38 beingoftheother?HereRicoeurstructureshisansweraccordingtothebasicschemedevelopedin theanalysesofthetranscendentalsynthesisofsensibilityandreason. ThePersoninbetweenCharacterandHappiness Intheanalysesofthetranscendentalsynthesis,wesawthattheperceptionofthesubjectis,dueto itsbodilyconstitution,linkedtoacertainperspective.Thisstructureisnowappliedtothesubjectas atotality(FM49/67).Thistotalityis‘alltheaffectiveandpracticalaspects,alltheattendantvalues andcountervaluesthatattractorrepel,alltheobstacles,thewaysandmeans,toolsandinstruments thatmakeitpracticableorimpracticableand,inanyevent,difficult’(FM47/65).Upuntilnow,we havedealtwiththesubjectasexperiencingandinteractingwiththeworldandtheother,butnow Ricoeur gathers these different aspects (active as well as passive) of the subject together in a totality,i.e.,intheconceptofaperson.Thisis the final move of the structural analyses of the subject.Howdoesthesubjectbecomeaperson?Asweshallsee,thisquestioniscloselylinkedto thequestionoflegitimacybecausetobeapersonistobehaveaccordingtolegitimatevalues. Ricœurstructurestheconceptofpersononthetranscendentalschemeofperspectiveandmeaning (FM64/81).Wemustrememberthattheconceptofperspectiveaccountsforthefinitecapacities (body,receptivity)ofsubjectivity,whereastheconceptofmeaningexpressestheinfinitecapacities (reason, spontaneity). These two capacities constitute the synthesis of conscious experience by meansoftranscendentalimagination.Ricoeurnowtransfersthissynthesisoffinitudeandinfinityto thetotalityofthepracticalsubject.Thethreeconceptsemployedinthispracticalsynthesisare:1) Character (finite), 2) Happiness (infinite), and 3) Respect (mediation): ‘ All the aspects of “practical” finitude that can be understood on the basis of the transcendental notion of perspective may be summed up in the notion of character. All the aspects of “practical” infintude that can be understood on the basis of the notion of meaning may be summed up in the notion happiness. The “practical mediation that extends the mediation of the transcendental imagination, projected into the object, is the constitution of the person by means of respect ’(FM4950/67.Translationslightly modified). The practical synthesis is, as the transcendental, analyzed by the concept of intentionality. Character and Happiness are not analyzed introspectivelyasinherentfeaturesofthesubject,but understoodthroughtheirmediationintheobject,namely‘ the constitution of the person by means of respect ’(FM50/67.Translationslightlymodified).

39 Earlier,wesawthatthepersonisnotafact,butaproblemandataskfortheindividualsubject becausethetotalityofthesubjectisamediationbetweentheheterogeneousaspectsofsubjectivity. Indeed,thedisproportionbetweentheseaspectsispresentateverylevel(theoreticaspractical)in the concept of subjectivity and makes possible the risk of failure. In the practical context, the disproportionisbetweencharacterandhappiness,andtheissueatstakeistheaffirmationofthe subjectasperson.Now,Ishallbrieflysketchthetwoconceptsofcharacterandhappinessandthen clarifyhowtheyaremediatedinthepersonthroughthenotionofrespect. The individual subject develops, through its continuous interactions with the world, a certain character:‘characterisalimitationinherentinthemediatingfunctionofone’sownbody,theprimal narrownessofmyopenness.’(FM59/76).Mycharacterisamixtureofcontingenceandnecessityin thesensethatinmyautonomyIamalwaysdependentonsomeoneorsomething(FM63/80).Iam born by two other persons and into a certain culture; I am endowed with at certain physical constitution;Iamaffectedbyeventsthatareoutofmycontrol;Iacquirecertainhabitsthroughmy existenceintime.Thesefactsformmyexistence,andtheyallconditionmyopennesstotheworld. Inotherwords,they, gatheredinthe conceptofcharacter, determine how I am affected by the world.Inthisway,‘[m]ycharacteristheprimalorientationofmytotalfieldofmotivation,andthis fieldismyopennesstohumanity’(FM63/81).Mycharacter is the expression of my ‘practical finitude’becauseitinfluenceshowanobjectappearsinthepracticalspaceofreason.Theobject stirsupacertaininclinationorwakedesire,whichinfluencemymotivationforacertaindecision (FM 69). My decision, immediately, goes in a certain direction determined by my character. In consequence,mycharacter‘istheindividualwhoIam’(FN368/345)and‘[c]haracterisalwaysmy ownwayofthinking,notwhatIthink.’(FN370/347).Thisbearsconsiderableeffectonmyvalues, because‘[e]achvalueisauniversalwhicheachindividualstampswithhisindividualmark’(idem; FM61/78).Butfortunately,thesubjectisnotonlymadeupofitscharacter.Thecharacterofthe subject may configure the practical space of reason in that it determines initial inclinations and desires,butitisreasonthathasthelastword(FM667/84). Reasonisour‘practicalinfinitude’inthesensethatitseekstoholdtogetherthesingledecisions intoatotality(FM68/86).Reasonisnotsatisfiedbymomentarypleasures,butseekssomething else,namelythesumofallpleasures.Ricoeurdefinesthissum(asafaithfulpupilofAristotle)as theconceptofhappiness(FM66/84).This,however,isanaïveconceptionofhappiness(FM82). Happinessisnotafiniteconceptandcanthereforenotbesatisfiedbythesumoffinitepleasures: ‘Happinessissomethingentirelydifferent;itisnotafiniteterm […]Justastheworldisthehorizon

40 of the thing ,happinessisthehorizonfromeverypointofview.’(FM65/82).Happinesstranscends the world of finite and perishable things and points to a demand of totality (FM 656/83). The totalityexpressedintheconceptofhappinessis‘thedemandforatotalityof meaning ’(FM66/84; FM136/152).Happinessisnotthisorthathappystatethatappearsandvanishes,butanideathat confersameaningtomyexistenceasatotality. Aswesawwiththetranscendentalsynthesis,meaningisconferredbyreasoninthewaythatthe differentobjectsbecometheseparticularthingsinthisspecificworldbytheworkofreason.Reason demandsatotalityofmeaningofthedifferentstimuliinconsciousexperience.Thus,ourconscious experienceoftheworldisintentionalinthesensethatweunderstandtheworldbymeansofthe meaningconferredbyourreason.Thisisnotthecaseonlyinconsciousexperience,butalsoinour practicalinteractionwiththeworld.Reasondemandsthatthetotalityofouractionsandaffections canbegatheredinameaningfulwhole,namelyinhappiness. Therefore,whenwedecideonwhichvaluetofollowinthepracticalspaceofreason,ourdecisions are not only induced from our immediate inclinations and desires (character), but also from a demandoftotalityissuedfromreason(happiness).Thesubjecthas,initsdecisions,tomediatein the disproportion between the inclinations of its character and the demands of happiness. How, then,doesthesubjectperformthismediationsuccessfully? Ricoeurnowintroducesathirdconcept,whichissupposedtofunctionasmediationintheway thatimaginationdidinthetranscendentalsynthesis.Characterandhappinessmustcoverthetotality ofthesubjectandtheirmediationhastobedoneinsuchawaythattheyformasynthesis,‘andthat synthesisisfoundintheperson.’(FM69/86). Mycharacterandmypursuitofhappinessaretobemediatedthroughtheintentionofbecominga person.‘Thepersonisstillaprojectedsynthesisthatseizesitselfintherepresentationofatask,of anidealofwhatthepersonshouldbe.’(idem).Mypracticalspaceofreasonhastobeconfigured accordingtothisidealsothatthehierarchyofvaluescomestoreflectthenatureofpersonhood, namelyanexistencetogetherwithotherpersons.ThevaluesaccordingtowhichIactintheworld areshapedbymyexistencetogetherwithotherpersons,andIcannotdisregardthehappinessofthe other person because of this coexistence. My happiness depends upon the others, because my existenceisnotconstitutedonlybymyself.Humanexistenceis‘anexistencethatoneapprehends, or, tobe moreprecise, apresence with which one entersintoofmutualunderstanding, exchange,work,sociality.’(FM71/88).Toenterintothesocietyofpersons,myhierarchyofvalues hastobeorderedaccordingtothenotionofhumanity.Ihavetorecognizethehumanityintheother

41 inordertointeractwithher.Wemustunderstandtheotherpersonin‘his“belonging”(asamember or as a leader) to a practical and ethical totality ofpersons.Outsideofthis,oneisnolonger a person.One’sexistencecanonlybeavalueexistence’(KH200/250).Onlybyrecognizingthiscan Ilegitimizemyvaluestomyselfandtotheother.Recognizingthehumanityoftheotherpersonis notarbitrary,sincethehappinessofmyownexistencedependsonit.Furthermore,humanityisnot onlyatheoreticalissue,butanactinginrecognizingthat‘[h]umanityisawayoftreatinghuman beings,youaswellasme.ItisneitheryounorI,itisthepracticalidealofthe“Self”inyouaswell asinme’(FM72/89.Translationslightlymodified). Iconferhumanitytomypracticalspaceofreasonbytreatingtheotherpersonwithrespect.Ricoeur employstheKantiannotionofrespectinordertoanswerthequestionaboutthelegitimacyofthe person’svalues.Indecidingonwhatvaluetofollow,IhavetorespectthehumanitythatIrecognize inthepersonsinfrontofme.Mypracticalspaceofreasonisnotonlyrootedinmyownbeing,but atthesametimeinthebeingofallotherpersons. And that which we, human beings, have in common in spite of all our ‘existential differences’ (perspectives and characters) is exactly our humanity. In respecting the other person as a person, never as a means, I myself confirm my personhood,myhumanity.TheKantiannotionofrespectfunctionsasthemediationbetweenthe twofundamentalaspectsofthepracticalspaceofreason,character,andhappiness.Itoperatesinthe samewayasimaginationdidinthetranscendentalsynthesisinthatitmediatesinthedisproportion atthecoreofthesubject(FM73/90). Wenowseethatmypracticalspaceofreasonisnottheexperienceofanindividualsubject,buta spaceconfiguredbythecoexistencewithotherpersons.Itisa‘practicalandethicaltotality’(KH 200/250)towhichIappertaininvirtueofmyhumanity.Myvaluesandactionscannotbeseparated fromthoseoftheother.Theyinvolveandaffectthebeingoftheotherperson,likehervaluesand actionsinvolveandaffectmybeing. Thesubject,however,hasahardtimelivinguptotheidealoftheperson.Itoftenfailstotreatthe other persons with respect and, often, it configures the values in the practical space of reason according to its own self. Kant blames sensibility for this degeneration of personhood. Our inclinations,desires,feelingsandemotionsdistorttheclearimperativesofreason.Therespectfor thehappinessoftheotherpersonissuffocatedbytheperson’ssensibility(bodilyperspectiveand character), and, therefore, sensibility must be extirpated from the practical space of reason. The personmustobeyreasonandavoidthedeceptivesensibility(FM75/92).Ricoeur,though,opposes sucha‘ethicdualism’(FM79/95),andtheconsequentlypessimistviewonhumansensibilityas

42 ‘theradical’.Reasonandsensibilityareintertwinedeveninthemostbasiccoreofsubjectivity (which Kant himself was very conscious of), and therefore we have to ‘explore the “practical” disproportion that is more primordial than the ethical duality, and to uncover a principle of limitation that would not already be radical evil ’(idem.Translationslightlymodified). Ricoeurconcludeshisstructural(stripped)notionofsubjectivitywithanaccountofhowthefailure toliveuptothepracticalidealofthepersonisrootedinafundamentaldisproportionofreason (mind)andsensibility(body)intheheartofthesubject.Thefragilityofthepersonderivesfromthis original disproportion in subjectivity. The structural analyses have purposely disregarded the affectiveaspectofsubjectivityconcentratingonhowthedisproportionacted‘ on theobjectivityof thething, on thehumanityoftheperson’(FM81/978).Inafinalstep,Ricoeurturnstothequestion of how this disproportion is experienced by the subject as a self (idem). To explore this self experience,Ricoeurturnstothequestionofaffectivity. Affectivity: The Conflict of Feelings In this concluding section, I will look on three notions that together unveil the ontological dimension of the foregoing analyses. First, the notions of disproportion and fallibility that tell somethingabouthowthesubjectexperiencesandunderstandstheworld,theotheranditselfand therebydeterminesitsdecisionsandactions.Then,Ianalyzethecomplexnotionofaffectivityin ordertoclarifyitsfunctioninsubjectivityand whatitrevealsabouttheontologyofthehuman subject.Inawayofconclusion,Ipreparethenextchapterbyexplaininghowthestrippednotionof subjectivitynaturallyleadstoquestionsthatRicoeurdealswithandelaboratesfurtherinhislater writings. DisproportionandFallibility Subjectivity is basically structured by body and reason. This implies, as we have seen, that the subject is always bound to a certain point of view that limits its openness to the world. Nevertheless,thesubjectcan,throughreason,transcendthisperspectiveandtrytounderstandthe meaning of the limited perception of the world. This basic transcendental structure clarifies a fundamentalconditionofsubjectivity:thesubjecthastomediatebetweenthetwoheterogeneous capacities of its nature. The relation between the two capacities is, however, marked by a disproportion.Theconceptofdisproportionwasintroducedwiththetranscendentalsynthesis(FM 37/55). Inthesynthesis,transcendentalimaginationplaysakeyroleinthatitmediatesbetween

43 bodyandmindinthegenerationofconsciousexperience.Experienceisbasicallyaresultofhow thesubjectjudgesthatwhichaffectsit.ThisiscentralpointinRicoeur’stheory.Thesubjectisan embodiedmindandnotareasonablebody.AlthoughRicoeurneverunderestimatestheimportance ofthebodyintheconstitutionofsubjectivity,hehasnodoubtabouttheprimacyofreason.The subjectisintelligibleonlyfromtheperspectiveofitscapacitytoreason(i.e.itscapacitytojudge betweenpossibleoptionsandvalues).Herepeatedlystressesthispointinhisearlyworks(FN8,37, 57,342;FM62,81).Thus,thereexistsadisproportioninthesubject. Theminddominatesthe body,butisneverthelessboundtoitandlimitedbyit.Togetherwiththeconceptofdisproportion, Ricoeurintroducesanothercriticalconceptfortheconditionofsubjectivity,namelytheconceptof fallibility:‘Wearelookingforfallibilityinthedisproportion’(FM1/22). Thesetwoconcepts,disproportionandfallibility,areuncoveredbythestructuresanalyzedabove. Inthetranscendentalgenerationofconsciousexperience,thesubjectisnotinanimmediaterelation totheworldortoitself.Theexperienceoftheworldandtheunderstandingoftheselfasaseparate andautonomouspartofthatworldalwaysinvolveanactivityonbehalfofthesubject.Inconscious experience,thesubjecthavetojudgeaboutthestimuliaffectingitthroughthebodilysenses.Inthe formingofpersonalidentity,thesubjectmustchoosethevaluesbymeansofwhichitinteractswith theothersubjects.Inbothcases,thesubjectisexposedtotheriskofmakingwrongjudgments.The riskisalwayshighlypresent,because‘[t]hebondwiththebody,eventhoughindivisible,ispolemic anddramatic’(FN227/212;cf.FN485/456).Thistenseanddifficultsituationisaresultofthe disproportionofsensibilityandreason.Ononeside, reason is the capacityby which the subject dissociatesitselffromtheworkingsoftheworldand,thereby,makesroomforfreedom.Onthe other,thebodyisthatwhich,inescapably,bindsthesubjecttotheworkingsofworld. Although reason is that which enables the subject to become a person (through decisions, i.e. actions),itcannotdisregarditsbodilyconstitution.Ineverydecisionthesubjecthastopayattention tobothits(potentially)unlimitedcapacitytoreasonandthelimitsimposedbybody:‘Itistothe extenttowhichtheentireworldisavastextensionofourbodyaspurefactthatitisitselfthe terminusofourconsent’(FN343/321;cf.FM2122/40).Thebodyproperaffectsandrestrictsthe subject’saccesstotheworld.Andthesubjectcannotignoreor,inanyway,escapethis‘purefact’. The body is both access (registration of stimulifrom the surroundings) and limit (the access is alwaysdeterminedbyaspecificperspective)totheworld.Thesubjectmustusereasoninorderto givemeaningtotheworldaccessedbythebody. Athreefold cord, ‘the notions of perspective, meaning, and synthesis’ make up ‘the melodic germ of all the subsequent developments’ (FM

44 49/66).Theriskoffailureinthissynthesisisalwayspresent.Thisfragilityaffectsthemosttrivial, andoftenunconscious,decisions(suchasclassifyingobjectsascertainthings),butbecomesmuch morevulnerablewhenthesubjectisinfrontoftheothersubject.Thesubjectisaself,thisparticular subjectwithitsowndesires,fearsandideas,inshort,withitsowncharacter,andyetitissituatedin aworldcomposedbyothersubjects(withdifferentcharacters). Hence,weseethatdisproportionandfallibilityhavebeenfollowingusatthedifferentlevelsofthe analysis.Now,inafinalanalysis,Ricoeuremploysthesestructuralfeaturesofsubjectivity(infinite verbvs.finiteperspectiveandhappinessvs.character)inordertofindouthowthesubjectitself experiences the disproportion and fallibility rooted deep in its constitution. He turns to what he claims to be the core of the disproportion, namely the affective dimension of subjectivity (FM 91/108).Withtheaffectivedimension,hehopestoimmersethestructuralanalysesinthepathetic (i.e. suffered, affected) nature of human existence. Human existence is pathetic, because our problematicrelationtotheworld,theotherandourselvesis felt beforeitis understood (FM81/97). The philosophy of feeling (idem) interiorizes the structural features in that it uncovers the disproportion in the heart of the subject and shows how fallibility is rooted in the fragile constitutionofsubjectivity:‘Thatistosay,theconstitutionalweaknessthatmakesevilpossible’ (FMXliii/11.Translationslightlymodified). TheNatureofFeeling Affectivityisthedimensionofsubjectivityrevealedbyfeeling.Theexistenceofthehumansubject is first of all characterized by feeling, ‘the affection through which I feel myself existing’ (FM 131/147). Thevaluesthatformthepracticalspaceofreasonarenotexplainedbyintentionality.Intentionality maygivethenames‘good’and‘bad’,butdoesnotexplain why ourexperienceisqualifiedinthis way(FM90/106).Feelings,onthecontrary,reveal why anobjectorasituationisgoodorbad. Reasonorganizeourhierarchyofvaluesaccordingtothebasicstructuresofthesubjectinrelation totheworldandtheothersubjects,butfeelingsarewhatmakethismattertomeinthequalityofthe subjectthatIam:‘feelinginteriorizesreasonandshowsmethatreasonismyreason,forthroughitI appropriatereasonformyself […]Inshort,feelingrevealstheidentityofexistenceandreason:it personalizes reason.’ (FM 102/118; cf. LS 260). My firstperson experience is permeated and qualified by feelings. But what are feelings? The term feeling covers a multitude of particular

45 functions: ‘affective regulations, disturbing emotions, affective states, vague intuitions, passions, etc.’(FM83/99). Thefunctionoffeelingsisbestexplainedinrelationtoreason.Weunderstandtheworldbymeans ofthetranscendentalsynthesisinthatwecategorizetheinformationreceivedthroughthesensesas objectsandpositiontheseobjectsinrelationtoourselves.Weunderstandbytheoppositionbetween subject and object. Now, fellings inverses this objective form of understanding because ‘[l]e sentiment est la manifestation sentie d’une relation au monde plus profonde que celle de la représentationquiinstituelapolaritédusujetetl’objet’(LS253;cf.FM85/101);inshort,‘ilrelie d’abordcequelaconnaissancescinde’(LS264).Feelingsdisclosemyexistenceasbeingalready situatedintheworldthatIattempttounderstand.IamintheworldbeforeIunderstandit. Still,feelingsandreasonarenottwoseparatefunctions in subjectivity, but work together as a unity. The structural analyses disregarded the feeling dimension in order to sort out the formal structuresofsubjectivity,butinthesituatedexistence of the subject the capacities are generated throughandbyoneanother(LS252).Feelingdisclosestheintentionofreason,andreasonclarifies theintentionalityoffeeling. WhenIconsideracertainaction,experienceasituationormeetanotherperson,thefeelingsreveal the importance of these phenomena to me. I may feel that the person is lovable, the action repugnant or the situation embarrassing. Feeling exposes my interiorityby manifesting ‘pre and hyperconnectionswiththebeingsoftheworld’(FM86/102).Wecancallthisrelationthepersonal relationtotheworld.Itispersonalbecausefeelingiswhatqualifiesexperiencesas my experiences. Itis my love, my repugnance,and my embarrassment.Ontheotherhand,feelingisalwaysafeeling ofsomething.Thequalitativedimensionoffeelingisalwaysboundtoanobject(physicalornon physical)(LS252).Thereisintentionalityinfeelingthatpointstosomethingotherthanjust my feeling:‘Our“affections”arereadontheworldtheydevelop,whichreflectstheirkindandnuances’ (FM84/100).Theintrinsicinterplayoffeeling(interiority)andreason(intentionality)inaffectivity disclosesacriticalfeatureofhumansubjectivity:thecoexistenceof self and the other than self in subjectivityitself.Thesubjectis,initsinmostcore,affectedbothbyitselfandbythatwhichis differentfromit.Feelingsareimportantbecauseofthisdualityofaffectivity.Theyare,atthesame time, generated by the world, the other and the subject itself. They reveal a complex dialectic betweenselfhoodandalterity,thevoluntaryandtheinvoluntary,activityandthepassivity,inthe coreofthesubject.Theexistingsubjectisnotafreefloatingbeingwithanunlimitedcapacityto choose;onthecontrary,itisabeingsituatedinandboundtoacontext,aworldandothersubjects

46 thatdetermineandshapeitsexistence.Theaffectivedimensionisexactlywhatrevealsdiscloseour ‘beingalreadyin…,throughthatprimodial inesse .’(FM103/119).Intheanalysisofthepractical aspectofthesubject,wesawthathumanactionisdeterminedbythecharacteroftheactingsubject (habits,physicalconstitution,education,cultureetc.).Thesubjectisinclinedtosatisfythevalues thatareshapedbyitscharacter.However,wealsonoticedthatthepresenceofothersubjectscall into question the legitimacy of those values. The subject is intertwined with the other in its existenceintheworld.ActioninthiscoexistenceofdifferentsubjectstakesplaceinwhatIchoseto call the practical space of reason. The practical space of reason is the world experienced as a coexistencewithothersubjectsconsideredaspersons.Itistheworldpervadedbyvaluesgenerated andshapedbytheself,theother,andtheworld.MyfeelingsrevealtomethatI‘amalreadyin’this practicalspaceofreason.Myexistenceisanexistenceinaworldconstitutedbyheterogeneousand discordantvalues. The complex nature of values is revealed by the affective dimension, since this dimension of subjectivity,asopposedtothetranscendental and the practical, expresses ‘living consciousness’ (FM108);anactive,livingconsciousnessisrelatedtotheworldanditself‘partouscesfilssecrets, »tendus«entrenousetlesêtres,quenousnommonsprécisémentles»tendances«’(LS253).These tendenciesaretheoriginofourvaluesandmotivations.Theydisclosethe why of thepredicates ‘good’and‘bad’.Atendencyholdsthispowertoqualifysinceit,thoughfeelings,solicitsasubject indirectionofacertainaction.Itstressestheinvoluntaryaspectofvaluesbylinkingthemtobasic needssuchaseating,drinking,sleepingandreproduction.However,itisdifficulttospeakabout tendencies in other animals than humans, since feelings in animals seem to coincide with their instinctualbehavior.Inthis,humanbehaviorisdifferent,whichbecomesclearwhenwelookatthe feelingsinvolvedinhumantendencies.Thehumansubjectisaffectedbyanobscureconfusionof tendenciesduetothedisproportioninherentinitsbeing.Webelongtobothbiologicalnatureand thesphereofpersons,orculture(asRicoeurcallsit).Ourtendenciesdriveustowardboththese dimensionswhichoftensituateusinastateofconflictortension.Infact,thefunctionoffeelings hastobeunderstoodinrelationtothistension:‘Feelingpointsouthowfaralongwearetowardthe resolutionoftensions.Itsmodalitiesanditsfeltnuancesmarkthephasesofactionlaunchedbya certaindisequilibriumseekinganewequilibrium.Feelingisthusafunctionoftherecoveryofthe livingcreature’sequilibrium.Tounderstanditsroleinthisprocessistounderstandfeeling.’(FM 99/115.Translationslightlymodified).Thejobof feelings is to mediate in the conflict between sensibilityandreason.Thenotionofconflicthasbeenfollowingusfromtheoutset.Theotherkinds

47 of conflicts, though, have been dealt with as formal conflicts with regard to subject’s objectal relationtotheworldandtheother( the thing inthetranscendentalsynthesisand humanity inthe practical).NowRicoeurwantstofindtheoriginalconflictinthenatureofthesubjectitself.Andhe findsthisconflictinthefeelings,becausetheydisclose‘theinnerconflictofhumandesire’(FM 92/108) All human conflicts originate in what Ricoeur calls the ‘affective node’ of subjectivity (idem), which is the radical and dramatic, i.e., the felt, manifestation of the original duality of human subjectivity;thedisproportionfeltasconflict(FM106/123).Toapproachtheintimateaffective coreofsubjectivity,RicoeurdevelopsthePlatonictreatmentoftherelationshipbetweentheheart [thymós],thesensousdesires[epithymía],andthespiritualdesires[éros].Vitalandspiritualdesires keepthesubjectinacontinuingtensionbetween‘pleasure’and‘happiness’feltduetothefactthat ourbeingissituatedintheworldasbothabiological and spiritual being. Our desires drive us towards a complex satisfaction of values generated by both of these aspects of subjectivity. However,thesubjectisnotdividedintotwoseparateparts,apurereasonandanobscuresensibility, butactsasaunitybymeansofamediationofvitalityandspirituality.Andthismediationtakes place in what Ricoeur calls the heart. The heart is, at thesame time, organ and symbol for the feelings involved in existence (FM 104/120). The notion of the heart secures that there is no ontological difference between (organic) pleasure and(spiritual)happiness. Inthisway,Ricoeur rejects the essence of Kantian and other philosophical anthropologies (the Thomist and the Cartesian),namelythatthesubjecthastoobeyonlytherationalpartofitsnatureinordertobecome aperson(FM778/923).ForRicoeur,humanityofthesubject,personhood,isnotconstitutedonly byreason;onthecontrary,itmakesnosensetospeak of a pure reason, since human reason is alwaysrootedinsensibility,justassensibilityisalwaysshapedbyreason.Aswehaveseenearlier, thesubjectcannotbeunderstoodasastaticbeingmadeupofdifferentparts,butonlythroughits unityinactions.Thesubjectisnotgivenbeforeits actions. Therefore, the complexity of human desireshastobeunderstoodthroughthebehaviorthatdefinesthesubject:‘Unetendance,c’estàla foisladirectionobjectived’uneconduiteetlaviséed’unsentiment;aussilesentimentn’estilrien d’autrequecettedirectionmemedelaconduiteentantquesentie;lamanifestationressentiedece »versquoi«s’approche,»loindequoi«s’éloigne,»contrequoi«luttenotredesir’(LS253).Itisthe feltrelationtothatwhichisnotthesubject(theworldandtheother)thatisexpressedinheart.Our conductisalwaysaproductofthemanifoldoftendencies,vitalasspiritual,feltintheheartas desires.Ourdesirescanthusbebothvitaldesires(pleasure)andspiritualdesires(happiness),butit

48 isimportanttoemphasizethatbothpleasureandhappiness are felt as desires in the subject (FN 1245/119).Wemustgobeyondthetraditionalconceptionofdesireaspathologicalaberrationand deliriumandseekouttheauthenticdesireatthecoreofalldesires,‘the“quest”ofhumanitybehind thepassional“pursuit”,thequestthatisnolongermadandinbondagebutconstitutiveofhuman praxis and the human Self’ (FM 111/127). This authentic desire is a seeking for happiness, understood as the totality of my actions as a meaningful whole. Whereas the vital desires seek immediatesatisfactionofneed(i.e.biologicalonessuchaseating,sleeping,andreproduction),the spiritualdesiresaimatasatisfactionofmyexistenceasatotality(i.e.mycoexistencewithother subjectinfriendshipandsociety,myconvictions,mydreams,etc.).Theheartofthesubjectisina continuoustensionbetweentheseheterogeneousdesires,whichisexperiencedinfeelings.Ricoeur separates the manifold of feelings into two categories, the schematized and the atmospheric feelings. Theschematizedfeelingsarethoseinvolvedinourinterpersonalrelationtotheothersubjects.By schematization,Ricoeurintendsthecategorizationofthefeelingsinvolvedintheconstitutionofour practicalengagementwiththeworld,i.e.,thefeelingsinvolvedinourdecisions,values,andactions thatconstituteourcoexistencewiththeotherinthepracticalspaceofreason:‘wemustspecifyand articulatetherelationshipoftheSelftoanotherSelfbymeansoftheobjectivitythatisbuiltonthe themesofhaving,power,andworth.’(FM113/129).Humanfeelingscanonlybeunderstoodinthe intentionalrelationtotheotherpersonthroughthedimensionsofpolitics,economics,andculture (idem).Possession,powerandvalue expressedinthese ‘new’ dimensions awake a multitude of feelingsattheheartofthesubject.Theydisclosethefeelingsinvolvedinourconcreteexistence withtheotherSelf. Notallfeelings,though,areexpressedbyanintentionalrelation.Weexperiencefeelingsthatdo not seem to refer to any distinct object. They are more like an atmosphere or a tonality accompanying our being situated in the world without relating to anything in particular. Thus, Ricoeurcallsthesefeelingsatmospheric.Theyaretheformlessbackgrounduponwhichweconduct ourlives.Theiroriginisthe‘beingalreadythere’ofourexistence,andtheyare,inthisway,thefelt expression of the involuntary or passive aspect of human subjectivity. They are experienced as moods(beinginagoodmood,abadmood,lightness,heaviness,welfare,uneasiness,happiness,joy etc.),gatheredasthetotalityofoursentimentsin‘thefundamentalfeeling’(FM105/121).Itisin this fundamental feeling that the schematized feelings originate, from which they develop into distinctfeelingswithanintentionalcontent,andintowhichthesedissolvethemselvesagain(idem).

49 Thisfundamentalatmosphereoftheheartistheinternalizationofthesubject’srelationtotheworld asatotality,‘[b]utbyinteriorizingalltheconnectionsoftheselftotheworld,feelinggivesrisetoa newcleavage,oftheselffromtheself. […]Itstretchestheselfbetweentwofundamentalaffective projects,thatoftheorganiclifethatreachesitstermintheinstantaneousperfectionofpleasure,and thatofthespirituallifethataspirestotonality,totheperfectionofhappiness.’(FM1312/148). This‘cleavage’inthesubjectrevealstheontologicalstatusofthesubjectintheformofconflict. We have met the concept of conflict several times in the previous analyses. Now it is time to confrontthisconflictintermsofanontologyofthesubject. OutlineforanOntology Beingthisparticularsubjectsituatedinacertainworldisalwayscharacterizedbyfeelings.Some feelings(theschematized)areexplicitlyrelatedtoourinteractionwiththeworld,othersaremere tonalitiesoratmospheresthataccompanyourexistenceasthebackgroundmoodfromwhichwe embark upon our doings and in which we sustain our sufferings. Ricoeur said that feelings, basically,functionasaffectiveregulationsthataimat‘thereequilibrationoftheliving’,andto understandtheirfunctioninthisprocessistounderstandthefeelingitself.Then,howdofeelings regulate the being of the subject? To answer this question, we have to return to the notion of disproportion. Thedisproportionofreasonandsensibilityextendsfromthemostbasicstructureofsubjectivity (transcendental synthesis of conscious experience) throughtheidealofthepersoninaction(the practicalspaceofreason)totheintimatefeelingofbeingaself(affectivity).Theintimatefeelingof beingaselfisexperiencedasanatmosphere,afundamentalfeeling,rootedintwoheterogeneous aspectsofthesubject,thevitalandthespiritual,thateachawakescertaindesires.Ononeside, desiresthatimpeltowardssatisfactionofimmediatepleasure,andontheother,desiresthataimat theexistenceasatotalityofmeaningor,inotherwords,happiness.Thesetwokindsofdesirearein tensionintheheartofthesubject,whichisexpressedinthefundamentalbackgroundfeeling,the mood, in which the subject exists. This can be a feeling of anguish, sadness, joy, satisfaction, pleasure,andsoon(FM106/122).Ourfeltrelationtotheworld,theschematizedfeelings,springs fromthisbackground,motivateouractionsbyconferingourvaluestheirembodiedandpersonal meaning.Itistheheartthatmediatesbetweenthetwoheterogeneousdesires,andintheheartwe findtheoriginalconflictthatcharacterizeshumansubjectivity:theseparationoftheselffromthe self.Thisnoncoincidenceisfeltasaconflictinsubject:‘Itseems,then,that conflict isafunction

50 ofman’smost primordial constitution;theobjectissynthesis;theselfisconflict’(FM132/148). Ourfeelingsregulatethisconflictinthesensethattheypersonalizethevaluesandtransformthe objectivestructuresintheworldintoapractical space of reason, wherein we see ourselves and engagewiththeworldandtheotherthroughahierarchyofvalues. The inmost intimacy of the subject, the heart, is in continuous unrest because of the conflict between the two heterogeneous aspects of its being, body (vital desires) and reason (spiritual desires), and feelings are what reveal ‘this noncoincidence of self to self’ (FM 141/157). The objective disproportion between verb and perspective, character and happiness that we analyzed above,nowfindsits‘ontological“locus”’(FM134/150)inthecomplexconstitutionofthesubject. Itisthroughaffectivitythatwefindtheontologicalnatureofthehumanbeingasanintermediary being(FM108),constitutedbybothfinitudeandinfinitude(FM134/150). Buteventhoughconflictisconstitutionalofhumansubjectivity,Ricoeurhasnodoubtastothe relationbetweenthetwoaspectsofournature.Wehavetounderstandthesubjectfromitspowerto affirm,itsinfinitude,whichinourforegoinganalysishasbeenexpressedintheverb,theideaof happinessandthesensiblehappinessoftheheart(spiritualdesire),‘Feelingalone,throughitspole of infinitude, assures me that I can “ continue my existence in ” the openness of thinking and of acting’(FM137/153).Ourcapacitytothinkandactspringsfromtheoriginatingaffirmation,which is ‘the effort to exist’ (FM 137/154) that characterizes our being. However, ‘the originating affirmation becomes manonlybygoingthroughtheexistential negation thatwecalledperspective, character,andvitalfeeling’(FM137/153).This‘existentialnegation’isthefactthatmybeingis contingentoroutofmyhands,sotosay:‘Existenceisdiscoveredtobe only existence, default of being-through-self ’(FM139/155). Thus,Ricoeurdefinesthehumansubjectasabeinginconflictbetweenanoriginatingaffirmation (awilltoexist)andan‘existentialnegation’(perspective,character,vitaldesires).Theselfisnota beingimmediatelygiventoitself,but becomes itselfthroughtheconflictintrinsicinitsnature(FM 141/157).Theselfisthefragilesynthesisbetweenthesetwoaspectsofitsselfhood.Ontheone hand, the self is rooted in the vital willtolive, which determines its desires and actions in the direction of selfpreservation. I am only a self aslongasIbreathe.Ontheother,itisaperson intertwinedwithotherpersonsinvirtueofitshumanity,anditcanonlybecomeaselfbybeingand actingbythedesiretobecomeapersonthroughandinthishumanity.Theanalysisofpractical synthesis clarified that we have to act in accordance with this idea of humanity, but it is only throughaffectivitythatweunderstandthatwe are thishumanity;thatourbeingisanexistencein

51 theideaofhumanitybecause‘thenreasonisnolongeranother:Iamit,youareit,becauseweare whatitis’(FM137/153).Ourfeelingsrevealthisduplicityinournatureasaconflictbetweenour desiretobewhatweare,thecontinuingexistenceofthisparticularsubject,thisself,andourdesire tobeapersonamongpersons,aselfunderstoodasmorethanitself,asapartofhumanity:‘The communityismygoodbecauseitleadstowardsmakingmewholewithina“we”wherethelacuna ofmybeingwouldbefilled’(FN128/122).Thesubjectcannotdisregardanyoftheseaspects.Itis boththisparticularsubject and apartofhumanity.Humanfragilityisduetothisontologicalstatus ofthesubjectasamixednature(FM156).Andthispeculiarnaturedeterminesthesubject’sactions because‘[h]umanfreedomisadependentindependence,areceptiveinitiative’(PW228/79). Atthispoint,however,itisimportantnottomisreadthenotionofexistentialnegation.Itisnota flawinordegenerationofthesubject.Itisaninexorableontologicaltraitofhumansubjectivity betterunderstoodasan‘existentialdifference’(FM135/152)thatqualifiesthesubjectasthethis particular subject, a self. It is the contingency or alterity that characterizes the existence of the humansubject.Itisthatbywhichwedifferfromeachother,butatthesametimealsothatwhich, together with the originating affirmation, enables ‘the understanding of language, the communication of culture, and the communion of persons’ (FM 138/154). The ontology of our being human is rooted in a continuous tension between selfhood and alterity felt as a conflict inherent in the self: ‘the Self is never certain’ (FM 126/142). The self is in restless search of restoringitselfasaself. ThenotionofexistentialnegationordifferenceiscriticalforthefurtherdevelopmentofRicoeur’s theoryofsubjectivitybecausethesubjectonlyfindsitselfthoroughthisdifference.Sincethebeing ofthesubjectismarkedbyanoncoincidencebetweentheselfandtheself,thesubjectmustturn towards that which can restore its being in existence, namely the existence together with other subjects in time, language, and society. We saw how the fundamental feeling of being, the atmosphere of existence, transforms into schematized feelings through the notions of ‘having, power, worth’. These schematized feelings are characterized by their objectdirectedness in the sensethattheirmeaningisproducedintheencounterbetweenthesubjectandalterity.Thesubject isdriventowardstheworldandtheotherinorder‘tofillthelacuna’initsownbeing. Therefore, Ricoeur makes a change in methodology in order to approach this detour over the meaningoftheencounterwithalterity.Heturnstothelanguage,culture,andtemporalbeingofthe subjectinitscoexistencewiththeothersubjectstodiscovertherestorationofselfhood. Thisdetouroverlanguage,time,andcoexistenceistheobjectofthefollowinganalyses.

52 ChapterTwo TheRedressedNotionofSubjectivity Thischapterfollowscloselyontheheelsoftheforegoing. It continues to reformulate Ricoeur’s theory of subjectivity as strict as possible. Something surprisingly takes place, however, in Ricoeur’stheoreticalworksafterFM(1960).Ricoeurstillengagesinthesamequestions:howdoes thehumansubjectexperiencetheworld?Howdoesitact?Howisitaffectedbyitsexistenceinthe world? But whereas his early works dealt with these questions by means of a reflective phenomenologicalmethod(intentionality,synthesis,andoriginatingaffirmation),henowturnsto hermeneutics.Butthisshiftinmethodisnotarbitrary. Thestrippednotionofsubjectivity,uncoveredbystructuralanalyses,madeitclearthatthefragility ofthesubjectstemsfromaconflictinherentinsubjectivity,namelytheconflictbetweensensibility and reason. We followed this conflict in three steps, from conscious experience over the basic structuresofactionintheconfigurationofthepracticalspaceofreasontothefeltconflictinthe heartofthesubject.Theconflictgrewmoredramaticuntilitculminatedinthefeltconflictbetween selfhoodandalterityinthecoreofthesubject(vitalandspiritualdesires). Thefollowinganalyseswillconcentrateonthequestionofhumanidentityinrelationtohowthe subjectactsinthepracticalspaceofreason.Wesawthatthedimensionofaffectivityconfersthe practicalspaceofreasonthepatheticdimensionofactualexistence.Itinteriorizestheintentional attitudesinvolvedinactionand,thereby,givesexperienceandactionstheirmeaning(i.e.value)for thesubjectasanindividualself.Thesubjectisdrivenbyanoriginatingaffirmationofexistence (expressedintheverb,practicaltotalityandhappiness),butthisaffirmationisalwaysconditioned byanexistentialnegationordifference(bodilyperspectiveandcharacter),feltasthevitaldesireto existonthetermsofmybodyandcharacter.Thesubjecthastomediatebetweenthesetwoaspects ofitsnatureinordertobecomeasubjectinscribedinhumanity.Andonlythroughhumanitycanit satisfythedesireofhappinesselicitedbytheoriginatingaffirmation. Atthispoint,theimportanceofthehumanityofthesubjectappearsmoreasahypothesisthanan argument. The previous analyses have showed that the happiness of the individual subject is necessarilyrelatedtotheother,buthaveonlycircumscribedtheconflictofselfhoodandalterityin theheartofthesubject.Todevelopandenrichtheconceptofhumanityinrelationtohappinessand argueforastrictconnectionwiththeconflictbetweenselfhoodandalterity,wehavetoturnfrom thestructuraltoanontologicalanalysisofsubjectivity.

53 Onceclarifiedthestructuresofexperience,actionandaffectivity,wemustplacethesubjectinthe world again. One of the central discoveries of the structural analyses was that the subject is not immediatelyaself,butmarkedbynoncoincidence.Thesubjecthasto become aselfbymediating thestructuralconflictinitsnature.Thisconflictmayberootedintheinmostcoreofthesubject,the heart,but,throughtheintentionalityofthefeelings,itexpressesitselfinthesubject’sinteraction withtheworld.Thisinteractiontakesplaceinthepracticalspaceofreason,theworldexperienced asaconfigurationofvalues,wherethesubjectfindsitselflostamongtheobjectsoftheworldand theirheterogeneousvalues.Ithasto reappropriate itselfthroughtheinteractionwiththeseobjects: ‘Appropriationsignifiesthattheinitialsituationfromwhichreflectionproceedsis”forgetfulness.”I amlost,”ledastray”amongobjectsandseparatedfrom the center of my existence,just as I am separated from others and as an enemy is separated from all men. Whatever the secret of this ”diaspora”,ofthisseparation,itsignifiesthatIdonotatfirstpossesswhatIam.”(FP45/53;see alsoA192).Tofindoneselfthroughreappropriationisanotherexpressionofthemediationofthe conflictbetweenselfhoodandalterity,whichisnowapproachedasaconcreteproblemofexistence. How does the subject affirm itself in the historical coexistence with alterity (objects and, more importantly,otherpersons)?Onlythroughalteritycanthesubjectaffirmitselfasaself.Theunrest anduncertaintythatcharacterizesthefundamental,ontologicalfeelingofthesubjectisrootedinthe noncoincidence of subjectivity. We noticed in the beginning that Ricoeur characterizes his philosophyasarestorationoftheoriginatingaffirmation,thebasicdesiretolive;now,hespecifies thatthisrestorationcanonlytakeplaceinareappropriationoftheselfsituatedinaworldwhichis constitutedbyselfhoodandalterity.Thesubjectmaybeanimmediate,originatingaffirmation,but thisaffirmationislostinthecoexistencewithalterity. Thesubjectfindsitselfsituatedinaworldinwhichithasnotplaceditself,anditisinthisworld,in interactingwithalterity,thatitmustreaffirmitselfasanindividualsubject;aselfthatisanIam…: ‘theself [lemoi ]mustbelostinordertofindthe“I” [leje]’(EH19/24).Theexistingsubjectisin continuous struggle with the question, who am I? The reappropriation of the self must measure itselfwiththeinsecuritystirredupbythealteritythatconstitutesitsbeing:‘Thehermeneuticofthe I am canaloneincludeboththeapodicticcertaintyoftheCartesian I think andtheuncertainties, eventheliesandtheillusions,oftheself,ofimmediateconsciousness.Italonecanyoke,sideby side,thesereneassertion I am andthepoignantdoubt Who am I ?’(QS259/262). Inthischapter,Ishallattempttoclarifythis‘hermeneuticoftheIam’incloseconnectiontothe structuralanalysis.ItisanattempttoarticulatewhatRicoeurnames‘anontologyofselfhoodin

54 termsofactualityandpotentiality’(OSA308/357);inotherwords,whatthesubjectisandwhatit canbe.Thechapteris,astheprevious,dividedintofoursections.FirstIbeginwithaclarification ofthemethodologicalconceptsofhermeneuticsandnarrativeidentity.Thissectioncentersonthe works Freud and Philosophy and Time and Narrative 3, butdrawssubstantiallyonminorarticles regardingthehermeneuticalturn.Ishalldealthoroughlywiththeconceptofhermeneuticsinorder to explain the reasons for the turn to hermeneutics and only briefly introduce the concept of narrative identity, since this concept is to be developed and explained further in the remaining sectionsofthechapter.Thefollowingthreesectionsinversestheschemeadoptedinthefirstchapter (fromexperienceoveractiontoaffectivity)inthatitbeginswithaffectivity,thenproceedstoaction and ends with ethical experience. In this way, I hope to show how the structural analysis is a necessary precondition for understanding the scope and meaning of Ricoeur’s theory of subjectivity.Themainreferencesfortheanalysesinthesesectionsare Oneself as Another and The Course of Recognition .

Basic Methodological Concepts The subject has no immediate knowledge of itself. We learned this from the stripped notion of subjectivity. Nonetheless, it has a strange, almost paradoxical, ring to it. If the subject were supposedtoknowanythingatall,thenthissomethingshouldbeitself,oratleastitscapacityto assure itself of itself through thinking. This was the assertion of the Cartesian Cogito and the fundamentuponwhichthemodernselfwasexploredanddeveloped,butsomethinghappenedwith ‘theschoolofsuspicion’whosemostprominentmasterswereMarx,Nietzsche,andFreud(FP32 3/401).Theideaofselfknowledgechangedfromanassertiontoaquestion.Consciousnessisnot immediatelygiven,buta‘task’(FP44/51).Wecannolongercontentourselveswiththeideaofan invinciblefirsttruthabouttheselfasanimmediateintellectualintuition,apsychologicalevidence oramythicalvision(idem).Suchkindofknowledgeisdoomedtoremainabstractandempty,or evenworse,itmaybeusedtoleadusastrayandintoillusionsaboutourselves.Themethodological lessontobedrawnfrom‘theschoolofsuspicion’isthatthesubjectmayposititselfasaCogito, ‘[b]utitisawounded [blessé ]Cogitothatresultsfromthisadventure–aCogitothatpositsitself butdoesnotpossessitself;aCogitothatseesitsoriginaltruthonlyinandthroughtheavowalof inadequacy,illusion,andlyingofactualconsciousness’(FP439/425). Immediateselfknowledge cannolongerbeusedasafirmphilosophicalfundament,sincethesubjectitselfhastobeincluded as part of the philosophical question and not as its presupposition. To accomplish the ‘task’ of

55 comingtoknowitself,thesubjectmustrefrainfromthepretensionofimmediacyandunderstand itselfas‘thewatchfulego,attentivetoitsownpresence,anxiousaboutitselfandattachedtoitself’ (FP54/62). Thepretensionofimmediacywasalreadyweakened,ifnotexpelled,inthepreviouschapter,since thebasicunityofthesubjectwasshowntobeaconstantmediationbetweenthetwoheterogeneous aspectsofsubjectivity,namelysensibilityandreason.Thismediationispresentateverylevelof subjectivity,eveninabasicfunctionsuchasconsciousexperience;and,astheanalysesturnedto subjectivity as selfhood, we saw that this mediation became a conflict between selfhood and alterity.Thesubjectisprimordiallycharacterizedbythecapacitytoaffirmitself,toposititself,to signifyandtoact,butthiscapacityisrestrictedbythebodilyperspectiveandthecharacter.The subjectdoesnotbecomeaselfbutinthemediationofthesetwoaspectsofitsnature.Allpossible knowledgehastopassthroughthe‘existentialdifference’thatdifferentiatesonesubjectfromthe other.ItisthroughmybodythatIentertheworldasaspaceofmeaning:‘Ameaningthatexistsisa meaningcaughtupwithinabody,ameaningfulbehavior’(FP382/372). Thesubjectmustthereforefinditselfthroughitsbodilyexistence,i.e.,ithastounderstanditselfas beingsituatedinaworldofobjectsthataffectitthroughthebody.Wesawearlierthatthesubject becomes a subject only through action. Action, though, is not a result of a pure choice, but an interactionwiththeobjects(andpersons)intheworld.Theobjectsaffectmyaction,justasmy action affects the objects. The answer to the question ‘who am I?’ is to be sought in an interpretationofthesubject’sinteractionwiththeworld.Itisnotthesubjectwhogivesmeaningto theobject;onthecontrary,itfindsitselfsituatedinaworldofmeaningthatshattersitspretension toposititselfasaself:‘itisthisinversionofthoughtwhichnowaddressesitselftomeandmakes measubjectthatisspokento.’(FP31/39).Theobjectsrevealmysituationasbeinganindividual subject,aself,inaworldalreadyloadedwithmeaning.However,thisrevelationofmyexistenceas aselfisnotimmediate,but‘remainsaninterpretedexistence’(EH23/27). HermeneuticalPhenomenology Inwhatsenseisexistencealwaysaninterpretedexistence?Beforeansweringthisquestion,wehave tolookmorecloselyontherelationbetweensubjectivityandlanguage. The previous chapter emphasized mediation as a critical feature of subjectivity: the subject is constitutedbyamediationbetweenthetwoheterogeneousaspectsofitsnature.Theverbisthat whichconfersameaningtoourlimitedperception.Withoutourcapacitytodesignate,theobjectsin

56 theworldwouldremainshatteredperspectivesandfragmentary information passing through our senses.This,however,isnotthecase.Ourperceptionoftheobjectsischaracterizedbymeaning.I donotperceiveanobjectasamultitudeofdifferentperceptions,forexample,redness,solidness, smoothness,lightness,bentindifferentangles,butasatotalityofmeaning,achair.Thisiswhatis meant by the intentional character of subjective experience: the object is already given to the subjectasameaningfulwhole,athing,intheactofperception(FP380/371).Inthecaseofbasic perception such as classifying objects as specific things, the mediation takes place without consciousattentiononpartofthesubject(exceptinthecaseswheretheclassificationgoeswrong). This is complicated drastically when it comes to the question of the identity of the subject in interacting with the world. Perception is meaningful because it is rooted in the existence of the subject;andtounderstandtheexistenceofthesubject,wehave‘toquestionbackfromtheuttered meaningtothemeaninginoperation,’andunderstandwhy‘[m]anislanguage’(FP383/374);orput inanothermanner,‘[i]tmustberediscoveredwith Hegelthatlanguageisthebeingthereofthe mind’(idem). Theexistenceofthesubjectischaracterizedbylanguage,sincethesubjectinteractswiththeworld through language. Perception finds its meaning in language. Hence, Ricoeur can say that the analysisoflanguageisanextensionofthatofperception(idem).Ourexistenceisnotcompletedin theimmediacyofperception,butprotractsitselftothatwhichisnotpresentinperception,namely thepastandthefuture.Thehumancapacitytodesignateabsentobjectsiswhatmakessubjectivity anexistenceintime.ItisthroughlanguagethatIcanretainwhathasbeenandimaginewhatwill be. Moreover, it is through language that the coexistence with other subjects is articulated and formed.Icommunicateandinteractwithothersthroughlanguage.However,Ricoeuriswellaware ofthecomplexityoftheassertionthatmanislanguage:‘Languageisnomorethefoundationthanit isanobject;itismediation;itisthe medium ,the“milieu,”inwhichandthroughwhichthesubject positshimselfandtheworldshowsitself’(QS250/252).Hedoesnotsaythatmanis only language or that language is the sole medium through which we can understand human subjectivity. He merelystressesthatmancannotbeunderstoodinisolationfromlanguage. Weshouldnowbeabletoanswerthequestionoftheinterpretednatureofhumanexistence.The rejectionofimmediacysuggeststhatsubjecthastoapproachitselfbyadetourovertheobjectsthat constituteitsbeinginexistence,andsincetheseobjectsrevealmainlythemselvesthroughlanguage, areflectiverecoveryofsubjectivitymustnecessarilybehermeneuticinnature.

57 Wehaveseenthatthesubject,initsinmostcore,ischaracterizedbyanoriginatingaffirmation,a basic desiretolive, and that this affirmation is conditioned by an ‘existential difference’ (body, characterandcontext).Now,the‘existentialdifference’iswhatmakesthesubjectahumansubject inthatitsituatesthesubjectinaworldwhosemeaningisderivednotonlyfromme,butalsofrom theworldandothersubjectsaswell(subjectsthatareexistentiallydifferentfromme).Ifindmyself embeddedinaworldofheterogeneousmeaningsandvalues,apracticalspaceofreason,andcan thereforeonlycometoknowmyselfinrelationtothatworldofmeaningsandvalues.Meaningand valuearenotproducedbyme,butIinteractwithandamaffectedbythem.Andlanguageisthe mediumthroughwhichmeaningandvaluearerevealedtome.Iinterpretmyexistencethroughthe signsofmeaninggeneratedinthecoexistencewiththeothersubjectsintheworld.Themeaningof myexistenceisnotimmediatelygiven,buthastoberecoveredinaninterpretationofmybeingin theworld:‘bypassingthroughahermeneutics,reflectivephilosophyemergesfromabstraction;the affirmationofbeing,thedesireandeffortofexistingwhichconstituteme,findintheinterpretation ofsignsthelongroadofawareness […]Theappropriationofmydesiretoexistisimpossiblebythe short way of consciousness; only the long path of interpretation of signs is open. Such is my workinghypothesisinphilosophy.Icallit concrete reflection ,thatis, the cogito mediated by the entire universe of signs .’(QS2578/260). Wenowseethattheaimofhermeneuticsistosituatethesubjectintheworld.Intheearlyworks, Ricoeur clarified the basic structures of subjectivity by means of a reflectivephenomenological method;nowthisapproachiscomplementedbyhermeneuticsinordertosortouttheconflictof selfhoodandalterityintheactualexistenceofthesubject.Ricoeurstillgroundshisanalysesina phenomenologicalmethod,butitnowbecomesahermeneuticalphenomenologyinthatitdevelops the abstract notion of subjectivity into a lived subjectivity in a concrete world. In doing so, he attemptstoanswerthequestionabouttheidentity of the subject in existence . The hermeneutical methodapproachesthenotionofconflictbymeansoftheconceptofinterpretation.Becauseofthe noncoincidence of the self, identity is possible only through an interpretation of the subject’s interactionwithworldandtheothersubjects.Thesubjectmustreaffirmitselfinaninterpretationof thecoexistencewithalterity;or‘[e]venbetter,itcouldbesaidthatwhatisone’sownandwhatis foreignarepolarlyconstitutedinthe same interpretation ’(PH128/80). The notion of the symbol might clarify the nature of the hermeneutical method. Symbols and metaphorshaveaprominentpositioninRicoeur’sphilosophy.Here,Ishalldisregardthequestion

58 ofmetaphorsanddealonlybrieflywiththeconceptofsymbol.Thisismeantonlyasameansto clarifyofthehermeneuticmethod. Asymboldisclosesthemeaningofinterpretedexistence in that it ‘renders manifest the double meaning of worldly or psychical reality’ (FP 49/57). Interpretation and symbol are correlated concepts,since‘thereisinterpretationwhereverthereismultiplemeaning,anditisininterpretation that the plurality of meanings is made manifest’ (EH 12/1617). Hermeneutics approaches the subject as an interpreted existence, situated and actinginaplurality of meaning. Inthisway,it attempts to clarify the noncoincidence, the conflict, inherent in subjectivity by analyzing the interpretationsthatthesubjectperformsinordertoreappropriateitsidentityasselfhood(FP48/56). Thenatureofsymbolsexplainsthestructureofinterpretation,sincesymbolsrendertheambiguity ofsubjectivitymanifestthroughthemultivocityofsigns(PD71/74). Thesubjectisembeddedinauniverseofsigns.Itrelatesitselftoanddifferentiatesitselffromthe worldthroughlanguage,becauseitinterpretstheworkingsoftheworldbydesignatingtheobjects andeventsintheworld.Thesubjectunderstandsthatitissituatedinaworldofmeaningbymeans of signs. I categorize and retain my sensations, plan my actions, and communicate with other personswiththehelpofsigns.Thesignsmostpertinenttohumanexistencearestructuredinthe systemofsymbolsthatweknowaslanguage.Language is an extremely sophisticated system of symbols that discloses, produces and communicates meaning. A symbol is characterized by a dialectic of presence and absence, since it is bound to sensible reality and, at the same time, transcendsit(FP384/374).Symbolsarecomplexinnature:asymbol,ontheonehand,designates anobjectasthisparticularsensibleobject,forexample,astain(touseanexampledeartoRicoeur) isacongregationofphysicalentities,butatthesametimeitmightdesignatesomethingotherthan the sensible object, which in this case could be a existential meaning, that is, a stain on one’s character(HSP231213/311).Theuseofsymbolsinhumanlanguagecoversavastsemanticfield thatdisclosesthemeaningofhumanexistence.Itisthroughthesymbolicnatureoflanguagethat the intentional structureof subjective experiencefindsitsmostclearmanifestationofambiguity: ‘thesymbolicistheuniversalmediationofthemindbetweenourselvesandthereal;thesymbolic, aboveall,indicatesthenonimmediacyofourapprehensionofreality’(FP10/20).Symbolsreveal our existential situation as subjects embedded in a meaningful world. They bridge the lacuna betweentheschematicnotionofsubjectivityandthe‘patheticdimension’ofactualexistence.They articulate,throughthesystemoflanguage,thespaceofmultiplemeaningsinwhichsubjectivityis rooted.Thesubjectfindsitselfsituatedinacontextofmultiplemeaningsinwhichitmustinterpret

59 itswaytounderstandingandaction.Symbolsmediatebetweenselfhoodandalterity,betweenthe subject and the world, the subject and the other, because they disclose the world as a space of multiplemeanings,‘[f]orlanguageisthegreatinstitution,theinstitutionofinstitutions,thathas precededeachandeveryoneus.Andbylanguagewemustunderstandnotjustthesystemof langue ineachnaturallanguage,butthethingsalreadysaid,understood,andreceived.’(TR3221/400). Theideathatmyexperienceoftheworldisanexperienceofaconfigurationofmeanings,i.e.that objectsandoccurrencesrelatethemselvestomeasmultiplemeaningstobeinterpreted,yieldsan importanttheoreticalinstrumenttoclarifyanddevelopthenotionofthepracticalspaceofreason. I characterized the practical space of reason as the experience of the world configured as a multitudeofvaluesgeneratedbytheself,theother,andtheworld.Thesevaluesarerootedinthe two heterogeneous aspects of the subject, that is, vital (body) and spiritual (reason) desires. However, in the structural analyses the concept of values remained rather unarticulated. To articulate and develop the concept of values, Ricoeur noticed that we have to investigate the feelingsinvolvedinourconduct.Ourdesirestransformthemselvesintovaluesthrough‘theobjects ofhigherorderinwhichhumanrelationscrystallize.’(FM119/135).Valuesoriginateinmydesire forwellbeing(bienêtre),basicallyavoidingpainandaugmentingpleasure,but,aswehaveseen, wellbeing is a complex affaire when it comes to human subjects. It cannot be reduced to my solitarystruggleforsurvival(FP471/455),because,duetotheheterogeneousaspectsinmynature, theobjectsofmydesiretranscendthemerephysicalones:‘Wemustaddtheeconomic,political, andculturaldimensionstoobjectivity;theymakeahumanworldoutofthemerenaturetheystart with’(FM112/128). The hermeneutic method explores these objects that constitute the human world through ‘the intentionalunityofsymbols’(FP522/501).Theschematizedfeelingsareconstitutedaround‘the trilogy of the passions of having, power, and worth [avoir, pouvoir, valoir]’ (FP 507/487/88. Translationmodified;cf.FM11325/129141).Thatistosay,Iassertmyselfintheworldthrough thesethreefundamentalfeelings.Myinteractionwiththeworldandtheothersubjectsismotivated bythesefeelings,andvaluesaregeneratedbytheinterplayofmyselfassertion,thepresenceofthe worldandthecoexistencewiththeothersubjects.So,howcanthe‘intentionalunityofsymbols’ helpclarifythegenerationofthevaluesthatformthepracticalspaceofreason? Ricoeur’sthesisisthathumanactionandsufferingisprimordiallymediatedthroughsymbols(TR3 221/400).Theambiguityofsymbolsrevealsthecomplexityofourinteractionwiththeworld,since themanifoldofmeaningdisclosedbysymbolsconfirmstheheterogeneityofhumanvalues:‘The

60 ambiguityof“things”becomesthemodelofallambiguityofsubjectivityingeneralandofallforms ofintentionality.’(FP385/376).Thesubjectdoesnotexperiencetheworldmerelyasaplaceofan evolvingstruggleforsurvivaloracontinuousmaximizingofitsownwellbeing;onthecontrary, theworldappearsasamanifoldofmeaning.Thesubject’sexperienceoftheworldiscircumscribed byacomplexsemanticsthatcannotbereducedtooneaspectofsubjectivity,i.e.,neithersensibility norreason.Toputitverysimply,whenthesubjectexperiencesactionandsufferinginitsexistence, thisexperienceis,foralargepart,mediatedthroughsymbols. The human world is a practical space of reason, since it is a space loaded with meaning that concernstheexistenceofthesubject.Ricoeurcanthereforeclaim‘thatonlymanhasaworldand notjustasituation’(MT201/211).Thesubjectunderstandsobjectsandoccurrencesinthepractical space of reason not as a succession of separate and noncorrelated situations, but as meaningful relations that make up its existence in the world. And this meaning is often confused and ambivalent because of the complex structure of its nature. Human experience is not merely a registrationofsensiblestimuli,butaninterpretationofthese.Muchofthisinterpretationisseemly immediate,i.e.,instantly,asinthecaseofperception,butsomerequiresaconsciouseffortonpart of the subject. The instant form of interpretation is a result of the intentional nature of human consciousness, and it can therefore not really be characterized as interpretation (FP 12/21); for example,weinstantlyandwithouteffortgraspthemeaningofaperception.However,theother, more reflective, form is different because it is a ‘seconddegree intentional structure, which presupposesthatafirstmeaningissetupwhichintendssomething,butthisobjectinturnrefersto somethingelsewhichisintendedthroughthefirstobject’(idem.Translationmodified). Now,Ricoeurusesthisseconddegreeintentionalitytoaccountforthesubject’sselfassertionin theworldbymeansofthethreefundamentalfeelingsofhaving,power,andworth.Thesefeelings arethethreefoldexpressionoftheoriginatingaffirmationofsubjectivity,i.e.,thesubject’swayof assertingitselfintheworld.Thesefeelingsmanifestthemselvesintheworldasobjectsofmeaning that transcend the immediate meaning of perception: ‘Such moments are indeed moments of objectivity: to understand theses affective factors, which we name possession, domination, and esteem,istoshowthatthesefeelingsinternalizeaseriesofobjectrelationsthatpertainnottoa phenomenologyofperception,buttoaneconomics,apolitics,atheoryofculture’(FP508/488. Translationmodified).These‘new’objectrelationsestablishthespheresofmeaningthatconstitute theworldof‘thehumanpraxisandthehumanself’(FP507/488).

61 Thejobofahermeneuticalphenomenologyisthentoapproachthesymbolicunitythatdiscloses this human world. Ricoeur proposes a hermeneutic method that combines two seemingly antithetical approaches, the Hegelian and the Freudian. He establishes a dialectic between archeology andteleology inordertoapproachtwofundamental dispossessions of consciousness (FP 460/4445). Freud and Hegel represent two complementarymodelsofapproachingthenon coincidence of the subject. Both of these thinkers conceive subjectivity as different from the immediate selfassertion of the conscious subject. Whereas Freud takes on an archeology of the unconscious to understand the behavior and conscious state of subject, Hegel embarks on the struggleforrecognition,theinscriptionofoneconsciousnessintheconsciousnessofanother,asthe aimoftheupgrowthofthesubject. Inthisway,we have two apparently opposite directions of analysis.TheFreudianthatturnstowardstheinternal(unconscious)forcesinthesubjectitselfand the Hegelian that aims at the external coexistence of subjects in an intersubjective world (FP 474/458). These opposite directions of analysis, the regressive (archeology) and the progressive (teleology),form‘thetwoendlimitsofasinglescaleofsymbolization’(FP522/501).Theunityof symbolizationiswhatweexperienceasthehumanworld:Aspaceloadedwithmultiplemeanings inwhichwefindourselvesembeddedasactingandsufferingsubjects.Thesubjectisanactivepart of this unity of symbolization, since it affirms itself as a meaningful existence in the world. Therefore, the hermeneutic method engages in ‘the taskofappropriatingtoitselftheoriginating affirmationthroughthesignsofitsactivityintheworldorinhistory’(NAS215/219.Translation slightlymodified).Thesubjectaffirmsitselfintheworkingsoftheworld,and,atthesametime, findsitselfsituatedasapartofthatworld.Subjectivityismovement,actionandsuffering,andnot immediateselfcertainty.Accordingly,Ricoeurdefineshismethodas‘areflectivemethodthathas itsstartingpointintheobjectivemovementofthefiguresofman,’andthenfurtherexplainsthat ‘[r]eflectionisthemeansforderivingfromthismovementthesubjectivitythatconstitutesitselfat thesametimethattheobjectivityengendersitself.’(FP510/491). Thetwoendlimitsoftheintentionalunityofthesymbolizationofhumanactionsare,ontheone hand,theunconscious,libidinalactionofthesubjectrooteditsvitalnatureandlimitedbyitsbodily perspective, its character, and habits; on the other, we have the conscious action that aims at a coexistencewithothersubjects. Thehumanworldissaturatedwithsymbolsthatunfoldandamplifytheconceptofvalue,since they develop and refine the heterogeneous forms of human action and suffering. They secure a conceptionofhumanvaluesthatisnotreducedtoeitherrawvitalpleasure(body)orpurespiritual

62 happiness(reason),butvaluesthataregeneratedasamixtureofboth.Thehermeneuticalmethod recapitulatesandamplifiesthestructuralanalysesofhumanvalues,sinceitinterpretsthesevalues intheirmanifestationofmeaningfulobjectsintheworld:‘Inhermeneuticssymbolshavetheirown semantics,theystimulateanintellectualactivityofdeciphering,offindingahiddenmeaning.Far from falling outside the bounds of language, they raise feeling to meaningful articulation’ (FP 19/29).Thismeaningfularticulationisunfoldedwiththeintentionalunityofsymbolizationinthat symbolsoriginatebymeansofthemediationofbody andreasoninhumaninteractionwiththe world.Inthisway,hermeneuticscombinetheregressiveandtheprogressivedirectioninthesame analysis. In interpreting the symbolization of action and suffering, hermeneutics discloses the meaningofvaluesinrelationtohumanexistenceasbothbodyandreason.Itinvestigatesinto‘the figures’ofhumaninteractioninordertosortoutthecomplexityofvalues.Thesymbolsofhuman valuesclarifythenatureoftheidentityofsubjectintheworld,becausetheyexpress,intheobjects orthefiguresofhumanexistence,thelivedunityofthenoncoincidenceofsubjectivity. Thehermeneuticalapproachdevelopstwofundamentalaspectsofsubjectivitythatremainedrather inarticulateinthereflectiveanalysis,namelytemporalityandtherelationtotheothersubjects.The dialecticbetweenpresenceandabsenceinthesymbolicconfigurationofmeaningrendersmanifest thetemporalaspectofsubjectivity.Thesubjectisrootedinthepresentinthesensethatitinteracts withtheimmediatecontextofitsbeingintheworld,but,atthesametime,itisdeterminedbythe nonpresenceofpastandfuture.Thevaluesthatmotivateitsactionisnotconfinedtoanimmediate situation,butpartofa worldwhichmeaningisderived by what is not immediately given, i.e., actions and sufferings in past and future. The objects with which the subject interacts are understood by means of this dialectic between presence and absence inherent in signs. The symbolic nature of the signs involved in human existence affects the values that shape and determinesubjectivity,becausethevaluesinvolvedinthesubject’srelationtotheotherarerefined and developedby the ambiguity of symbols. The subjectisnotonly relatedtotheotherinthe immediateencounterinthepresent,butalsorelatedovertime.Theabsenceoftheotherdoesnot cancelthevalueoftheother;onthecontrary,thevalueoftheotherisintactthroughthesignsleft byhisorherpresence.Thehermeneuticalapproachexploresthispresenceoftheotherinhisorher absencethroughthemeaningoftheotherexpressedinthesignsthatmaketheworldofthesubjecta humanworld,namelythroughwordssaidanddeedsdonebyothers.Thesignsoftheothermakeit explicitthatthevaluesinvolvedinmyexistencedepend on more than my own wellbeing: ‘My existenceformyselfisthusdependentonthewayIamregardedbyotherpeople;theselfisshaped

63 bytheopinionandacceptanceofothers […]Itisthroughthemediumoftheseworksormonuments that a certain dignity of man is formed, which is the instrument and trace of a process of reduplicatedconsciousness,ofrecognitionoftheselfinanotherself’(FP523/5023). Ricoeur’sturntohermeneuticsisanattempttoconferthestructuralanalysesofthestrippednotion ofsubjectivitythepatheticdimensionoflivedexistence.Thesubjectisthusapproachedasaliving subjectintime,intertwinedwithotherlivingsubjects.The foregoinganalyseshaveoutlinedthe notionofapracticalspaceofreasonwhereinthesubjectexperiencesitselfembeddedinaspaceof valuesissuedfromtheworld,theother,anditself.Thenotionofaffectivityshowedthatthesubject initsinmostcore,theheart,ismarkedbyanoncoincidence,whichpreventsimmediateidentityof thesubject.Subjectivityischaracterizedbyaconstantconflictbetweentwofundamentalaspectsof the self, sensibility and reason, experienced as vital and spiritual desires. The subject does not possessitself,butmustbecomeitselfinthemediationoftheconflictbetweenselfhoodandalterity (FP45/53).Thisconflictcannotberesolvedatthelevelofstructuralorreflectiveanalyses,sincethe subjecthastofinditselfthroughthealteritythatmakesupitsbeing.Inordertoinvestigateintothis alterity,theanalysesmustturntotheobjectsandpersonsthatqualifythebeingofthesubjectasan coexistence with other subjects situated in a human world. The identity of the subject must be retrievedbymeansofaninterpretationofitsexistence,i.e.,thestoryofthesubject’saffirmationof itself in the world through interaction with the world and the other. We have seen how this interpretationisboundtotheambiguityofsymbols,which,ontheirpart,revealsthecomplexityof the values that constitute the practical space of reason. Values have multiple meanings. Nevertheless,themeaningsinvolvedinthesymbolizationofthesubject’sinteractionwiththeworld arenotarbitrary,butgatheredinanintentionalstructurethatisintrinsicallyrelatedtothenatureof subjectivity.Andparticularlytwoaspectsofthesemanticsofsymbolsareofinteresttoatheoryof subjectivity,namelytemporalityandtherelationtoothersubjects.Themeaningofhumanvaluesis notbound to immediacy, thepresent,but extends itself back into the past and forward into the future. Furthermore, values cannot be reduced to the unconscious, libidinal workings of one individualsubject(archeology),butmustincludethe conscious inscription of the actions of one subjectintotheactionsofanother(teleology). Toclarifytheproblematicidentityofthesubjectinrelationtothesetwoaspectsofthesymbolic interactionwiththeworld,Ricoeurintroducesanotherconceptinhisanalyses,namelytheconcept ofnarrativeidentity.HereIwillmerelyintroducetheconcept,thatis,brieflyexplaintherelation

64 betweenhermeneuticsandnarrative,andtherebypreparetheuseanddevelopmentoftheconceptin theremainingsections. Explainingthehermeneuticalturn,Ricoeursaysthat‘[t]hemanwhospeaksinsymbolsisfirstof all a narrator; he transmits an abundance of meaning over which he has little command […] interpretation consists less in suppressing ambiguity than in understanding it and explicating its richness’(FP49/56). NarrativeIdentity Theconceptofnarrativeidentityisfirstintroducedinrelationtothetemporalcharacterofhuman experience, more specifically in ‘the mediations between the discordant concordance of phenomenological time and the simple succession of physical time’ (TN3 22/42; cf. 9091/167 169). Human existence is marked by time, and, in order to develop the schematic notion of subjectivity into concrete notion of lived subjectivity, one must clarify how the subject is characterized by time 12 . Ricoeur challenges what he calls the aporetics of temporality. Human temporalitycannotbereducedtoneitherpersonal,phenomenologicaltimenorimpersonal,cosmic time (TN3 20/402). Once again he confronts himself with (among others) Kant and Husserl. Whereas Kant emphasizes invisible time as an objective transcendental condition for conscious experience,i.e.,timeofnature,Husserlinvestigatesthephenomenologicaltimeofintentionality, i.e., subjective time experience. Ricoeur, however, retains that neither can fully explain the temporalcharacterofhumanexperiencebecausetheirrespectiveanalysesexcludethatoftheother (TN3 57/1067). On the contrary, the particular nature of human time depends on both the subjectiveandobjectiveconceptionoftimeandfindsitsexplanationinwhatRicoeurcalls‘athird time’(TN3245/441;cf.96/177).Thisthirdtimeistimeconfiguredbothbywhataffectsthesubject involuntarilyandbyhowthesubjectactsvoluntarily,andthesetwoaspectscometogetherinthe practicalcategoryof‘narrativeidentity’(TN3246/442).Thetwoaspectsofnarrativeidentityare interlacedinadialecticbetweenhistoricalandfictionalnarratives:‘Fromtheseintimateexchanges between the historicization of the fictional narrative and the fictionalization of the historical narrative is born what we call human time, which is nothing other than narrated time’ (TN3 102/185).Historyisboundtowhathasreallyhappened,aconcreteeventthatoccurredinaspecific physicalplaceandtime.Historyissomethingthatcannotbeundone,reversedorreflectedaway.

12 ‘Inthisregardmybasichypothesisisthefollowing:Thecommoncharacterofhumanexperience,whichismarked, articulated,andclarifiedbytheactofstorytellinginallitsforms,isits temporal character ’(NPH63).

65 Andyethistory,sinceitisbasedonaninterpretationofarchives,documents,andtraces,always containsanimaginaryelement,orwhatRicoeurnamesa‘fictioneffect’(TN3186/337)or‘quasi fictive’element(TN3190/346).Historyisanarrativetoldasa‘taskofmemory’(TN3189/342)in ordernottoforgettheactionsandsufferingsalreadydone.Weunfoldthisnarrativebyengagingin imaginative mediations on cosmological time (exemplified by the calendar and the sundial) and phenomenologicaltime:‘History,Isaid,inscribesthetimeofnarrativetimewithinthetimeofthe universe’(TN3181/331).Wetellhistorytounderstandhumantime,and,notlessimportant,we mustunderstandtimeinordertounderstandthenatureofhumanity:‘Tothinkofhistoryasoneisto posittheequivalencebetweenthreeideas:onetime,onehumanity,andonehistory’(TN3258/461). Fiction, on the contrary, is the reenactment of what might have been, of ‘the probability of the universal’(TN3191/345).Whenweengageinfictivenarrativesweexplore‘certainpossibilities that were not actualized in the historical past,’ and therefore fiction is ‘able, after the fact, to performitsliberatingfunction’(TN3191/347).Fictionalnarrativesengageinacreativeimitation,a mimesis,thatliberatesthelogicalstructureormeaningofthepossibleeventsinahumanlife;or saidotherwise,‘Ioffertomyselftothepossiblemodesofbeingintheworldwhichthetextopens upanddisclosestome’(MPH177).FictionpossesseswhatRicoeurcallsa‘heuristicforce’tore describerealityasweknowit(IDA248). History and fiction are interwtwined in a circular relationship in the act of narration (TN 3 190/345), which refigures the experience of time insuchawaythatwecometotermswiththe aporeticsoftemporality.Bynarratingtime,livedtime(phenomenologicaltime)isreinscribedinthe timeofnature(cosmictime)(TN399/1812)sothatabridgeissetoverthepolarityofthetwo conceptionsoftime(TN3244/439).Humantimeisneitherlivedtimenorthetimeofnature,buta complexofthetwo.Weareboundtothetimeofnaturethroughourbody,sinceourbodyisfirmly rootedinthephysicalworkingsoftheworld,andstill,livedtimeisnotrestrictedtothephysical aspectoftime.Ourpastisnotonlymeasuredbytheanonymousquantityofdaysgonebyorbythe tracesoftimevisibleonourfaces(TN3138/2456);italsorevealsitselfastheintrinsictimeof consciousnessthatweexperienceinmemory.Wearenotsituatedintimeashelplessspectators;on thecontrary,weareinvolvedwithtimeasagentsintheconstitutionoftime.Humantimesprings formtheambivalenceofactingandsuffering(TN3221/400)inthesensethatwe,ontheonehand, areaffectedbytimethroughtheevolvingofanonymouscosmictime,thesuccessionofgenerations, cultural tradition, and the involuntary events of a lifestory. On the other hand, we ourselves constitute time in that we seek to understand and ordinate the experience of temporality. We

66 developsuchanunderstandingoftimeindifferentways,forexample,bymeasuringtimewiththe clockandthecalendarortellingitthroughhistoryandfiction.Timebecomesintelligiblethrough ourattempttospeakaboutourexperienceoftemporality,orsaidinanothermanner,weunderstand ourrelationtotimeandhowwe,ashumanbeings,aresituatedintimeinspeakingabouttimeby means of narratives and metaphors: ‘Humanity becomes its own subject in talking about itself’ (TN3 212/383). Thus the thirdtime, human time, is time as it is narrated with reference to the identityofthesubjectwhospeaksaboutandintime. Temporality isacriticalforthequestion aboutpersonal identity, or more precisely, we cannot inquire into the identity of the subject without dealing with the temporal dimension of human existence(OSA1134/1378).Weareaffectedbytimeandtrytocometotermswithtimebecause timeprofoundlyaffectsouridentityashumans.Timeisthehorizonwithinwhichwelive,act,and suffers,since(andhereRicoeurjoinsand,atthesametime,criticizesHeidegger’sanalysesoftime) humanexistenceischaracterizedbybeing‘intratemporal’,byitshistoricity(TN31223/2223) 13 . Nowhere does the noncoincidence of the human subject become so critical as in the temporal characterofahumanlife.Apersonchangesovertime,gainsnewcharactertraits,transformsand losesoldones,andyetsheremainsthesameperson.Still,itisproblematicsimplytoassertthatthe personremainsthesamepersonovertime,since,aswehaveseen,personhoodisnotsomething static or certain,but a conflict approached in terms of an intrinsic process of appropriation and affirmation(orrestoration)oftheself. Theconceptofnarrativeidentityisapartofthehermeneuticalapproachtothisconflictinherentin human subjectivity. The hermeneutic answer to the question ‘who am I?’ understands human existenceasanencounterbetweenthesubjectandtheworld.Theworldbecomesahumanworld throughthemediationofsignsinthat‘humanactingisintimatelyarticulatedbysigns,norms,rules, and evaluations that situate it in the region of meaning, or, if you will, within the symbolic dimension’ (TN3 232/419). The subject engages with the world, with its own identity in the workingsoftheworld,bymeansofsymbolicmediations.Themeaningoftheworld,andthereby the meaning of the individual subject in the world, is apprehended by an interpretation of the symbolicunitythatdisclosestheworldasahumanworld,apracticalspaceofreason,whereinthe subjectcontinuouslyseekstocometoanunderstandingofwhataffectsit(alterity)andwhatitdoes itself(selfhood).

13 AccordingtoRicoeur,Heideggerpayslittleattentionto“ordinarytime[letempsvulgaire]andwithintimeness”, whichRicoeursessas‘ time of the trace [le temps de la trace ]thatwefindin,forexample,calendartime(1223/223).

67 Theconceptofnarrativeidentityisintroducedtocopewiththeproblematictemporalcharacterof subjectiveidentityinthattheconceptintegratestheapparentpolarityintheidentityofthesubject, between permanence and diversity over time (OSA 140/1678). How can I affirm my self constancy,ordenyitforthatsake,ifIdonotmakemy‘lifeitselfaclothwovenofstoriestold’ (TN3246/443)?Irelatemyselftotheidentityofmyexistenceintimebyexaminingmylifeasa complex of stories told about my life. Thus, Ricoeur establishes a connection between self constancyandnarrativeidentitythat,asheclaims,confirmsoneofhisoldestconvictions:‘Theself ofselfknowledgeisthefruitofanexaminedlife[…]Andanexaminedlifeis,inlargepart,one purged, one clarified by the cathartic effect of the narratives, be they historical or fictional, conveyedbyourculture.Soselfconstancyreferstoaselfinstructedbytheworksofaculturethat ithasappliedtoitself’(TN3247/4434).Theidentityofthesubjectcannotbereducedtowhat happenstothesubjectovertime,tothewaytimeworksonthesubject(thecosmologicaltime),but mustnecessarilyincludehowthesubjectitselfactsonitsbeingaffectedbytime(livedtime).The dilemmaofpermanenceanddiversity,i.e.,whetherthesubjectremainsidenticaltoitselfthrough thediversityofdifferenttemporalstatesortheidenticalsubjectdisintegratesintoamereflowof different ‘nows’ with nothing but a contingent connection, disappears when we approach the identity of subject as ‘refigured by the reflective application of narrative configurations’ (TN3 246/443.Translationslightlymodified). Asnotedabove,narrativeidentityisapracticalcategory,whichmeansthatitdealswithaporetics oftimeandidentityinrelationtotheconcreteexistenceofthesubject,thatis,withhowthesubject actsandsuffersintheactualcoexistencewithothersubjectsinahumanworld.Ricoeurwouldinno way deny that narrative identity has its limits with regard to the explanation of both time and identity.Infact,heexplicitlypointstothelimitsofnarrativityinrelationtotheunrepresentability orinscrutabilityoftime(TN32703/4828),andfurtheremphasizesthat‘ [n]arrativeidentitythus becomesthenameofaproblematleastasmuchasitisthatofasolution […]andhastolinkup withthenonnarrativecomponentsintheformationofanactingsubject’(TN3249/4468).Hence, Ricoeurinsiststhattheconceptofnarrativeidentityhastobeunderstoodinrelationtotheother aspectsofhistheoryofsubjectivity.Inotherwords,itisawaytodealwiththeproblemofidentity asitisfeltandlivedbyindividualsubjectsinahumanworld,or,toputitotherwiseandmorein linewithourpreviousanalyses,itisatheoreticalinstrumentcoinedtodevelopthebasicconflict betweenself(vitaldesires,i.e.,body)andself(spiritualdesires,i.e.,reason)onthelevelofconcrete subjectivity.ItisapartofhishermeneuticalturninthesensethatwiththisconceptRicoeurseeksto

68 reinstatetheschematicnotionofsubjectivityinaconcrete,historicalcontext.Wecannotunderstand humansubjectivityinisolationfromitsexistenceintime,andtimecannotbereducedtoneither anonymouscosmictimenorlivedphenomenologicaltime;ithastobeacomplexofbothaswe actuallyexperienceit,livinginahumanworldmadeup,foralargepart,byhistoryandfiction.The conceptofnarrativeidentityconceivesthehumansubjectasabeingsituatedandembeddedin a worldofvaluesthataregeneratedbythesubjectitselfandbythatwhichisnotthesubject.The identityofthesubjectisapracticalmatter.Wecannotunderstanditwithouttakingintoaccountthe historicityoftheworldinwhichthesubjectisembedded.Ontheonehand,thishistoricity‘isitself therecordofhumanaction’(MT207/218)asweexperience it through traces such as archives, documents, generations and traditions. We create a past by narrating the times past, which, however,doesnotmeanthatwearefreetocreateanarbitrarypastbasedonourlikesordislikes, since‘ we belong to history before telling stories or writing history ’(NF294).Ontheotherhand, the historicity of our beingintheworld is not restricted to an understanding of the past, but expandedandthickenedbyfictionalnarrativesthatdonotlimitthemselvestoredescribewhathas been. On the contrary, they liberate our imaginative capacities in that they imitate the actual possibilities hidden in the ontological structure of human action and thereby point towards the future,orsaiddifferently,‘whatmimesisimitatesisnottheeffectivityofeventsbuttheirlogical structure,theirmeaning […]Mimesisisakindofmetaphorofreality’(NF292). Interpretedinthisway,weseehowRicoeurusestheconceptofnarrativeidentity asawayto articulate andsystematizetheinsightsdevelopedinhishermeneuticalturn,which,ontheirpart, draw heavily on the structures uncovered by the reflectivephenomenological analyses of the schematicnotionofsubjectivity.Thehermeneuticapproachtosubjectivityelaboratesandthickens the practical space of reason, since it emphasizes the historicity of values and the unyielding presenceoftheothersubjects. Intheremainingsections,Iwilldeveloptheconceptofnarrativeidentityinordertoclarifyhow Ricoeur uses the concept to confer historicity to the schematic notion of subjectivity, or said differently, how he reinstates the subject in the pathetic dimension of situated existence. Furthermore, I shall argue for the necessary connection between the hermeneutic approach to subjectivityandethics,sincetheconflictbetweenselfhoodandalteritybecomesmorecriticalwhen theexistenceofthesubjectisconsidered as concreteexistence andits valuesasembeddedand situatedinsocioculturalcontext.Asmentionedabove,Iinversethestructureoftheanalysesdone inchapteronesothatIstartwithaffectivity,thenturntoactionandendwithethicalexperience.

69 Thethreesectionsarestructuredinthiswaytoemphasizehownarrativeidentityisrootedinthe ‘nonnarrative components’ of human subjectivity. I place the analysis of narrative identity in betweenthetwononnarrativedimensionsofsubjectivity,affectivityandethicalexperience.Ibegin withaffectivityasitisexperiencedinbodilyexperience.Thenarrativenatureofhumanidentityis boundtotheembodiednatureofsubjectivity,which means that the subject already exists inthe world in a certain way before it begins to understand this existence through narrative configurations.Inthefollowingsectionabouthumanaction,Iwilldealexplicitlywiththeconcept ofnarrativeidentityinordertoclarify,ontheonehand,howRicoeurusesthisconcepttoexamine the question of human identity in the concrete world of history and culture, i.e., his attempt to redressthestrippednotionofsubjectivitywiththepropertiesthatheintentionallyabstractedfromin the structural analyses, and, on the other hand, to evidence how human identity necessarily transcends the capacity of narration and leads to thenonnarrativedimensionofethics.Thefinal sectionwill,inwayofconclusion,focusontherelationbetweensubjectivityandethics.Iwilltryto substantiatehisclaimthatthequestionofsubjectivityremainsobscureandinconsistentifitisnot dealtwithinrelationtothenotionsofhumanityandpersonhood. The Affected Subject: Body and Alterity One of the most pertinent ideas in Ricoeur’s works is that the body is the primary existential mediationbetweenselfandworld(OSA150/178).Withoutthebodytherewouldbenointeraction betweenselfandworld,sincethesubjectcouldnotinscribeitselfintheworldnorbeaffectedbythe world (OSA 31920/3701); world and self would remain two separate beings. Hence, the body remainsfundamentalatalllevelsoftheanalysesofhumansubjectivity.Butthebodyismorea problemthanafact.Thebodyisconstitutedas‘themixedstructureof“I–suchaone”;asonebody amongothers,itconstitutesafragmentoftheexperienceoftheworld;asmine,itsharesthestatus ofthe“I”understoodasthelimitingreferencepointoftheworld.Inotherwords,thebodyisat onceafactbelongingtotheworldandtheorganofasubjectthatdoesnotbelongtotheobjectsof whichitspeaks’(OSA545/712.Translationmodified;cf.FN19,193).Ricoeurusestheanalyses of the body done in the phenomenological tradition (Heidegger in particular) and confronts the problemthatone’sownbodyisatonce‘the flesh’sintimacytotheselfanditsopeningtothe world’(OSA326/377) 14 .Inthesubjectiveexperienceofone’sownbody,Ricoeurfindstheorigin of all experience of alterity: we are exposed to that which is not ourselves through our body. 14 RicoeuradoptstheHusserliandistinctionoftheexperiencethebodyas body (Körper ,aphysicalobjectamongother physicalobject)and flesh (Leib ,mybody).

70 Therefore,itisthroughourbodilyexperiencethatwefirstbecomeawareofthepassivityinherent inbeingaperson.Alterityisthatwhichtranscendsoreveneliminatesourcapacitytoact,tosetour markontheeventsoftheworld,andtherebyitrevealsasufferingpassivityintheexistenceofthe subject (OSA 31920/370). The concepts of nonimmediacy and passivity are disclosed by the alterityinvolvedintheembodiednatureofsubjectivity;theyfindtheirfirst(personal)expressionin theambivalentexperienceofone’sownbody. Now,Ricoeurwantstodeveloptheproblemofthealterityinsubjectivity,theconflictbetweenthe selfasreasonandtheselfasbody,atapracticallevel.Infact,heisconvincedthatthequestionof humansubjectivitycannotberesolvedbutbyturningtothepracticaldimensionofselfhood(OSA 1112/1356) 15 . NonimmediacyandAmbivalenceoftheBody Wehaveseenthatitisbymeansofthebodythatthesubjectiscapableofaffirmingitselfinthe worldand,atthesametime,thatthebodyrestrictsthesubjectinthisaffirmation.Butwhereasthe previous analyses limited themselves to the structural analyses of the subject’s intentions and projects,Ricoeurnowtrytodevelopanontologythatplacesthesubjectintheworldofhistoryand cultureand,furthermore,explaintherelationbetweenactionandsubjectivity(OSA74/93);orsaid otherwise,anontologyof‘abeinginproject’(OSA86/107.Translationmodified).Thispassage from phenomenology to ontology must first deal with the enigmatic nature of the body in subjectivity,i.e.,one’sownbody(OSA319/368). Anontologyofselfhoodisrootedintheambivalenceofthebody,because,ontheonehand,my bodyismine,i.e.,apartofmymostintimateexperiencesandtheexteriorizationofmyintimacyin beingthemediumofmyinscriptioninthesurroundingworld;ontheother,mybodyisapartofthat whichisnotmine,i.e., thealterity experienced inbeing subjected tophysical causality and the impersonal events operating in the world (OSA 322/372). Ricoeur formulates this fundamental ambivalenceinthefollowingway:‘Totheextentthatthebodyasmyownbodyconstitutesoneof the components of mineness, the most radical confrontation must place facetoface two perspectives on the body – the body as mine, and the body as one body among others.’ (OSA 132/159). 15 Ashewriteselsewhere,claiminghisaffinitywithAristotle:’Inthiswaythepracticaljudgementgivesarichcontent theideaofthehuman ergon ’(CR88/134).Andthishuman ergon isthepeculiarwayinwhichhumanbeingsinteract withtheworldintransformingtheirmerepresenceintoexistence,intoalife:‘Takenasasingularterm,theword“life” receivestheappreciative,evaluativedimensionofergon whichisusedtoqualifymanassuch.This ergon istolife, takeninitsentirety,asthestandardofexcellenceistoaparticularpractice”(OSA1778/209)

71 Thenoncoincidenceinthecoreofsubjectivityfindsitsprimaryexperienceintheambivalenceof thebody.Ourdecisionsmustbeworkedoutbymeansofthebodytobecomeactionsand,further, the world reveals itself only through our bodily senses. I cannot escape my body neither by abstractingfromitnorbyignoringit.Thatis,mydecisionsmightbedonewithoutpayingattention tomybodilyconstitution,butmyattempttorealizesuchdecisionsmyownbodyrevealsthelimits ofmypossibilitiesbytransformingtheminto actual possibilities.Mypracticalknowledgeofthe worldisshapedbythebondsofmysensesandtheabilitiesofmybody,andmyselfknowledge mustbebalancedwithmypracticalknowledgeoftheworld.Thatistosay,Ibecomeawareofmy being this individual subject with these specific capacities and situated in this particular world through the appropriation of my own body. In bodily experiences, the subject experiences an alterity that is part of itself, and thus the subject cannot dispose of it, but is, by plain fact, constrictedtointegratethisexperienceintheattempttounderstanditself.Forexample,Icannotsee whatmyeyeslooklikewhenIamnervous. Wemaybeable,onatheoreticallevel,toabstractfromourbodilyconstitution,butallpractical experience is bodily experience, since the subject acts and is affected through its bodily constitution.Ientertheworldthroughmybody,sincemyactions,whicharecarriedoutbymeans ofmybody,determinemybeingintheworld.Thus,mybodyassumesaninstrumentalcharacterby meansofwhichIliberatemyselffromthepurepassivityofnotacting.Isetmymarkontheevents intheworld(OSA319/370),whichmeansthatthebodythatIfindmyselfboundto,myflesh,is my bodyinthemostintimateway.Still,thebodyalsoescapesmyinitiativeinthatitsituatesmein agivencontext,disobeysme,confinesmewithincertainlimitsanddeterminesthescopeofmy actions.Inthissense,theworldworksonme,affectsmybeingthisindividualsubjectthroughmy ownbody.Iamboundtoacertainperspectiveandgiventhisparticularphysicalconstitution(e.g., theseears,thishair,thiscolorofskin,andthistoneofvoice)withoutmyownconsent;Iamsubject topain,sickness,ageing,andeventuallydeathbecauseofmybody.Orsaidevenmoresimply,my bodydoesnotalwaysbehavethewayIwantittobehave.Forexample,Ireachoutforacupof coffeeandendupwithapeninmyhand.Thus,Ilive‘withtheothernessofthefleshthatIam’ (OSA326/377) However,theambivalenceofthebodyisnotlimited to the neat distinction between praxis and pathos,actingandsuffering,butincludesthedialecticsofselfhoodandalterityinactionitself,i.e., inthewayIusemybodytorealizetheaffirmationofmyselfhood.ThemomentItransformmy decision in action, that is, inscribe my intimacy into the world, I am no longer in complete

72 commandofmydecision.Icannotcontrolhowmyactionsinscribethemselvesintheeventsofthe world.Mybodyopensuptotheworld,butdoesnot havepowerovertheworld,sinceitis an integratepartoftheworkingsoftheworld;thescopeandeffectofmyactionnecessarilyescapes myinitialintention(OSA2945/3412). In my bodily existence, the nonimmediacy of my being is experienced as a facticity, i.e., a practicalconditionofmyselfhood.ThepersonthatIamisnotsomethingimmediatelygiven.Imust gaincontrolovermybody,payattentiontohowmybodyinscribesmybeingintheworldand, moreover,Ihavetoacceptthatmybodyisnotonlyanobjectofmywill,butalsoapartofthatover whichIhavenocontrol.Myactionsarerealizedthrough my body,butalreadypartofanalterityin theactionitself(becauseofthealterityinmybody).TobecometheselfthatIamImustacceptand consenttothebeingofmybody.Mybodyiswhatopensuptotheworld,myparticularaccessto theworld,and,inthisway,ittransformstheworldfromsomethingtotallyforeigntotheprimary alterity of human finitude ‘insofar as it is sealed by embodiment’ (OSA 327/378). Or put differently:‘one’sownbodyisrevealedtobethemediatorbetweentheintimacyoftheselfandthe externalityoftheworld’(OSA322/372).Theembodiednatureofhumansubjectivityshapesthe experienceoftheworldandtheselfexperienceofthesubjectinsuchawaythattheworldinwhich thesubjectissituatedistransformedfromsomethingtotallyforeign,somethingwithoutrelationto thebeingofthesubject,toanalteritythatispartofthesubjectinitsexistenceintheworld.The worldbecomessomethingthatthesubjectcaresabout:‘Onlyabeingthatisaselfis in theworld; correlatively,theworldinwhichthisbeingis,isnotthesumofbeingscomposingtheuniverseof subsistingthingsorthingsalreadytohand.Thebeingoftheselfpresupposesthetotalityofaworld thatisthehorizonofitsthinking,acting,feeling–inshort,ofits care ’(OSA3101/360). Therefore,toclarifyhowtheworldandthesubjecttogetherconfiguretheworldofthesubject(the practicalspaceofreason),wehavetoconsider,asaninevitablefirststep,thepassivityinherentin thebodilyexperienceoftheworldand,moreimportantly,howthispassivitydetermineshowthe subjectexperienceitsbeingintheworld. PassivityandanOntologyoftheFlesh In the last section of chapter one, we saw how the affective dimension of subjectivity revealed, through the complex nature of human feelings, the noncoincidence in the heart of the subject. Throughourfeelings,wecontinuously,atanintimateandprereflectivelevel,experienceaconflict betweentheoriginalaffirmationandtheexistential negation (perspective, character, vital desire)

73 inherentinhumansubjectivity.Now,Ricoeurwantstodeveloptheimplicationsofthisfundamental conflictatapracticallevel.Thatistosay,whenweareaffected through and by thebody,howdoes thebodydetermineourpracticalexperience? First,thefactthatweareaffected through thebody,i.e.,thebodyisouropennesstotheworld, revealsthatwearethe soleoriginofourexistence. We do not experience our coming into the world. Our existence is marked by an experience of ‘already having been born and of finding oneselfalreadythere’(OSA327/378).Inthisway,wefindourselvesunwillinglypresentinand exposedtotheworldthroughourembodiment.RicoeurelaboratesontheHeideggerianconceptsof thrownness (Geworfenheit) and mood (Befindlichkeit) in that he explores what it means to the subjecttointeractwithaworldinwhichithasnotputitself.Theaffectivedimensionofthisbeing alreadythereisexperiencedbythesubjectasacertainaffectivestate,amood(Befindlichkeit),i.e., afeelingofbeingthisindividualsubjectinthisspecificworld.Heidegger’sanalysesofthrownness andmoodopensupforanontologyoftheflesh,thatHeideggerhimself,inRicoeur’sopinion,never developed:‘anontologyoftheflesh,inwhichthelattergivesitselftobethoughtnotonlyasthe embodimentof“Iam”butasthepracticalmediationofthatbeingintheworldthatweareineach case.Thisconjunctionbetweenfleshandworldisheldtoallowustothinktheproperlypassive modalities of our desires and moods as the sign, the symptom, the indication of the contingent characterofourinsertionintheworld’(OSA3267/3778,note).Further,inanextremesense,the contingencyofourexistenceintheworldisaburdenthatthesubjecthastoendurein‘thetaskof havingtobe’ (idem),sinceithasnotitselfchosentoexist.Therefore, ourbody, whichisitself rootedinpassivity,placesusintheworldinacertainway. Ourbodily existenceprecedesevery distinctionbetweenvoluntaryandinvoluntarybecausethat‘Iwill’isfirmlyrootedin‘Ican’.Ionly havethepossibilitytochoose,toaffirmmyself in the world, because I am given certain bodily capacitiesinthefirstplace(OSA324/375). Now,howdoesRicoeurdevelopthisontologyofthefleshthathefindssoimportantforthenotion ofsubjectivity?HislateanalysesinOSAleavesthereaderratherperplexed,becauseherepeatedly returns to the ontology of the flesh and emphasizes the importance of what he calls authentic spatialityasacrucialelementofthecoiningofsuchanontology.Andstill,heneverarrivesatan explicitdefinitionofwhatheintendsbyanontologyoftheflesh.Heleavesthereaderonlywith sporadicallysuggestivehintstothenotionofauthenticspatiality.Forexample,authenticspatiality isessentiallydifferentfrom‘thegeometricspaceasasystemofindifferentplaces’inthatitis‘the spatial dimension of beingintheworld […] the backdrop of the spatiality of available and

74 manipulablethings’(OSA328/379).Or,hewritesthattheselfisinrelationtotheworldastoa totalityofconcernsinthesensethateverythingconcernsthesubject(OSA314/363).Andfurther, thatweneedtocoordinatethehumaninitiativewiththe‘themovementoftheworldandallthe physicalaspectsofaction,’becauseonlybydoingsocanweexplaintheextensionofthetotalityof ourconcernsfrombeingalivetothepraxisoflivingwell(idem).Still,hedoesnotgatherthese observationsintoasystematicnotion,and,therefore,theimportanceofthereflectionsonauthentic spatialityandanontologyofthefleshremainssomewhatinarticulate. Here,though,thepreviousanalysesoftheschematicnotionofsubjectivityturnouttobehelpful. Theinvestigationsdoneintheearlyworks,FNandFMinparticular,havealreadydelineatedsuch anauthenticspatialityinrelationtothepracticalspaceofreason. Thepracticalspaceofreasonis,asstated(perhapstoo)manytimesnow,theconsciousspaceof experienceproducedbythetranscendentalimaginationinthemediationofreasonandsensibilityin suchawaythatthedifferentmotivesandtheirjoined feelings are weighted against one another accordingtoahierarchyofheterogeneousvaluesgeneratedbytheworld,theselfandtheother.At thispoint,however,Ricoeurwantstodevelopthisschematicnotionofsubjectivitybygroundingit inthehistoricityofconcreteexistencebymeansofahermeneuticphenomenologicalmethod.He wants,sotosay,toredressthestripped,structuralnotionofsubjectivitywiththeconcrete,pathetic dimension of the subject’s actual (co)existence with other subjects. This shift in interest (and therefore,inconsequence,alsoinmethod)mightbethereasonwhyRicoeurdoesnotdevelopthe ontologyofthefleshthatheneverthelessbelievessoimportantforanontologyofselfhood(OSA 3289/37980).Itmightbeduetohisemphasisonamorehermeneutic(i.e.,concrete,historic,and practical)notionofsubjectivitythattheimmediate bodily experience remains inarticulate in the laterworks.Ibelieve,however,thattheideaofanontologyofthefleshisimportantforRicoeur’s generaltheoryofsubjectivityandthatitcouldbecomemorearticulatedandclear,ifoneputsthe somewhat scanty analyses of bodily experience in OSA in relation to previous analyses of the schematicnotionofsubjectivity. Wefindourselvesembeddedinaworldthatwehavenotchosentobeapartof.We,asindividual subjects,aredifferentfromtheworld,andstillweareapartoftheworldinwhichweconductour existence.Ourexistenceintheworldischaracterizedbythecontinuousexperienceofbothselfhood and alterity, and neither world nor subject can be fully understood in isolation from the other: ‘Thereisnoworldwithoutaselfwhofindsitselfinitandactsinit;thereisnoselfwithoutaworld thatispracticableinsomefashion’(OSA311/360).This,however,isnotthesameastosaythatit

75 isnonsensicalorillegitimatetoconsidertheworldinabstractionfromthesubject,asitisdone,for example, in physics and other branches of the empirical sciences, but only that the subjective experience of the world, i.e., the world of the conscious subject, cannot be reduced to the impersonal world uncovered by the physics or biology. As we saw chapter one, Ricoeur is interestedintheinteractionoftheworldandthesubject,andthisinteractiontakesplaceinwhatthe subjectexperiencesasthepracticalspaceofreason.Thesubjectexperiencestheworldpersonallyin thesensethattheworldisaconfigurationofheterogeneousvaluesthatcorrespondtothesubject’s concerns, or expressed differently, the subject cares about the world in which it finds itself embedded. The previous analyses of values and motivations help clarify the notion of authentic spatiality, since they place bodily experience in the larger context of the practical space of reason. The ambivalenceofthebody,markedbyactivityandpassivity,selfhoodandalterity,istheprimordial (i.e., immediate) experience of the interaction of subject and world. We experience the world throughourinteractionwiththeworldinsuchawaythattheworldbecomesthecorrelatetoour actionsandoursufferings.Thus,authenticspatialityistheimmediate,prereflectiveexperienceof worldasapracticalspaceofreason,thatis,asaconfigurationofheterogeneousvaluesthatexpress thetotalityofourconcerns.Itisaspatialityinternaltotheflesh,becausetheprimordialformof sensingplacesthesubjectinaprelinguisticspacethatbecomesapracticableworldthroughthe subject’scapacitiestointeractwiththealteritypresentinthatspace(OSA325/376).Thesubjectis part of that alterity, because its body is merely a body among others, and yet it is capable of appropriatingthealterityofthespaceinwhichitfindsitself,transformitintoafamiliarworldby meansofthecapacitiestoaffirmitselfinherentinitsownbody,itsflesh.Theontologyoftheflesh isthefirst,necessarysteptowardanontologyof selfhood,sinceitgivesanaccountofhowthe beingofthesubjectisrelatedtothebeingoftheworld.Itisthespatialequivalenttothetemporal analyses in TN3 in the sense that the subject’s bodily experiences (perception and voluntary movement)isinscribedintheanonymousworkingsoftheworldinthesamemannerthatlived, phenomenologicaltimeexperienceisinscribedincosmologicaltime(OSA326/3767).Thus,an authenticspatialityisthecentralconceptinanontologythatbringstotheforefrontthecomplexity ofembodiment,thatis,thefactthatthesubjectisbothpartofthephysicalworld(spatiallyand temporally) and, at the same time, somehow different from the workings of that world. In our immediateinteractionwiththeexternalworld,wefeelandexperiencethedialecticofselfhoodand alteritythatisinternaltoourbeinghumansubjects(idem).Althoughourbodilyexperiencemight

76 seemimmediate,itisstillgroundedinamoreprimordialmediationbetweenthetwofundamental aspectsofhumansubjectivity,namelybody(passivity)andreason(activity). A hermeneutical approach to the notion of subjectivity is not possible without the preliminary reflectivephenomenologicalanalysesofthestructuralpropertiesofsubjectivity,sincetheseclarify thetranscendental,prereflectivestructuresofsubjectiveexperiencethatremainprimarytoamore concrete,hermeneuticnotionofsubjectivity.Ricoeurhasalwaysemphasizedthis,but,atthesame time,heinsiststhatthephenomenologicalapproachfindsitslimit,whenitcomestoreinsertingthe structuralnotionofthesubjectintheworld,i.e.,developinganontologyoftheself(SPH144;PW 7980; KH 2456; FN 34/78, 4712/4434; FM 456/63; PH 101/44, 114/61). The structural analysesofthesubjectendsintheontologyofthe flesh, since the experience of my own body pointstothelimitofmyselfawareness,tothepassivityinmybeingthisbody,‘namely,notwhat itmeansthatabodyismybody,thatis,flesh,butthatthefleshisalsoabodyamongbodies.Itis herethatphenomenologyfindsitslimit’(OSA3256/3767).Phenomenologycannotaccountfor thealterityexperiencedinhumansubjectivity,sincethisalterityexceedstheconsciouscapacitiesof thesubject.Thehermeneuticapproachtosubjectivitythereforebeginswherephenomenologyends, namely with the conflict between alterity and selfhood in the heart of the subject in that it emphasizesthemediatednatureofsubjectivitybymeansofinterpretation. Therefore, in my opinion, the structural analyses of the early works are precisely the outline of suchanontologyoftheflesh,becausetheyclarifyourbasicbodilyinteractionwiththeworld.The schematicnotionofsubjectivityprovidesanindispensablefundament,byoutliningthestructural elementsofthepracticalspaceofreason,forthedevelopmentofanontologyofselfhood,sinceit insists on the primordial dialectics of selfhood and alterity inherent in the most basic form of subjectivity,namelythatofbodilyexperience.Itisthefirststeptosolvingtheapparentparadoxthat ‘ifthereisabeingoftheself–inotherwords,ifanontologyofselfhoodispossible–thisisin conjunctionwithagroundstartingfromwhichtheselfcanbesaidtobe acting ’(OSA308/357). Beforeturningtotheproblemofselfhoodandidentityinaction,wemight,forthesakeofclarity, sumupthemainpointsoftheanalysesdoneinthischaptersofar: • Ricoeur changes (around 1960) his method from reflectivephenomenological to hermeneutic phenomenologicalinordertoconfertheschematicnotionofsubjectivitythepatheticdimensionof concretehistoricexistence.Onecansaythatheredressesthestrippedsubjectwiththeproblemsthat he intentionally abstracted from in the early works (temporality, culture, historicity, and the concretepresenceoftheother).

77 •Thehermeneuticalturnthickensandcomplicatesthenotionofthepracticalspaceofreason,since itemphasizestheexistenceofthesubjectintimeandculture.Theconceptsofmotivation,valueand the other become somewhat more complicated in that they are faced with the contingency of concreteexistence,i.e.,thesubjectassituatedinacertainsocial,linguistic,andculturalcontext. •However,althoughthesituatedsubjectisdeterminedbythesocialandculturalcontextinwhichit findsitself,Ricoeuriscautiousaboutnotreducingthenatureofthesubjecttothesemorecontingent factors.Hethereforeemphasizestheembodiednatureofsubjectivityasanecessarypresupposition forthehermeneuticalanalysisofthesituatedsubject.Thispresuppositionisfoundinhisanalysisof theschematicnotionofsubjectivity.Herehedevelopedanontologyofthefleshthatclarifiesthe prereflective structures of subjectivity with regard to which the further analyses of the situated subjectmustbecarriedout. Action: Selfhood and Identity How,then,doesRicoeurdealwiththequestionofselfhoodandidentityinsituatedsubjectivity? Already in FN (1950), Ricoeur was convinced that the phenomenological description of the structuresofsubjectivitymustbeadjoinedwithmetaphysicalorontologicalanalysesinorderto clarify ‘the unity of man with himself and his world’ (FN 467/439). Although the affective dimension of subjectivity is what ‘truly represents man’s humanity’ (FM 136/152), the conflict solicitedbyvitalandspiritualdesirescannotberesolvedbutthroughananalysisofthesocialand cultural objects in which the subject finds itself and affirms itself in the situated nature of its existence.Thus,Ricoeurisconcernedwiththelifeofthesubject,butthetermlife‘isnottakenina strictlybiologicsensebutintheeticoculturalsense […]Theword“life”designatesthepersonasa wholeinoppositiontofragmentedpractices’(OSA177/2089). Thestructuralanalysesemphasizedthatthesubjectexistsasaselfonlytotheextentinwhichit acts.ActionremainsasalientfeatureinRicoeur’slateanalyses.Thistime,however,thequestionof action is not a strictly theoretical one about the intrinsic structures in human action, but is transferredtoapracticallevel(CR138/90):Howdoestheselfrelatetoitsaction?Andfurther,how dowedistinguishapersonalactionfromanimpersonalevent? Inordertoanswerthesequestions,weneedanontologythataccountsforthedifferencebetween actionand event. Ifwe adoptamaterialistontology that reduces personal actions a subclass of impersonalevents,wecannotdistinguishbetweenactionandeventandtherebynotarticulatethe relationbetween agentandaction(OSA74/93).By assigning personal action to an ontology of

78 anonymousevents,weneglectthepersonalaspectthatis,accordingtoRicoeur,thefundamental aspectofhumanaction,namelythequestionof“who”didtheaction(OSA60/78).Therefore,we must‘seekinanothersortofontology,onemoreconsonantwiththesearchfortheself,thegenuine placeoflinkagebetweentheactionanditsagent’ (OSA74/93). Ricoeurisonthelookforan ontologythatdoesnotsacrificethespecificdifferencebetweenthenatureofhumanandnonhuman eventsinordertogainaclearandunifiedexplanationofeverythingthathappensintheworld(OSA 834/104).Wehavetorespectthefactthatthereissomethingsubstantiallydifferentatstakewhena person brings about a change in the world with respect to an impersonal event such as an earthquakeoradogcausinganaccident.Nonetheless,Ricoeurdoesnotignoreanotherpertinent factaboutpersonalaction,namelythat,althoughapersonalactionisdifferentfromananonymous event,theeffectuatedactionisstillapartofthephysicaluniverseandthereforesometimesvery difficulttodistinguishfromamereevent(OSA69/88).So,thisnewontologyhastopayattention toboththepersonalandimpersonalaspectofaction,butmostimportantlyitmustbedifferentiated fromanontologybasedstrictlyonimpersonalevents:‘Thisdifferentontologywouldbethatofa being in the making, possessing de jure the problematic of selfhood, just as the problematic of samenessbelongsdejuretotheontologyofevents’(OSA86/107;cf.OSA96/118). MotivesandCauses What characterizes, intuitively, the difference between personal actions and anonymous events? Onemightsayintuitively,theideaorfeelingthatanactioncouldhavebeendoneotherwiseoreven preventedbytheagent,whereasaneventcouldnot have,i.e.,itisnotamatterofdoingornot doing,itsimplyhappens.Inourattempttofindcauseforanoccurrenceintheworld,oursearch stopswiththeagentwhenitcomestoaction(heorshedidit,andthat’sit!),whereaswefaceall sorts of difficulties trying to narrow down on an ultimate cause for anonymous events (this happenedbecauseofthatwhichagainwascausedbythis,andthat,onitspart,wasareactionto this, and so forth ad infinitum ). Said in another way, personal action is characterized by an intention:‘Describinganactionashavingbeendoneintentionallyisexplainingitbythereasonthe agenthadtodowhatshedid’(OSA75/95). Now,apersonalreasonforanactioncannotbeexplainedbythecausalmodelbuiltonanontology ofanonymousevents,andthekeynotionforanalternativeexplanationistheconceptofmotivation (OSA77/97).Aswesawinthepreviouschapteronlyhumanbeingshavemotivesandnotcauses (p.2630).Ricoeurinsistsonthishumanparticularityandrepeatsthat‘ [o]nehasnotforgottenthe

79 oppositionbetweentheeventthathappensandtheeventthatonebringsaboutortheopposition betweencauseandmotive’(OSA103/125.Translationslightlymodified). Amotiveiswhatconnectstheactionandtheagent.Theactionisascribedtotheagentinthatthe agentmustappropriatetheaction.Theagentcannotdisposeoftheactionmade,butremainsthe possesorofwhatheorshemakes(CR978/1489).Theactioncausesachangeintheworld,which cannotbutfindsitsoriginintheselfthatinitiatedthatchange(OSA109/133).The“how”andthe “why” finds its common root in the complex question “who?” (idem). The opposition between cause andmotivefinally findsitsjustificationin the distinctionbetween subject and object. An actiondifferentiatesitselffromaneventinthewaythatitscausecanneverderivefromanobject, butdoalwaysoriginateinasubjectthatpossessesthecapacitytorealizeorrestrainfromthatgiven action.Thesubjectmaybeanobjectofexternalforces,andyet,italwaysremainsasubjectbecause ofitscapacitytodeliberateonwhattodowhenitisaffectedbytheworldinwhichitissituated: ‘Ascriptionconsistspreciselyinthisreappropriationbytheagentofhisorherowndeliberation: makingupone’smindiscuttingshortthedebatebymakingoneoftheoptionscontemplatedone’s own’(OSA95/117).Thatiswhywearedirectedtotheselfanditsmotivesandnottotheforcesof ananonymouscausality,whenwewanttoknowthe“how”and“why”ofacertainaction. Theprevioussectionshowedthatthedistinctionbetweenselfhoodandalterityinsubjectivityisnot asclearcutasmightseeminthedistinctionbetweenmotiveandcause.Theselfispartoftheworld andassuchitisalwaysdifficulttodiscernexactlytowhichextentonemaysaythatanaction dependsontheself.Nevertheless,Ricoeuremphasizesthatinordertotalkaboutsubjectivity,we mustnotletthenatureofactionbeconfoundedwiththecausalityofanonymousevent,because ‘[t]heactionmustbeabletobesaidtodependontheagentinordertobeblamableorpraiseworthy’ (OSA101/123). Thenatureofpersonalactionisthereforetobesoughtinthenatureoftheselfthatinitiatesthe action.Onceagain,wehavetotakeacloserlookontheselfthatiscapabletocauseaneventina worldgovernedbylawsdifferentfromthoseoftheself.Thus,wemustindividuatethedimension ofpersonalactionwithintheanonymouseventsintheworldbyrestrictingouranalysestowherewe cantalkaboutresponsibility(OSA1067/130).Thisisnotatallaneasyprocess,butwemaybegin by delineating ‘a new and properly practical dimension’ of subjectivity (OSA 101/121). The ontologyofthefleshisapresuppositionforthispracticaldimension,sinceitoutlinesthepragmatic dimension of action. The subject is capable to act through its body. The subject and the world comestogetherinthebody,sincethe“Ican”dependsonthebodythatis,atthesametime, my body

80 and abodyamongtheotherbodiesintheworld(OSA111/135).However,thesubjectismoreand otherthanitscapacitiestoact.Thesubjectisitsactions.Amongthepossibleoptionsthataremade possible by its capacities, the subject decides on a certain option by realizing it through action. Now, these actions may be ‘blamable or praiseworthy’ according to certain norms or standards (these will be dealt with in the concluding section), in short, they are characterized by their imputability. In this way, the agent and the action are related by means of the concept of imputability.Theactionreferstoaselfthathaschosentoactinonewayandnotinanother,and therebytheselfputsitselfatstakeintheactionsthatitperforms.Thus,thesubjectivityofactionis ultimatelyaquestionoftheselfthatinitiatestheaction:‘withimputabilitythenotionofacapable subjectreachesitshighestmeaning,andtheformofselfdesignationitimpliesincludesandina way recapitulates the preceding forms of selfreference’ (CR 106/158). Said differently, the differencebetweenactionandeventisthatanactionispersonalwhereasaneventisimpersonal. Andthisdifferencerevealsthedifferencebetweenmotiveandcause.Amotive initiates anaction whenchosenandrealizedbyasubjectwhereasacause continues alargerchainofreactionswithout anexplicitinitiation,whichthereforecannotbequalifiedasanactionbutonlyasanevent.And since the subject somehow initiates the action, thatis,heorsheisthepossessoroftheaction, attention must necessarily shift from the action to the agent. Whereas we cannot place a responsibilityconcerningevents(sincetheyareanonymous),actionsarealwaysbeingevaluatedin thattheyoriginateinasubjectthatcouldhavedoneotherwise.So,inordertoclarifythepersonal aspectofaction,Ricoeurturnstothepractical dimension of subjectivity. His analyses therefore shiftsfromthelogicalandpragmaticaspectsofactiontotheethicalandmoralaspectsunderthe guidanceoftheconceptofimputability:‘Imputability,weshallsay,istheascriptionofactiontoits agent, under the condition of ethical and moral predicates,whichcharacterizetheactionasgood, just,conformingtoduty,doneoutofduty,and,finally,beingthewisestinthecaseofconflictual situations’(OSA292/338). However,beforedealingexplicitlywiththepracticaldimensionofsubjectivity,Ricoeurdevelops theconceptofnarrativeidentitythatheclaimswillfunctionasabridgebetweenthedescriptiveand normative aspect of subjectivity, namely by relating ‘describing, narrating, prescribing’ (OSA 140/166). The attempt to relate the descriptive and the normative aspect of subjectivity is an importantfeatureofhistheory,becauseitinstantiateshisideaofanintegralnotionofsubjectivity. Thenotionofsubjectivityisneitherpurelydescriptivenorpurelynormative.Itrestsonanontology capableofexplainingabeingthatisrootedinbothafactualandnormativedimension.Ontheone

81 hand, the subject is a part of physical nature, which means that we must pay attention to the embodiednatureofsubjectivity(ontologyoftheflesh).Ontheother,thesubjectisamemberof humanity,thatis,itlivestogetherwithotherhumansubjectswhodemandthatthesubjectconsiders its existence a coexistence. Moreover, it is situated in a certain social and cultural context, inscribedinatradition,andgovernedbyspecificrulesandnormsthatcannotbereducedtothelaws ofphysicalnature.Thesetwoheterogeneousdimensionspertaintodifferentontologies.Onethatis groundedinthecausalityofanonymousevents,andanotherthatconsidersthenormativenatureof subjectivity: ‘Are these two ontologies mutually exclusive? I do not think so; they are, in my opinion,simplydifferentbyreasonoftheirstartingpoints,whichthemselvescannotbecompared’ (OSA86/107).AlthoughRicoeurfocusesonanormativeontology,heiswellawareofthepossible integrationofanormativeontologywithacausalone. Now,however,Ishalltakeacloserlookontheconceptofnarrativeidentityinordertoclarifyhow narratingmaybridgetheapparentgapbetweendescriptionandprescribing. TheNarratingSubject:PersonhoodandIdentity Thedifferencebetweencauseandmotiveturnedtheanalysesofactionawayfromtheactiontothe agentwhoperformstheaction.Theagentisnotjustacauseamongothercausesintheanonymous chainofworldevent.Onthecontrary,theagentisaselfotherthan apartofthe world.Now,a descriptiveapproachtohumanactionmustconcentrateon how theactioninscribesitselfintothe workingsoftheworld,thatis, how doesthesubjectcauseachangeintheworld;or,isitlegitimate tosaythatthesubject,autonomously,enactsaneffectivechangeintheworld?Istheactionnotonly part of a largerscale system of anonymous cause and effect? Said differently, the descriptive analysesofactionconcentrateonthe“why”andthe“what”ofacertainaction.Ontheotherhand, thenormativeapproachturnstotheagentandemphasizesthe“who”oftheaction 16 .Inthissense, thenormativeapproachexceedsthatofatheoryofactionbecauseitsurmisesthatpersonalaction mustincludenormativefeatures:‘Anagentisnot in thefardistantconsequencesasheorsheisina sense in hisorherimmediateact.Theproblemisthentodelimitthesphereofeventsforwhichthe agent can be held responsible’ (OSA 106/130). So, we are left with two distinct approaches to humanactionthatareseeminglyincongruent.However,aswehaveseen,Ricoeurdoesnotconsider

16 Thetermsdescriptiveandnormativearebothdescriptivein the sensethat theyareboth valuefreeaccounts.The differenceisthattheone(thedescriptive)focusesoncausalrelation,whereastheother(thenormative)dealswiththe valuesandnormsofthe“who”thatdidtheaction.

82 thetwoapproachesexclusiveofoneanother.Onthecontrary,heattemptstoconnectthetwo,and inordertodosoheemploystheconceptofnarrativeidentity. The concept of narrative is supposed to bridge the factual and the normative dimension of subjectivitybyintroducingthetemporaldimensionofexistence,namelythefactthatthesubjecthas its own history (OSA 113/137; CR 101/153). So, although the fact that the subject has its own historymightseemintuitiveandtrivial,Ricoeurdevelopshisconceptionofpersonalactiononthe problems concerning personal identity by emphasizing the historicity of human existence (OSA 114n/138n).Howdoesthesubjectremainidenticaltoitselfthroughoutitsexistenceintime? We saw earlier that Ricoeur uses the concept of narrative identity in order to cope with the aporetics of human temporality. On the one hand, the subject is firmly rooted in physical (cosmological)time,whichmeansthatthesubjectisboundtochangetogetherwitheverythingelse in the world. On the other, the subject experiences time somewhat differently than merely the changingofseasons;anhourcansometimesseemtolastayearandothertimesitvanishesina second. This is what Ricoeur calls phenomenological time. Both conceptions of time play an important role in understanding subjectivity and cannot be reduced to one another. Therefore, Ricoeurproposesathirdconceptionoftime,namelytimeasconfiguredbynarratives.Weshallnow look at how the question of personal identity may be approached by means of narrative configurationsoftime. I answer the question in two moves. First, I show how narratives articulate the difficulties concerningpersonalidentitybystressingthedynamicsinvolvedintheconstitutionofidentity:How canthepersonbesaidtoremainthesamepersonthroughthechangesitmakesandsuffersover time?Secondly,IwillclarifyhowRicoeurusesthenotionofnarrativeconfigurationstoemphasize theimportanceoftheconceptofresponsibilitytopersonalidentity. Narratedtimeissupposedtoincludeboththepassiveandactiveaspectofhumantemporalityin thatitpaysdueattentiontohowtimeworksonthesubjectaswellastohowthesubjectcopeswith time.Indifferencetoaplantoradog,ahumansubjectdoesnotremainpassivelyreceptivetothe workingsoftime.Forexample,wegotoahairdresserwhenourhairbecomestoolong,stopeating cholesterolrichfoodwhenwebecomeolderorplanourfuturewithrespecttoourpast.Weadaptto time, reflect, and work on time. Therefore, our being this particular subject is thoroughly determinedbytime,becausetimeposesachallengetoouridentityinthesensethatitis‘afactorof dissemblance,ofdivergence,ofdifference’thatwe,aspersons,havetodealwith(OSA117/142).

83 Ricoeur individuates three components in personal identity: 1) numeric identity, 2) qualitative identity, and 3) uninterrupted continuity, which on their part express the main principle of permanenceintime(OSA1167/1401).Apersonmustfulfillallthreecriteriaoveranunspecified periodoftimeinordertobesaidtobethesamepersonandnottwodifferentones.Numericidentity referstothefactthatapersonmustremainthesamephysicalobjectthroughallkindsofimaginable changesintime.Apersonmightlooseallherphysicalcharacteristicsovertheyearsorcompletely loosehermemoryofalldeedsdoneoreventsoccurredtoherandstillbethesamepersonina numericalsense,becausesheisstillthesamephysicalmatterthathasevolvedthroughtime,asfor example, verified by looking at her DNAcode (OSA 117/142). Nevertheless, we might find it difficult to accept that her personal identityhasremainedthesameifallthecharacteristics that defined her as a certain person at some point has changed into something completely different. Therefore, to understand personal identity we must also pay attention to the qualitative and the uninterruptedcontinualaspectofthepersoninquestion.Weidentifyapersonaccordingtocertain charactertraits.Shewalksinacertainway,hervoicehasthatspecificintonation,hertemperisbad late in the afternoon, and she loves fishing and is faithful to her longstanding principles about monthlycharitytothelessfortunate,thedisciplineofhardworkandearlyrising,andthenecessity ofdeathsentence.Now,timeplaysanevenmorecriticalrolewithrespecttothiskindofidentity (CR656/101).Asweageweremainthesamephysicalmatterbutourdispositionsandcharacter traits may change, and that sometimes drastically. Could we say that a person is still the same personifhisorhersprinciples,ideasandoveralllifeplanarechangedbeyondrecognition? The question is extremely difficult. For example, we allow that a coldblooded and horrible murderercanchange,servehersentenceandbecomeabetterpersonthathasnothingwhatsoeverin commonwiththecrimesdoneinthepast.Sheisquiteliterallyadifferentperson.Thus,wejudgea persononhowheorsheactsnowandnotonpastmischiefsorbenevolenceforthatsake.Onthe otherhand,wearewellawarethatitis,infact,notanotherperson.Itisstillthemurdererthathas changed into something better because she has learned from her terrible deeds, transformed her principles and worked out a significantly different lifeplan for herself. How, faced with these difficulties,isitpossibletospeakaboutthepermanenceofpersonalidentitythroughthesometimes dramatic changes in time? Ricoeur is convinced that ‘ [t]he idea of structure, opposed to that of event,repliestothiscriterion[permanence]ofidentity,thestrongestonethatcanbeapplied’(OSA 117/142).Wemustconcentrateonthestructuralpermanenceofthepersonandnotontheevents thatseemtodissolvepersonhoodintofragmentedpieces of a self. In other words, we must find

84 whatremainsinvariableinthedifferentrelationsinwhichthepersonfindsitselfthroughthecourse oftime:‘Theentireproblematicofpersonalidentitywillrevolvearoundthissearchforarelational invariant,givingitthestrongsignificationofpermanenceintime[...]aformofpermanenceintime whichcanbeconnectedtothequestion“who?”inasmuchasitisirreducibletoanyquestionof “what?”Aformofpermanenceintimethatisareplytothequestion“WhoamI?”(OSA118/142 3.Translationslightlymodified). Ricoeurnowattemptstofindthis‘relationalinvariant’ofpersonhoodbyanalyzingidentitywith referencetotwooppositemodelsofpermanenceintime: character and keeping one’s word (idem). These two models of permanence form a dialectics that, articulated by means of a narrative structure, might capture and explain the subtle difficulties surrounding the notion of personal identity. Ricoeur puts it like this: ‘My hypothesis is that the polarity of these two models of permanencewithrespecttopersonsresultsfromthefactthatpermanenceofcharacterexpressesthe almost complete mutual overlapping of the problematic of idem and ipse , while faithfulness to oneselfinkeepingone’swordmarkstheextremegapbetweenthepermanenceoftheselfandthat ofthesameandsoattestsfullytotheirreducibilityofthetwoproblematicsonetotheother[…]the polarity I am going to examine suggests an intervention of narrative identity in the conceptual constitutionofpersonalidentityinthemannerofaspecificmediatorbetweenthepoleofcharacter, where idem and ipse tendtocoincide,andthepoleofselfmaintenance,whereselfhoodfreesitself fromsameness’(OSA1189/143). Inordertounderstandthisprogram,wefirsthavetobrieflyclarifythetermsthatheisintroducing. The notion of character was introduced in the previous chapter as the person’s immutable perspective and opening to world, the socalled ‘existential difference or negation’, which we cannot change (our birth place, physical constitution, and, to a certain degree, also our habits). Ricoeurremainsfaithfultohisearlyanalyses,butnowheconcentratesonthetemporaldimension of character, which brings into question theimmutable status of character. Some aspects of our characterloosetheirfeatureofimmutabilitywhenconsideredinrelationtotimeinthesensethat ourhabitsanddispositionsmaychangethroughthespanofourlife.So,‘ [c]haracter,Iwouldsay today,designatesthesetoflastingdispositionsbywhichapersonisrecognized’(OSA121/146).In thisway,thenotionofcharacterfunctionsasacriterionbywhichweareabletoidentityapersonin relationtothegeneralthingsortraitsthatwecandescribe,withoutaskingabouttheselfbehindthe differentpredicates.Wecanthereforesaythat‘ [c]haracteristrulythe“what”ofthe“who”’(OSA 122/147).

85 On the contrary, the model of keeping one’s word ‘expresses a self-constancy which cannot be inscribed, as character was, within the dimension of something in general but solely within the dimensionof“who?”’(OSA123/148).Thiskindofpermanenceintimecapturestheselfthatwe cannotidentifybymeansofmerecharactertraits,thatis,theselfthatismorethanthesumofits descriptivelyrecognizabletraits.Tokeepone’swordistodefythechangesthattimebringsabout. Ricoeurexemplifiesthisdynamicswiththenatureofpromise.SaythatIhavepromisedafriendto visithiminBerlinwithinafewmonths.However,workpilesup,moneyrunslowandmydesireto visithimseemstosubsidewithrespecttootherandmoreinterestingagendas.Nonetheless,Ihave givenhimmywordthatIwillbecoming,andnottodosowouldthereforebeinconsistentwith whatfriendshipstandsfor,namelytrustandsincerity.Itisobviousthatthiskindofpermanencein timedealswithanotheraspectofidentitythatcannotbeaccountedforinneutral,descriptiveterms butinvolvesajustificationable‘torespondtothetrustthattheotherplacesinmyfaithfulness.This ethicaljustification,consideredassuch,developsitsowntemporalimplications,namelyamodality ofpermanenceintimecapableofstandingasthepolaroppositetothepermanenceofcharacter’ (OSA124/149). Thus,Ricoeurindividuatestwodistinctpolesofpersonalidentity:Adescriptiveformwhichhe namesidentityofthesame(idem)andanormativeformwhichisnamedidentityoftheself(ipse). Thefirstexpressesthepassiveformofpersonhoodthatremainsthesameinthatitfulfillsthethree criteria for identity through time (numeric, qualitative,anduninterruptedcontinuity)withoutany significantactivityonbehalfofthepersonitself.Theseconddemandsthatthepersonisconstantly awareofhowtoremainfaithfultohisorherpromisesandengagementsinlightofcertainvalues, normsandsocialcodices.Ontheoneside(identityofthesame,i.e.,character),wehavethatwhich is seemingly the most stable aspect of personhood, namely the physical characteristics and longstandingdispositionsshapedbyupbringing,education,andconvictions,whichareallgathered inthenotionofcharacter.Ontheother(identityoftheself,i.e.,keepingone’sword),wehavethe more dynamic and impalpable normative aspect, which has to do with how the person acts according to the norms and procedures that govern the social interface between him and other persons. Onceclarifiedthekeynotions(character,same,idemvs.keepingone’sword,self,ipse),wecan begintounderstandhownarrativeidentitymaybeahelpinapproachingthedifficultiesconcerning personalidentity.

86 Althoughcharacteristhemoststableformofidentity,i.e.,thatbywhichwearereidentifiedand therebyrecognized,manyofourcharactertraitsarestillaresultofongoingconsciouschoicesmade duringourlifetime;choicesbecomehabitsandlongtermdispositions,whichturnintosomething thatwedonolongerchoose;orsaidmoreeloquently,habitsare‘thereturnfromfreedomtonature’ (OSA121/147).Theformationofhabitsandseeminglyunconsciousorautomaticdispositionsto act is our most obvious and docile tool to cope with alterity, since they internalize the alterity outside of us (the world and the other) and make it a part of our person (OSA 122/147). Our dispositions to act are shaped by how we are brought up and by our social, geographical, and cultural context. If Ihave grown up in a violent environment, my first reaction to fear and provocationismorelikelytobeanactofviolencethanifIhadalwaysbeentaughttoavoidtheuse ofviolenceatanycost.Thus,amajorpartofourpersonhoodisdeterminedbyhowourhabitsand dispositionsaredeveloped.Apersonis,however,morethanitshabitsanddispositions.Itisaself thatcanrelateitselftothenatureofitscharacter,sinceitcanchoosetofollowitsinclinationsand dispositions or choose not to. The identity of the person depends on the dialectic of self and character; or as Ricoeur writes: ‘The dialectic of innovation and sedimentation, underlying the acquisitionofahabit,andtheequallyrichdialecticofothernessandinternalization,underlyingthe processofidentification,aretheretoremindusthatcharacterhasahistorywhichithascontracted, onemightsay,inthetwofoldsenseoftheword“contraction”:abbreviationandaffection’,andhe goesontoexplainwhatnarrativeidentitymightcontributetotheunderstandingofthatdialectic, namely ‘to balance, on one side, the immutable traits which this owes to the anchoring of the historyofalifeinacharacterand,ontheother,thosetraitswhichtendtoseparatetheidentityofthe selffromthesamenessofcharacter’(OSA1223/1478). Thekeynotionhereis‘thehistoryofalife’.Narrativeshelpevidencethestructureanddynamicsof our identity in that they articulate the reasons for our character and dispositions. The narrative defies,sotosay,theimmutabilityofthecharacter,becauseitmakestheotherwiseinalterablepart of our personhood (the same or idem) less fixed and a dynamic part of our personal history. Throughnarratives,wemaybecomeawareofhowwecametohavesuchastrongcharacterorsuch violentdispositions,andnotjustacceptthat,intheend,thatisjusthowweare.Thedialecticof selfhoodandsamenesshasahistory.Wearewhowe arebecauseofthehistoryofactions and sufferings. To approach our identity as a narrative structure makes us capable of distinguishing betweenwhatwehave doneourselvesandwhathasnotoriginatedinourselvesbutproducedby others factors such as upbringing, friends, birthplace, education etc.. We are always the same

87 person,butourpersonhoodischaracterizedbyatensionbetweenwhatwedoandwhatweare.I mightbeakindandlovingperson,butinordertoremainsoImustcontinuetoactaccordingtothat whichmakesmeakindofperson.Or,Imightbeacruelandviolentperson,butthatdoesnotmean thatIamdestinedtoremainsuchaperson.Now,narrativesarticulatethisdynamicsbecause‘[w]hat sedimentationhascontracted,narrationcanredeploy’(OSA122/148). Atthispoint,itmightbeclearthatRicoeurcontinuestoelaboratethestructuralschemesthathe developedintheearlyworks.Thesubjectismarkedbyafundamentalnoncoincidence,sometimes evenaconflict,inthecoreofitsbeing,namelybetweenvitalandspiritualdesireswheretheformer tendstowardpleasureaccordingtotheimmediatewellbeingofthesubjectitselfwhereasthelatter seeksamoretotalformofhappinessthatmustincludethepresenceofandcoexistencewiththe othersubjects.Thisproblematicisnowtransferredtothepracticallevel.Howcanthesubjectbe said to remain an integrate person when continually faced with the threat of disintegration and fragmentationthattemporal(co)existencewithotherpersonsbringsaboutinthecourseofalife? Onceagain,wearefacedwiththeproblemofconflictandnoncoincidence.Thistime,however, theexperiencing,acting,andfeelingsubjectisconsiderednotasastructuralbeingbutasaconcrete personsituated and actinginacertainhistorical,temporal,andsocioculturalcontext.Andasthe foregoingsectionhaspointedout,thequestionofpersonhoodiscloselylinkedtothatofaction, sincehumanactionispersonalactioninthatthesubjectalwaysinitiatestheactionaccordingtoits ownmotivessuchasdesires,inclinationsandrational cognitions, in short, according to its own hierarchyofvalues(i.e.theconfigurationofthepracticalspaceofreason;thiswillbedealtwithin the last section). Responsibility is what renders human action distinct from the realm of mere, anonymousevents.Andyet,responsibilityisaproblem,notafact.Theissueatstakehereisto narrowdownonwhereresponsibilitybegins.Wehaveseenthatnarrativesmayhelpindividuatethe “who”inthe“what”,thatis,towhatextendcanwebesaidtoberesponsibleforwhatweare.For example,howare wetoblameforourviolence,ifthatisallthatwehaveeverexperienced?Of course,narrativeidentitycannotsolvethedifficultiesinvolvedinpersonalresponsibility,butitcan bringforthnuancestotheproblem.Personalidentityisnotjustaquestionofwhatweareorhow weremainthesame,butalsohowwerelateourselvestothepersonthatweare.Thequestionisthen howarenarrativessupposedtoclarifyourunderstandingofresponsibilityinrelationtopersonal identity? Understanding personal identity becomes a very difficult task, when we want to account for identityinothertermsthannumericidentity.Qualitativeidentity,orthe‘relationalinvariant’,seems

88 to be impossible to grasp, since the person keeps changing throughout his or hers entire life. Ricoeur, however, chooses to confront this problem with the concept of responsibility. And, according to his reflections on motive and cause, responsibility is originally a question of imputability:‘ItisfortheotherwhoisinmychargethatIamresponsible.Thisexpansionmakes whatisvulnerableorfragile,asanentityassigned to the agent’s care, the ultimate object of his responsibility’(CR1089/162).Myidentityasapersonisultimatelyaquestionofmyactionsin regardtotheother.Thisiswherethefragilityofmypersonhoodbecomesclear.Ifmyidentityonly dependedonme,thenIcouldchangemyopinions,motives,andprinciplesatmyheart’sdesire withoutendingupindifficulties.Ididnothavetoaccountformyactionstoanyone.Now,thisis notthecase.Ialwaysactasapersonintheeyes of the other. I would be unrecognizable, as a person,ifIonedaysupportedcapitalpunishmentandthenextdaymarchedfortheabolitionofthis legalaction,orsaidonMondaythatIlovecatsandhatedogs,andthenonWednesdayclaimedthat Ihatecatsbutlovedogs.Inordertomaintainpersonalintegrity,Ihavetoremainidenticalinat leastsomematters,thatis,IamresponsibleforwhatIdoandsay.Now,theproblemsarisewhen wehavetodeterminehowmuchandinwhatmatterscanapersonchangeandstillremainthesame ‘relationalinvariant’,thesameperson?Thisiswherenarrativetheorycomesin.Thereseemstobea gapbetweendescribingapersonandprescribingwhatapersonmustdotoremainaperson,i.e., betweentheascriptionofanactiontoanagent(theoryofaction)andtheimputationtotheagentof anobligationtoactinacertainwayinordertoremain the same person (ethical theory) (OSA 152/180).Thekeyconceptthatissupposedtobridge this gap is ‘narrative configuration’ (OSA 142/169).Toconsiderthestructureofactionintermsofnarrativesisawaytoextend‘thefieldof practice’sothattheagent’svariousactionsbecomeconfiguredaccordingtoahierarchyofpractical units that calls for a revision in the concept of action (OSA 1523/181). The practical field is extended and qualified, because narratives view actions from a topdown perspective that differentiates human events from neutral occurrences and furthermore consider actions over the courseoftime(OSA141/169).OrwithRicoeur’swords,‘Tellingastoryissayingwhodidwhat, whyandhow,byspreadingoutintimetheconnectionbetween these various viewpoints’ (OSA 146/174.Translationmodified).Contrarytoacausalexplanationofaction,narrativeconfiguration is concerned about the qualitative aspects of personhood that become articulated in the story. Whereasacausalmodeltendstodissociatetheagentfromthenormativeaspectofitsaction,the narrativemodelemphasizesthisaspectbecausenostoryis‘ethicallyneutral’andtherefore‘proves tobethe first laboratory of moral judgment ’(OSA140/167).Thus,narrativeconfigurationprovides

89 ‘supports and anticipations ’(OSA152/180)foranethicaltheory.Inusingthestructureofliterary fictionasamodelforpersonalidentity,Ricoeurasserts that a story always involves agents and sufferersandopensupafieldofevaluationswherewejudgethevalueofanaction(andtherebyits agent)inrelationtohowitaffectsanotherpersonwhothusbecomesasuffereroftheactiondone (OSA144/172).Inthisway,thenarrativeconfigurationarticulatesandemphasizeswhatisactually the case with all human action, namely that ‘every action has its agents and its patients’ (OSA 157/186).Ofcourse,thisisnottobetakenliterallyas,forexample,whenIpourmyselfacupof coffee,Ithendeterminethesufferingofanotherhumanbeing.However,ouractions(eventhemost insignificantone)are,somehow,alwaysinscribedinalargercomplexofhumanrelations.Thisis whatisemphasizedinthenarrativeconfiguration,andwhichtendstobeconfusedandhiddeninour everydayexperience(OSA148/176),andtherefore‘[i]tispreciselybecauseoftheelusivecharacter ofreallifethatweneedthehelpoffictiontoorganizeliferetrospectively,afterthefact,preparedto takeasprovisionalandopentorevisionanyfigureofemplotmentborrowedfromfictionorfrom history’(OSA162/1912). Narratives are an attractive model for explaining personal identity because it does not exclude causalexplanations(bottomupperspective),butseekstointegratetheminawiderexplanation.Itis truethatnarrativeconfigurationapproachesthequestionofpersonalidentityfromanormative,top downperspective,butitoperateswithadialecticsthatemphasizesthecomplexityofhumannature, namelythatapersonisbothpartofnatureandhumanity.Wecannotunderstandpersonalidentityin isolationfromoneoftheseaspects.Thepersonisdeterminedbothbyitsphysiologicalconstitution andbyitsbeingpartofhumaninterrelations:‘Thepractical field then appears tobe subjected a twofoldprincipleofdeterminationbywhichitresemblesthehermeneuticalcomprehensionofatext through the exchange between the whole and the part. Nothing is more propitious for narrative configurationthanthisplayofdoubledetermination’(OSA159/187). Thisplayofdoubledeterminationisemphasizedinthenarrativeconfigurationofourpracticalfield of experiencebecause, although narratives are structuredaroundwhatRicoeurcalls‘ imaginative variations ’ of our personal identity (OSA 148/176), and that these always involve ‘an unstable mixture of fabulation and actual experience’ (OSA 162/191), our personal identity remains groundedin‘theexistentialinvariantofcorporalityandworldliness’(OSA151/179).Imaginative variationsareinstablebecausetheydealwiththe moreimpalpable featuresofpersonalidentity: ideas,wishes,dreams,norms,socialheritage,upbringingetc.andarethereforeliabletofabulation, selfdeceptionanddenial.Thisis,nevertheless,balancedbytheinvariablenatureofcorporalityand

90 worldlinessinthesensethatthestorieswe(andothers)makeaboutourselvesfindtheirverification orappropriatenessinrelationtoourbodyandtotheotherpersons aroundus.Ourexperience of ourselvesandothersisconfiguredbynarratives,butthenarrativesthemselvesarealwaysgrounded inthenonnarrativedimensionsofaffectivityandthepresence of the other. Theprevious section dealtwithaffectivityandtheambivalenceofthebodyasbeing,atthesametime,mineandjust anotherobjectinnature.Thenarrativeconfigurationsofourselfexperiencearealwaysdetermined bythisambivalence,sincewemayascribetoourselvesphysicalqualitiesthatwe,inreality,donot possess,butthisselfdeceptionwill,normally,shatter confronted with the mirror of alterity (my actualbody,theworld,andtheother).EventhoughRicoeurfocusesonthenormativeaspectof personal identity, his model is, as we have seen, compatible with a more descriptive, causal approach. However,itisthenormativeaspectthatRicoeurfocuseson.Narrativeconfigurationissupposedto bridgethedescriptiveandprescriptivelevelofpersonalidentity,whichmeansthatitisanecessary but not sufficient explanation of personal identity. On the one side, it is conditioned by the descriptive explanation of the body, and on the other, it is determined by the concept of responsibility.Now,theconceptofresponsibilityisemphasizedbythenarrativeconfiguration,but it also transcends the explanatory power of narratives, since they may clarify the dynamics of personhoodbutleavetheproblemofresponsibilityopen:‘Thestoryofalifeincludesinteractions withothers[…]Inthetestofconfrontingothers,whetheranindividualoracollectivity,narrative identityrevealsitfragility’(CR1034/1556). Responsibilityisoneofthekeyconceptsthatboththeschematicnotionandtheredressednotionof subjectivity have revolved around. Ricoeur has considered it a fundamental concept in the constitutionofhumansubjectivitysincehisearlystructuralanalysesinFN(FN567/55).Therefore, intheseconcludingpages,wemustfindouthowthisconceptcantietogethertheresultsthatthe precedinganalyseshavebroughtforth.Inordertodoso,wehavetotakeafinallookonthenotion ofapracticalspaceofreason.

Ethical Experience: The Practical Space of Reason Inthislastsection,IshallargueforwhatIhavenamedthepracticalspaceofreason.Byandlarge,I will try to show that subjective experience is configured as a practical space of reason, and, furthermore,thatthisisacentralideainRicoeur’stheoryofsubjectivity.Tosaythatsubjective experience is configured as a practical space of reason means that human subjectivity must be

91 approachedandunderstoodfromtheperspectiveofsuchanexperientialspaceofvaluesandnorms. However,thisisnotthesameastosaythatthehumansubjectcannotbeapproachedfromother perspectivessuchasphysicsandbiology(i.e.,theempiricalsciences),whichwehavealreadyseen regarding the ambivalence of the body; only that such approaches has to be integrated with an accountofthesubjectiveexperienceoftheworld,theotherandtheselfinordertogiveacogent accountofhumansubjectivity. The section is divided in three parts. First, I will clarify what I mean by the configuration of experienceaccordingtoahierarchyofheterogeneousvaluesbyanalyzingfurthertheconceptsof valueanddesireinrelationtohumanpractices.Herewefindthatnarrativeconfigurations,asaway of explaining human action, are a preliminary exploration of the practical space of reason. Secondly, I shall explain the relation between the self and the other in the configuration of experience.Thisrelationshapesouractionintheworldandiscriticalforthewayweexperience ourselvesasaselfandrecognizetheothersubjectasaselfaswell.Finally,inwayofconclusion,I arguefortheexistenceofaprimaryethicalexperience.Ourexperience oftheworldisprimarily ethicalinthesensethatweperceiveobjectsandespeciallyothersubjectsinworldaccordingto some sort of hierarchy of values. Our perception is basically saturated with normativity. As we develop into adult subjects, become aware of ourselves as an individual person with a specific history and embedded in a certain society with particular norms and values, this normativity enrichesandgrowsmorefinegrainedandcomplex.Iclaimthatresponsibilityisthefundamental notion for way we understand ourselves as persons. Identity and selfesteem both find their correlateinourresponsibilitytowardtheotherperson.Thus,Iarriveattheconceptofresponsibility asthekeyconceptthatbindstogetherthevariousaspectsofRicoeur’snotionofsubjectivityinthe developmentofanontologythataccountforthesubjectasapersonaswellasaperishablepartof physicalnature.Iclaimthatthenormativeexperienceoftheworldisprimarilyethical,becauseour existenceintheworldisacoexistencewithother subjects, and that this coexistence affects our experienceina radicalway.Thelegitimacyof mypossibleactionsinfrontoftheothersubjects determinesthewayIexperiencetheworldasaspacefortheattestationofmyselfhood. Ishallnotdealwiththespecificnatureofwhat Ricoeurcallshis‘littleethics’(OSA290/337), sincetheprimaryinterestofthepresentinvestigationisabouttherelationbetweensubjectivityand ethics,andnotaboutwhichkindofethicaltheoryisthemostappropriateone.Ricoeur’stheoryof subjectivity is an attempt to clarify the structures and dynamics that are at play in human subjectivityand,further,anargumentforasofteningofHume’swatershedbetweenjudgmentsof

92 factandjudgmentsvalue,thatis,between‘is’and‘ought’(OSA171/2012).Infact,Ricoeurisnot particularlyinterestedinanormativeethicaltheory,butconcernedwithmetaethicalquestionssuch as the ontological and epistemological nature of human values and the relation between human nature and ethical dispositions (i.e. imputability, obligation, and responsibility). He delineates a humanontologythatarticulatestheintimaterelationbetweenfactsandvaluesinordertoanswer howwecanlegitimateaclaimforethicsinaseemlyindifferentphysicalworld.ButIamgetting aheadofmyself.Letustaketheargumentstepbystepandstartbyfirstlookingattheconfiguration ofexperience. TheConfigurationofExperience In the previous chapter, I defined the practical space of reason as experience of the world configuredasahierarchyofheterogeneousvaluesgeneratedbytheself,theworldandtheother. Thesevaluesareoriginallyproducedintheaffectivedimensionofthesubjectthatexperiencesitself asaselfwithcertaindesires.Themanifoldofsubjectivedesireswasstructurallydividedintwo distinctkinds,namelyvitalandspiritualdesires.Thesegenerateanoncoincidence,oftenaconflict, intheheartoftheselfbetweentheselfaspartofphysicalnaturethatseeksitsownwellbeingand theselfaspartofatotality,thatis,humanity.Thisbasicconflictistheontologicaloriginofthe fragilityandunrestofthehumanself.Now,ourexperienceoftheworldisshapedbyourinteraction withtheobjectsintheworld.Theconceptofintentionalitymadeitclearthatwearenotpassive spectators,butactiveparticipantsintheunfoldingeventsoftheworld.Objectsandeventsdonot justappearbeforeus,butareloadedwithmeaningthatisrelevanttousasexistingintheworld. Objectsgainvaluethroughtheinversemovementofintentionality(fromtheobjectstothesubject) revealed by the feelings that we experience. These feelings manifest themselves as values (sometimesvagueanddiffuseandsometimesclearandstrong)accordingtotheroughdistinctionof vitalandspiritualdesires.Thisdistinctionisimportanttokeepinmindwhenweinthefollowing look at how values are generated in the subject that is embedded and situated in a concrete, historicalworld. He develops his hermeneutics on the notion of conflict produced by the fundamental tension betweenvitalandspiritualdesires.Theoriginatingaffirmationisnowchangedtoattestationbutthe meaningremainsthesame:‘attestationisfundamentallyattestation of self[…]atrustinthepower tosay,inthepowertodo[…]attestationcanbedefinedasthe assurance of being oneself acting and suffering (OSA22/345).However,thisassuranceofbeingoneselfiscomplicatedbythefact

93 thatthesubjectdoesnotactandsufferintimeless isolation, but is always situated in a certain contextdeterminedbytheworldandtheother.Theattestationoftheselfisthereforeconditionedby theexistenceoftheworldandthebeingofotherselves.Ourpowertosayanddoisconditionedby whatRicoeurinhisearlywritingscalled‘theexistentialdifference’,thatis,thatweliveinaworld inhabitedbyselveswhoseexistenceisdifferentfromours.Thismeansthatwecannotjustsayordo anythinginordertoattestourselves;ifwewanttoaffirmourselvesasaself,wemustdosoby recognizing the existence of other selves that are part of the world that we all inhabit: ‘the explorationofhumancapacitiesshouldjointoeachmodalityofthe“Ican”anoftentacitcorrelation betweenselfassertionandsomereferencetoothers.Selfassertiondoesnotsignifysolipsism’(CR 252/363). Whatdoesthisrejectionofsolipsismmeanforourroughdistinctionofvitalandspiritualdesires? Thesubject’sselfassertionbecomesproblematic.Ontheonehand,itwantstoassertitselfasaself atanycost.Ithasspecificdesires,wishes,ideas,andplansforthefuturethatitfeelsthatitmust realizeinordertobetheselfthatitwantstobe.Ontheother,itcannotdisregard(ifitwantstoexist inthesameworldasothersubjects)thedesires,wishesandplansthattheothersubjectshaveand wanttorealize.Therefore,iftheactionsofthesubjectshallworktowardtheattestationoftheself, thevaluesthatorientitsdesiresmustinvolveboththeseaspectsofselfassertion.Thus,onceagain, wehavetoexplorethebasicideaofahierarchyofvaluesbutnowinrelationtotheembeddedand situatednatureofthesubject. Wesawinthestructuralanalysesthatvaluesareprimarilyrootedinthespontaneityofthebody andoriginatesascertain needs :‘Throughneed,values emerge withoutmyhavingpositedthemin myactgeneratingrole:breadisgood,wineisgood’(FN94/90).However,thefactthatthesubject isembeddedinasocioculturalcontextandsituatedamongothersubjectsdemandsthatthisbasic ideaofvaluesisdevelopedintomorecomplexnotionsofgoodandbad.Athingoranactisnot necessarily good because it satisfies my immediate bodily need. It must also satisfy my more generalideaofwellbeing.Idonotliveonlytosurvive;neitheraremy needslimitedtobodily needsnormydesiresrestrictedtobodilysatisfaction.Myvaluesmayoriginateinthebiological functionofneeds(asortofhomeostaticbalance),butinfullydevelopedadultstheyarealsodefined byamorereflectiveinstanceofwellbeingthatRicoeurnames(inspiredbythemoralphilosopher AlasdairMacIntyre)‘thegoodlife’:‘Lifemustbegatheredtogetherifitistobeplacedwithinthe intentionofgenuinelife.Ifmylifecannotbegraspedasasingulartotality,Icouldneverhopeitto besuccessful,complete’(OSA160/190).Thus,weseehowthestructuraldistinctionbetweenvital

94 (immediate)andspiritual(totality)desires,asthecoreofhumanaffectivity,remainsafundament forthehermeneuticanalyses;orasRicoeurputsit:‘ifthereisabeingoftheself–inotherwords,if anontologyofselfhoodispossible–thisisinconjunctionwitha ground fromwhichtheselfcanbe said to be acting’ (OSA 308/357; translation slightly modified). That ground is precisely the affective dimension of human experience that was analyzed in the last section of the previous chapter. Whatisimportant,atthispointofthetheory,istoclarifyhowthenotionof‘thegoodlife’affects anddevelopstheideaofastructuralhierarchyofheterogeneousvalues.Todoso,Ricoeuremploys theanalyseshemadeconcerningnarrativeidentity. The concept of value grows more complex and refinedwhenthesubjectisconceivedasaself embeddedinasocioculturalcontextandsituatedamongothersubjects.Thiscomplexityisdueto thefactthattheconceptofvalueisalwaysacompromise,andthereforeonlyqualifiesasaquasi concept:‘Inthissense,Iholdthequasiconceptofvaluetobeacompromiseterm,atthepointof intersectionoftheclaimtouniversalityandtheadmissionofthehistoricityofcertainderivative dutiestowhichcorrespondstherightofotherstomakeclaimsonus’(OSA289/336.Translation slightlymodified).Valueisaquasiconceptbecauseitisavariableandheterogeneousentitythat doesnotallowforacleardefinition.Valuescannotbedefinedapriori,butarealwaysshapedbya certaincontextandaspecificsituation.Nonetheless,somevaluesstillseemtopossesssomekindof universal aspiration that separates them from mere whims and preferences and procures them a morefirmstatusamongourmotivesfor a givenaction. This is where narratives come into the picture.Thestructureofnarrativesmayhelpclarifythecomplexnotionofvaluesbyindividuating thedifferentaspectsofsituation,culture,anduniversalityinvolvedincertainvalues. Thesubject gainsitssingularitythroughthetemporalunityofitslife inthesensethattheself cannotbeseparatedfromtheactionsandsufferingsthatconstituteitsidentitythroughthechanges inandoftime(OSA1478/175).Thisisexactlywhatisemphasizedinthenarrativeconfiguration of experience. Narratives ascribe actions to an agent andexploretheimplicationsandeffectsof thoseactions,especiallywithrespecttointerpersonalrelationships:‘storiesareaboutagentsand sufferers’(OSA144/172).Wesawhowpersonalidentitycanbeunderstoodintermsofnarratives, becauseouridentityasapersondepends(partially)onstoriesthatexplainthe why ,the what ,and the how ofourbeingthisindividualselfwithcertaincharactertraits,dispositions,idea(l)s,plans, and behavior. By providing answers to these questions, narratives organize our confusion concerning personal identity. Now, narrative configurations not only clarify questions regarding

95 personal identity, but they also assist us in our explanation of human action and behavior. Narratives structures extend the practical field of human action by configuring the otherwise incomprehensible multitude of actions into ‘a hierarchy of units ofpraxisthat, each on its own level,containaspecificprincipleoforganization,integratingavarietyoflogicalconnections’(OSA 153/181;translationmodified).Anactionisunderstoodaccordingtotheseunitsofpractices,since values, motives, and decisions find their explanation in light of the logic governing a certain practice.Forexample,Imovemyarmandfinger because Ihavetoswitchonthelight because I needtoseeinanotherwisedarkroom because Ihavetofindtherefrigerator because I mustfindthe sandwich because Iamhungry.Eachofthese because signifiesapracticalunitthatexplainswhyI doacertainaction.Theyrunfromthemostbasicaction,suchamovingmyfinger,toamoreglobal level that involves actions concerning such serious issues as life projects or general ideas of happiness,goodness,andjustice.Anyapproachtothedynamicsofthishierarchyofpracticesmust beginwith‘thesimplefactthatthepracticalfieldisnotconstitutedfromthegroundup,starting fromthesimplestandmovingtothemoreelaborateconstructions;ratheritisformedinaccordance withthetwofoldofascendingcomplexificationstartingfrombasicactionsandfrompractices,and ofdescendingspecificationstartingfromthevagueandmobilehorizonofidealsandprojectsin lightofwhichahumanlifeapprehendsitselfinitsoneness’(OSA158/187). Thus,thelogicofanactioncanbeexplainedondifferentlevelsinaccordancewiththeunityof practicewetakeintoconsideration,andthedifferentlevelspossesstheirownkindoflogic.Imove myfingertograb,Igrabtopulloutachair,Ipulloutachairtosit,IsitbecauseIamtiredetc. Nonetheless, the logics involved at different levels are somehow interrelated. I may perform innumerablebasicactionswithoutpayingattentiontomyhorizonofidealsandprojects,butoften evensimpleactionsinvolvethepresenceofotherpersons.Thus,myactionbecomesaninteraction, andwereturntothefactthat‘everyactionhasitsagentsandsufferers’(OSA157/186).WhenI performanaction,thatactionisalwayssaturatedwithnormativitybecauseithasavaluebothto myselfandotherpersons.Inthisway,Ricoeurarguesthatourunderstandingofhumanactionis alwaysorientedaccordingtoahierarchyofheterogeneousvaluesconstitutedbyrulesthatpointin thedirectionofmoralrules(OSA155/183).However,itisimportanttoemphasizethattheserules arefirstofallrulesofmeaning,asforexampletherulesofchess:‘Therule,allbyitself,givesthe gesture its meaning: moving a pawn; the meaning stems from the rule as soon as the rule is constitutive,anditissobecauseitconstitutesmeaning,“countingas”.Thenotionofconstitutive

96 rulecanbeextendedfromtheexampleofgamestootherpractices,forthesimplereasonthatthat gamesareexcellentpracticalmodels’(OSA154/183). Therulesthatconstitutethemeaningofactionaregovernedbytheconfigurationofexperienceasa practicalspaceofreason,whereweexperiencetheexternalalterityasanorganizedwhole,aworld thatmeanssomethingtousasindividualsubjects.Actionsandeventspresentthemselvesinterms ofvaluesaccordingtothepracticethattheyareinscribedin.Whenthesubjectwantstoassertitself asaselfintheworld,thepracticesbywhichitrealizesthisassertionhavetopayattentiontorules that govern the practice. Values are defined by the rules that constitute the practice. To put it simple,somethingisgoodifitattainsthegoalofthepracticeandbadifithindersorpreventsthe fulfillmentofthepractice.Forexample,ifIsuccessfullygrabachairthatactionisgoodinlightof thepracticeofgettingachair;oropeningtherefrigeratortogetfood;orworkingtogetmoney. Thus,ourexperienceoftheworldisorganizedbyahierarchyofvaluespertainingobjects,things, persons,andactions.Whenweperceiveobjectstheypresentthemselvesasmeaningsaccordingto different practices and their value is determined by the fulfillment or failure of the practice. Subjectiveexperienceisprimarilyconfiguredaccordingtothesepractices.Humansubjectsdonot experienceafragmentedsuccessionofindifferentobjects,butthingsandpersonsinscribedinthe, for the most part, coherent unity that we experience as our existence in the world. This human existencecanbeapproachedasanarrativeunitythatyieldsourexperienceitscharacteroftotality,a life.Ricoeurputsitlikethis:‘Theterm“life”thatfiguresthreetimesintheexpressions“lifeplan,” “narrativeunity,”and“goodlife”denotesboththebiologicalrootednessoflifeandtheunityofthe humanbeingasawhole,asthathumanbeingcastsuponitselfthegazeofappraisal[…]Asforthe term“narrativeunity,”theaspectthatweareemphasizinghereislessthefunctionofassembling together,performedbythenarrativeatthesummitofthescaleofpraxis,thantheconnectionthe narrative makes between estimations applied to actions and the evaluations of the characters themselves’(OSA178/209). Thishasanimportantimpactontherudimentarynotionofdesirethatwasdevelopedinthelast chapter. We saw that human action is ultimately rooted in two basic kinds of desire, vital and spiritualdesire.Thisschematicnotionofdesirewasthebasisofhumanaffectivitythatwasrevealed by our feelings. These generated a noncoincidenceintheheartofthesubjectthatwasfeltasa conflictbetweenadesiretoselfpreservation(myownwellbeing)atevery costandadesirefor happinessasakindoftotalitythatprocuredglobalmeaningtothemanifoldofdifferentactions donebythesubject.Inoticedthattheconflictcouldnotbesolvedatareflectivelevel,buthadtobe

97 understoodthroughthevariouscrystallizationsofthesebasicdesiresintheconcreteexistenceofthe subject,i.e.,embeddedandsituatedinlanguage,society,culture,history,economics,andsoon. Thus,wehavetounderstandthequasiconceptofvaluesonthebasisofthesefundamentaldesires, butweneedtoapproachthemintermoftherulesthatgovernthepracticesofasubjectembedded inacertainsocioculturalcontext.Ourhierarchyofvaluesisthereforedeterminedbyhowweassert ourselvesthroughpracticesinaparticularsocietygovernedbycertainrulesandnormsofbehavior. Valuesarepartiallycontingentbecauseofthisdependencyoncontext,but,atthesametime,atleast somevaluesseemtoaspiretoakindofuniversality.Theseuniversalvaluesareforthemostpart thoseinvolvedininterpersonalrelation.Mostactionsinvolveandinfluencethepresenceofother persons;orasRicoeurputsit:‘Practicesarebasedonactionsinwhichanagenttakesintoaccount, asamatterofprinciple,theactionsofothers’(OSA155/184).Thepresenceofothersubjectshas criticalimpactonourhierarchyofvalues(andthustheconfigurationofexperience),becausevalues regardingthepresenceoftheotherclaimagreaterdegreeofuniversalitythanothervalues. Tounderstandwhythisisso,wehavetoanalyzewhatthepresenceoftheothersubjectsmeansto theself,andinthisconnectionweneedtotakeacloserlookonthenotion‘thegoodlife’. TheSelfandOtherSelves:‘TheGoodLife’ The practical space of reason is thus configured according to certain values derived from constitutiverulesofpractices.Iunderstand(i.e.theyhavemeaningandthereforeavalueforme) actionsandeventsintheframeworkofsuchpractices:‘theselfisessentiallyanopeningontothe world,anditsrelationtotheworldis[…]arelationoftotalconcern: everything concernsme.And thisconcernindeedextendsfrombeingalivetomilitantthinking,passingthewayofpraxisand livingwell’(OSA314/363).Now,althougheverythingconcernsme,somethingsconcernmemore thanothers.Myconcernsoriginateinthebasicdesires,sincemyactionsintheworldaregenerated bymygeneraldesiresforselfpreservationandhappiness.Theworldbecomesthehorizonforthe realizationofselfhood:‘Thebeingoftheselfpresupposesthetotalityofaworldthatisthehorizon ofitsthinking,acting,feeling–inshort,ofitscare[…]Thereisnoworldwithoutaselfwhofinds itselfinitandactsinit;thereisnoselfwithoutaworldthatispracticableinsomefashion’(OSA 3101/360).WhenIexperiencetheworld,Ifinditprimarilyconfiguredaspossibilitiestosatisfy theseconcerns.Inthemultitudeofmyconcerns,thebasicvalueoflivingisalwayscounterbalanced bythemorecomplexvalueofliving well .Icareaboutliving,butjustasmuchaboutlivingwell. Now, the hierarchy of values that configures my experience of the world as apractical space of

98 reasonisaffectedbymyconcerns,inparticularmyconcernforlivingwell.Therefore,wehaveto returntothenotionof‘thegoodlife’andseewhatthisnotionmeanstoourconceptionofpractices. The notion of ‘the good life’ is a qualification of the existence of the subject conceived as a singulartotality(OSA160/190);thatis,thesubjectconsideredasauniqueselfthatseekstoassert itself through and, sometimes, in spite of time. All our actions, practices, and sufferings come togetherinthequalificationofourexistenceasatotality.Thebasicdesireofhappiness(thetotality ofpleasure)imposesuponustheneedtoqualifyourexistenceaccordingtoanideaofthegoodlife. Formanyreasons,thisisnotasimpleneedtofulfill.Howcanwegraspourentireexistenceina singlenotionsuchas‘thegoodlife’?Andwhatisactuallymeantby‘good’?Aswehaveseen,the valuesbywhichweliveourlifearepartiallycontingentandcontextualwhichmeansthatsucha generalnotionas‘thegoodlife’becomesextremelyfragile(OSA179/210).Nonetheless,Ricoeuris convincedabout‘theideaofahigherfinalitywhichwouldneverceasetobeinternaltohuman action’(idem).Humanactionisalwaysinterpretedaccordingtoahermeneuticaldialecticbetween theparticularandtotality,asitwaspointedoutbythenarrativeapproachtopersonalidentity(OSA 158/187);withanotionborrowedfromthephilosopherCharlesTaylor,Ricoeurdefinesthehuman selfasa‘selfinterpretinganimal’(OSA179/211) 17 .Ontheonehand,ourdifferentpracticeshave theirownlocalvalueaccordingtothelogicdeterminingtheirspecific fulfillment.Ontheother, theirvalueisinfluencedbytheglobalideaofthegoodlife,ourexistencequalifiedasatotality. Somehow, all our actions and practices are governed,consciouslyorunconsciously,by ahigher finality according to this global idea. The obscure and intuitive nature of such an idea needs interpretationinordertobecomearticulate.Therefore,althoughthespecificideaofthegoodlife maychangeinthecourseofourlivesduetothemutableandcontextualnatureofourfeelingsand ideasand,thoughmorestable,ourcharacteranddispositions,thegeneralideasomehowremains. Andassuchitinfluencestheconfigurationofourexperienceoftheworld,becauseitaffectsthe valuesbywhichweliveourlife.Weascribecertainvaluestotheobjectsthatweperceiveasthings thatmattertous;ourconcernsaredeterminedbywhatwecareabout. Theseconcernsareexperiencedasvaluesofmoreorlessimportance.Somearemorecontextual and vague than others; some arise and fade in the moment and depend heavily on haphazard circumstanceswhereas othersseemtohavea moreuniversal claim on our concerns. As I have

17 Ricoeurdescribesthisdialecticsinthefollowingmanner:’betweenouraimofa’goodlife’andourparticularchoices asortofhermeneuticalcircleistracedbyvirtueofthebacktoforthmotionbetweenthdeideaofthe’goodlife’andthe mostimportantdecisionsofourexistence(career,loves,leisure,etc.).Thiscanbelinkedtoatextinwhichthewhole andthepartaretobeunderstoodeachintermsoftheother’(OSA179/210).

99 alreadypointedout,thelatterfrequentlyinvolvestheexistencesourownselfandtheexistenceof otherselves.Tounderstandthehierarchyofheterogeneousvaluesthatconfigureourexperience,we mustconsidermorecloselytherelationbetweentheselfandotherselves. Aswesawinthelastchapter,thesubjectisaselfthatcontinuouslyseekstoaffirmorassertitself intheworld.ItsbeingisfundamentallycharacterizedbywhatSpinozacalled conatus :‘theeffortto preserveinbeing,whichformstheunityofmanasofeveryindividual’(OSA316/366).Thiseffort topreserveinbeing,toassertoneselfintheworld,isneverthelessconditionedbyalterity,andin particularotherselves.Butwhyisthepresenceofotherselvesaconditionfortheassertionofour ownself?Canwenotjustpreserveourownbeingwithoutregardingthepresenceofotherselves? Ricoeuranswersthesequestionsbyemphasizingthepresenceofalterityintheconstitutionofthe self.Theidentityoftheselfisvulnerableandfragilebecauseitsneedscannotbesatisfiedbyits ownpowerandeffort.Otherthantheoriginalefforttopreserveitsownbeing,thebeingoftheself ischaracterizedbya‘need,hencealack,thatdrivestheselftowardtheother’(OSA185/216).This needorlackoriginatesinthespiritualdesireforhappinessthatcounterbalancesthevitaldesirefor selfpreservationintheheartofthesubjectandexpressesitselfinourideaof‘thegoodlife’.My identityasaselfisqualifiedthisidea,andthereforeselfhoodcannotbesustainedinsolitude,but requiresthepresenceofotherselves.IamwhoIaminthecontextofotherselves,andmyideaof ‘thegoodlife’isdeterminedbytheotherselveswithwhomIaminvolvedinmyexistence.Ricoeur employstwointerrelatedconceptsinordertoemphasizethisstrictrelationbetweenthebeingofthe selfandthebeingoftheother,namely self-esteem and solicitude (OSA180/212). Selfesteemis‘theprimordialreflexivemomentoftheaimofthegoodlife’(OSA188/220),since ourlifeconsideredasatotalityisvaluedinaccordancetoourownconduct.Ourideaof‘thegood life’ finds its reflective correlate in the concept of selfesteem, because ‘it is in appraising our actionsthatweappraiseourselvesasbeingtheirauthor’(OSA177/208).Myselfesteemdepends ontheactionsthatIperform.ThevaluesthatIascribetotheunfoldingofmylife(actionsaswellas sufferings)arepartofamoreglobalevaluationofmyexistence.Now,theconceptofselfesteemis inextricably linked with the concept of solicitude: ‘To selfesteem, understood as a reflective momentofthewishforthe“goodlife,”solicitudeaddsessentiallythedimensionoflack ,thefact thatwe need friends;asareactiontotheeffectofsolicitudeonselfesteem,theselfperceivesitself as another among others’ (OSA 192/225). The other considered as a self like me and yet autonomouswithrespecttomeisconstitutivefortheideaof‘thegoodlife’.Myconcernforthe otherdoesnotoriginateonlyinadesiretodominatetheother,butinalackinmyownexistence

100 thatgeneratesaneedforadialogicalcoexistencewiththeother(OSA180/212).Weneedtheother notasameanstosatisfyourowndesiresbutasautonomousselvesthatconstitutemyglobalideaof ‘thegoodlife’.ThisneedforothersaffectsdrasticallythevaluesbywhichIactintheworldinthe sensethatthevaluesthatinvolveotherselvesarecriticalformyownexistence.Whentheother selvesaddressme‘inthesecondperson,IfeelIamimplicatedinthefirstperson’(OSA193/225). Therefore,myselfesteem,whichisadominantpartoftheglobalideaof‘thegoodlife’,depends onthepresenceofotherselvesthatfulfillandsatisfythebasicneedofothers.Thisneedisfeltas solicitudefortheexistenceoftheother.Selfhoodisnotconstitutedsolelyofmineness:‘Tosayself isnottosaymyself’(OSA180/212).Theotherselfisfundamentalformyidentityintheworld, sincetheworldiscommonworldwhosemeaningisderivedfromthecoexistenceofdifferentselves (OSA332/384).Myidentityasauniqueselfdependsontheother’srecognitionofmybeingso. Theothersrecognizemyactionsasactionsofaselfwithacertainhistory,ideas,andplansforthe future;therefore,theunityandcoherenceofmyvariousactionsinrespecttotheideaofmyselfasa self is deeply influenced by the reception of these actions by other selves. I have a need to be recognizedandviceversa:‘Becominginthiswayfundamentallyequivalentaretheesteemofthe other as a oneself andtheesteemof oneself as an other ’(OSA194/226). Hence,thepresenceofotherselvesiscriticalformyhierarchyofvaluesbecausethishierarchy must reflect this recognition of the other as a oneself and oneself as an other. My actions and practices in the world is rooted in this primordial condition of selfhood, namely that the self is constitutedbyalterityinallitseffortstoattestandaffirmitsownexistence.Theglobalideaof‘the goodlife’(happiness)involvesthisalterityandrequirescarefulattentiononpartoftheselftobe realized. Therefore, the values that involve our relation to other selves have a somewhat more universallyclaimonusthanothervaluesinourexistence.Thesolicitudeforthewellbeingofthe otherdefiesthemutableandcontextualnatureofmyothervalues.Icannotdisregardtheotherin myactionsandpractices,becausemyidentityasapersondependsonthepresenceofhimorher. Ourexperienceoftheworldisoriginallyconfiguredasethicalexperience,sinceourefforttoassert ourselvesasselveshingesonthisfundamentalrelationtotheotherselves. Inwayofconclusion,Ishalltrytoarguefortheprimordialnatureofsuchanethicalexperienceby lookingontheconfigurationofexperienceasapracticalspaceofreasonrootedinanontologyof care.

101 SubjectivityinanOntologyofCare Inthisconcludingsection,Ishalltrytogatherthesomewhatlooseendsthatthepreviousanalyses havebroughtforthwithoutdrawinganygeneralconclusion.Twonotionswillguidethisattemptto roundupthedifferentanalyses,namelythepracticalspaceofreasonandanontologyofcare 18 . The practical space of reason is the world experienced as a hierarchy of heterogeneous values generated by the self, the world, and the other. This space is configured as a unity of various practicesthateachhavetheirownlogic,butwhichareneverthelessstillinterrelatedandorganized accordingtothevaluesthatpertaintoourexistence as selves with an integrate identity through time. The narrative configuration of personal identity functions as a primary clarification of the practicalspaceofreasonbecauseitexplainsthe how ,the why andthe who oftheexperienceofthe world.Itstructurestheotherwiseconfuseandheterogeneouscharacterofexperiencebygathering togetherthevariousactionsandsufferingsinthetemporalunityofanarratingself.Furthermore,it emphasizesthehermeneuticcharacterofhumanexistence.Thevaluesthatconfigureourexperience oftheworldareinscribedinacertainsocioculturalcontextthatneedsinterpretationinorderto becomearticulateandsometimesevenconscious.Itisaspaceof reason becauseitisalwaysby means of the reflective capacity of reason that we articulate and cope with the alterity in and through whichweseek toassertourselves.Nonetheless, the narrative approach still embeds the subjectfirmlyinthepatheticdimensionofhumanexistence. The subject is pervaded by alterity whichisfeltas‘thereduction,eventhedestruction,ofthecapacityforacting,ofbeingabletoact, experienced as a violation of selfintegrity’ (OSA 190/223). The selfintegrity of the subject is continuously challengedintheembeddedandembodiedexistenceintime.Reasonworksonthe groundofthisfragileintegrityandmustconstantlyseektoappropriateandasserttheirreplaceable unityoftheselfbymeansofongoinginterpretationsofalterity.Ourexperienceisconfiguredby thisinterpretationinthesensethatweconceiveofourexistenceapracticalproblemofhowtocope with the alterity that challenges our identity. This results in practices that aim to enhance our wellbeing(i.e.selfassertionexpressedinasearchforidentity)accordingtoahierarchyofvalues.A massive part of these values involves the presence and wellbeing of other selves in our own personallifeplansandourgeneralideaof‘thegoodlife’.

18 Ricoeur’sterminologyisslightlyunstablewithregardtothenotionofcare.Heusesthetermssolicitude(sollicitude), care (souci), and the Heideggerian notion Sorge (the German word for care) interchangeably. I do not see any substantialdifferenceinhisuseofthedifferentterms,soIstickwiththetermcare,unlessoneoftheothertermsfeature inadirectquote.

102 Now,inwayofconclusion,Ishallarguethattheseinterpersonalvalueshaveaprivilegedstatusin respecttoothervaluesandarethereforeextremelycriticalfortheorganizationofourhierarchyof valuesand,thus,fortheconfigurationofsubjectiveexperience.Theseinterpersonalvaluesareall groundedinthephenomenonof responsibilitywhich Ricoeurbelievesisnotimposedexternally ontothesubject,butanintrinsicpartofthestructureofsubjectivity.Inthesamemove,Iwilltryto show how the relation between selfhood and otherness, particularly visible in interpersonal relations,constitutestheontologicalsituationofthehumansubject. Theidentityofthesubjectis,aswehaveseen,acomplexproblemthatcannotbereducedtoa questionofnumericidentity.Otherthanpassivelyremainingthesame(sameness/idemorcharacter) through time, the subject must actively remain the same person (selfhood/ipse or keeping one’s word).Thus,identityisalsoanormativequestionofintegrityandselfesteem(OSA167/195).Our identityasuniqueandirreplaceableselves,i.e.,persons,dependsonhowourconduct(doingand saying)conformstothevaluesandnormssharedtogether with other selves that are themselves unique and irreplaceable. The ‘nonsubstitutibility’ornonfungiblenatureofthehumanselfis a fundamentalpartofourpersonalidentity(OSA193/225).Iamthisuniquepersonandnotjusta congregation of different qualities, actions, feelings, and dispositions. My existence, or more specifically my personal identity in this existence, matters, and much of my effort goes into assertingthispersonalidentitythroughandinspiteoftime. This normative feature of human subjectivity is fundamental for understanding the effort that Ricoeurmakestostresstheparticularontologyofhumansubjectivity.Thesubjectisrootedinboth physicalnatureandinaspiritualnaturethathenameshumanity.Thelawsandrulesthatgovernits existence are characterized by a polysemy that prevents a straightforward understanding of the meaning of human action and suffering, and ‘which authorizes no more than the idea of an analogicalunityofaction’(OSA3123/362).Ouractions(andsufferings)donotonlyfollowthe rulesofphysicalnatureorunconsciousdesires(archeology),butfindapartoftheirconstitutive meaning and motivation in the desire to be inscribed in a human society, that is, humanity (teleology)(OSA346/399).Thebeingofthehumansubjectischaracterizedbythisintersectionof physicalandspirituallaws,values,rules,andnormswhichcreatesthetensionorfragilityinthe coreofthesubjectandfindsitsexpressioninthevulnerabilitytoconflictsthathauntstheself assertionofthesubject.Themeaningfulworldexperiencedbythesubjectisnotexhaustedbya physicalistic explanation, but requires a more openstructured approach that does not decide to hastyonthenatureofhumansubjectivitybutrelyonaninterplaybetweenselfandotherness:‘The

103 polysemyofselfhood,thefirsttohavebeenremarked,isrevealingwithrespecttothepolysemyof theOther,whichstandsoppositetheSame,inthesenseofoneself’(OSA318/368).Thehumanself isinaparticularontologicalpositionbecause,ontheoneside,itisfirmlyrootedinphysicalnature, andontheother,itseekstoassertitselfthrough,andofteninspiteof,thatnature.Alterityand selfhoodareinterrelatedinacontinuoustensionthatresultsinan‘unusualontologicalsituation[…] thissituationistheobjectofan attestation which is itself broken ,inthesensethatthealterityjoined toselfhoodisattestedtoonlyinawiderangeofdissimilarexperiences,followingadiversityof alterity’(idem.Translationslightlymodified).Wehaveseenthatthisalterityplaysaconstitutive role on every level of subjectivity, from the body over the world to the other subject. The ontologicalstatusofthehumansubjectisconstitutedinthisinterplaybetweenselfhoodandalterity inthesensethatthesubjectbecomesaselfthroughaninteractionwiththealterityinwhichitis rootedandsituated.Thisinteractionisshapedasaconfigurationofthesubjectiveexperienceofthe world,theother,andtheselfthroughlanguage,society,history,institutionsetc.Alteritybecomes meaning,objects,things,andotherpersonsthroughthatconfiguration.Thesubjectmustfinditself, assertitself,throughtheconfigurationofthatwhichisother.This,however,isnotthesameasto saythatthesubjectiveworldiswhatthesubjectmakesitinto.Onemustrememberthatselfhoodis notsimplymineness.Theexperienceoftheautonomousnatureandvalueofotherness(thebody, the world and the other) excludes the possibility of solipsism and emphasizes the pathetic dimension of subjective experience: we act and suffer, experience and feel, think and sense. To understandmore clearlythis‘unusual’ontologythatRicoeuraimsat, wehavetolook,onelast time,atthepeculiarexperienceofalterityrepresentedbytheotherself. The most compelling experience of alterity is thatoftheotherself.Thisisnottosaythatthe experienceofbodyandworldisnotcompellinginitsmultifariousformsofmanifestation,onlythat theotherselfplaysamoredynamicandprecariousroleinthesubject’sselfassertion.Theother respondstoouractioninafarmorecomplexwaysthantheothermanifestationsofalterity.The otherselfisanactivepartofouridentityaspersons.Thepresenceoftheotherisnotsomething externallyimposedontheexistenceoftheself,butanintrinsicpartoftheconstitutionofselfhood. Thesubjectexperiencesthealterityoftheotherselfasaneedoralackinitsnormativeideaof‘the goodlife’:‘Tofindoneselfcalleduponinthesecondpersonattheverycoreoftheoptativeof livingwell[…]istorecognizeoneselfasbeingenjoinedto live well with and for the others in just institutions and to esteem oneself as the bearer of this wish ’ (OSA 352/406). The attestation of selfhoodisintrinsicallyinterlacedwiththeexperienceofinjunctionintheconstitutionofpersonal

104 identity. When we assert ourselves as selves we find our identity as persons dependent on the response of the other. We need the response of the other in order to maintain the integrity of identity.Thisneedisexperiencedinselfassertionasthepassivephenomenonof (OSA 351/4045).Wecannotescapethepresenceoftheotherinourselfesteemandourwishfor‘the goodlife’.Theotherispartoftheexperienceofourselves,sincethelegitimacyofourdoingsand sayingisalwaysweightedagainstthepresenceoftheotherintheattestationofourownself.Inthe experienceofconscience,weexperience‘beingenjoinedasastructureofselfhood’(OSA354/409. Translation slightly modified). We simply care for the other’s opinion, because that opinion is constitutivefortheintegrityofourpersonalidentity.Facedwiththeother,weareheldresponsible foroursayingsanddoingsinourexistenceovertime(keepingone’sword).Theotherselfgrounds ouractionsincommonhumanworldthatisnotconstitutedbymyowninitiative.Mycareforthe wellbeingoftheotherselfisexperiencedinthe need oflegitimacythatcharacterizesmymotives anddispositionstointeractwiththeworldandtheother.Conscienceiswherethisneedmanifest itself. My identity as a person cannot be sustained in a constant disregard of the other subject. Althoughthevoiceoftheotherisnotactuallypresent, the otherness experienced in conscience makes this voice fundamental for the integrity of my identity, for my selfesteem. Ricoeur can therefore say that care gives ontological weight to the conception of human practices (OSA 311/361). The human self cannot be explain by an ontology that disregards this fundamental relationbetweencare,conscience,andattestation,sincetheselfis‘aconceptthatonlyanontology of care enable us to constitute’ (OSA 188/220). We care for ourselves, i.e., the attestation of ourselvesasanindividualselfthroughtime(personalidentity).Inthisattestation,weareenjoined bythepresenceoftheothertotakecareoftheotherintheappropriationofourownselfhood.This beingenjoinedisexperiencedasaneedforlegitimacyofouractions,sinceweareresponsiblefor thoseactionsinfrontoftheotherself.Theexistenceoftheselfisnotconductedinisolationbutas anintegrate person amongotherpersons.Ourselfesteem(thereflectiveinstanceof‘thegoodlife’) isconstitutedbythebasiccarefortheotherandsolicitsaspontaneousdesiretoobtaintheapproval oftheother,arecognitionofmyintegrateidentityasaperson.Itisonthebasisofsuchanontology of care that it is important for Ricoeur to emphasize that the question of responsibility is not somethingexternaltothestructureofhumansubjectivity;onthecontrary,itresidesdeeplyinthe constitution of subjectivity: ‘This is why it is so important for us to give solicitude a more fundamentalstatusthanobediencetoduty.Itsstatusisthatof benevolent spontaneity ,intimately

105 relatedtoselfesteemwithintheaimofthe“good”life.Onthebasisofthisbenevolentspontaneity, receivingisonanequalfootingwithsummonstoresponsibility’(OSA190/222). Personhoodandresponsibilityisthereforeintrinsicallyintertwined.Theidentityofthesubjectasa person is constituted and maintained by the responsibility for the other because it is also responsibilityforitselfasaperson:‘Becausesomeoneiscountingonme,Iam accountable for my actionsbeforeanother.Theterm“responsibility”unitesbothmeanings:“countingon”and“being accountablefor.” Itunitesthem,addingtothemtheideaofa response tothequestion“Whereare you?”askedbyanotherwhoneedsme.Theresponseisthefollowing:“HereIam!”aresponsethat isastatementofselfconstancy’(OSA165/195).Thisintrinsicrelationbetweenpersonhoodand responsibilityhasasubstantialimpactontheontologicalstatusofhumansubjectivity.Thebeingof thehumansubjectdoesnotallowforastrictdistinction between fact and value. Human nature cannotbeenvisagedandexplainedwithtakingintoaccountthenormativedimensionofitsbeing. Normativityisnotsomethingthatisaddedontothefactualnatureofthesubjectinasecondmove, buttheverycoreofitsbeing.Theselfisnotstaticbutalwaysonthewaytoappropriateitselfasan identical,irreplaceable,andintegrateself,i.e.,aperson.Selfhood,ashavebeenemphasizedfrom thebeginning,ismarkedbyanoncoincidencethatoftenisexperiencedasaconflictbetweenthe selfasapartofphysicalnature(vitaldesires)andasapartofhumanity(spiritualdesires).This conflictisultimatelyaconflictbetweenselfhoodandalteritythatisexpressedintheattestationof theidentityoftheselfthroughtheworld,thebodyandtheotherself.Thebeingoftheselfismade upbyalterityanditsidentityasapersonandcannotbeunderstoodinisolationfromthisotherness. Theselfisrootedinthealterityofphysicalnature(thebodyandtheworld)andinthealterityofthe otherselves(humanity).Thevaluesthatmakeuptheexistenceoftheselfaredeterminedbythese differentexperiencesofothernessotherthanbyitsdesireforselfassertion. Inchapterone,thestructuralanalysesofthesubjectuncovered atensionintheselfbetweenan originatingaffirmationandanexistentialdifferencethatsolicitsconflictintheheartofthesubject between vital and spiritual desires. These analysesledtoanoutlineforanontologyrootedina continuousencounterbetweenselfhoodandalterity.Thehumansubjectisfragileandvulnerableto conflictduetothiscomplexnatureofitsbeing.Thesubjectisnotatrestbutinconstantsearchof restoringtheidentityofitselfasaself.Thisrestorationofitselfisexperiencedasaconflictbetween theselfhoodandalterity,sincepersonalidentityisconstitutednotonlybyitsownselfbutalsoby thealteritythatcontinuouslychallenges(andthreatens)thisidentityinthecourseofitsexistence. Thefeelingsthatqualifyitsexistenceandmotivateitsinteractionwithalterity(thebody,theworld,

106 and the other) are structurally differentiated in vital and spiritual desires. On the one hand, it relentlesslyseekstoaffirmorassertits(well)beingateverycost.Ontheother,itneedsalterity, especiallytheotherself,becauseitsexistenceisanexistenceinandthroughthatwhichisdifferent fromitself.Now,Ricoeurshiftstoahermeneuticalmethodbecausetheconflictintheheartofthe subject cannot be solved at a structural level, since the felt alterity is crystallized through the subject’spracticalinteractionintheworldthroughtime.Thesubjectislostintheembeddedand situatednatureofitsexistenceintime.Alterity manifestsitselfthrough history,society,culture, institutionsetc.,andthesedifferentmanifestationsneedongoinginterpretationstobeappropriated astheworldofthesubject.Thisinterpretationisalwaysrootedincareoraconcernforitself and for alterity.Thatis,thesubjectcaresfortheother,althoughitseekstoassertitselfinandthroughthat alterity.Careiswhatbindstogetherthedifferentaspectsofthesubject. Thisontologicalstatusofcareisparticularlyclearwithrespecttotheotherself.Thesubjectcares foritsplaceamongotherselves(itsideaof‘thegoodlife’)andfeelsastrongdesiretobepartofa humansociety.Thisdesireforhumanityisfundamentalforitsidentityasapersonamongother persons,becauseitneedstheotherselftoaffirmitsidentityasanintegrateandirreplaceableperson. Selfesteemispartofouridentity,andtheother’srecognitioniscriticaltohowweesteemourselves asaperson.Weareresponsibletotheotherselfbecausetheotherselfrespondstoouractions,and we,onourpart,actandsufferinaccordancewiththatresponse.Wecareaboutwhattheotherhave tosayaboutourperson.Therefore,ouridentityaspersonsdependsontherecognitionoftheother selfotherthanonthemerefactualcontinuationofourbeing. Theparticularlycriticalimportanceoftheotherselfisthereasonwhyethicalvaluesaredominant intheconfigurationofsubjectiveexperience.Thebasiccarethatanimatesthesubject’sinteraction withtheworldisparticularly emphasizedwith regardtotheotherself,sincetheotherselfisa fundamentalpartofourpersonalidentity.Ouractionsarecharacterizedbyanunrelentingclaimfor responsibility,whichisrootedinthestructureofourbeingbecauseweneedandcarefortheother’s recognition.Ethicalvaluesandnormsarethereforeneededinordertoassertourselvesaspersons inaworldsharedwithotherpersons.Ourcoexistence with the otherpersons is oftenpermeated withconflict,disagreement,anddilemmas,whichsolicitthisneedforanethics.Toassertitself,the subjectmustknowhowtointeractwiththeotherself.Thequestionofnormativityisnotanextra dimensionaddedonthefactualdimensionofsubjectivity,butinscribedinthenatureofbeingaself. An ontology of care attempts to embrace this complex structure of human subjectivity by emphasizingtherelationbetweenselfhoodandothernessintheconstitutionofthesubject.

107 Conclusion: A Framework This attempt to reformulate Ricoeur’s theory of subjectivity is a first, necessary, step in the investigation of the relation between subjectivity and ethics. I could have chosen to attack the problemdirectlywithoutfirstconsultingRicoeur’swork.Ibelieve,however,thatsuchanapproach wouldstartonalesssubstantialandclarifiedgroundthatIdonow.Thus,Ideemtheforegoing reformulationnecessary. The following analyses will use the reformulation as a framework for the question about subjectivityandethics.ItwilldepartfromRicoeur’sanalysesindecisiveways.Iusealotoftimeof theconceptofhumanaffectivity,whichinRicoeurplayedacriticalroleinthestrippednotionof subjectivity, but was somehow left out or only peripherally touched upon in his later works. Further, I articulate the neurophysiological dimension of emotions in order to understand the embodied(biological)natureofhumanfeeling. Ricoeurdidnotdothis,andnormallyhedidnot involvebiologyinhisanalyses.HisdialogueswiththeneurobiologistJeanPierreChangeux(WT) showsthathedoesnotexcludethatwecanlearnsomethingaboutthesubjectfromneuroscientific research.However,hecontinuallyrecommendsthatwedonotdrawhastilyconclusionsorperform immaturereductionsofsubjectiveexperiencetosubpersonalmechanismsofbodyandbrain. Infact,thefollowingpageswillbeanextensiveanalysisoftherelationbetweensubjectivityand ethicsinordertoargueforanonreductivenaturalisticconceptionofhumanpersonhood.Iextend theargumentsemphasizedinthereformulation,namelythatsubjectivityandethicsareirreducibly related,andthatsubjectiveexperienceisconfiguredasapracticalspaceofreason.Ithenclaimthat thisisnotcontrarytoaneuroscientificapproachtohumannatureifsuchanapproachrespectsthe irreduciblenatureofhumansubjectivity.Igroundthisclaiminthetwonotionsthatwerebrought forthintheforegoingreformulation,i.e.,thepracticalspaceofreasonandanontologyofcare.

108 PartTwo FeelingEthical

The subject cares about being a person, just as she or he cares about so many other things. However,personhoodstandsoutamongthethingsthatwecareabout;maybenotexplicitlyinour dailylife,butwheneverourpersonhoodisinjured,threatened,oroffendedwefeelhowmuchwe careaboutbeingthepersonthatweare.Somehow,thepersonthatwearecharacterizeswhatwe careabout,orhowwecareaboutthethingsthatwecareabout.Personhoodremainsthefirm,but obscure, point of reference when we talk about ourselves and other people. A person can be humiliated,loosehisorhersdignity,meaningoflife,respectforotherpersons,changecharacter, becomeabetterorworseperson.Peoplecanbetreatedasiftheywerenotpersons(mostofusin the western world learn this from history and television, but too many suffer this horrifying experience). We can kill, torture, humiliate, starveandlaughataperson,butwecannotkillor torture personhood out of a person. Persons, as Richard Wollheim writes, ‘have something in common, which is membership of a particular biological species, and, since we also know no humanbeingswhoareincontestablynotpersons,itiseasytoconcludethattobeapersonistobea human being. They are one and the same thing’ (1984: 3). This is an interesting feature about humansubjectivity.Wearepersonsbythesimplefactthatwebreatheandexistasamemberofthe human species, and still we care about being persons. We care about being something that we alreadyare. ThereformulationofRicoeur’stheoryofsubjectivityinsistedonanineradicablerelationbetween subjectivity and ethics by emphasizing the critical presence of the other in the experience of selfhood. The subject’s experience, action, and feeling are constituted by the presence of other subjectstosuchanextentthatsubjectiveexperienceisnotconstitutedprimarilybytheexistenceof aself,butbyacoexistencetogetherwithotherselves;thatis,theexistenceoftheselfasa person embeddedinphysicalnatureandsituatedinahumansocietyinhabitedbyotherpersons.Itherefore introduced the notion of a practical space of reason to argue for a configuration of subjective experienceasahierarchyofheterogeneousvaluesgeneratedandrefinedbytheself,theworld,and theother.Further,IbrieflytoucheduponRicoeur’sideaofanontologyofcareasthefundamentfor suchaconfigurationofexperience.Thebeingofthehumansubjectischaracterizedbywhatthat particularsubjectcaresabout.

109 Thispartisdedicatedafurtherexplorationofthe problematic relation between subjectivity and ethics.Theanalyses,however,rarelyinvolveethicsasanexplicittheme,and,whenIfinallydothis in the second chapter, is might be characterized more as metaethics than ethics. This is done intentionally,sincemymaininterestinthisworkistoclarifywhyandhowsubjectivityandethics arerelatedandnotethicsinitself.Ishallargue thatsubjectiveexperience,feelings,values, and practices are primarily ethical and conclude that we cannot not understand properly neither subjectivitynorethicswithoutunderstandinghowandwhythisisso.Personhoodisessentialtothis conclusion.Thiswillbealludedtothroughouttheanalyses,butfirstclarifiedmoreindetailinthe finalsectionsofthesecondchapter. The analyses will be carried out in two main sections. The first chapter looks on the affective dimensionofsubjectivity.Humanaffectivitymarkstheinterfacebetweenthephysiologicalandthe intentionalaspectofhumansubjectivityandwillthereforerequireatreatmentofboththeseaspects. Thesecondchapterdealswithethicalexperience.Ianalyzethenormativeaspectofsubjectivityand arguefortheconstitutionofhumanexperienceasapracticalspaceofreasonrootedinanontology ofcare.

110 Chapterone HumanAffectivity Humanaffectivityismainly experiencedand expressedasemotions.Wearemovedbytheway that the world affects us which has therefore made emotions the central theme in the study of human affectivity. Nonetheless, emotions have had their ups and downs for little more than a centurynow.Intheendofthe19 th centurytwoimportantthinkersoccupiedthemselvesextensively withthenatureofemotions,namelyCharlesDarwinandWilliamJames,butforthebetterpartof the 20 th century emotions have lived a quiet existence in philosophy. Most philosophers and psychologists agreed that emotions are fundamental for human existence, but they nevertheless chosenottodealwiththemexplicitly.However,inrecentyearsemotionshaveonceagaincome into focus in philosophy as well as in other branches of cognitive science. This might be a consequence of the growing interest dedicated to the phenomenon in the empirical sciences, or maybejustoneofthemanyturnsinsidephilosophy itself.Nonetheless,todayatleastonething seemscertain:aphilosophicalinvestigationofemotionscannotbedoneseriouslywithoutbringing intoaccounttheempiricalinvestigationsofthebiologicalnatureofhumanaffectivity. In this section, I will first look at the conceptual background for the philosophical study of emotions.Ipresentthreemaintheories: the feeling theory , the cognitive theory, and the narrative theory ,sincethesegiveaprettygoodideaofthecontemporarydebate.Ibrieflysketchthegeneral featuresofthethreetheoriessothatIcanpreparethegroundformyownaccount.However,before turningtomyownconsiderations,Ishalllookattheneurophysiologicaldimensionofemotionsthat Iretainafundamentalelementinanyattempttoapproachhumanemotions.ThenIfinallyarguefor an alternative account of emotions that is inspired by Ricoeur, nourished by neurophysiological insights,anddirectedbythegroundworkdonebythethreetheoriesincontemporarydebate.Iclaim thatthesetheoriesneglecttheimportanceofmoodsinemotionalexperienceandargueforatheory that accounts for the neurophysiological dimension of emotions and furthermore differentiates feelings,moods,andaffectsasdifferentaspectsofthesameexperientialphenomenon.

Conceptual Background TheFeelingTheory Thistheoryisperhapsthemostrepresentativeofcommonsense,namelythatemotionsarespecial kind of felt experiences like sensations (hearing and seeing) and proprioception (registration of

111 changesinthebody).However,emotionssomehowdifferfromotherfeltexperiencesbymeansof thequalitativefeatureoftheirmanifestation;theyarevestedwithacertainfeltquality. ThetheoryfounditsclassicalexpressionintheJamesLangetheoryofemotion.Thetwoscholars, independently,proposedatheorythatreducedemotionstoperceptionsofbioregulatorychangesin thebody.James’famousexampleoffearofthebearstatesthatcommonsensetellsusthatwesee thebear,becomeafraid,andthenrun.Jamesturnsthispictureupsidedownsayingthatthisisall wrong. We fear thebearbecause we try to run fromit.Emotionisnotaresultofourcognitive relation to the bear as if I see a bear, know that itisdangerous,becomeafraidandrun.Onthe contrary,ouremotionsaretheexperienceoffeelingscausedbytheperceptionofasetofbodily responses.Iseethebear,mybodyreactstothedangerthatIperceive,andIhavethefeelingof beingafraidbecauseIperceivethevisceralreactionsofmybody.Jameswrites:‘Whatkindofan emotion of fear would be left, if the feelings neither of quickened heartbeats nor of shallow breathing,neitheroftremblinglipsnorofweakenedlimbs,neitherofgoosefleshnorofvisceral stirrings,werepresent,itisquiteimpossibletothink’(James1884:1934). During most of the 20 th centurythetheoryhasbeencriticizedfornotbeing able to distinguish between different kinds of emotions caused by the same visceral reactions. The first important criticism,carriedoutonaphysiologicalbasis,wasexpressedbyW.B.Cannonwhoin1927argued that‘theresponsesinthevisceraseemtoouniformtoofferasatisfactorymeansofdistinguishing emotionswhichareverydifferentinsubjectivequality.Furthermore,iftheemotionsweredueto afferentimpulsesfromtheviscera,wewouldexpectnotonlythatfearandragewouldfeelalikebut thatchilliness,hypoglycemia,asphyxia,andfeverlikethem’(Cannon1927:110).Thesamebodily statemayunderlietwodifferentemotionalexperiencessuchasfearandrage.Thephenomenology offear andragedifferinsucha radicalmannerthat the difference cannot be accounted for by visceralchangesalone.Thereisobviouslysomethingmoretotheemotionsthanfeltbodilychanges. Afterthisfrontalattack,thefeelingtheoryseemedsurpassedinthephilosophicalandpsychological studyoftheemotions. Nevertheless,aboutadecadeagothetheorygainednewforcewiththecompellingstudiesofthe neurobiologistAntonioDamasio(1994,1999,2003).WhereasJamesandLangecametotheiridea ofemotionsasfeelings mainlyfromthevisible physiognomic expression of emotions, Damasio scrutinizesemotionsinsidethebrain,thatis,intheneurophysiologicalpropertiesanddynamicsof emotions.HeconcordsbroadlywiththeJamesLangetheory(Damasio1994:129)anddevelops theirthesisbyreflectingonnewevidenceprovidedbyacombinationofclinicalobservationand

112 cognitiveneuroscience.Heconvincinglydefendsthefeelingtheoryfromthecriticismlaunchedby Cannon.Amongotherthings,heshowshowthebodyisnotalwaysdistinctlypresentinthefeeling ofanemotion.Thebrainisabletosomehow‘bypass’thebodybymeansofwhathecalls‘asif’ feelings:‘weconjureupsomesemblanceofafeelingwithinthebrainalone.’(Damasio1994:156). Andyetheimmediatelyemphasizesthat‘Idoubt,howeverthatthosefeelingsfeelthesameasthe feelingsfreshlymintedinarealbodystate’(idem).Hesurmisesthatthereisnotalwaysadirectline betweenaspecificbodystateandacertainfeelingofemotion.Hedifferentiatesthevariousfeelings and works out an elaborate account of the idea that emotions are feelings, going from simple homeostaticregulationstoacquired,socialemotions.Forexample,hegivesamoredetailedaccount ofthefeelingofsadnessthantheonewefindinJames who just emphasizes the physiological machineryofsorrow:‘eachfitofsobbingmakesthesorrowacute,andcallsforthanotherfitstill stronger’(James1884:197).Damasioclaimsthatalongsidetheperceptionofthebodystatethereis the perception of certain thoughts that might just contribute to the feeling of sadness (Damasio 2003:85).Thesethoughtsaremetarepresentationsofourownmentalprocessthatallowthemindto representotherpartsofthemind(metalimagesandlongtermmemory).Inthisway,Damasiotries toargueforthevarietyofemotionalexperiencebyemphasizingthecomplexityofourperception: ‘a feeling is the perception of a certain state of the body along with the perception of a certain mode of thinking and of thoughts with certain themes ’(Damasio2003:86). Inordertodevelopthisdetailedversionofthefeelingtheory,hehasinvestigatedfurtherintothe subjectivityofemotionalexperience,butneverceasingtoemphasizethefundamentalimportanceof the homeostasis, i.e., the ebbs and floods of ‘the bodily landscape’, his notion of subjectivity remainssomewhatsimplistic.Andthissimplicityaffectshistheoryofemotion.Asubjectiswhatit is, and nothing else. It is a core self that, throughout our existence, develops into an autobiographical self, shaped by education, culture, and unique and contingent personal events. Theses factors create, in a sort of orchestration, the person that we are. Naturally, he does not excludeourcapacitytocreateimaginativevariationsonouractualbeing,butheseemscertainthat, intheend,wearetheentitiesthatweareconstitutedtobe:‘WecanbeHamletforaweek,or Falstaffforanevening,butwetendtoreturntohomebase’(1999:225).Thisideaofahomebase underestimatesthereflexiveaspectofsubjectivity, i.e., our capacity of to evaluate and critically reviseouractuallybeingthepersonthatweare. I return to Damasio’s account again in the next section, but first we shall look two competing theoriesthatcriticizethereductionofemotionstopurebodilyfeelings.Emotionsplayanimportant

113 roleinourevaluationsandcannotbereducedtothefeelingsofbioregulatorychangesinthebody state.Ouremotionshaveanintentionalnaturethatsurpassestheinternalfeelofbodystates.Itis thisintentionalnaturethatthecognitivetheorieshaveleveledatintheircriticismofthefeeling theories. TheCognitiveTheory Mostphilosophicaltheoriesofemotionareainsomewayoranothercognitivetheories.Theyclaim thatemotionsinvolvepropositionalattitudes.WhenIamangry,Iamnormallyangryatsomeone becauseofsomething.WhenIamhappyorsaditisnormallyduetosomethingthatIamaware about. Emotions have a logic (Solomon 1976) or a structure (Gordon 1987) that surpasses the perceptionofbodilychanges.Theyarejudgementsabouttheworldandmysituationinit,involving amoreglobalstancetowardsmyexistence.Feelingsmayoccurtogetherwithemotions,butasone ofthemostenduringdefendersofthecognitivetheory,RobertC.Solomon,writes:‘onecanhave anemotionwithoutfeelinganything,andonecanfeelanything(includingallofthe‘symptoms’of emotionality, for example, flushing, pulsing) without having any emotion whatever’ (Solomon 1976:161) 19 .WhatSolomonemphasizesisthatemotionsrevealourintimaterelationtotheworld andtoourselves,notonlyaspossessorsofacomplex primate brain and an autonomic nervous system,butaspersonswithcertainideas,beliefs,andcommitmentsnotreducibletotheinternalfeel ofbodystates:‘everyemotionestablishesaframeworkwithinwhichwecommitourselves–or refuse to commit ourselves – to our world and to other people’ (Solomon 1976: 202). Most cognitivetheoriesconsideremotionsasjudgementsthathaveaspecificlogicorrationality(Sartre 1971;Nussbaum2001:1985;Taylor1985:602).Thislogicorrationalityissometimesidentified withthecomplexconceptofintentionality inthesense that emotions are expressions of certain beliefsordesires.WhenIfeelirritatedinagivensituationitisbecauseofsomethinggoingonin thissituation.Iamirritatedatthepersonbecauseofsomethingthepersonsaidordid.Perhapshis statementmakesmyopinionlookridiculousorperhapsjustbecausehemoveshimselfinastupid way. I am jealous because my neighbour has an expensive car or his apple tree carries more deliciousapplesthanmine.Thecombinationsareendless,butitisaquestionofstructure.Thereis anobjectorpropositionoftheemotion.Inordertounderstandthedifferentemotions,wemusttry

19 SolomonismainlyinspiredbyNietzsche,Sartre,andtheexistentialisttradition.Hewrotehisfirstworkasapolemic attackonthefeelingtheory(1976).Butinthelastyearsuptohisdeathin2007,hecametomodifyhistheoryinthe sensethathemadeitlesspolemicalandincludedfeelingsasanimportantpartofemotionalexperience.Nonetheless,he stillemphasizedtheprimaryimportanceofthecognitive,evaluativestance(2001:189192;2007:2056).

114 tosortoutthedifferentstructuresorcomplexesofthisobjectrelation. Thismaybefollowedby feelings, but the feelings are secondary. What is primary is the propositional attitude, belief or desire expressed in the emotion. The emotion is explained and defined by scrutinizing the propositionalattitudewhateverthismayimply:beliefs,judgements,desiresorcomplexesofthese. Feelingsareinthisscenarioreducedto‘addons’(touseanexpressionfromPeterGoldie,2000a: 401). They are not part of the explanation of the logic of emotions. This may sound familiar. Actually, feelings seem to suffer from the same overintellectualization that for a long time excluded emotions from philosophical investigations. Russell wrote in 1927: ‘The emotions are whatmakeslifeinteresting,andwhatmakesusfeelitimportant.Fromthispointofview,theyare the most valuable element in human existence. But when, as in philosophy, we are trying to understandtheworld,theyappearratherasahindrance’(1960:228).Itisthesamedistinctionthat isatplayinthecognitivetheoryofemotion.Feelingsarewhatmakesemotionsinterestingandwhat makesusfeelthemimportant,buttheyareahindrancewhenwetrytounderstandthem. Itisglaringlyobviousthatsuchtheorieshavebeenmetwithmuchskepticism(Goldie2000a:74 78; de Sousa 1987: 401, 1656; Stocker 1983: 1823). How can one explain emotions without includingthefeelingaspect?OneoftheclassicargumentsagainstthecognitiveapproachisMichael Stocker’s‘fearofflying’objection(Stocker1996:389).Weknowthatflyingisthesafestwayof transportationandstillwemaybeafraidtofly.Thismaybeexplainedasanirrationalemotion,but cannotbesolvedbyshowingthatstatisticsdemonstratethebelieftobeuntrue.Changingthebelief willnotchangetheemotion.Andwedonotconsiderapersonanidiotforbeingafraid.Itisjust howairplanesmakeherfeel.Itmaybeaninappropriatefeelingbutitmaystillcausehertochoose othersandmoretediousformsoftransportationinordertoavoidtravelinginanairplane.Feelings cannotberejectedaspartoftheemotionbecauseofthesimplefactthatthenonlogicalfeeling oftencausesthepersontoactinacertainway. TheNarrativeTheory Inrecent years,athirdtheoryisslowlycomingin to shape. Or more correctly, an old view on emotionshastakenanewform.Itisanattempttocombinefeelingtheorywithsomeaspectsofthe cognitivetheorybecause‘[f]eelingsare,asweallknow,attheheartofemotion’(Goldie2000a:12), andyetemotions,andthefeelingsinvolved,haveacertainstructureofintentionality.Emotionsare notreducibletobeliefsanddesires,andstilltheycausedbymorethanmereinternalbodystates. ThispositionhasbeenpreparedbythelateRichardWollheim(1987,1999)andisundercontinuous

115 elaborationbyPeterGoldie(2000a,2002ab,2003abc,2004,2007).Thegeneralidea,however,is notnew.ItdrawsoninsightsfromFreud,Heidegger,Sartre,Ricoeur,CharlesTaylor,andSolomon. Itemphasizesthepersonalaspectofemotionalexperience.Anemotionremainsunintelligibleifwe trytoapproachitfromanimpersonalstance(Goldie2002b:249).Emotionstellussomethingabout how the person experiences the world, itself and other people. Where a scientifically inspired philosophy aims at explaining the impersonal aspects of the human subject and the world, a philosophyofemotions,unavoidably,hastodealwith how the person experiences the ‘magical world’ of emotional experience. Sartre describes emotional consciousness in the following way: ‘[it]isanewconsciousnessinfrontofanewworld–aworldwhichitconstituteswithitsownmost intimate quality, with that presence to itself, utterly nondistance, of its point of view upon the world’(Sartre1971:78/42.Translationmodified). Inthenewapproach,however,thispersonalstancebecomesthecentreofanarrativestructurethat holds together the different elements of an emotion: past episodes of emotional experience, imagination,desire,belief,charactertraits,anddispositionstofeel,think,andactincertainways.It reactsagainstthebeliefdesireaccountofemotionarguingthatwhereasabelieforadesirecanbe feelingless,anemotionalwaysinvolvesfeelingsasfundamentalpartofitsnature.Forexample,I mayhavethebeliefthatthefjordsinNorway arefreezingcold,butdonotfeelitunlessIgoto Norwayanddipmytoeinoneofthem;Imaydesire togoonatouraroundtheworldwithout experiencingitasanemotion.Thisisnottosaythatbeliefsanddesiresdonotcarryanyimportant relation to emotion. The theory simply emphasizes that emotions cannot be reduced to such accounts.Thenatureofanemotionisacomplexaffaire,whichisbestapproachedasanarrative structure,orinGoldie’swords:‘Thebestunderstandingofaperson’semotionswilltakeaccountof thedistinctionsIwillbediscussing[Bodilyfeelings,feelingstowards,dispositions,mood,character traits, and so on], but will nevertheless be holistic in its overall approach, seeing feelings as embedded in an emotion’s narrative, as a part of the person’s life’ (2000a: 51). This way of investigatingtheemotions(whichIhavenamedthenarrativetheory)consideremotionsinhowthey areexperiencedbytheperson,whichis–phenomenologicallyspeaking–acomplexphenomenon constitutedbyintentionalfeelings,dispositionstoact,andmoods.Thesecomplexexperiencesare thenarticulatedbylanguageandthestoriesinwhichtheyareembedded.AsCharlesTaylorwrites: ‘Toexperienceanemotionistobeinasensestruckormovedbyoursituationbeingofacertain nature.Hence,Isaid,wecandescribeouremotionsbydescribingoursituation’(Taylor1981:107). Themostintriguingfeatureofthenarrativetheoryisthatbyunderstandingemotionstobeofan

116 essentialnarrativenatureweobtainatooltoinvestigatemoreaccuratelyintotheancientrelation betweenemotionsandethics(athesisdevelopedfurtherinchaptertwo). One critical problem about this theory is that its defenders do not account for the biological dimension of emotions. They are too preoccupied about defending the intentional and personal aspectsoftheemotionsthattheyneglectthefactthatemotionsarethemostprofoundlyembodied phenomenaofhumanexperiences(deSousa1987:47) 20 . ThethreetheoriesthatIhaveoutlinedaboveemphasizethreeimportantconceptsthatwillserveas guidelinesinmyownaccountofhumanaffectivity:1)feelings,2)cognition(intentionality),and3) narratives. But before I turn to this account, we have to look more closely on the embodied nature of emotions.AsImentionedearlier,todayatheoryofhumanemotionmusttakeintoaccount,atleast to a certain degree, the biology of emotions. The following section will present two neurophysiological theory of emotions. I begin with a brief presentation of Damasio’s work on emotionsandfeelings,sincehisstudiesofemotionalconsciousnesshavemuchofthecreditfor introducingneuroscientificresearchintothephilosophicaldebateofemotions(somemightevensay that it was his work that revived emotions in philosophy). However, it is the work of another neuroscientistthatIbelievecontributesmosttothephilosophicalstudyofemotions,namelyJaak Panksepp’spioneerresearchontheaffectivedimensionofthemammalianbrain.

Neurophysiological Dimension of Emotions21 Thecomplexityandimportanceofhumanemotionsaredeeplyinvolvedinitsembodiednature.The phenomenology of emotions cannot be severed from the ontogenesis of these ubiquitous phenomenaofhumanlife 22 .Thebiologicalnatureofemotionsistoocompellingtobepassedover

20 In fact, Goldie argues for ‘a profound distinctionbetweenthescienceofhumannatureandthenatural sciences’ (2002a:98)inatleastthreerespects.Humannatureischaracterizedbyperceptive,normativity,andhistoricalcondtion (1067),whichcannotbeexplainedbythe natural sciences, since they adopt an impersonal perspective (cf. Goldie 2002b:24950;Goldie2000a:1812).Ilargelyagreetothis,butIwillstillinsistthatthedistinctionislessprofound thanGoldiemakesit. 21 IhavefounditnecessarytoavoidspecificneuroanatomicalandneurophysiologicaltermstotheextendthatIdeem defensible, since the general ideas of the theories may be described without the technical detail. The anatomy, physiology, and chemistry of the brain are complex matters and require, to be only minimally understood, a long preparatory introduction that is not possible here. However, the technical detail is important, and in order to fully understand the scope and argument of the theories one must turn to the references indicated in this section. A fine introductiontothetopicisfoundin(Bear,ConnorsandParadiso2006). 22 Ricoeur emphasizes that it is the affective dimension of subjectivity that evidences the ontological dimension of subjectiveexperience(FM103/119;FN88/84;cf.pp.4550above).Thesubject’sbeingintheworldisrevealedbythe feelings; it is already in the world before it comes to know about its being in the world. The particular being of

117 insilence.Thefactisthatmybodyisoftenthefirst indicator that I am experiencing a certain emotion or find myself involved in an emotional episode. I feel a tension in my stomach and uneasinessinmylimbsduringaconversationwithacertainperson;Imaybedrummingmyfingers on the desk or moving my feet rapidly under the table. And then I come to realize that I am intenselyirritatedbyorwithsomethingaboutthatperson.Bodilyfeelingsareofteninvolvedinthe expressionandexperienceofemotions. One way to investigate the role of the bodily feelings in emotions is to look at the neurophysiologicalpropertiesanddynamicsinvolvedinemotionalexperience.Inthelastdecadeor so, three scientists in particular have set the agenda for the bridging of philosophy and the neuroscientific study of emotions: Antonio Damasio, Joseph LeDoux and Jaak Panksepp. They have all three done extensive research on various aspects of the neuronal underpinnings of emotions.Damasio’smostimportantcontributionconcernsthecriticalroleofemotionsinhuman decisionmaking (1994) and the relation between consciousness and emotion (1999), whereas LeDouxhasworkedmainlyonthebasicemotionalmechanismsthatarecommontobothhumans andotheranimals(inparticularinsightsonemotionallearningandemotionalmemoryderivedfrom thestudyofrats)withoutincludingthesubjectivedimensionofemotions(1996).Panksepp,onthe contrary, is highly concerned about the subjective dimension (the feeling) of emotions in the mammalian brain. He differs from both Damasio and LeDoux (who both mainly deal with the corticalelaborationofemotions)bystressingthesubneocorticaldynamicsofaffectivity(1998).In thefollowing,IwillbrieflypresentDamasio’sandPanksepp’stheoriesoftheneurophysiological dimensionofemotions.IarguethatPanksepp’sresearchismorecongenialwithaphilosophical approachtohumanaffectivitybecauseofitsemphasisonthesubjectiveexperienceofemotions. But although I disagree with Damasio’s general methodology,hisresearchontheimportanceof feelings in decisionmaking (the socalled ‘somaticmarker hypothesis’) remains decisive for the analysesofethicalexperienceinthenextchapter.Ledoux’sresearchdeservestobeaccountedfor, butforthefocusoftheanalysesIhavechosennottodoso. AntonioDamasio:ObjectiveEmotionsandSubjectiveFeelings Damasio’scontributiontothephilosophicalinvestigationofemotionsremainsindispensable.He has convincingly shown that the feeling aspect of emotion is fundamental not only in our subjectivityisdeterminedbyourbeingasubjectinexorablyrootedinthebiologicalnatureofourbodyasanobject amongobjects.

118 understandingofemotionsbutinallcognitiveprocesses.Heconcentratesonwhathehasnamed the somaticmarker hypothesis. By and large, the somatic marker consists of gut feelings ‘that increase the accuracy and efficiency of the decision process’ (1994: 173). Examining neuropathologicalcasesDamasiohascometotheconclusionthat“cool”reasoningisnotenoughto triggeradecision.Apersonwouldneverbeabletodecideonanythingwithoutthehelpofbodily inducedemotions.He wouldbeintheundesirablestate of infinitepossibilities of equal (or no) importance.Thebodilyinducedemotionsarewhathighlightsomepossibilitiesandnotothers.The emotionsarethuswhatqualifyourexperienceasasetofaffordancesthatpresentthemselvestous as feelings of what is the most convenient, appropriate, or reasonable among different possible choices. Hehascometothisinsightfromthestudyof,amongothers,ayoungmaninhisthirtiesthathe,for thesakeofdiscretion,haschosentocallEliot.Eliotwasintelligentman,agoodhusbandandfather, whotragicallydevelopedalargetumorthatendedupcoveringbothfrontallobes.Fortunately,the tumor was benign and successfully removed by surgical intervention. However, during the interventionmuchofthefrontaltissuethathadbeendamagedwascompletelyremoved.Thishada criticalimpactonEliot’slife.Hehadundergonearadicalchangeofpersonality,eventhoughhis mentalskillsandmemoryseemedcompletelyintact.Hebecameunrecognizableintheeyesofhis friendsandnearestfamily:‘EliotwasnolongerEliot’ (idem: 36). He was never happy nor sad, incapableofdecisionandunabletofocusonlongertermprojects.Furthermore,healwaysremained uncommonly controlled and indifferent even when he told the tragedies of his life (divorces, unemploymentandbankruptcy).AsDamasiowrites:‘Ibegantothinkthatthecoldbloodednessof Eliot’sreasoningpreventedhimfromassigningdifferentvaluestodifferentoptions,andmadehis decisionmakinglandscapehopelesslyflat’(idem:51).Onemightsaythatreasonalonecannever makeachoice.Experiencehastobesomaticallymarkedintermsoffeelingsinordertoguidestable consciouschoices.Inthissense,feelingsarewhatmakesourlifematter,andthequalificationofour experienceresidespreciselyinthiscapacityoffeelingtheworldandourselves:‘consciousness feels likeafeeling,andifitfeelslikeafeeling,itmayverywellbeafeeling’(1999:312). Onthebasisofthesomaticmarkerhypothesis(i.e.,theimportanceoffeelings),Damasiohasover theyearsdevelopedafinegrainedneurobiologicaltheoryoftheemotions.Onthefollowingpages, Iwillpresentaveryroughoutlineofhismainideasonemotionsandfeelings, andfurthermore argueforthereasonswhyIchoosePankseep’smodeltohis.

119 Damasio’saccountisbasedonasomatictheoryofemotions.Asmentionedabove,itisavariantof theJamesLangetheorythatemotionsarebasicallyfeelingsofbodilychanges.Thereare,however, two important contrasts to the earlier theory. The first is the already mentioned possibility that feelingscanbeactivatedendogenouslyby‘asif’loopsthatbypassthebodyandsimplystimulate somaticbrainareas(idem:156).Inthisway,wecanhavefeelingswithoutactualbodilyreactions, whichsavesbothtimeandenergy(1999:281)andprocuresamorenuancedpictureofthefeelings (notallaredirectlyinvolvedwiththebody).Thesecondcontrastishisemphasisonunconscious emotions. The brain can register alterations in the bodily landscape without this resulting in conscious feelings: ‘emotions can be induced in nonconscious manner and thus appear to the conscious self as seemingly unmotivated’ (idem: 48). For example, we may smile or sob spontaneouslywithoutknowingwhy(1994:1402;2003:703).But,byandlarge,Damasiosticks to the general idea of emotions as constituted primarily of bodily changes (e.g. visceral, musculoskeletal, and hormone alterations). The bodyisa‘theatreoftheemotions’(1994:155), becauseouremotionalresponsesalwaysoriginate,insomewayortheother,inthe‘internalmileu’ of somatic reactions. Thesephysiological responses, triggeredby certainbrain systems when the organismrepresentsobjectsandsituations,arepartofthebioregulatorydevicesfundamentalforthe survival and wellbeing of the organism and can basically be reduced to regulations of the automatic ‘homeostasis machine’ that approaches or avoids certain objects (2003: 3031) in accordancewithpleasureandpain(2004:51). His model is worked out by means of the methodological distinction between emotions and feelings.Althoughemotionsandfeelingsarepartofthesameprocess,they areneverthelesstwo separate mechanisms (2000: 15). Whereas the emotions are specific and coherent collections of physiologicalresponses,feelingsare‘thementalstatesthatarisefromneuralrepresentationofthe collectionsofresponsesthatconstituteanemotionwithinthebrainstructuresappropriateforsucha representation’(idem:20).Ontheoneside,wehaveemotions:consistentphysiologicalreactions that span from the basic process of metabolism (automatic mechanisms of internal chemical balances)oversimplepainandpleasurebehaviors(reactionsofapproachorwithdrawal)anddrives andmotivation(appetitessuchashunger,thirst,orcuriosity)toemotionsproper(e.g.happiness, sadness,disgust,surprise).Ontheother,wehavefeelings that functions as a mere ‘readout’ of these physiological reactions, that is, as mental patterns that map or perceive bodily changes. Sometimesthismappingisastraightforwardreadout;atothertimesitfunctionsbymeansofthe ‘asifbodyloop’ that procures a pure neural map of the body state, but nevertheless it always

120 functionsinreferencetothebody.Alongsidetheperceptionofthebodilychanges,feelingsdoalso dependonthesubjectivestateoftheexperiencingorganism:‘Afeelingaboutaparticularobjectis based on the subjectivity of the perception of the object, the perception of the body state it engenders,andtheperceptionofmodifiedstyleandefficiencyofthethoughtprocessasallofthe abovehappens’(1994:148). This leaves us with a picture of two separate physiologicalprocessesatthebottomofwhatwe know as emotional experience, emotions and feelings. But whereas emotions are objective and public, feelings are subjective and hidden. Hence, we are able to observe and investigate the emotion,sincetheseareengenderedbymeasurableandclearbiologicalchanges,buttheworkings ofthefeelingsremainin‘completeprivacy’(2000:15).Wehavetoderiveourunderstandingof feelings from what we are able to discover about the emotions. Damasio continues to produce elaborateaccountsonhowhumanbeingscomearoundtohavesuchanenormousvarietyoffeelings thattheyactuallyhave,buteverytimehereturnstotheideathatfeelingsarealwaysstrictlybound tothebody(evenifthebodyisonlyvirtuallypresent)simplybecause‘thebodyisthemainstage foremotions’(1999:287).Therefore,heboilshistreatmentofthevarietyoffeelingsdowntosix universalfeelingsthatarecoinedonthesixuniversalemotionsderivedfromfacialexpressionand recognizability,namelyfear,anger,sadness,disgust,surprise,andhappiness(idem:285) 23 . ThecriticismthatDamasionowfacesistheoldquestionthatCannonleveledatJamesin1927:can suchatheoryoffeelingsasperceptionorreadoutofbodilychangesaccountforthesubtleand multifarious nature of actual human feelings? I believe not, and this is mainly because of the methodologicaldistinctionoffeelingsandemotions.Ifweoperatewithsuchadistinction(private vs.public,subjectivevs.objective),weironicallyendupwiththesameCartesiandistinctionthat Damasiofightssohardagainst(thetitleofhisbookfrom1994was Descartes’ Error ).Whereas Descartesdistinguishes strictlybetweendeanimatedbodies(res extensa)anddisembodiedspirits (res cogitans), Damasio transfers this distinction inside the human being itself by talking about feelings as a mental readout of a mindless body. The body becomes an entirely depersonalized object rooted so firmly in the theoretical soil of evolution that the conscious person’s active, practical and thoroughly personal relation to his orherbodyisonlyseenas feebleanduseless scratchingonthehardersurfaceofanobjectiveandanonymousnature.Inmanymatters,Damasio

23 Damasio here conjoins the distinctions worked out bythefamousresearchofthepsychologistPaulEkman who individuatedtheseemotionsasbeinguniversalacrossculturesandgender.Ekmandefinedthebasicemotionsaccording toseveralcharacteristics:distinctiveuniversalsignals,presenceinotherprimates,quickonset,briefduration,automatic appraisaletc.(Ekman1992:175).

121 rightlyobserves,thebodywillhaveitswaysnotwithstandingthecontinuousstruggleoftheperson. Wehavetounderstandthelifeofthebodyinordertounderstandthelifeofthepersonwhohasthat body.Damasiowarnsus(asmostpaleontologists,neuroscientists,andevolutionarytheorists)that themindisonlyaconglomerateofnewlydevelopedbrainsystemsdeeplyembeddedinmillions andmillionsofyearsofevolution(1994:254).Therefore,wemustunderstandthatthebodyhasits reasons,itsownrationality(theworkingoftheemotions)thatisultimatelyrelatedtotheneedof survival(1994:2624). Now,Iwillnotinanywaydisputetheimportanceofemotionsasembodiedappraisalscarriedout intermsofregistrationofphysiologicalresponsesinthebody 24 ;onthecontrary,Idobelievethat emotionsareintrinsicallylinkedwiththebody,butitistheconceptionofthebodyanditspresumed relation to the cognitive faculties that I resist. Ricoeur’s analyses of the body individuated an ambiguityinourconceptionofthebody(abovepp.708).Thebodyis,atthesametime, both my bodyand abody;thatis, my personalbodybywhich I accesstheworld,i.e.,abodycharacterized by my personality (when and where I was born, how I was brought up and educated, physical constitutionetc.)andthen abodyasanautonomousobjectwhichispartofananonymousnature thatdeterminesmanyofthereactionsofthatbody,i.e.,basicallyjustabodyamongotherbodies. ThisambiguityofthebodyismissedinDamasio’s(andevenmorePrinz’s)accountofemotions, andthecognitiveelement(judgmentandintentionality)isthereforereducedtoasomewhatstrange, artificialelaborationofthereal,basicemotions.Thebodyhasitsreasons,butwecannotstrictly separatethesereasonsformthenatureofthepersonwhofeelsandactsthroughthatbody.Inthe courseofalife,thebodybecomesapartofthesubjectinthatthesubjectisshapedbythebody,but the body is also shaped by the subjectivity that it expresses. For example, on a pure neurophysiological level, the body of a skilled athlete differs only minimally from that of an

24 Damasio’sneurophysiologicalaccountofemotionshasrecentlybeendefendedandelaboratedphilosophicallybyJ. Prinz (2004) who argues for emotions as embodied appraisals (778). All emotions are qualified by a kind of gut reactionsthat‘useourbodiestotellushowwearefaringintheworld’(69).Emotionsthatfeeldifferentfromthebasic bodyrelated emotions are simply ‘blends of basic emotions or cognitive elaborations of basic emotions’ (93). For example,romanticloveisablendofthemorefundamentalemotionsofattachmentandlust,because‘somecasesof lovemaybenothingthanlasciviousattachment’(124).Thispurelyphysiologicalapproachtotheemotionsisthenread backintothephenomenologyoffeelings.Prinzwrites,forexample,that‘Ithinkthephenomenologyofguiltisoften just like the phenomenology of sadness […] The point is that certain emotions have similar or identical phenomenology. There are many other plausible examples: indignation feels like anger, disappointment feels like sadness,awehasanelementofsurprise,contempthasanelementofdisgust,pridefeelslikeakindofjoy,exhilaration feelslikeablendoffearandjoy,andjealousyfeelslikeablendofanger,disgust,andfear’(2005:19).Allemotions have ‘core relational themes’ that are relevant to our needs and interests, in short our wellbeing (2004: 66), which meansthatfear,forexample,isalwayssomehowrootedinphysicaldanger(219).Thisviewonemotionsasembodied appraisalsdeterminedbycorerelationalthemeshavecriticalresultsfortherolethatemotionsplayinethics.Ireturnto thisproblemintheconcludingpagesofpartthreewhereIbrieflydiscussPrinz’sethicaltheory.

122 immobileacademic,andyetthetwopersonshavecompletelydifferentexperiencesandexpressions of the body. Their bodies are, at least in this sense, radically different from one another. A neurophysiological investigation of the emotions that operates with such a methodological distinctionbetweenemotions(body)andfeelings(mind)willnotbeabletointeractwithamore phenomenologically based account. I mentioned earlier that Damasio’s account of the emotions suffers from the simplicity of his view on human subjectivity, and this becomes evident in his reductionoffeelingstoperceptionsofanonymousphysiologicalreactions. Ihavethereforechosentouseanotherneurophysiologicaltheoryofemotionsasthebackgroundfor myownaccount.Strangelyenough,sinceIemphasizedthepersonalaspectofemotions,thistheory comesfromascientistwhohasspentmoretimewithanimalsthanwithhumans. JaakPanksepp:SubjectiveAffectivity Overthelastthirtyyears,Panksepphasarguedfortheneedofmorethoroughanimalstudiesifwe are to understand the neurophysiology of human emotional experience: ‘Through basic cross speciesneuroscienceresearch,thebestwe canpresentlyachieveistheidentificationofessential neural components shared by all mammals, some of which may suffice to generate affective experiences–ancientexperientialcapacitiesIcall affective consciousness ’(2004a:48).Heinsists thatemotionalexperienceisnotgeneratedonlyatthe cortical levelby newly gained neocortical cognitivecapacitiessuchasmemory,attention,andcognition.Hepersistentlylevelsacritiqueat the cognitive and behavioral neurosciences for ignoring the affective nature of human consciousness(2001:136,2003:112,2004b:179;2005b:634;2005c:1668).Thepictureofthe humanbrainpresentedbythecognitiveandbehavioralneurosciencesisenvisagedonthegroundof aneodualismthatisevenstrongerthantheoldCartesianone,becauseatleastDescartesconceded animals to have various passions (1998: 340). This neodualism (present in both Ledoux and Damasio)believesthatemotionalexperience(aswellashumanconsciousnessingeneral)isborn only with the development of higher brain functions (the specifically human neocortex). Other animalsdonothaveconsciousexperienceandcanthereforenotfeelemotions,butonlyreactwith instinctual emotional behavior (enabled by a combination of working memory and specific emotional systems concentrated in limbic system) (2007: 232). Therefore, this view holds that emotionalexperienceisparticularlyhumanandmustbesoughtoutinthecognitiveelaborationof bodily reactions. Accepting this presupposition, we end up with Damasio’s sharp distinction between objective emotions and subjective (human) feelings as the only viable approach to the

123 natureofhumanemotion(2005a:25).Ontheonesidewehavetheancientemotionsdevelopedand refinedthroughouttheeonsofevolution,andontheotherthecognitiveskillsasnewly evolved capacities(language,symbols,longtimememory,etc.)thatinhumanhavegivenrisetomuchmore complexandelaborateemotionalexperience(feelings)andtheconsequentsophisticatedbehavior 25 . Asareactiontothistraditionalview,sometwentyyearsagoPankseppcoinedadisciplinethathe called affective neuroscience (1991). Contrary to the other kinds of neuroscience, affective neuroscience aims at explaining ‘the existential reality of our deepest moods and emotions’ (1998:14). The central workinghypothesis is that emotional experience, including subjectively experiencedfeelings,doesplayanimportantroleinthechainofcausalreactionsthatdeterminethe actionsofbothhumansandotheranimals.And,further,thesubjectivenatureoffeelingsdoesnot excludescientificinvestigation.Wemustsimplystartbyinvestigatingtheneurophysiologyofthe various subneocortical emotional systems that are homologous in all mammalian brains (2005c: 160). These systems generate different ‘raw affects’ or ‘rawfeels’ that instantiate intrinsic emotional values to orient the animal in the environment. Human and other mammal behavior originatesfromthisinterplayofdifferentbasicaffectivevalues.Thefunctioningofthemammalian brainreliesonacommonaffectiveconsciousness,andcrossspeciesresearchwillhelpclarifythe neurobiologicalunderpinningofmanybasichumantraits(2006:7812).Themammalianbrainis basically affective (it interacts with the environmentonthebasisofcertainfeltvalues),andthe higherbrainfunctionsthatcharacterizehumanscannotbeseveredfromthesebasicaffectivevalue systemsorretainedtooperatefrom‘topdown’readoutsofmerebodilyaffects(2004b:179).The higherbrainfunctionsarethemselvesimmersedintheaffectivedimensionofecologicallife,andto understandwhatisparticularabouthumanfeelingswehavetoresorttoa‘bottomup’perspective that‘helpclarifyprepositionalaffectivepsychodynamicsthatemergefromsubneocorticalregions ofthebrain’(2005c:173).Combiningtheexperimentaladvancesofanimalstudy(wecanstudy otheranimalsmorethoroughlythanhumanduetobioethicalrestrictions;e.g.,itisnotallowedto cutopenalivinghumanbraininordertotakeaprecisesampleofthesubregionsofthebrain)and a phenomenological approach, we beget a new pictureoftheemotionalbrain,where‘emotional

25 Panksepp,however,admiresandlargelyagreeswiththeworkofbothDamasioandLeDoux(1998:340;2003:7; 2004b:181).Whatheresistsisthe methodologicaldistinctionbetweenobjectiveand subjectiveaspectsofemotion. WhereasDamasioemphasizestheimportanceoffeelings(althoughheindividuatesthehighercognitivebrainsystems tobetheoriginandthusmaintainsthedualism),LeDouxisevenmoreradicalandconsiderstheconsciousaffective aspectofemotions(feelings)tobelargelyepiphenomenal.Hewrites,forexample:‘Emotionsevolvednotasconscious feelings,linguisticallydifferentiatedorotherwise,butasbrainstatesandbodilyresponses.Thebrainstatesandbodily responsesarethefundamentalfactsofemotion,andtheconsciousfeelingsarethefrillsthathaveaddedicingtothe emotionalcake’(Ledoux1996:302).

124 affects may be thoroughly embedded within the extended activities of brain operating systems’ (2005b:38). Panksepp calls this research strategy dual-aspect , which he considers the only way to challengetheclassicalbehaviorismthatisstillverymuchaliveinneuroscience(2005a:24).We havetoconsiderthecomplexitiesofthebrain,causalandpsychologicalproperties,asbeingofone nature that nonetheless have to be studied from different (at least two) perspectives. The subneocorticalaffectsystemsthatcauseinstinctualbehaviorandthehighercognitivefunctionsthat byexperienceandeducationdevelopandrefinetheseinstinctsaretwosidesofthesamecoinand mustbelinkedtogetherinordertoindividuate‘basicdynamicfeaturesofbrainandmind’(2005c: 163).Thisenables ascientificresearchofthecausalfoundationofaffectiveconsciousnessinall mammals and not only the neural correlates of human cognitive elaboration of bodily emotions (idem). If we consider crossspecies basic affects systems to influence and be present, with a constantvariegatingintensity,inallhumancognitionsandactions,wehaveaparadigmtostudythe neuroevolutionary mechanisms involved in the feelings that influence the being and action of humans. Neuroscience can thereby stick to observable and causal dynamics and properties of affectiveconsciousnesswithoutjumpingtospeculationsaboutthefarmorecomplexfunctionofthe neocortex. We cannot say anything even slightly definitive about the higher brain functions, let alonethewaythedifferentbasicneocorticalsystems(e.g.auditory,vestibular,somaticsensory,and visualsystems)conjointowhatweknowashumanconsciousexperience.So,althoughPanksepp’s thesisaboutcoreaffectiveconsciousnessinanimalsmayseemaninvalidatespeculationsincewe cannotverifysuchaseemlyradicalpresupposition,hisstrategyisnotmoreinvalidateorradical thanDamasio’slongspeculationsaboutfeelingsas mentalimages aboutbodilyresponses.They both presume more than can be empirically verified.Therealquestionis,atleastinthepresent contextconcerningtheneurophysiologicaldimensionofhumanaffectivity,whichresearchstrategy is best at explaining the actual human feelings and emotions 26 . In my opinion, Panksepp lays a betterfoundationforaninterdisciplinaryapproachtohumanaffectivitybecauseofhisinsistenceon thefeelingaspectofemotions.Hedoesnotdriveamethodologicalwatershedinbetweenemotions

26 Pankseppiscriticaloftheenthusiasmgeneratedbythenewlyacquiredbrainimagingtechniques,sincetheresultsare oftenbasedonafragileand‘blind’experientialdata(whatarewelookingforandhowdowedeciphertheimagesof thelivingbrain?):‘Crossspecies,experimentalanalysis,wherekeybrainvariablesareevaluated,providesanapproach thatisnotfulloffalsenegativesandmisleading“neuroechoes”asismodernfMRI[FunctioningMagneticResonance Imaging, which is based on a combination of registration of neural activity and computer simulation that together generate an image of the brain in function]’. The interweaving of animal neurobehavioral and human neuropsychologicalresearchpermitssubstantivedynamicanalysesofthecoreemotionsandtheirassociatedfeelings’ (2005a:26).

125 andfeelings,butemphasizethelatterasthemostviableaccesstothefirst.Hisdualaspectmonism include evolutionary accounts without excluding feelings as merely subjective ‘frills that have addedicingtotheemotionalcake’cookedupbyamoreimportantevolutionaryprocess(seenote 25). Feelings cannot be methodologically severed from emotions, but their actual presence in humanliferemindsusthatemotionalprocessesaretobeconsideredasunifiedexperientialstates, and that these states rely on both objectively detectable evolutionary mechanisms shared by all mammals and subjectiveregulationandrefinementduetoethologicaldifferencesinbrainstructure (e.g.theneocortexinhuman)andsocialinteraction.Affectiveneurosciencedoesnotlockhuman feelingsontothebody;onthecontrary,itseekstoclarifytheneurophysiologicalfoundationfor ‘the full emotional feeling state that ramifies throughout the organism’ by considering the core affective systems that ‘can be regulated, but not created, by higher corticocognitive activities’ (2005b: 64). Panksepp does not speculate in how humans actually regulate the core affective processes,neitherdoeshepretendthatneuroscientificresearchcaneffectivelyclarifytheabundant and unique variety of human emotional life (1998: 42). He just claims that human feelings are tethered to the primary affective consciousness of the mammalian brain and argues that a neurophysiological elucidation of the systems operating in this affective consciousness will help understandsomeoftheaspectsofthehumanconditionwhichis,likethatofotheranimals,deeply embeddedinaffectivity(2004b:174). Now, what is exactly Panksepp’s proposal for a primal affective consciousness that may help explaintheaffectivenatureofhumanconsciousness?HeoperateswiththeacronymSELF(Simple EgotypeLifeForm)thatisembeddeddeeplywithinthebrain(1998:309;2004a:50;2005c:1789). Thisisakindofprimordial“selfrepresentation”or“selfschema”thatoriginatedinthebrainstem anddevelopedfromtheorganizedmotorprocessesinthemidbrain.Itisprimordialinthesensethat itdoesnotatallaccountforwhatweknowashumanconsciousnessand,furthermore,becauseitis largely independent of higher corticocognitive processes. It operates as an ‘archaic SELF Representationnetwork’(1998:309)thatgeneratesbasicinstinctualbehaviorinallmammals.The dynamics internal to this network constitute an affective consciousness that reacts directly to environmental stimuli by initiating endogenous sensory and emotional responses within the subcortical areas of the brain. The reverberations caused by this affective relation to the environmentarecriticalfor‘themostcrucialbiologicalvaluesthatallmammalsshare’(1998:183). Themammalianbrainisgeneticallygearedtorespondincertainwaystotheenvironment,andthe intrinsic nature of these responsesystems influences the more complex being and behavior of

126 humans.TheinstinctualnatureoftheSELFisstructuredbyvariousemotionalandmotivational operatingsystemsthatencodeintrinsicneurodynamicvaluestructures.Thesevaluestructuresare thenexperiencedbythelivingsubjectasrawfeelingsofpleasureandpainthatprovidethesubject withinstinctualchoicesofrespondingtothestimulioftheenvironment.Itmayseemparadoxicalto usethetermexperiencewhenspeakingofinstinctualbehaviorortalkingaboutinstinctualchoices, butPanksepp’sthesisisthattheSELFexperiences internal raw feelings aboutwhatisthemost appropriatechoiceorresponsewithouthavingto think aboutit.Itisanaffectiveconsciousnessthat feelsthevalueofcertainstimuliandtherebyenactsacertainreaction.Thebehavior,however,isnot reflective but instinctive in nature, i.e., the system responds immediately without delay due to cognitiveelaboration. In fact, Panksepp operates with different levels of consciousness developed throughout the evolutionofthemammalianbrain(2004a:49):firsttherewas primary process consciousness that experiences (feels) raw sensory, perceptual, emotional, and motivational properties (instinctual behavior). Then the secondary consciousness that possesses the capacity to think about those experiences (nonlinguistically). And finally, thetertiary form of consciousness thatweknowas human consciousness and its specific capacity to have thoughts about thoughts. The SELF is generated with the primary process consciousness and reacts to intrinsic values independent of other,moredeveloped,layersofconsciousness:‘Oursubneocorticalanimalianbrain,withit’smany basicattentional,emotionandmotivationalsystems, may actually lie at the center of our mental universe’(idem).Whatisimportantinthisworkinghypothesisisnotthespecificlayers(thatmight seem somewhat artificial), but the general idea that human brains have ‘a multidimensional conscioussenseofself’(1998:300)thatisrootedinaprimordialaffectivesenseofselfandthe relationtotheenvironment. Overthelastdecade,Panksepphasindividuatedandrefinedsevendistinctendogenousemotional systemsinthesubneocorticalstructuresofthemammalianSELF(1998:125298;2006:77780). These systems all exhibit a certain ‘affect logic’ (2003: 5) that prevails in human cognitive deliberationsandwhichcanbeenvisionedinbasicinstinctualanimalbehavior.Ashewrites,‘[m]y mainpointisthataffectivefeelingsare,toasubstantialdegree,distinctneurobiologicalprocessesin terms of anatomical, neurochemical, and various functional criteria, including peripheral bodily interactions.Emotionalandmotivationalfeelingsareuniqueexperientiallyvalenced“statespaces” thathelporganismsmakecognitivechoices–e.g.,tofindfoodwhenhungry,waterwhenthirsty, warmthwhencold,andcompanionshipwhenlonelyorlusty’(2003:6).Theenormousvarietyof

127 human affective feelings has, at its core, raw affective experiences that ‘appear to be pre propositionalgiftsofnature’(2005c:169). Thesevensystemsthatgeneratetheaffectiveinternal‘statespace’are:SEEKING,FEAR,RAGE, LUST,CARE,PLAY,andPANIC(thesystemsarecapitalizedtoemphasizetheemotionalimport). Affectiveexperienceissatiatedwithintrinsicvaluespertainingtothesebasicsystems.Thesystems function without cognitive interference and can therefore by investigated by a crossspecies approach. Here I will not explain the mechanisms involved in all the systems but only briefly outlinethemaindynamicsofSEEKING.Thedynamicsoftheothersystemslargelyreflectthose involvedinthisone. SEEKING is characterizedby a certain feeling tonethat‘leadsorganismstoeagerlypursuethe fruitsoftheirenvironment–fromnutstoknowledge,sotospeak’(1998:145).Itmediatesallthe appetitivedesiresthatdriveandmotivatetheanimaltoengagewiththeenvironment.Itisaself stimulatingsysteminthesensethattheanimalisnotapassiverecipientwithregardtothestimuli fromtheenvironment,butdoesactuallyvoluntarilyregulatetheactivitythatthesestimuliproduce inthesystem.When,forexample,theappetiteforfoodissatisfied,thesysteminhibitstheintensity ofthestimuliconcerningnutrition (1998:1467). This is view opposes the classical behaviorist viewonanimalbehavior,sinceitpresupposesanevaluativeaffectiveexperiencethatdoesnotfit with a ‘cold’ mechanistic conception of pleasure and reward. The animal actually feels the raw valuespertainingtotheobjectsoreventsintheenvironmentandtherebyestablishesaninteractive relationshiptotheobjectsbasedonthesefeltvalues.Pankseppcan,therefore,talkof‘statespaces’ inprimaryprocessconsciousness.Thesystemaccountsfortheanimal’srelationtoandpositionin theenvironmentasthatofavalencedspaceexperiencedbytheanimalasaffectivefeelingsladen withcertainvaluesduetotheinternalstructureanddynamicsofthesystem.Thesamemechanisms are at stake in the other systems, and together the different systems structure the primordial encounter with the world as an affective consciousness that registrates and reacts to certain biologicalvalues.Inthisview,‘affectisanorganicallyembodiedpartofsubcorticalinstinctual emotional systems that arouse basic action-to-perception processes’ (2001: 136). Perception is determinedbytheaffectivestatesofthebeingthatperceives. Inhumans,thevaluesexperiencedasrawfeelingshavea‘profoundinfluenceoverwhatwethink anddo’(2004b:177),becausetheaffectivevaluesgeneratedinbasicsystemshapeandinfluence theperceptionofourselvesandtheenvironment(1998:160).Thesystemsofprimalaffectiveand motivationalprocessesthatwesharewithotheranimalsmaywellbefoundationalintheevolution

128 ofmanyofthecognitiveskillsthatcharacterizehumanexistence(2003:8).Wecannot,according toPanksepp’sgeneralidea,approachthefeelingaspectofourmentallifewithamethodological separationoftheneurophysiologicalpropertiesofbodilystatesandthosepertainingtotheparticular human neocortical capacities. Feelings are not more subjective than emotions simply because emotions are feelings – although these may not be articulated as conscious affordances. The unconsciousfeelingsneednotbethematizedinordertoinfluencehumanbehavior.Wemaybehave orfeelincertainwaysthatarecognitivelyimpenetrable.Ontheotherhand,notallhumanfeelings aredeterminedbythesecoreemotionalsystems,althoughtheymayfindsomeoftheirenergyor bodily feeling in more raw feelingstates. The individuation of subneocortical systems of core feelingsdoesnotexcludethepeculiarandprofoundnatureofpsychicfeelings(1998:32930). SomeConsiderationsonEvolution,Neurophysiology,andIntentionality Emotionsandfeelingsareaprivilegedentryintothequestionofnaturalization.Surely,cognitionis abiologicalphenomenonaswellasemotionsandfeelings,butbecauseofthethoroughlyembodied nature of emotions they emphasize the inevitable encounter of biological and philosophical investigationsofhumannature.DamasioandPanksepppresenttwodifferentperspectivesonthe neurophysiological dimension of emotions, but they both stress the evolutionary importance of emotionalexperience.Andthetheoryofevolutionindeedseemsanunavoidableissuewhentalking aboutemotions;infact,itisnotanoptionalbutanecessaryfactortotakeintoaccount(Searle2000: 40). On the other hand, as Solomon writes concerning an emotion that many evolutionary explanationscenteron,namelyanger:‘Thereisnodoubtthatanger(andsomeotheremotions)are part of our evolutionary heritage and include physiological responses that we share with other animals. But this is surely just a piece of the story’ (Solomon 2007: 14). Solomon insists that emotionsarenotonlycausedbydistantevolutionaryforces.Ourrelationtotheobjectsoreventsof ouremotionsisalsoconstitutedbymorethantheancient‘selfishgenes’ofourancestors.Emotions areintentional.Theycontainourmostprivatewishes,desires,andideas,andthusouremotional relationtoobjectsoreventsisqualifiedbythisintentionality. Howdowethenbalancetheevolutionaryandtheintentionalaspectsofemotions?Firstofall,we havetodistinguishbetweenevolutionandbiology.Biologicalexplanationsarenotidenticalwith evolutionaryexplanations.Biologydoesnotnecessarilyinvolveteleologicalpresumptionsaboutthe origin of the organisms that it investigates. It is mainly interested in discovering the laws and mechanisms that govern the manifold of biological entities in the world. Naturally, etiological

129 questionsposethemselvesmoreforciblyoncewediscover‘possiblecopyingmechanismsforthe genetic material’ (DNA) in all living organisms (Watson and Crick 1952: 737). Evolutionary explanationscannot,however,relyonbiologyasajustificationforitstheories.Biologyhasnotyet emptiedthemysteriesofthelivingorganism;somethingsstilljustseemtohappenwithoutany explanation (de Sousa 1987: 1045). This brings us to a second, more interesting, point about evolutionandintentionality,namelythequestionofteleology.Howdoweaccountfortheobjects ofemotions?Ifemotionsarenottobeconsideredmerely epiphenomena then they must have a reasonandenactanactualchangeintheworld.Thequestioniswheretolookforthisreasonand change:inthelifeoftheindividualpersonorinthe general, anonymous,need forsurvival.The philosopherRonalddeSousahasdealtsystematicallywiththisproblemintermsofthe remote or proximate explanationofemotions(deSousa1987:78).Theneurophysiological explanations of emotionsare,strictlyspeaking,proximal;theyaimatuncovertheneurophysiologicaldynamicsand propertiesofemotions.Evolutionaryexplanations,ontheotherhand,areexplicitlyremoteinthat theyseektoexpoundemotionsasmechanismsinageneralprocessofadaptationtotheneedof survival.Now,deSousaquicklydismissesthesimplisticideaofadaptationassurvivalofthefittest bystressingthat‘evolutionarychangeinvolvesnoprogress,noinherentdirectionor“orthogenesis,” nobuiltindrivetomentalityorspiritualityorgroupharmonyorevencomplexity’(deSousa1987: 80). However, if we subscribe to the general idea ofevolution(asdeSousadoesandIdotoo), emotionscannotbecompletelymaladaptive,sincethecreaturesthathavethemremainaliveand evenflourish.Emotionsdohaveabiologicalfunctionthatmustbeenvisaged(deSousa1987:195). So to maintain the complexity of human emotions under the pressure of reductive evolutionary explanations, de Sousa looks at the motivational force of emotions; and more specifically, the relationbetweenthebiologicalneedandthepsychologicalmotivationorwant.Emotionsinfluence human behavior at different levels that may be individuated by the notions of instinct and intentionality.First,hedistinguishesbetweenwhathecallsTinstinctsandHinstincts(deSousa 1987: 84) 27 . Tinstincts are those we find in simple animal behavior that exhibits predictable stereotypedresponsestoprecisestimuli.Hinstincts are human emotions that are experienced as motivationalforces,whichdonot,however,resultinfixedpatternsofpredictablebehavior.Now,it isnotdifficulttopointoutradicaldifferencesofthetwotypesofinstincts.Itis,however,hardto showhowtheyrelate.DeSousadoesthisbyindividuatingdifferentdegreesofintentionalityby meansoftheconceptoffungibility.TheteleologicaldifferencesinvolvedinTandHinstinctsare 27 TheyarecalledTinstinctsaftertheDutchethologistandornithologistNikolaasTinbergenwhoindividuatedthistype ofbasicinstincts.Hinstinctsareparticularlyhumaninstincts.

130 determinedbythefactthathumanshaveacapacityforsingularreferencewhereasotheranimals operatewithfungiblereferences.Toexplainthedifference,heusestheexampleofthedogFido(de Sousa 1987: 98100) that likes its owner and recognizes this person by means of the physical qualities(smell,voicetone,characteristicmovements,etc.).Therefore, wespontaneouslybelieve thatFidoactuallylikesthatparticularpersonandnotsomebodyelse.This,however,isamistake.If weimaginethatthepersondiedbut,miraculously,aperfectcloneofthatpersoncouldbemade, thenFidowouldneverbeabletotellthedifference.Hewouldlikethatpersonjustasmuch.The samewouldnotbethecasewithhumans.Weknowthatifweloosealovedone,nobodycanever filltheplaceofthatperson.Weknowthatheorsheisdead,soifweencounterapersoncompletely identical,westillknowthatthisisnotourlovedone;heorsheisanotherpersonalbeitthephysical identity. This is due to our capacity for singular reference. Humans operate with nonfungible referencestotheiremotionalstates(Ilike this walletand not anotheridenticalone),whereasother animalsonlyrefertotheenvironmentintermsofgenerality(deSousa1987:97).Animalseasily transfertheemotiontootherobjectsthathavethesamegeneral,butnotparticular,features(e.g.,if adishisempty,thedogimmediatelyturnstoanother;or,thecrowsmistakeascarecrowsforareal person).Thetransitionfromonekindofinstincttoanotherisnotduetoanontogenticaldifference betweenhumansandotheranimals.Itisduetoadifferenceinintentionality.DeSousatalksabouta quasiintentionalityinanimalsthatreliesonthegeneralcharacterofthereferencebywhichthey livetheiremotionallife.Humansarecharacterizedbya‘mentalgradeofintentionality’(idem)that reliesonthespecifichumanlogicolinguisticcapacities. What is important in de Sousa’s picture of human emotions is that the mental grade of intentionalityparticulartohumanbeingsisnotradicallyirreducibletothecommonbiologicalstory thatwetellaboutotherlivingcreatures.Humansaremovedbyemotionsjustlikeotheranimalsand arethereforerestrictedbysomeofthesameevolutionaryforcesthataremoreeasilydiscoveredin animals,becausetheirbehaviorisrestrictedbythegeneralityofTinstincts.Theemotionalbehavior ofotheranimalsarebetterexplainedbytheremoteexplanationsofevolution,becausethegeneral featuresoftheirreference(foodisnutritionandsexisreproduction).Andeventhoughthesame forcesarepresentinhumanbehavior,humanemotional behavior is different and more complex basically due to the fact that ‘we care about individuals’ (de Sousa 1987: 100). Evolutionary explanationsareimportantifwewanttounderstandtheembodied,physiologicalnatureofhuman emotions. We are rooted in biology particularly by our emotions and to fully understand these ubiquitousphenomenainhumanlife,weneedtoclarifytheneurophysiologyoperatinginthem.The

131 reason why an evolutionary account is never enough is due to the singular reference of human emotions.Humanemotionalbehaviorreliesonaproximalexplanation.AsImentionedabove,the neurophysiologicalexplanationiscarriedoutataproximallevel.However,theexplanationneedsto be proximal in another sense. Contrary to other organisms, humans have a biography and their desires are time-indexed , therefore ‘having a causal history is not sufficient’ (idem). Human emotionscannotbeunderstoodifwedonottakeintoaccountthespecifichistoryoftheindividual person(deSousa1987:1045).WhyIscreamandcryoverhavinglostanoldworthlesswalletis perhapsbecausethatwallethasaccompaniedmealongtime,orbecauseitwasagiftfromaperson that I care about 28 . The idea of personal history and time will have important bearings on the following;butbeforeturningtomyownaccountofhumanaffectivity,Iwillbrieflytrytoposition Ricoeurinrelationwhathasbeensaidabouttheneurophysiologicaldimensionofemotions. Conatus:Spinoza,Ricoeur,andNeurophysiology AlthoughDamasioandPankseppbothadheretoevolutionaryexplanationsofhumanemotions,it shouldbeclearfromwhathasbeensaidabovethattheirneurophysiologicalexplorationsdonot coincide.Damasioconsiderhumanfeelingstobeperceptionsofbodilychangesthatarethereal emotions,andassuchfeelingsaremeresubjectiveregistrationsofmorefundamentalandobjective emotions.Wehavetounderstandthespecifichumanfeelingsbyclarifyingtheneurphysiological dynamics of bodily emotions (Damasio 2004: 56). Panksepp, on the contrary, resists this methodological separation of feeling and emotions, which he sustains leads to an ontological neglectofbasicaffectivity(Panksepp2005c:160).Emotionsarefeelings,andthatalreadyona purebodilylevel.Consciousnessisaffectiveconsciousness,inhumansaswellasinotheranimals. The cognitive capacities in humans is not ‘addedon’ to the body, but deeply immersed in the affectivitythatcharacterizesthewholeorganism.Wedonotperceiveorreadouttheemotionsand therefore feel in a certain way. On the contrary, affective feelings shape and influence our perception and cognition in such a way that our higher brain functions are always in a certain affectivestate.ThereforePankseppwrites:‘Descartes’sfaithinhisassertion“Ithink,thereforeI am”maybesupersededbyamoreprimitiveaffirmationthatispartofthegeneticmakeupofall mammals:“Ifeel,thereforeIam”’(Panksepp1998:309).

28 Thetemporalandpersonalaspectofinanimatethingsisahotlydebatedtopicincontemporarysocialpsychology, whichgoesunderthename’endowmenteffect’.Peopletendtovaluethingshigheroncetheyareactuallyendowedwith them(seeGoldie2007:111).

132 Despite their differences, Damasio and Panksepp nevertheless resort to the same thinker as the speculative background for their empirical research, namely the Dutch seventeen century philosopher Baruch Spinoza. This is not uncommon among philosophically interested neuroscientists scientists; for example, the neurobiologist JeanPierre Changeux confesses, in a extendeddiscussionwithRicoeur,hisaffectionforSpinoza’smonismandthathehimselfisstriving foranewsynthesisoftheobjectivescienceandsubjectiveexperience(WT:8/14,27/356,31/39). WhatisinterestinghereisthatRicoeurhimselfusestheSpinozianconceptof conatus as a key concept in his theory of subjectivity, and particularly with regard to human affectivity. Ricoeur transcribes conatus as the originating affirmation or attestation (in the later works), that is, the subject’s basic ‘willtolive’ (vouloirvivre) or original willtosayyes. The concept of an originatingaffirmationismorethanjustawilltosurviveandyetevenmorebasicthanrationality (TFA2901/361362).Itisaprimordialenergythatdrivesthesubjecttoattestitsbeingintheworld (FP 46/53). At a first glance, it might seem a wild metaphysical postulate without any serious grounding or possible argument. But if we look at the way that neuroscientists employ this Spinozianheritage,wemightnourishitabitwithsomeplausiblearguments. DamasioistheneuroscientistwhohastreatedtheheritagefromSpinozamostcarefully.Infact,his lastbookispartlydedicatedtodemonstratinghowSpinoza’sphilosophywouldhelpusunderstand thebiologyofthemind(2003:13).Heisparticularlyinterestedinmonisticideathatthemindand thebodyaretwoattributesofthesamesubstance,andfurthermore,thatthehumanmindistheidea ofthehumanbody(2003:12).Butmostofall,itisthenotionofconatusthatattractshisattention because,accordingtohim,itcanbetranslateddirectlyintocurrentbiologicaltermsofgenetically determined dispositions in the brain that seeks both survival and wellbeing (2003:367). The conatusgoeswellwithhissomaticmarkerhypothesisinthesensethattheconatusrenderswellthe emotionalforcespresentat‘thetheatreofthebody’,i.e.,themanifold ofbodilyresponses,that highlight the positive and negative values in the experience of the world. All living organisms endeavor to preserve themselves and, furthermore, optimize pleasure and minimize pain. The conativeforcesarenotconsciousbutworkwiththeanonymousenergyofnaturalwisdomthatisthe product of millions and millions of years of evolution. The conscious, subjective experience of theseanonymousforcesisdescribedinthefollowingway:‘Whentheconsequencesofsuchnatural wisdomaremappedbackinthecentralnervoussystem,subcorticallyandcortically,theresultis feelings,thefoundationalcomponentofourminds’(2003:79).Thisconceptionofconatusasan aggregate of evolutionary forces that automatically drive the organism toward bodily self

133 perseveranceandsatisfaction,whichislaterextendedwithacognitivebrainmapandmentalideas ofthesereactions,thesocalled‘machineryoffeeling’(2003:80),presentsasomewhatdistorting andpoorinterpretationoftheSpinoza’suseoftheconcept.Thehypothesisthatthemindistheidea of the body does not entail that human knowledge is completely tethered to that body. On the contrary,Spinozawritesclearlyinhis Ethics :‘Bodycannotdeterminemindtothink,neithercan minddeterminebodytomotionorrestoranystatedifferentfromthese,ifsuchtherebe’(Spinoza 1955:31;III,pro.2).Now,IdonotwanttogointotheinterpretivedifficultiesofSpinoza,butonly emphasizethattheSpinozianmonismdoesnotnecessarilyleadtotheconclusionthatmentalideas alwaysrecurtobodilystates.Theconatusisageneralendeavororwilltolivethatisirreducibleto themorerestrictedideaofevolutionaryforces.Thisgeneralwilltoliveissurelyinfluencedbythe processofevolution,butthereismoretothenotion,whenweconsiderhumanaffectivity.Ricoeur pointstothisinhisdiscussionwithChangeux.OnehastoreadSpinoza’s Ethics more carefully whentalkingabouthumanaffectivityandthenatureoftheconatus.Thereisadifferentfinalityat stakeinhumanendeavortopreserveitslifesimplybecausethereismoretohumanlifethanthe absenceofdeath.Ricoeuragreestotheideathatconatusisindeed‘[t]heefforttolive–thedesire toexist’(WT229/242)butretainthatwehavetoseethiseffortinrelationtotheideaof‘thegood life’ (WT 228/241). This is somewhat similar to de Sousa’s analyses of remote and proximate explanations.Inordertofullyunderstandhowtheconatusworksinthehumansubject,wehaveto takeintoaccountboththeevolutionaryandpersonalaspectofthesubjectivewilltolive.Wemay havethesameanonymousforcesworkingwithinus,butthesearealwaysexperiencedinrelationto our personal characteristics or biography (Ricoeur would say our ‘existential difference’). The conatusthatdrivesthehumansubjectrelieson,atleast,boththesefactors. Now,inmyopinion,Panksepp’suseofSpinozianmonismismorecongenialtoRicoeur’sideaof theconatus.LikeDamasio,Pankseppsubscribestotheideathatmindandbodyaretwoattributesof thesamesubstance,namelyhisdualaspectmonism(Panksepp2007:232;2005a:23;2005c:163), and he points to this idea as Spinozian (2004b: 412). The neurobiological and psychological propertiesofthebrainareofthesamesubstance,buttheyhavetobeunderstoodfromdifferent perspectives. The neurophysiological investigation must focus on the basic affectivity that is commontoallmammalsandwhichresultsin‘ basic emotionaltendencies’(2006:775).Suchan investigationmightclarifythe‘ethologicalanimalbrain’andthus‘weshouldbeabletoshedlight intocoreemotionaltendenciesbystudyinganimalbrains’(idem).Hefocusesonthe‘intrinsicvalue guides for existence’ (2005a: 22) that characterize all animal affectivity and the consequent

134 behavior.However,hismethodologicalstartingpoint(allmammalshaveaffectivefeelings)allows forwhathecalls‘conativevariants’(2005b:40)inmammalianaffectivityduetothevariationof brainstructuresinthedifferentanimals.Theconatusisnotthesameinhumansasinotheranimals. Wemaysharemanyofthebasicinstinctualfeelings,butthereissomethingmoretoconsiderin human feelings. Such a neurophysiological approach seems to go better with the philosophical treatmentoftheconatusinRicoeur. Ricoeur defines affectivity in the following manner: ‘In a general way, affectivity is the non transparentaspectoftheCogito.Wearerightinsaying“oftheCogito.”Affectivityisstillamode of thought in the widest sense. To feel is still to think, though feeling no longer represents objectivity,butratherrevealsexistence[…]Wecanexpressitotherwisebysayingthatthrough feelingthepersonalbodybelongstothesubjectivityoftheCogito’(FN86/83;cf.FM131/147). Feelingsarethoughts;notadisinterestedcategorizationofobjects,buttherevelationofexistence. Ourthoughtsabouttheworld,theother,andourselvesarequalifiedbyfeelingsinthesensethat affectivity‘personalizesreason’(FM102/118).Theenvironmentbecomesaworldforme;aworld characterizedbyheterogeneousvaluesthatorientmybehavior.Theconatus,mywilltolive,drives metoengagemyselfinmyexistenceinthisworld,butmyaffirmationisalwaysaffectedbythe valuesthatIexperienceinmyaffectiverelationtotheworldandmyownengagement.Now,ifwe consider Panksepp’s neurophysiological model of affectivity as the experience of raw emotional valuesthatcharacterizebasicmammalianinstinctualbehavior,wemightmakeRicoeur’snotionof conatus as originating affirmation more than just a speculative postulate. Panksepp’s empirical studiesargueforabasicmammalianaffectivitythatinfluenceshumanbehavior,becauseourhuman feelings are deeply rooted in a common ethological ground. Our behavior is not qualitatively differentfromtheinstinctiveconductofotheranimals,but,asRicoeurwrites,‘[i]tistheinstinctive conductwhichdecreasesinthecaseofman.Manhasquantitativelymoreinstincts,ifweinclude thenewanxietiesandnewincentiveswhichheinvents,butheislessinstinctiveifwestresshisloss ofunlearnedformsofconduct,spontaneouslyadaptedfromhismilieu’(FN95/91). Ricoeur emphasizes the importance of basic instincts in human behavior, but insists on the increasedquantityofinstinctsinvolvedinhumanlife.Thehumandesireorwilltoliveisdifferent fromthatofotheranimalsbecauseofthemediatednatureoftherelationtotheenvironmentandto itselfasahumansubject.Thehighercognitivehumancapacitiesthatenablethismediaterelation are indeed bound to the ecological life of the subject, which ‘attest to the nonautonomy of knowledge,itsrootednessinexistence[…]Therebyisdiscoverednotonlytheunsurpassablenature

135 oflife,buttheinterferenceofdesirewithintentionality,uponwhichdesireinflictsaninvincible obscurity, an ineluctable partiality’ (FP 458/442). In human emotional experience there always remains‘aninvincibleobscurity’dueto,atleastpartly,theecologicalnatureofhumanlife.We cannot understand human emotions without resorting to general ethological accounts that often includeevolutionaryexplanations.Manyofouremotionsaredrivenby desireswhoseimmediate satisfaction is rendered impossible by the multitude of laws and rules of conduct instantiated throughouttheprocessofcivilization(Goldie2000b:33).Imight,forexample,intenselywantto strikeablowattheidioticcollegewhohasinsultedme;insteadIyellathimandthumpmycup downonthetableandleavetheroom.Ihavemomentarilyventedmyanger,butImayremainwith afeelingthatafistinhisfacewouldhavebeenamoreappropriateexpressionofmyanger.Itwould not,however,bethemostappropriateinthegivencontext,sinceIwouldproperlyloosemyjoband perhapsevenfacealawsuit.Theseimmediatereactionsmightfindtheirexplanationinsomebasic affectivitythatgeneratesinstinctualmammalianbehavior.Humanemotions,however,containmore thanthesebasicaffectivefeelings.Andwecannotexplainthemonlywithanarcheologicalsurvey intothemammalianbrainsystems.Ricoeurthereforecallsoutforadialecticsofarcheologyand teleologyastheadequateapproachtohumanemotionalexperience(above,pp.625).Thecomplex nature of human emotions is related to the larger quantity of human instincts generated by the symbolic nature of our interaction with the world and other human subjects. Our emotional behaviorisinfluencedbythepeculiar,proximateteleologythatgovernshumanexistence,namely theinscriptioninasocietywithotherhumansubjects.Andfurther,wedonotjustwanttolive amongothersubjects;wewanttoberecognizedasaselfbyotherselves(inourpursuitof‘thegood life’,ofhappiness).Thisteleologyofrecognitionisindeedrootedinand,toacertaindegree,shaped bytheorganicnatureofourbeing,butsomehowitrebelsagainsttheorganicnatureoflife.Ricoeur writes: ‘No doubt the passion to achieve recognition goes beyond the animal struggle for self preservationordomination;theconceptofrecognitionisnotastruggleforlife;itisastruggleto tearfromtheotheranavowal,anattestation,aproofthatIamanautonomousselfconsciousness, Butthisstruggleforrecognitionisastruggleinlifeagainstlife–bylife[…]Thisisthesensein which desire is both surpassed and unsurpassable. The positing of desire is mediated, not eradicated;itisnotaspherethatwecouldlayaside,annul,annihilate’(FP4712/4556). Ricoeur’s use of the Spinozian concept of conatus is not contrary to or hostile toward a neurophysiological approach grounded in an evolutionary theory. On the contrary, Ricoeur emphasizesthebasicmammalianaffectivefeelingspresentinhumanemotionalexperience(e.g.the

136 struggle forsurvivalandtheseekingofpleasureandavoidanceofpain).Whathedoescontest, however,isthereductionofhumanemotionstothe regulationofphysiologicalresponsesinthe body.Thereisanotherkindofteleologyatplayinhumanemotionalexperience,namelythedesire for recognition. We want to be part of a human society as well as staying alive. Our emotional behavioristhereforeconditionedandarticulatedbyourexistenceinthatsocietyalongsidewiththe organicvaluesofourbiologicallife.Furthermore,humanshavethecapacityforsingularreference whichmeansthattheobjectsofhumanemotionsoftenareofanonfungiblenature.Wecareabout singularobjectandindividuals,andbecauseofthisourfeelingsaremuchmoredifferentiatedand complex than those of other animals. Some of the obscure and seemly irrational features of emotionalexperiencemayverywellfindtheirexplanationintheevolutionaryforcespresentinour basicaffectiverelationtotheenvironment.Andaclarificationoftheneurophysiologyofemotions mayhelpusunderstandwhywesometimesfeelandactirrationally.Thebodyhasitsownreasons that deeply influence our being in the world, and therefore one should not underestimate the embodiednatureofemotions.But,asSolomonrightlypointedout,thisisonlypartofthestory. Althoughwemightbedrivenbythesameconatusasotheranimals,thereareimportantdifferences (‘conativevariants’asPankseppcallthem)whenitcomestohumanaffectivity.Thesevariantsor differences are mainly due to the higher cognitiveskillspresentinhumans,andwhichmightbe characterizedbywhatdeSousanames‘fullfledgedmentalintentionality’togetherwiththefactthat humanshaveabiographyandtimeindexeddesires(deSousa1987:100). Intheconcludingsections,Iwilltrytopresentanapproachtohumanaffectivitythataccountfor thedifficultiesdiscussedabove.ItwillonlybeanoutlineoftheorythatIhavearguedforinmore detailelsewhere 29 .Whatisimportantinthepresentcontextistoshowwhyanarticulationofhuman affectivityisimportantfortherelationbetweensubjectivityandethics.

29 Iampresently(from2005)workingtogetherwiththepsychiatristGiovanniStanghellinionatheoryofemotionsthat seekstocombineaphilosophicalandpsychopathologicalapproachtohumanemotionalexperience.Wehavewrittena forthcomingarticle(RosfortandStanghellini,forthcoming)andarecurrentlyworkingonotherthreearticlesaboutthe HeideggerianconceptofBefindlichkeit,thehistoricalimplicationsoftheconceptofmood,andtherelationbetween personhoodandtheembodiednatureofemotions.Thesearticlesaregoingtobethegroundworkforacoauthoredbook (Emotions and Personhood: A Philosophical and Psychopathological Exploration). I owe many of the following argumentsfromthiscollaboration,bothfromlongdiscussionsathishouse,intrains,athisseminars,attheDepartment ofPsychologyatTheUniversityofChieti,Italy,andfinallyfromhisbooks(Stanghellini1992,1997,2004,2007).I havechosennottoincludehisextensiveworkonpsychopathologyinthefollowinganalyses,becausethiswouldmake theargumentsmoredifficultandthereforemorethepresentationlesspoignant.However,mytreatmentofmoodsand affectdrawssubstantiallyonargumentsfromourforthcomingarticlementionedabove.

137 Emotions and Personhood: Moods and Affects. Itistimetonarrowdowntheconceptofaffectivityandlookmorecloselyonwhatispeculiarabout humanaffectivity.DeSousahasrecentlyobservedthat‘[b]eyondthe‘coresystems’describedby Panksepp,thesetofemotionsthateachofusiscapableofexperiencingare,likethebeliefwehold, bothpotentiallyinfiniteand,intheirtotality,uniquetoeachindividual’(deSousa2007b:329).As wehaveseen,humanaffectivityhasmuchincommonwiththatofotheranimals;nonetheless,the behavioralneuroscientistT.M.Preusscallsforcaution when we observe ethological similarities amongmammalsbecause‘[e]venignoringourintellectualabilitiesandculturalaccretions,people aremostpeculiarbeasts’(Preuss2004:5).Andthemainreasonwhyhumanaffectivityisdrastically differentis,becausehumanbeingsarepersonsotherthanbeingpartofaphylogenicalstaircase.The concept of emotion and the concept of a person have to be considered as parts of the same experience.Humanemotionalexperiencecannotbeunderstoodwithoutconsideringthenatureof thebeingthathasthisparticularexperience.Thismeansthattheconceptiononehasoftheperson willinfluenceone’sviewofemotions,andviceversa.Althoughemotionsoccurinmostanimals, someemotionsareparticularlyhumansuchasshame,resentment,delusion,pride,sadness,love, guilt, hopelessness, euphoria, and so on. As Charles Taylor observes: ‘The peculiarity of these emotionsisthatitisatoneandthesametimethecasethatourformulationsareconstitutiveofthe emotion, and that these formulations can be right or wrong’ (1981: 101). Especially when interpersonalemotions(suchasshameorguilt)areconcerned,whattheyaretoapersondepends significantlyonwhatthatpersontakesthemtobe.Notonlyisourunderstandingoftheemotions that we experience constitutive of the emotion itself, but also our understanding of ourselves is constitutiveoftheemotion.Furthermore,ifourunderstandingofanemotioncanberightorwrong, thenthisentailsthatemotionstellussomethingaboutourselvesaspersons,aboutoursituationand our behavior (and its motivations). But now I will first briefly define some of the fundamental aspectsofpersonhoodasIseeit. Personhood IconcludedabovethatDamasio’sconceptionoftheselfisoversimplified(althoughheclaimsitnot tobethecase(RudraufandDamasio2005:239)),becauseitreducestheselftoalivingsystemin time and space primarily controlled by what Harry Frankfurt once called ‘firstorder desires’ or ‘wantons’(1971).Ourmindisthusreducedtoacomplexsurvivalmachine,intrinsicallyelaborated during evolution, wherein our body highlights the most favorable options in the process of our

138 decisionmaking.However,thereismoretothesenseofselfthanjustperseveranceorimmediate desires.Indeed,wehaveto want tobetheselfthatourorganismorotherpeopletellusthatweare. Frankfurt points, once again, to the fact that humans are peculiar beasts: “They are capable of wantingtobedifferent,intheirpreferencesandpurposes,fromwhattheyare[…]Noanimalother thanman,however,iscapabletohavethecapacityforreflectiveselfevaluationthatismanifested in the formation of secondorder desires” (1971: 7). To be a person involves the capability for evaluatingtheidentityandchangethatconstituteone’stemporalandsituatedself. Invirtueofourreflectiveselfevaluation,wedistanceourselvesfromourimmediatedesiresand inclinations,andmightperhapschoosesomethingevencontrarytothosebecauseofanotherdesire orasenseofduty,shaped,forinstance,byimaginationoremanatedfromafirmprinciple.Thereby, wecreateasecondorderdesirethatiscompletelypersonalandmayevenappearidioticintheeyes ofotherpeople.Forexample,apersonwhocommitssuiciderevoltsagainstanorganicinclination tolive,againstallpossiblerationalargumentsabout the incomparable value of life and perhaps evenagainstherorhisowndesiretolive.Wecanbeangry,condemntheact,remainwithoutan explanation(‘sheseemedtohavealltheheartcandesire’),butitwouldnevercrossourmindsto contest her personhood because of her decision. In fact, Ricoeur argued that the autonomy of decision is a structural capacity of the subject, because we are able to ‘designate in emptiness’ (désigner à vide); the human subject is structurally pure possibility, although some possibilities mightbeabsurd(abovepp.29,FN43/42).Thus,tobeapersonisnotessentiallytoberational,but to have a will (Frankfurt1971:11;cf.Blackburn1998:65).Wearepersonsbecausewearecapable tochoosetobewhatwewanttobe.Althoughthismayseemanobscurereminiscenceofexistential philosophythatgoesagainstintuitionandthelawsofbiophysics(forexample,amanwhowantto be a woman because he feels thatheisawomancapturedinaman’sbody),this capacity still prevailsasafundamentalcharacteristicofbeingaperson 30 . A person is a contextualized and situated self with intentional attitudes, characterized by ontologicalfragility(above,pp.502)andcapableofselfevaluation,asopposedtoaminimalself (GallagherandMarcel1999;Zahavi2005)oracoreself(Damasio1994,1999;Russell2005).The reasonforthisisthat‘[der]MenschistalsPersonimmerschonein‘homoduplex’.Erstehtsich selbst gegenüber und wird sich fragwürdig; er steht auf eine Bühne vor seinesgleichen und schwanktzwischenSeinundSchein’(Fuchs2002b:144).Theterm‘homoduplex’wasoriginally

30 AsGoldiepointsout(referringtoAugustin):‘Hewantsto want tobeotherthanthewayheis’(2004:109).

139 elaboratedbythe19 th centuryFrenchphilosopherMainedeBrian 31 ina contextwhereinmanis seenasasinglenatureinhisvitalstatesofbeingbutasadouble(orcomplex)natureinbelonging to humanity. We are passive in our nature as sentient beings because we are shaped by our physiologicalnature,environment,andpasthistory.Yet,weareactiveinvirtueofbeingpersons. Ontheonehand,weareapartofnature,andthereforenaturesetsaprereflectiveagendaforour behavior in the form of instincts and emotions (an affective core SELF endowed with basic instinctualbehavior);inshort,anextremelycomplexmachinesettosolvetheproblemsencountered duringourlifetimeintheongoinginteractionwiththeenvironment.Ontheotherhand,asRicoeur pointsout,‘[m]orefundamentallymanisabeingwhoposesproblemsandraisesquestions–ifonly bybringingintoquestiontheveryfoundationsofthatsocietythatbidshimtoadapthimselfquietly toitssystemsofwork,property,law,leisureandculture’(FM101/117;cf.FN2279/2134).Our being this‘double’person,endowedwithaspecificphysicalconstitutionandsituatedinacertain historical,social,andculturalcontext,iscomplicatedevenfurtherwhenweconsiderourcapacityto transcend our being this person by questioning it. Notonlydo wequestionourbeingapartof nature and the social and cultural context wherein we are situated, we also question our own identityasbeingthisparticularperson,constitutedbyacertainphysicalconstitution,pasthistory, presentenvironment,andcharacter. Being this specific person might be a problem to me (remember that Ricoeur characterizes personhoodasatask,notafact(FM61/86)).Imay feel thatIamdifferentfromwhatIappeartobe. Thisoftenbeginswithadiffusebutpertinentfeeling,whichslowlydevelopsintoaconvictionthat thepersonIappeartobedoesnotexpressthepersonwhoIreallyam.Wemightsaythattheperson issituatedinthedynamicdialecticof‘being’( Sein )and‘appearingtobe’( Schein )32 .Becauseof the fundamental possibility of wanting to be different, we always evaluate our being and our 31 Thefullsentencegoes‘Homosimplexinvitalitate,duplexinhumanitate’andis,asmentioned,quotedseveraltimes byRicoeur(e.g.FN228/213,249/234;FM91/107)torecallthedramaticdualismthatweexperienceasadailyreality. 32 NietzscheandKierkegaardhavededicatedmuchoftheirworktothisproblem.Kierkegaardwriteseloquently: ‘Personhoodisasynthesisofpossibilityandnecessity.Itscontinuedexistenceislikebreathing( re spiration),whichis aninhalingandexhaling.Theselfofthedeterministcannotbreathe,foritisimpossibletobreathenecessityexclusively, because that would utterly suffocate a person’s self’ (Kierkegaard 1983: 40/172). The philosopher Arne Grøn has workedmuchonthisthemeinKierkegaard(e.g.2004a):‘Inseekingtoaccountfortheembodiedandembeddednature of human consciousness we have in various ways encountered a remarkable feature of the human being, a double characterora redoubling :toexististobeinaprocessofbecoming and torelatetooneselfinthisprocess’(34);orsaid otherwise:‘weareheterogeneoustoourselves,andouridentityasunityisaproblemtoourselves’(43n).Nietzsche,on theotherhand,hasemphasizedtheinterestingdialecticof‘being’and‘appearingtobe’inthedevelopmentoftheself, e.g.:‘ How appearance becomes being […]Ifsomeoneobstinatelyandforalongtimewantsto appearsomethingitis intheendhardforhimto be anythingelse’(Nietzsche1986/1954a:39/487,§51);orashewriteselsewhere:‘Whatare ourexperiences,then?Muchmorewhatweattributetothemthanwhattheyreallyare.Orshouldweperhapssaythat nothing is contained in them? that experiences in themselves are merely works of fancy?’ (Nietzsche 2007/1954b: 128/1096,§119).

140 appearingtobe,and,insomewayoranother,relateourselvestoourselvesinthisdialectic.Tobea personisanormativematter. FeelingsofBeingintheWorld Thefundamentalwayofbeingsituatedintheworld is,beforeitbecomesanexplicitthemefor rationalthinking,being inagivenfeelingoremotional tonality. One approach to the normative characterofpersonhoodistoinvestigateintothisimplicitfeelingoremotionaltonalityofhuman existence;thisentails,aswewillsee,lookingattheworkingsofmoodsandaffects. FeelingsaretheprimordialmediuminwhichIencountertheworldasasetof affordances :asetof relevantpossibilitiesthataremyownpossibilitiesasanembodiedpersonsituatedinthisparticular world. This being situated in a world of possibilities through certain feelings is described by Heidegger as Befindlichkeit (1996:126131/13440);atermthatcombinesthenotion of location (finding oneself somewhere) and that of being in a certain feeling or attunement (the English translationoftheGerman Stimmung ).Itisequallywrongtosaythatacertainthingintheworld causes a specific feeling (e.g . that a wild animal causes fear) or that a certainfeeling colors my perceptionoftheworld(e.g.anxietycausesmetoseeastickasasnake).Thereisnocausalrelation between perception and feelingstate, or vice versa. Both feeling and perception find their explicative correlate in the actual and concrete situation of theperson. We feel andperceive the worldinacertainwaybecauseofourbeingintheworld( In-der-Welt-sein ).Themainforceofthe concept of Befindlichkeit might be that it emphasizes the work of feeling as a disclosure (Erschliessen ) of one’s embedded and situated relation to the world and oneself, and not an impedimenttoobjectivelyappreciateacertainstateofthings.Thesignificanceofaneventorstate ofaffairsisnotmerelyamatterofitsintrinsicproperties,ratherofitsrelationtomyconcernforand currentengagementintheworld,theotherandmyself.Feelingstatesrevealhowtheworldis for me . The concept of Befindlichkeit is closely tied to that of understanding (Verstehen), which Heidegger has spent much of his work to argue for. He writes, for example: ‘Attunement [Befindlichkeit] always has its understanding, even if only by surpressing it. Understanding is alwaysattuned[gestimmtes]’(Heidegger1996:134/142).Wecanonlyunderstandourselvesand theworldinwhichwearesituatedthroughthecontextofourpracticalengagement,and,aswehave seen,thisengagementisprimordiallyenvelopedinacertainfeeling.Thiswayoflookingatfeeling has fundamental implications for the understanding of emotional experience that will be best

141 appreciated if we first discuss the relation betweenfeelingsandemotionsandthenthatbetween moodsandaffects. FeelingsandEmotions Insteadoffightingoneanother,thefeelingtheoriesandthecognitivetheoriesshouldlearnfromone another 33 .Emotionsarerootedinbothphysiologicalreactionsandpsychologicalphenomena.On theonehand,‘emotionsarebioregulatoryreactionsthataimatpromoting,directlyorindirectly,the sortofphysiologicalstatesthatsecurenotjustsurvivalbutsurvivalregulatedintotherangethatwe, consciousandthinkingcreatures,identifywithwellbeing’(Damasio2004:50).Ontheotherhand, ‘[o]necanbeangrywithoutfeelinganythinginparticular,withoutdoinganythinginparticularand withoutdisplayinganyphysiologicalsymptomsofauniquesyndromeforthatemotion’andthereby the feeling theories ‘ignore what might be called subjectivity , one’s viewpoint and what one experiences–otherthansensationsandtheirlike–whenheorshehasanemotion’(Solomon1977: 44).Although I doubtiffeelingscan everbecompletely absent, Solomon is right, however, in pointingtothefactthatanemotionisnotalwaysboundtotheebbsandflowsofthebioregulatory reactions of our body, but is constituted by subjectivity as well as physiology. The following approach to human affectivity employs important insights from both the cognitive and feeling theories,butdiffersfromthesebytheemphasisontheconceptofpersonhoodasfundamentalto humanemotionalexperience. Emotions are kinetic, dynamic forces that drive us in our ongoing interactions with the environment.Thisdefinitionofemotionfocusesontheembodiednatureofemotions,butrejectsits reduction of the body to the objectbody or physiological mechanism (e.g. visceral changes registered by higher cognitive brain systems). It obviously also rejects the conceptualization of emotions as pure mental phenomena since an emotion is not a purely and primarily cognitive phenomenon affecting the mind, but a phenomenon rooted in one’s lived body, and it can to a certain extent be subconscious (Prinz 2005: 1518; Pankseep 2005b: 613). One might say that emotions are characterized by their connection to motivation and movement . Emotions are functionalstatesthatmotivateandtherebyproduce(orhindercertain)movements.Asfunctional

33 Thisis,infact,becomingmorefrequentinthephilosophicalresearchonemotions.Aswehaveseenabove(note19), Solomonhas,inhislaterresearch,cometoconsiderfeelingsanimportantpartoftheotherwisecognitiveemotions.And Goldie, who is emphasizing the feeling aspect of emotions, considers intentionality fundamental in at least some feelingsthathecalls‘feelingtowards’(2000a:5862).However,thedichotomystillexistsandmoreworkhastobe doneinordertosortoutthecomplexrelationbetweencognitiveandfeelingaspectsofemotionalexperience.

142 states that motivate certain movements (and check others), emotions are closely connected to dispositionsinthesensethattheydisposethepersoninafeltreadinessorimpedimentforaction. Feelingsmakeupacrucialpartofemotionalexperiencebut,aswehaveseen,thereisdisagreement about how they do so. James identifies feeling with emotion (1884: 190), and yet Solomon distinguishesthetwobysayingthatwecanexperienceanemotionwithoutfeeling.Still,todetach feelingfromemotionincludestherisktooverintellectualize emotion (Goldie 2000a: 41). If we consider an emotion structured as a feelingless judgment about the world, then we loose an importantcriteriaofdistinctionbetweenactionsdoneoutofemotionandactionsnotdoneoutof emotion.Forexample,ajudgeshouldbeabletotreatapersonregardlessofhowshefeelsabout him.Onlytherebycanwesaythatitwasasentencebuiltonjustcausesandnotonthepersonal feelingsofthejudge.Thefeelingdimensionofemotion is what permits to distinguish emotion amongothercognitivefunctions(perception,deliberation,evaluation,judging,etc.).However,the distinction between emotion and other cognitive functions is often blurred by the fact that it is difficulttoascertainwhetheranactionisdonewithorwithoutanemotion.Emotionsimmersethe othercognitivefunctionsintheircomplexmovementwhenevertheyappear.Thejudgeisperhaps repudiatedbytheappearanceoftheaccusedorbyhisword.Orshemaybeinanirritablemood withoutbeingabletoputherfingeronwhatexactlyitisdueto.Andbothoftheseemotionsmight influenceherfinalsentence.Ofcourse,agoodjudgeisonewhoisabletosetasidethesepersonal aspects.Nonetheless,thefactthatisdifficulttobeagoodjudgerevealssomethingimportantabout the feelings of emotions, namely that they tend to impose themselves on all our thoughts and actions.Feelingsareaconstitutivepartofallemotionalexperience,althoughhowanemotionfeels mayremainvaguetothesubject.Inordertodifferentiateamongdifferentemotionalexperiences, weneedtotakeacloserlookonthefeelingsthattheycause.Feelingis,inmyopinion,thebestway torevealthatweareinacertainemotionalstate. Onereasonwhythefeelingdimensionofemotionisimportantisbecauseemotionscanbeboth consciousandsubconscious.Consciousemotionstakeup,byvirtueoftheirintentionalattitude,a substantialpartofourattentioninagivensituation.Forexample,Ichoosenottoundressmyselfin frontofotherpeoplebecauseIfeelembarrassed.Unconsciousemotions,onthecontrary,arenot direct objects in our attentional field. They manifest themselves through certain feelings. These feelingscanbevagueandopaque(asinthecaseofmoods;seebelow).However,thefeelingsthat anemotioncausesareanessentialcomponentoftheemotionitself,sincewe,aspersons,needto

143 acknowledgethesefeelingsinordertofullyaccesstheemotion 34 .Forinstance,ourgoodjudgemay beina‘badmood’thedayofthetrial.Thisisindeedaveryvagueconstellationoffeelings.Her bodyfeelsheavierthanusualandthesunlightisannoying.Thecoffeetastesstrange,andeventhe smallestobstacle,suchasabindingdoor,leavesherexasperated.Butalthoughtheexpression‘bad mood’mightseeminnocentandinsignificantitis,however,wrongtosay(asRatcliffedoes,2005: 55)thatthisisarathersuperficialsubjectivestate.Indeed,beingina‘badmood’ofteninvolves profound feelings that reveal oneself asbeing in a certain dispositional state and readiness to a (althoughstillimplicit)givenaction.Weshouldnotletourrathercasualuseofwordsobscurethe importanceofmoods,because,asRylewrites,‘[m]oodwordsareshorttermtendencywords,but theydifferfrommotivewords[i.e.inclinations],notonlyintheshorttermoftheirapplication,but in their use in characterizing the total ‘set’ of apersonduringthatshortterm.Somewhatasthe entireshipiscruisingsoutheast,rolling,orvibrating,sotheentirepersonisnervous,serene,or gloomy’(Ryle1949:100). Furthermore,theconstellationoffeelingsinvolvedinanemotionalexperiencemaycontainmore orlessexplicitcognitiveelements.Thefeelingsinvolvedinfear,forexample,mayblockourhigher cognitiveskillsinordertopromotetheimmediateinstincttoflightfromtheobjectthatcausesthe emotion(e.g.Panksepp’sbasicaffectiveinstincts).Insadness,however,feelingsandcognitionare moreintrinsicallyintertwined.Thefeelingsarebothsubjectandobjectforourreflections.Weare sadbecausewefeelsad,butthethoughtsinvolvedinoursadnessmayenhanceordiminishour feelingofsadness. Andfinally,timeplaysafundamentalroleinthe feelingsinvolvedin anemotionalexperience. Whereas some feelings are more or less instantaneous (panic, joy, sexual arousal), others are prolonged(grief,hatred,boredom). In order to access these emotional states we need to pay attention to the diffuse and vague constellation of feelings involved in our interaction with the world. This is not an easy job. Nevertheless,Ibelievethatbysortingoutthemaincharacteristicsofthedifferentfeelingsinvolved in two main emotional states, moods and affects, we gain an effective tool to close up on an understandingofhowthepersonlives,experiences andunderstandstheiremotionalstates.Both moodsandaffectare characterizedbytheconstellationoffeelingsinvolvedintheexperienceof

34 Prinzarguesconvincinglyforunconsciousemotions(2004:2015).However,heinsistsonrelatingtheseexclusively to‘corerelationalthemes’regardingbasic‘dangersandgoalattainment’thatonceagainpointtoadistantevolutionary teleologyorexplicitculturalinfluences.I,onthecontrary,shallarguethatunconsciousemotionssuchasmoodsplaya muchmoreproximateandsubtleroleintheperson’slife.

144 them,andananalysisofthephenomenologyofthesefeelingsenablesabetterunderstandingofthe emotion,itsinfluenceontheperson,and,finally,ofthenatureofpersonhooditself.

MoodsandAffects Phenomenologistshavecontributedtoexplainingthisdistinctioninanexplicitandsystematicway (for an overview see Strasser 1977, Smith 1986, and Fuchs 2000). This distinction is merely incipientinHusserl’swritingsandisafterwardsmadeexplicitbyScheler(1912;1916),Heidegger (1996), Sartre (1939), Ricoeur (FN; FM), Stephan Strasser (1977), and Thomas Fuchs (2000): whereasaffectsareresponsestoaphenomenonthatisgraspedastheirmotivation,moodsdonot possesssuchdirectednesstoamotivatingobject.Althoughtheirterminologydiffers,andthatoften confusingly (Scheler: Affekten/Gefühlen; Heidegger: Affekten/Stimmungen; Sartre: affects/emotions; Ricoeur: sentiments schematizes/ sentiments informes; Strasser: Emotionen/Stimmungen),theiranalysesofthephenomenaconcurinthegeneralcharacteristics(see Table1below). Affectsarefocused,intentional,andpossessdirectedness.Affectsarefeltasmotivated;theyare moredeterminatethanmoodsandmorearticulated.Affectsdonotopenupahorizontalawareness, butoccupyallmyattentionalspace(e.g.infearIamcompletelyabsorbedbythephenomenonthat terrifiesme).WhenIamaffected,arelevantfeatureoftheworldcaptivatesme,irruptsintomyfield ofawarenesswithoutmehavingdecidedtoturnmyattentiontoit.Ibecomespellboundtoitandall myattentioniscapturedbyit.Typicalexamplesofcaptivatingaffectsaregrief(whenthedeathofa belovedpersonoccupiesallmyattentionalspace)orphobias. Moods,onthecontrary,areunfocusedandnonintentional.Theydonotpossessdirectednessand aboutness.Theyarefeltasunmotivated,andthere are no ‘felt causes’ for them. They are more indefinite and indeterminate than affects and are often inarticulate. Moods have a horizontal absorptioninthesensethattheyattendtotheworldasawhole,notfocusingon anyparticular object or situation (cf. Ricoeur’s ‘fundamental feeling’ (FM 105/121)). Moods often manifest themselves as prolonged feelingstates as opposed to the more instantaneous nature of affect 35 . Whereasmostaffectsfillupthewholefieldofawarenessforabriefperiod(forexampleinfearor anger),moodsconveyaconstellationofvaguefeelingsthatpermeatemywholefieldofawareness, andtheyoftenlastforalongerperiodthanaffects.

35 In fact, Russell’s neuropsychological account of core affect (“the simplest raw (nonreflective) feelings evident in moodsandemotions”)definesmoodsas“prolongedcoreaffect”(2003:147148).

145 Moodsareglobalfeelingstatesthatdonotfocusonanyspecificobjectinmyfieldofawareness. Whenweareinacertainmoodwerelateourselvestotheworldandtoourownperson through that mood(FM1312/148).Ineuphoriatheperceptionofmybodyisfeebleandmayevenvanish.Ifeel absorbed in my concerns; my selfawareness, my body, and the world fuse together in perfect harmony.Insadnesstheperceptionofmybodycomestotheforeground;Imayfeelmybodyasan obstacle,ahindranceseparatingmefromtheworldandperhapsevenfrommyself(Fuchs2002a: 123).Thus,moodsareatmosphericandoftencorporealinthattheypermeatemyperceptionofthe environment.Theycanbringmeclosertoordistancemefromtheworldinthattheyelicitacertain atmospherethatbecomesthetonalitythroughwhichIperceivetheworldandmyself.WhenIam feelinghappy,theworldandotherpersonsappearinasoftlightofpossibilityandopenness;Ifeel differentlywhenIamjealous.Inthiscase,thingsappearasprowlingperils;eventhemostsincere smilemightbeperceivedasfalseanddangeroustomyperson(Smith1986:1314). Animportantaspectofmoodsisthatinvirtueofbeingprolongedandpervasivefeelingstates,they are dispositional in nature and may develop into character traits: “our traits are shaped by our emotionsandmoods,justasouremotionsandmoodsareshapedbyourtraits”(Goldie2000a:141). GoldiehereputsforwardaninterestingdialecticthatIwillreturntointheendofthissection. Thetablebelowroughlyresumesthemaincharacteristicsofmoodsandaffectsinsuchawaythat theiroppositionalnaturebecomesclear. Table 1 36 Mood and affect Mood Affect Unfocused Focused Nonintentional Intentional Notmotivated Motivated Inarticulate Articulate Horizontalabsorption Nohorizontalabsorption Emanatedfrom,notby Emanatedfromandby Nocaptivation Captivation No‘feltcauses’ ’Feltcauses’

36 Adapted, with modifications, from the descriptions in Smith (1986: 10946). Recently an interesting empirical investigationonhow106nonacademicpeopledistinguishedbetweenemotionandmood(hereIprefertheterm‘affect’ to‘emotion’,butthecharacteristicscoincide)producedaresultverysimilartothetablepresentedhere.(Beedie,Terry, andLane2005:817).

146 Indefiniteandindeterminate Determinate NodirectednessDirectedness Sustained Instantaneous Examplesofmoodsasopposedtoaffectsareanxietyasopposedtofear,sadness(asopposedto) grief,euphoria/joy,dysphoria/anger,tedium/boredom. ThereislittleworkdoneonmoodsintheAngloSaxonphilosophicaltradition.Thetreatmentof moodsisoftenreducedtoperipheralmentioninginlargeranalysesofemotions 37 .Onemightsay thatmoodsarenotconsideredtobeaseriousphilosophicalmatter,butfairlysuperficialfeeling states38 . If they are mentioned, their main characteristics concur with the phenomenological account,namelyanobjectlessphenomenon(foropposingviews:Kenny1963:6062;Crane1998: 23846;Goldie2000a:14351).However,thefactremainsthatmoodsareoftentreatedasopposed toemotion(e.g.Blackburn1998:130,deSousa1987:311)sothatthedistinctionisnotmoodvs. affect,butmoodvs.emotion.Ibelieve,however,thatifwetreatbothmoodandaffectsasdifferent constellationsoffeelingswithintheemotionalexperience,thenitenhancesthepossibilitytopursue anunderstandingofthedialecticaltransitionsbetweenthetwophenomenaandtheirsignificancefor theperson.Whereasaffectsseemtoenjoyafirmdefinitionbecauseoftheirobjectdirectednature, moods(duetotheirdisorientedandhazyphenomenality)donotenjoythesameprivilege.Itcan thereforebeofhelptoelaboratemorethoroughlyontheprincipalcharacteristicsintherelationto theconceptofaperson. Averygeneraldefinitionofmyuseofthetermemotionmightbelikethis.Iuseemotionsasan ‘umbrella’ term that describes what is known as emotional experience. This experience is characterizedbydifferentconstellationsoffeelingsthatrangefrombrief,clearaffectsatoneendto longer,morediffusemoodsattheother.Whatweexperienceasdifferentemotionslieswithinthese twoextremesandcanbecategorizedaccordingtothenatureofthefeelingsinvolved(intentionality, temporality,andcognitiveelementsevidencedbynarrativestructures).Butmoreaboutthisinthe following.

37 AninterestingexceptionisGilbertRyle’ssuccinctanalysisofmoodsinemotionalexperienceinhisThe Concept of Mind (1949:98104). 38 ThephilosophicaltreatmentofmoodsoftencoincideswiththeattitudeoftheinfluentialpsychologistPaulEkman:‘I arguedthatemotionsarenecessaryforourlives,andwewouldn’twanttoberidofthem.Iamfarlessconvincedthat moodsareofanyusetous.Moodsmaybeanunintended consequence of our emotion structures, not selected by evolutionbecausetheyareadaptive’(2003:501).

147 ThePersonbetweenMoodsandAffects Moods and affects are oppositional extremes in the person’s emotional experience and are characterized by different constellations of feelings and by different temporal, intentional, and narrative patterns. In the previous section, I have enlisted the principal phenomenological characteristicsoffeelingsinvolvedinthesetwokindsofemotionalexperience.Inthisfinalsection, I shall put these characteristics of emotional experiences in relation to the concept of a person outlinedabove.Thiswillbedoneaccordingtothreefundamentalaspectsoftheconceptofaperson thatwerealsoemphasizedbyRicoeur:intentionality,temporalityandnarrativeidentity. a)Intentionality Intentionalityis,aswehaveseen,theaspectofamentalstatetobe‘of’or‘about’something.The standardphenomenologicalviewonmoodsandaffectsismoreorlessclearononefundamental difference:moodsareunintentionalandaffectsintentional.AsStrasser,whohasworkedoutarich anddetailedphenomenologicalanalysisoffeelings, writes: ‘We must therefore distinguish more carefullythanusualbetweenanirritated,angry,happyoranguishedmood[Stimmung]ontheone hand,andbeingirritated,angry,happy about something ,beinganxious over something ontheother. In the first case, irritation is “in the air” without the conscious apprehension of any motive for irritation.Inthesecondcase,wearedirected,inthemodeoffeelingirritation,towardsomething: beingirritatedherehasanobjectthatisintentionally“meant”[…]weshallunderstandbymood only the felt state of mind [Befindlichkeit], pure beinginamood […] mood must be carefully distinguishedfromdirectedfeelings’(Strasser1977:183/111.Translationslightlymodified).This view,however,maybemodifiedbyrelatingthetwofeelingstatestotheperson.Itiscorrecttosay thatanaffectasfearisabouttheparticularobjectoffear(e.g.thebear),andthatananxiousmood doesnotpointtoanyspecificintentionalobject,butmanifestsitselfasanunarticulatedbackground tonalityoratmospherethatpervadesmywholefieldofawareness.Nevertheless,mymoodseemsto affectthewayIrelatetotheworldinthesensethatitisaccompaniedbyacertainatmosphereinmy perceptions. A situation that beforehand would not intimidate me at all now fills me with an irresistible desire to run away and look for protection. The feelings involved in the intentional attitude of my affects are indeed changed by my current mood. My mood is expressed by how perceptionsorthoughtsaffectme.MoodsmaterializeinaffectsinthatIamaffected through my mood.Thismaysuggesta covert intentionality inmoods.Whereasaffectshaveadirectandclear intentional object (an object of perception or a thought), moods are characterized by multiple

148 objects 39 . Whereas affectspoint to an explicit experience suchasadangeroussituation,ahappy smile,abeautifullandscape,adifficulttasketc.,moods,onthecontrary,pointtomybeingthe person I amin a given situation.Moodscanbecompared with what Ricoeur calls ‘ontological sentiments’inthat‘[t]hey denotethefundamental feeling […], namely, man’s very openness to being’(FM105/120). Wecansaythatwhereasaffects point outward towards a specific object, moodspoint inward towardsmybeingthepersonIam.Moreprecisely,onecouldsaythatmoods containa bipolar intentionality inthesensethattheyoftenmaterializeinacertainaffectduetoan explicit object, but at the same time point to my being the person I am, and thereby awake questions,doubts,considerations,evaluations,andfinallydeliberationsaboutmybeingthisperson. Moodsandaffectsinteractbymeansofthepersonwhohastheemotionalexperiences.Onewayto distinguishamoodfromanaffectand,perhapsevenmoreimportantly,tounderstandthedialectic betweentheminrelationtotheperson,istoconsiderthetemporalityoffeelings. b)Temporality Theconceptoftemporalityisunderstoodashowthepersonexperiencestimeandhowtheexistence ofthepersonisinevitablyformedanddevelopedin time. Temporality is, therefore, a subjective modalityoftheconceptoftime;itistimeconsideredaconstitutivepartofboththebeingandthe subjective experience of the person. The person changes through time and experiences how the world,otherpeopleandherselfchangeintime.Temporalityisnottimeasanexclusivelyprivate (solipsistic)orpurecosmological(objective)phenomenon,butbothtimeasexperiencedandlived bythepersonandtimeasworkingonandwiththeperson. Moodsandaffectsdisplaydifferenttemporalpatterns.Affectsareoftenbrieferthanmoods.They captivateme,occupymywholefieldofawarenessandtherebymovemetoadeterminateaction withinarestrictedperiodoftime.Moods,onthecontrary,maylastfordays,weeksorevenyearsin thattheyparalyzemythoughtsandretainmefromacting(sadness)orthrowmeintoweirdactions withoutanythoughtsofthepastorthefuture(euphoria).Theintensityofthefeelingsinvolvedin affects demands a concrete action regarding our present situation such as to express our anger, escapethebear,returnthehappysmile,workonthedifficulttask,andsoon.Obviously,weoften donotactoutoftheaffectbutretainourselvesfromactingoutofit.Wecandominatetheaffectby 39 ThepsychologistMatthiasSiemeriscurrentlyworkingonasimilartheorythatiscalledthe dispositional theory of moods which‘holdsthatmoodsare,atleastinessentialpart, temporary dispositions tohaveortogenerateparticular kinds of cognitions, specifically to make particular kinds of emotionrelevant appraisals’ (Siemer 2005: 8167). He emphasizes that moods are ‘ multiple-object directed ’ (818) and contrasts the idea that moods are ‘intrinsically objectless,rawfeelings’(842).

149 acognitiveeffort 40 .Forexample,theirresistibledesiretoinsultorpokeamaliciousbossmaybe suppressedbythefearoflosingmyjob.Theintensityoftheaffectthengraduallysubsides,andI turn my attention on other matters. This, however, does not imply that the affect vanishes altogether.Itmayremainasabittermemorythatbringsforthunpleasantfeelingseverytimeitpops upinmymind(Goldie2000a:14951). Thedialecticofmoodsandaffectsiscomplex 41 .Affectsmaytransformthemselvesintomoodsand finallybecomeapermanentpartofourcharacter;moodsmaydetermineaffectsbecausetheyalter thewayweareaffectedbyobjectsandthoughts.Lastbutnotleast,agivenmoodmaybecomean affectwheninreflectionIarticulateitandfinditsmotivationsand‘feltcauses’,i.e.,thewayitroots me inagiven situation . Anaffectcantransformitselfintoamoodthatimposesitselfonmefordaysorevenlonger(grief cantransformintoageneralsadness;angerintodysphoria;boredomintotedium).Thus,amood may develop out of an affect as the affect itself loses its instantaneous, focused, and motivated character.Also,amoodmightnotbetheproductof a single affect and the following action or suppression of action, but a constellation of feelings caused by several episodes. Moods (e.g. irritability,sadness,tedium,euphoria) changethe way I am affected by the world (and my own thoughts)inthattheypredisposemyfieldofattention(thusmyconsciousexperience)inacertain way. And,aswehaveseen,inthecourseoftime,moodscan,invirtueofbeingdispositional,transform themselvesintoaninherentand permanent partofmyself.Anaffectcandevelopintoamood,and amoodcandevelopintoabasicemotionaltonality.Forinstance,adysphoricstatecangainsucha holdonmypersonthatitturnsintoacertaintrait,forexampleanirritable,hostile,mean,polemic, misanthropic,oradversecharacter.Thisbasicemotionaltonalityisapermanent (oftenimplicit) protention or readiness to (re)act and be affected in a given way, and probably also to develop certainmoodsmorethanothers. Inthisway,emotionsbecomeanessentialpartofaperson,of one’s sense of personal identity. This feeling of sameness comes close to what Ricoeur calls ‘character’ (se above, pp. 3942 and 8587). This basic emotional tonality is usually tacit and I noticeitonlywhenitisnotthere.Itisimportanttonoticethatallthesetransformationsfromaffects

40 This has recently been demonstrated in a neuroscientific study that shows how cognitive reappraisals can affect emotional experience by reducing activity in the amygdala and increase activity in the left lateral prefrontal cortex (Phelps2004). 41 I have learned much from on the skilled and detailed phenomenological analyses of affective transitions and alterationsmadebyStephanStrasser(1977:203242/12860)andThomasFuchs(2000:193251).

150 tomoodstocharacteroccurprereflectivelyandwithoutadeliberateandthematicinvolvementof thepersonintheprocess. Thisbringsustothefinalconsideration,namely howthedialecticofmoodsandaffectsplaya significantroleintheprocessoftheperson’snarrativeidentity. c)NarrativeIdentity The phenomenological analyses of moods and affects uncover important detail about the basic structures of feelings and the subject who experiences them. However, they need to be complementedbyanarrativeperspectiveinordertorenderinformationaboutthepersonhoodofthe experiencingsubject(Zahavi2005:114).AsRicoeur noticed, the subject is characterized by an unrest,noncoincidence,thatseekstorecoveritselfinattestation(oraffirmation)ofitsselfhood.An criticalpartofthisselfattestationisconstitutedbypersonhood,i.e.,theselfassituatedinahuman society together with other selves (i.e. the humanity of the self) and deeply imbedded in and affectedbythehistoricityofitsownbeing(mediatedbythelanguage,traditions,andnormsofthat society).Personhoodinvolves,asIemphasizedabove,theradicalcapacityofthewill,thatis,that thesubjectalwaysrelatesitselftothepersonthatitis;orsaidotherwise,thesubjectmustwilltobe thepersonthatitis.Nevertheless,theactive,reflectivecharacterofhumanreason(selfevaluation) andvolitionareintrinsicallyconnectedtothepassive(pathetic)dimensionofthefeelings.Strasser putsitlikethis:‘Humanindependenceischaracterized,amongotherthings,bythefactthatits feelingstratum functions as susceptivum for all the seeds of reason and, viceversa, the pathetic powersareorderedtothespiritualrealmfortheirfullnessofmeaning[…]theproperlyhumanis thewayinwhichthereasonofthepersonstandstoitspatheticpowersinahierarchicalrelation’ (Strasser1977:259/1745).Ibelievethatoneway to approach the problematic relation between reasonandtheperson’spatheticpowers(emotionalexperience)ispreciselyintermsofmoodsand affects.Andnarrativeidentityisanimportantpartofthisapproach. Now,Ricoeur’smodelofnarrativeidentityiscomplexandworkson,atleast,fourexplanatory levelsboundtogetherbythenotionoftemporality.Ononelevel,narrativeidentityseekstoexplore what is particular about human time by individuating a third category configured by both cosmological(objective,anonymous)andphenomenological(subjective,lived)time.Onanother,it isatooltoapproachthehermeneuticalnatureofthehumanidentitybyarticulatingthehistoricityof thesubject(thesubjectfindsitselfembeddedinaconcretehumanworldconstitutedbyvaluesand norms shaped by certain traditions and sociocultural contexts). A third dimension of narrative

151 identitydealswiththeintrinsicproblemsofpersonalidentity(identityanddiversity,samenessand selfhood).Andfinally,itbridgesthedescriptiveandprescriptivelevelbyarticulatingthenormative problemsinvolvedinpersonhood(theaxiologicaldimensionorvalues).Ihavedealtmoreclosely with these different aspects in part one and showed how the different aspects are closely interconnected. Here I shall only deal explicitly with the two latter ones, personal identity and normativity. Ricoeur surmises that narratives can articulate the problematic dynamics involved in personal identity (the complex relation and continuous interaction between choices, desire, long time dispositions, habits, character, etc.), because ‘[w]hat sedimentation has contracted, narration can redeploy’(OSA122/148).Andmoreover,hearguesthatnarrativesare‘ the first laboratory of moral judgment’ (OSA 140/167), since they emphasize the normative aspect of actions and personal identity. These two aspects of narratives explore the fact that personal identity is not only a descriptiveprocessofreidentification,butalsoanormativeproblemabouthowwerelateourselves tothepersonthatweare.However,Ricoeurdoesnot, regrettably, analyze the role of emotional experienceinnarrativeidentity.AndeventhoughRicoeur’sanalysesofpersonalidentityremainthe conceptualframework,thefollowinganalysisofemotionalexperienceandnarrativeidentitywill bearmuchontheworkofdeSousaandGoldie.AlthoughdeSousadoesnotadvocateanarrative approach, he has nevertheless coined a concept that has important implications for narrative theories,namelytheconceptof paradigm scenarios .Goldie,onthecontrary,isworkingintensely onemotionsandnarrativesandhasdeveloped,amongmanyothers,twohelpfulconceptsthatwill beemployedinthepresentanalysisofmoodsandaffects, the external perspective and emotional resistance .Further,hegivesseriousroomfortheconceptofmoodsinhisaccountofemotional experience,whichisinitselfarareand,formyaccountatleast,verypreciousthing. DeSousaproposesthatwe‘aremadefamiliarwiththevocabularyofemotionsbyassociationwith paradigm scenarios ’(deSousa1987:182).Thesescenarioscanlargelybeexplainedasanarrayof differenttypesofmoreorlessuniformresponsestocertainemotionalobjectsoremotionalevents. Thereexistsamultitudeofuniformresponsesthatareparadigmaticforhumanpersons.Sinceearly childhoodweexistinaworldcharacterizedandqualifiedbyemotionalexperience;forexample,we learn to fear glowing hotplates because they might hurt us; or that a genuine smile expresses happiness,compassionorpleasurewhereasafrownindicatesangerandunpleasantscreamingfear ordesperation,downcasteyessadnessorgrief.Ouremotionalregisteriscontinuouslyrefinedand revisedinourinteractionwiththeworldandotherpersons(idem:187);andinanimportantsense,

152 ‘paradigm scenarios indeed define the very character of our emotions’ (idem: 183), because emotionsareunderstoodinrelationtomeaningfulchoicesandactions(whatStrasserabovecalls ‘fullnessofmeaning’), andtherefore‘theiressentialroleliesinestablishingspecificpatternsof salience relevant to interference […] they areperfectlytailoredfortheroleofarbitratorsamong reasons’(idem:200).Whenweperceiveacertainscenario(e.g.aparenthittingherchild,aperson helpinganotherinneed,starvingchildreninthethirdworld,thedeathofalovedone)werespond emotionally to it, and de Sousa argues that the emotions that the such a scenario elicits (e.g. contempt, compassion, sadness, or sorrow) are defined by paradigmatic scenarios that are again constitutedbyexperienceandthebiologicalnatureofourbeing.Thesescenariosareofcoursevery contextualandfurthermoreinfluencedbyamultitudeofpersonalandsocialfactorsthatmakethe paradigm scenarios deeply individual. Nonetheless, de Sousa argues for an objective account of emotions:‘emotionstellussomethingabouttherealworld.Tobesure,theirobjectivityisrelative to the characteristic inclinations and responses of human and individual nature’ (idem: 203). Emotionshaveacertainrationalitythatisirreducibletocognitiveorstrategickinds,butwhichisan axiological rationality linked to values and evaluation (idem: 173). Our paradigmatic emotional responsestoobjectsandeventsrevealsomethingaboutthevaluesthatorientourconductinthe world. ThereareatleasttwoimportantinsightstobegainedfromdeSousa’saccount.First,theparadigm scenarios allow for an understanding of emotions that include both the biological and personal natureofemotionalexperience.Individualityandtemporal(‘biographical’)developmentarekeptas essential features of our emotional relation to the world (idem: 1001) without rendering the biologicaldimensionsuperfluous;onthecontrary,basicaffectiveresponses(e.g.fear,anger,panic, lust) ‘retain their power even over individuals whose repertoire include the most “refined” emotions’ (idem: 184). Secondly, it emphasizes the axiological aspect of emotions. Emotional experienceprovidesinformationabouttheworldandaboutmeasapersoninthesensethatthey, grossly speaking, reveal what I care about and what I despise. And paradigm scenarios are importantfortheunderstandingofourvalues,because‘ouronlyaccesstothelevelofrealitythat emotionsrevealisthroughtheparadigmscenariosthathaveshapedourworldview’(idem:315). Now, one way to explore the idea of paradigm scenarios is to dig into the narrative aspect of emotions.DeSousadoesnotgointhisdirectionhimself,althoughheemphasizestheimportanceof literature and art for the development and refinementofouremotions(1987:184;2005:3512). Goldie, however, makes narratives an explicit structure of the experience and explanation of

153 emotions.HisgeneralideaisverysimilartodeSousa’spictureofemotionalexperience:‘Foreach sort of emotional experience there will be a paradigmatic narrative structure […] learning the paradigmaticnarrativestructureofanemotion,onecancomereliablytojudgethatsomeoneelseis experiencing that emotion’ (2002a: 105) 42 . Like de Sousa, he emphasizes the personal and developmentalaspectofemotionsandstillmaintains that our emotional responses, despite their individuality,oftenarisefromcommon,paradigmaticstructures 43 .Whereasthephenomenological and neurophysiological accounts mainly concentrate upon the what and how of emotional experience,thenarrativestructurerevealsthe why (Goldie2007:112).Forexample,whydoIhave thisunpleasantfeelingofemptinesswhenIunlockthedoortomyapartment,althoughIknowthat myfamilyiswaitingformeinthekitchen?Or,whydoIbecomeangryatmylittlechildevenwith themostinnocentmistakethatshemakes? Inspired by the works of the late Richard Wollheim (1984; 2001), Goldie explores the relation betweenthepersonandemotionalexperiences(andactionsdoneoutofemotions).Todoso,he analyzes what he calls the external perspective or acentrallyimagining involvedinthenarrative structureofemotions(2000a:196219;2002a:1078;2003a;2003b:589;2003c:212;2005:135 8).Whenwe,infictionandinreallife, 44 experiencetheactionofanother,weimmediatelyconnect thisactiontocertainreasonsinordertounderstandthemeaningofthatspecificaction.WhenIsee, touseoneofGoldie’sfavouriteexamples,apersontreatingachildroughlyonthestreet,yelling andpullingthelittleone’sarm,Iimmediatelyexperiencean emotional resistance (2007:637)to thatactionandtothepersondoingit.Imaytrytofindallimaginablekindsofreasonsthatexcuse suchacrueltreatmentofthechild(atuffdayatwork,anexasperatingdivorce,thekid’sobnoxious character, financialdesperation,etc.),butsomehowIjudgetheparenttobeabadperson.Imay possiblyidentifymyselfwithherfeelings,butIfeelaresistancetowardheraction(‘Iwouldnever 42 Heis,however,criticizingdeSousaformakingtheparadigmaticnarrativestructuresconstitutiveofthedifferentsorts ofemotions(Goldie2000a:33note).Hesays,rightly,thatanarrativemayinvolvewhatisnonparadigmatic,e.g.,laugh outofgrieforkilloutoflove(Goldie’sexamples).IbelievethoughthathemisinterpretsdeSousa’sideaofparadigm scenariosbecausedeSousadoesnotexcludethatsuchemotionalresponsesmightoccur,onlythattheycontrastwith whatisparadigmatic(normal)ofgrieforlove,namelytearsorkisses.Theparadigmscenariosorparadigmaticnarrative structuresarewhattellsusthatanemotionalresponseisappropriateorinappropriate.Inthissense,theyareconstitutive ofanemotion.(deSousa1987:1856). 43 Hewrites,forexample,‘onecannotgrasptheunfoldingofaparticularemotionalsequencewithoutknowingwhat emotional life is like, and knowing the characteristic ways in which human emotions unfold in response to the vicissitudes of human experience’ (Goldie 2003a: 308);or,‘withinverybroadparameters,thereisarather moving common humanity of emotional responses, but, as with faces, there are subtle and important differences between individualcharacterizations’(2000a:109;cf.2005:97,109;2000a:856). 44 Goldie argues that ’there is no systematic divide between fictional and nonfictional narratives’ (2003b: 66); nevertheless, he stresses that this is not to be taken as a straightforward assimilation of the two cases: ‘rather, one shouldsaythatalife can be narrated ,sothatthenarrativeis about the life ,andthusthereremains,inthereallifecase, butnotinthefictionalcase,thepossibilityofreferenceandtruth’(2003c:216).

154 treatachildlikethat’).GoldiearguesthatIdonotunderstandthefeelingsandactionsofanother person(e.g.,anger,profoundgrief,charity,loving,orcoldindifference)merelybymeansof,for example, empathy or ‘inhisshoes imagining’ (2000a: 194204; 2005: 1378), which are both centralimaginativeprocesseswhereIimaginemyselfaspartoftheaction,butIemployanexternal perspectiveontheactionandjudgeaccordingtocertainvalues. Now,theinterestingmoveinGoldie’saccountisthatheappliesthissortofreasoningtoaperson’s ownfeelingsandactions.WhenIthinkofmyactions (past and future ones) then I engage in a narrativeprocessthatremindsoftheoneweexperiencewhenreadingliterature.Onetheonhand,I find the causal relations between my separate actions (2004: 114; 2007: 111). On the other, I individuatemore‘thicker’explanationsthatoftenare‘personspecific’(2004:112)andincludean evaluativestancetowardactionsandevents. As Imentioned in part one, there are many of my actionsthatIdonotthinkabout(orevenremember),buttherearealsosomethatIdothinkabout, andtheseoftenrevealsomethingaboutthekindofpersonthatIam;theyinvolveanevaluativeand normative reflection. Those are the ones that I normally understand by means of narrative structures. For example, if I bump into a table so that the coffee cup turns over and ruin my newspaper,itmightbecombinationofbadluckandaninstantdistraction;however,ifIrepeatedly bump into things and other people, then this might tell something about my person or, more specifically,mycharacter:clumsy,confused,absorbedinmyownthoughts,inconsiderate,andso on.Orastrongerexample,ifIdonotlookpeopleintheeyeswhenIamtalkingtothem,thisalso revealssomeaboutmypersonsuchasarrogance,shyness,orembarrassment.WhenIreflectupon myexperienceoftheworld,theother,andmyself,Iconfiguretheactions,events,andoccurrences accordingtonarrativestructuresthatincludebothcausalandthickerexplanations.Theconceptof personspecificthickerexplanationsisnaturallyextremelybroadandvergesonconfusion,butifwe (asRicoeurdoes)restrictourselvestotheexplanationsthatinvolvetheconceptofresponsibilityand selfesteem, perhaps we might see the relevance of this kind of explanations with regard to emotionalexperience 45 . How, then, are emotional experience, responsibility, and selfesteem structured in narratives? Following Ricoeur, we may use the concept of personal identity to understand the narrative approachtomoodsandaffects.

45 Goldie has written a fine, little book that attemptstosortoutsomeoftheproblemsinvolvedinpersonspecific explanations, where he individuates broad categories of personal characteristics: a) ways of acting, b) habits, c) temperaments, d) emotional dispositions, e) enduring preferences and values, f) skills, talents and abilities, and g) charactertraits(2004:113).

155 The temporal aspect of our being is what binds together the various aspects of the narrative approachtopersonhood.Wearechangingeverysecondofourlife,and yetweremainthesame person.Ouridentityprevailsthroughtime,eventhoughourbodymayalteranddeformandour ideaschangedrastically.Althoughouridentityremainsthesame,wehoweverchangeaspersons duringourlifespan.Thus,identity,inthesenseof personal identity,isnotmeresameness.Now, according to Ricoeur, personal identity is formed through a dialectic of two forms of identity: character (idem/sameness) and selfhood (ipseity/keeping one’s word). The fundamental trait of characterispermanenceintime,whichRicoeur,aswehaveseen,alsoreferstoascharacter:‘[t]he setofdistinctivemarkswhichpermitthereidentificationofahumanindividualasbeingthesame’ (FM119/144).Mycharacteristhatinwhichmyfeelingofremainingthesameintimeandthrough changesisrooted,andthatbywhichotherpeopleidentify and describe me. Aperson, however, doesnotcoincidewithhercharactertraits;beingwhosheisinvolvesanotherkindofidentity:an identity constituted in selfhood. Whereas my character is formed, at least for some part, involuntarilyinthesensethatitisdeterminedbymypastactions,randomevents,andcontingent factorsthatarenowoutofmycontrol,theidentityofmyselfhood,onthecontrary,dependsonhow Ivoluntarilyrelatemyselftobeingapersonwiththisparticularcharacter,constitutedbyacertain past,andsituatedinaworldmadeupoftheanonymouslawsofnature,andthesocietalexistence withotherpersons.Myselfhoodisconstitutedbymy active relationtothepersonIam(withallthe ambiguitythatpersonhoodentails);itisIwhohavetheresponsibilityformybeingthisperson. Hereentersthequestionofresponsibilityinvolvedinbeingaperson.AsDieterTeicherteloquently putsit:‘Identityasselfhoodislinkedtoarealmwhereactionsareascribedtoagentsinthelightof ethicalnorms’(2004:177178).Itisstillmewhodidthatterriblethinginthepast,eventhoughit wouldnotcrossmymindtodoanythinglikethattoday.Selfhoodentailsakindofselfcontinuity thatimpliesresponsibilitynotasacontingent,butasanessentialcomponentofpersonhood.This dimensionofselfcontinuityismainlyshapedthroughnarratives. HereGoldie’sworkmightshedsomelightonRicoeur’smoreabstractconceptualthinking.The ideaofanexternalperspective 46 hingesonthe(Augustinian)ideathat‘wesometimesneedtosee ourselvesfromtheoutside’(Goldie2004:111).Goldiearguescontinuouslyfortheideathat‘the narrative sense of self’ (idem: 11728) involves a certain detachment from the firstperson perspective similar to what we experience when engaged in narratives. We experience both the feelingsthattheauthorbreathesintothelivesofthecharactersandourownemotionalresponseto 46 Goldieusesdifferenttermstorenderroughlythesameideaofanexternalperspective,i.e., acentrally imagining , peripherally imagining (Goldie2000:196;2003b:5459;2003:3;2005:1367).

156 thosefeelings.WhenIengageinRaskolnikov’scontemptforAlyona,thepawnbrokerorEmma Bovary’s fascination of a street map of Paris or her fatal attraction to Léon Dupuis, I remain somehowexternaltothesefeelingsinthesensethatIdonotidentifymyselfwiththemalthough completelyabsorbedinthefeelingsthemselves.Thisdistanceopensupaspaceofevaluationnot identicaltoaspaceofreason(Goldie2007:110),butsomewhatdifferentinthatIrelatemyselfto thenormativeaspectofthefeelings.Ioftenexperienceanemotionalresistancetothefeelingsofthe fictional characters, which engenders a normative response to such resistances that reveal our values:‘ouremotionalresponsescanrevealtouswhatwevalue,andwhatwevaluemightnotbe epistemicallyaccessibletousifwedidnothavesuchresponses’(Goldie200:49). Now,ifweapplythisnarrativestructuretoourownemotionallife,wemightcometosee‘oneself asanother’(Goldie2003:312).ThefactthatwhatIdoandsuffer,asmyexistenceingeneral,is embeddedincertainfeelingsbecomesarticulatedthroughnarrativesaboutmyself.We‘loosen’the firmsedimentationofourowncharacterbyseeinghowthefeelingsinvolvedinpastactionsand sufferingshavecontributedtohowwerespondtotheeventsofourcurrentdailylife.Throughour life,interactionwiththeworldandtheotherhassedimentedintoahierarchalorganizationofwhat Stassercallsour‘patheticpowers’(feelings)thatresultsin‘acertaindispositionalcomportmentof man’(Strasser1977:325/224).Ourvaluesarefeltinhowwerespondtowhatweexperienceand do.Someofthesevaluesareimplicit,sincetheyaredispositionsandnotclearlyformulated,but onlyexpressedinthewayweengagewiththeworldandotherpersons.Goldie’scentralideaisthat whenweapproachourselveswithanarrativestructure,weendorseanexternalperspectiveonour ownthoughts,actions,andfeelings,andoftenweexperiencethesamesortofemotionalresistance toourownfeelingsastothoseofother,fictionalorreallife,persons.Thus,wealwaysevaluateour feelings in accordance with a kind of external perspective that from time to other provoke an emotional resistance to what we actually feel. The fact that we can experience an emotional resistance to our own feelings and doings might suggest that our feelings can reveal something aboutthefragilityofpersonalidentity.Wedoandsaythingsthatwewouldnotdoorsay.Ourself esteemdependsontheresponsibilitythatwehaveforthepersonthatweare.Myideas,principles, andemotionaldispositionsarepartofwhatIam,buttheycanbecomeaburdentomebecausemy personhoodisdeeplyintertwinedwiththeexistenceofotherpersons.WhenIfeelinacertainway, thisfeelingismineandyetIshareitwiththepersonsaroundme,becausethereisalwayssomething ofthefeelingintheactionsthatIdoorthethingsthatIsay.Myfeelingsarepartofmycharacter, even though they often motivate my choices silently and unconsciously (the deceived lover’s

157 complaint:‘IcannotchoosetofeelwhatIfeel’); in fact, they effectively shape my choices and attitudes.Feelingsareatthecenteroftheintersectionofthevoluntary(activity,spontaneity)and the involuntary (passivity, receptivity), and they need to be unraveled in order to deal with the complex fragility of personhood. The interrelation of selfesteem and responsibility reveals this complexity.Selfesteemdrawsonmyresponsibilityinrelatingtoothers,andyetitalsoscrutinizes myheart’sinmostfeelingsanddesires.Myinnerlife is somehow intimately related to my outer appearance (doings and sayings), because both are part of the person that I am. The narrative approachandtheconceptofexternalperspectivehelpengagewiththeproblemofresponsibility, selfesteem,andpersonhood. Therearetwoimportantfeaturestobeemphasizedhere.First,howdoweunderstandthenotionof external perspective, and, and in particular, what is the relation between such a perspective, personhood,andethicalnorms?Thiswillbethecentralthemeofthenextchapter.Andthesecond point,whichIshalldealwithontheconcludingpagesofthischapter,namelytheimportanceofthe relationofmoodsandaffectswhendealingwithemotionalexperienceandpersonhood.AsIhave mentioned, Goldie is among the few who pay close attention to the concept of mood when exploringwithemotionalexperience:‘Moods,too,canaffectyourthoughtsandfeelingstowards things: moods can crystallize into emotion, becoming directed towards a specific object, and emotioninturncandiffuseintomood’(2002:100). How,then,domoodsandaffectsfigureinthedialecticofcharacterandselfhooddevelopedinthe narrativestructureofselfexperience? Aswehaveseenintheprecedingsection,amoodcandevelopitselfintoacharactertrait,i.e.,a permanentpartofone’ssenseofpersonalidentity;thistransformationoftenoccursprereflectively andwithoutadeliberateandthematicinvolvementoftheperson. However, through narratives, moods can also be incorporated actively, reflectively and thematicallyintoaperson’sidentity.Moodsareconnectedtoselfunderstanding.Iunderstandwho Iaminthecontextofmypracticalengagement,asembeddedinacertainworld(privateassocial), andthisengagementisprimordiallyenvelopedinacertainfeelings.Myquestioningaboutmyselfis oftenelicitedbymymood(andbydisturbingaffectsthatdisclosemymood)beforemyidentity becomesanexplicitproblem.Moodsmaydisclosetomewhatwordanddeedsdonot.Feelingsare no hindrance to ‘cold’ rational knowledge, but as Heidegger pointed out our ‘understanding’ is always attuned, i.e., embedded in a certain feelings. The possibility of selfdisclosure, which belongstomoodsandaffects,isfundamentaltoselfunderstanding,becauseagivenmoodcanpoint

158 toabreachinthewayI,reflectively,understandmyself.Icanbelockedupinmyownwayof thinking,chainedtomythoughtsinsuchawaythatmyformulationsaboutmyselfreflectawrong oratleastproblematicunderstandingofmypersonhood(Goldie2004:125). Although our capacity to choose to be what (who) we want to be is a constitutive feature of personhood,thesechoices(evaluations)arealwaystiedtotheinvoluntaryaspectofmypersonhood: “Thenormativedimensionthuspertainstotheself thatonealreadyisinrelatingtoothers,toa worldinbetween,andtooneself”(Grøn2004:151). Thiscomplexdialecticbetween to be and appear to be (betweencharacter,selfhoodandworld) exposesthefragile,normativenatureofpersonhood:mynarrativeformulationsaboutmyselfare constitutiveofmyperson,andyet(asTaylorobserves)theseformulationscanberightorwrong.I cantellawrongstoryaboutmyselfandthereforeliveaccordingtothisstory,butmymood(andits expression in certain affects) may disclose, through its bipolar intentionality, that something is wrongaboutthisstory(theexternalperspective).Ifwethereforetakeouremotionsseriouslyand seektointerpretthemasdisclosingsomethingaboutourselvesandoursituation,thenwemaygain atooltoapproachtheproblematicnotionofpersonhood. This,however,presupposesthatweunderstandidentityandpersonhoodasessentiallyanchoredin acontinuitythatdemandsthatwetakeresponsibilityforourchoices,pastasfuture,andthatwedo notliveourlivesas‘episodiccreatures’(asproposedbyStrawson1999;2004) 47 .Wecannotbase ouridentityonLordShaftesbury’sdictum:“The now ,the now .Mindthis:inthisisall”(quotedin Strawson 2004: 438). In fact, by emphasizing the interconnection between emotions and the normativestructureofnarrativityweseethatfeelingsmaydisclosetheconsequencesoflivingas episodiccreaturesinthemagicalnow.ThefeelingofhopelessnessemergingwhenIearnestlytryto convinceothers(andmyself)thatitwasnotmewhostoletheshirtthatIamnowwearing.Itmight havebeenmeeonsofselvesago,butnotthemethatIaminthisnow(orrather3secondsago). 47 ThephilosopherGalenStrawsonhasattackedthenotionofnarrativeidentityveryharshly.Thenarrativeapproach expresses ‘an ideal of control and selfawareness in human life that is mistaken and potentially pernicious […] the narrative tendency to look for a story or narrative coherence in one’s life is, in general, a gross hindrance to self understanding:toajust,general,practicallyrealsense,implicitorexplicit,ofone’snature’(2004:447).Hebuildsthis claimonathoroughanalysisoftheconceptofaself,wherehearguesforadistinctionbetweenselfandpersonhood: ‘therearemanyshortlivedandsuccessiveselves(ifthereareselvesatall),inthecaseofordinaryindividualhuman beings’(1999:100).Aself‘isbelowanyculturalvariation’(103)andconstitutedontologicallywithadurationupto threeseconds,althoughthephenomenologicalexperienceofselfhoodmight,wrongly,suggestotherwise(111).Selves arecharacterizedare‘SESMETs(SubjectsofExperiencethatareSingleMEntalThings)’inthesensethateachthought involves a self (118) and ‘are physical objects, as real as rabbits and atoms’ (120). He the uses this ontology to distinguishbetweenepisodicanddiachroniccreatures,wherethediachronics(narrativepersonalities)tendtobestuck withthepastandcontinuousrevisingandtheepisodics(amongwhomStrawsonfindshimself)whothinkthat‘[t]he businessoflivingis,formany,acompletelynonNarrativeproject’(2004:448)andthat‘[t]he‘examinedlife’isgreatly overrated’(1999:100).

159 Athematicarticulationofmyemotions(moodsaswellasaffects)inanarrativestructuremayhelp tounderstandtheemotionsthemselvesandtherebyapproachafundamentalfeatureofpersonhood: apersonisconstitutedofbothfactual(aspecificphysicalconstitution,agivenworld,acertainpast, andaparticularcharacter)andnormative(Icanchoosetoidentifymyselfwiththefactualornot, butI,somehow,havetorelatemyselftothesefacts)features.Emotionsopenupthisdialecticand help us sort it out, if we try to understand (by thematic articulation) the complexity of human affectivity. Itistimetoclosethechapteronhumanaffectivity.Ihavespentconsiderabletimeonarguingfor theirreduciblecomplexityofhumanfeelings,inparticulartheirnormativenature,andIwillnow endbydrawingtheconclusionsofthepreviousanalyses. HumanAffectivity:FeelingsandEmbodiedNormativity Michael Stocker is one of the philosophers who has spent most time and energy defending the moralimportanceandcomplexityofaffectivity.Hewritesthatwemustunderstandthat‘feelings arecomplex,intrapersonalandinterpersonal,social,andalsothattheyareevaluativelyandmorally important […] feelings are not mere feelings; there is little that is mere about them; and this explainshowwhatismistakenlythoughtofasmerefeelingscanbeofvitalevaluativeandmoral importance’ (Stocker 1996: 54). My account is deeply inspired by his seminal work about the irreducibleaffectivedimensionofcare,concern,andinterest.Theprincipaldifferenceliesinmy attempttoarticulatetheinterrelationbetweenmoodsand affectwithintheemotional experience itself,andfurthertoestablishtheoutlineofanargumentfortheimportanceofsuchanarticulation inrelationtopersonhood.Thefollowingchapterwill extend the argument of the evaluative and moralimportanceofemotionsbydevelopingwhatGoldiehascalledtheexternalperspectiveinthe narrativestructureofemotions.IwillattempttolinksuchaperspectivetowhatIhavecalledthe practicalspaceofreasoninordertoarguefortheindispensablerelationbetweensubjectivityand ethics.Ishallarguethatsubjectivitybecomes,tosomeextend,anemptyconceptwhenconsidered asafeelingless(minimal)senseofagencyandownership;andfurther,ifthesubjectisconsidered asafeelingloadedagent,questionsofpersonhoodandethicaldispositionsbecomesindispensable for a comprehensive account of subjectivity. My argument is basically that the concept of subjectivityisathoroughlynormativeconcept.Butbeforeturningtothatcentralchapter,Iwill,in wayofconclusion,articulatethemostimportantinsightsarrivedatinthislongchapter.

160 I will first recapitulate, and thereby clarify, my account of human affectivity. I structure my analysesononeofRicoeur’smostbasicideas(inspiredasheisbyKant),namelythatsubjective experienceisconstitutedbyatranscendentalsynthesisofreasonandsensibility,thatis,subjective natureisconstitutedbothbyspontaneityandreceptivity.Ontheonehand,thesubjectiscapableto thinkandactspontaneouslywithoutbeinginducedbyanythingbutitself.Ontheother,thesubject isaffectedbythatwhichisother(theexternalworld,theothersubjectandevenitself)throughthe sensesand,ofparticularinterestinthepresentcontext,thefeelings.Subjectiveexperienceisneither purereason(spontaneityoractivity)norpuresensibility(receptivityorpassivity),butasynthesisof thetwo.Furthermore,IagreewithRicoeur’sotherbasicideathatactualsubjectiveexperienceis alwayscharacterizedbyaffectivity.Thesubjectalwaysexperiencestheworldanditselfasloaded with feelings; there is no such a thing as a feelingless experience or feelingless reason. This is becausehumanexperienceis,atitsinmostcore,asynthesisofspontaneityandreceptivity.Inthis generalsense,affectivityaccountsforthereceptiveaspectofbeinghuman.Weareaffectedbythe externalworld,time,and,inparticular,bytheotherpersons(throughoursenses),butalsobythe physicalstateofourbody,ourthoughts,ideas,principles,memory,andsoon.Inamorespecific sense,however,affectivityaccountsforwhatweknowasemotionalexperienceoremotions.As mentionedbrieflyabove,Iuseemotionsasanumbrellatermforthevarietyofaffectivephenomena (feelings,cognitions,affects,ormoods)thatwecallemotionalexperience.Emotionalexperience involves two fundamental elements, cognitions and feelings, and emotional theories have been fighting over which element is the dominant one. I give them equal weight in the sense that, dependingontheemotion,thecognitiveandfeelingaspectsvaryanddifferastowhichelementis the salient feature of the emotional experience. Some emotions are characterized as more prominentlycognitivewhereasothersareclosertomerebodilyfeelings.Thedecisiveargumentis that all emotions depend on both cognitive and feeling elements; we never experience a pure cognitivenorapurefeelingemotionduetothefactthatourexperienceisprimordiallya synthesis ofspontaneityandreceptivity.Wealwayscontributesomethingofourselvestotheemotion,our worldview,ourdesires,andideas;andstilltheemotioncapturesus,rendersuspassive,andimposes acertainfeelinguponusthatwecannotescape.Theemotiontellussomethingabouttheworld(the informativeclaimortheobjectivityoftheemotion) 48 andaboutourownrelationtothatworld,the

48 ‘TheinformationIhaveinmindisnotconfirmedtotheworldoutsidethesubject:ifIamangryatyou,myangertells menotmerelythatyouhavedonesomethingwrongbutalsothatIaminapositiontoassessandreacttoit.Themany kindsofinformationimplicatedmakeforarichmess,butonemess,afterall,canstillmakeonetopic’(deSousa1987: 114)

161 other, and ourselves (the subjectivity of emotions)49 . My proposal is then that to access and understandthecomplexvarietyofhumanemotions,wemustfirstphenomenologicallyindividuate theconstellationoffeelingsinvolvedinagivenemotionalexperience.Thetooltodosoisamodel which classifies the emotion within one unified scale from affects to moods according to the phenomenology (intentionality and temporality) of the feelings involved, and then we must contextualizeandpersonalizethefeelinginanarrativestructurethatrevealsthecognitiveelements in that emotional experience and the complex ambiguity of the factual and normative aspect of personhood(whattheemotionmeanstome,andwhatitrevealabouttheworld,theother,andmy personhood). The feeling aspect is a necessary, but not sufficient part of the explanation of emotions (Strasser 1977: 194/120). This phenomenologicalnarrative approach puts my account close to Goldie, and yet my emphasis on the affectmood model and the normativefactual ambiguityofpersonhoodmakesmyaccountquitedifferentfromhis. Second,whytheemphasisofmoodsandaffectsasextremepolesofhumanemotionalexperience? I have made this model because I believe that by gathering our emotional experience within a unifiedscaleoffeelingsandcognitionsthatisheldtogetherbytheextremepolesofmoodsand affects we get an effective tool to phenomenologically analyze and categorize the different emotionalexperiencesaccordingtotheirintentionalityandtemporalduration.Thiscategorization helps the narrative analysis of the emotion, because we come to terms with the object(s), phenomenologicalmanifestationandtemporaldurationinvolvedintheemotions.Furthermore,it makes the developmental aspect of emotions clearer than it ispossible if we distinguish strictly betweenmoodsandemotionsasifthereweretalkabouttwocompletelydifferentphenomena.In addition, it evidences the salience of cognitive elements involved in the emotional experience. Moodsoftenseemtolackadistinctobject(IcannotputmyfingeronwhyIamsad)butwhich mightsuggestamorecomplexcognitiveelement(acovertbipolarintentionalitycharacterizedby being multiobject directed), whereas affects often involve a clear object (I fear the bear), brief temporal duration, and more simple cognitive elements. Finally, the emphasis on moods are important when it comes to the values involved in or revealed by emotions. The multiobject directednatureofmoodsconstitutesamorefinegrainedapproachtoemotionsandvalues,because whereas more simplelayered emotions (e.g. affectssuchasjoy,anger,surprise,fear,disgust,or 49 ’I and the world are embedded in an undivided experience of totality. Disposition is the feeling of Iandworld together’(Strasser1977:188/115);or‘Now,one’sownIisonepoleofconcreteindividualitywhichisfirstbroughtinto reliefinIfeeling,selffeeling,feelingofparticularity,andsoforth.Ontheotherhand,theworldisamassive,concrete andindividualobjecttowhichtheIisnecessarilyrelatedinitsstruggleforselfrealization.This,too,isfirstrevealedin feeling’(idem:192/119).

162 panic)revealmoredirectandclearvalues(e.g.offence,safety,wellbeing,survival),moods(e.g. anxiety,melancholy,emptiness,indifference)revealmycomplexrelationtothevaluesthatIhold, to the person that I am, and to other people. Whereas affects reveal my values, moods may effectuatequestionsaboutmyvalues,andthewayIrelatemyselftotheworld,other,andmyown person. This brings me to the third and final conclusion about the embodied and normative aspect of emotionalexperience.Aswesawabove,theneurophysiologicaldimensionofemotionsemphasizes theimportanceofemotionsinperson’scomportmentintheworld.Damasioadvocatedthesomatic marker hypothesis that emotions highlight certain possible choices in the process of decision makingandtherebyrestrictourfieldofattentionthatwouldotherwisebeimmenseandimpossible tocomprehend.Withoutemotions,ourexperienceoftheworldwouldbeflat,andeverythingwould seem indifferent. I agreed to the general hypothesis but refuted the implications of the theory, because it reduces the notion of subjectivity to a simplistic notion and the aspect of emotional normativityto aquestionof evolutionarybenefits, primary emotions and physiological changes. This, however, does not reduce the importance of the neurophysiological dimension. Panksepp showedhowemotionsmightbeconceivedasbasicaffectiveprograms(rawfeelings)thatdetermine primaryinstinctualbehaviorsandrevealbasicecologicalvaluesembeddedinhumanlife;further, heemphasizedthatthesevaluesaffectallourcognitiveskillsinthesensethathumanfeelingsare immersedinthesebasicaffectprograms 50 .Aclarificationofsuchprogramsmighthelpunderstand thecognitiveimpenetrablenatureofmanyofouremotions.Ourexperienceoftheworldisalways embeddedindeepaffectivestructuresthatpointtobothourgeneralmammaliannatureandour specifichumannatureandconcerns. This tells us something about the normativity involved in emotions. Emotions reveal the complexityofvalues.Forexample,physicalvaluesappertainingtothephysiologicalconstitutionof mybeing(vitalvalues);personalvaluesthatreflectmyown(sometimes)peculiarvalues,social values(etiquetteandaestheticvalues)thatinfluencehowIcomportmyselfinsocietywithother persons, and finally ethical values that reflect the practices and norms by means of which I act towardtootherpeople.Thequestionofethicalvalueswillbethetopicofthenextchapterwhich hopefullywillmakeitclearerwhat Imeanbythefundamentalrelationbetweensubjectivityand ethics.Inthislongchapter,Ihavetriedtoshowthecomplexityofhumanaffectivity,andhowour feelingsmayrevealsomethingaboutthevaluesbywhichweleadourlife.Feelingsshowuswhat 50 Actually,Goldieproposesthatwesubstitutethetalkaboutbasicemotionwithtalkofaffectprograms(Goldie2000: 106).

163 wecareabout,andhowourpersonhoodisanormativequestioninitiatedbyhowwefeelabout ourselves and the world. One might say that emotions are primary indicators of the normative dimensionofhumanlife;ourfeelingsrevealanembodiednormativitythatcomplicatestherigid distinctionoffactandvalue,becausetheyemphasize that our human experience of facts in and aboutourexistenceisalwaysloadedwithvalues.

164 ChapterTwo EthicalExperienceandOntology In this concluding chapter, I shall tie together the foregoing analyses and answer the central questionofthework,namelyabouttherelationbetweensubjectivityandethics.Ihavespentalong timeonhumanaffectivitybecauseIbelievethatitdisclosesabasicnormativitythatistoooften disregarded in both theories of subjectivity and theories of ethics. But subjectivity is obviously muchmorethanrevealedbytheaffectivedimension.HereIshallfocusonwhyethicalexperience is of primary importance to a theory of subjectivity, and further how such an experience might revealsomethingessentialaboutofhumanontology.IpickupwhereRicoeurconcluded,namely withethicalexperienceandanontologyofcare.Ihaveextendedconsiderablytheanalysisofthe affective dimension in comparison with his analyses, because I consider the absence of a developmentofthenotionofaffectivitytobeoneoftheweakpointsinhistheoryofsubjectivity. Although the following analyses continue to draw heavily on his groundwork, I think that an elaborationtheideaofthepracticalspaceofreasonwillclarifynotionsandargumentsthatremain somewhatinarticulateandobscureinhisextensivewritings.Theideaofanontologyofcareisonly mentioned peripherally, and without a clear argumentforsuchanontologyhisotherwisestrong argumentsabouttheprimacyofethicalexperienceremainacuriosityinthecontemporarydebateof subjectivityandethics.Further,Idevelopandusehisbasicideasandanalysesinadifferentcontext thanwheretheyarecommonlyemployed. Idrawheavilyontheworkoftwoothercontemporaryphilosopherstoarticulatemyconclusions. ThefirstistheSimonBlackburnwhoseworkonpracticalreasoninghashelpedmeunderstandthat anaturalizationofvaluesdoesnotnecessarilyinvolveareductiveaccountofneithersubjectivity nor normativity. The other is the Charles Taylor whose extensive writings on the primacy of morality,inparticulartheideaof‘theselfinmoralspace’hasinspiredmetothedevelopmentofthe notionofapracticalspaceofreason. Butbeforeturningtotheprincipalanalyses,itmightbeagoodideatotakeabrieflookbacktotwo greatphilosopherswhoseworkhasproducedmanyoftheconceptsandargumentsthatareusedin thecontemporarydebateaboutsubjectivityandethics.Suchamovebackwardscanhelptoclarify, position,andrefinethefollowinganalyses.

165 A Preamble: Kant and Hume on Emotions, Ethics and Subjectivity Emotions, ethics, and subjectivity have been intertwined in western philosophical tradition throughoutmorethantwomillennia.Aswithsomanyotherphilosophicalissues,HumeandKant arestilltheonestoconsultforhistoricalandargumentative insights into contemporary debates. Theyarenotoriouslyfamousfortheircompletelyoppositeviewsontherelationbetweenemotions andsubjectivity.Ontheonehand,wehavetheviewexpressedinHume’sfamouswords:‘Reason is,andoughtonlytobetheslaveofthepassions’(Hume1978:415)andfurther‘[m]oraldistinction cannot be derived from reason’ (idem: 458). This psychology of action is the foundation upon whichHumebuildshisethicaltheory.Itisnotthatreasondoesnothaveanythingtosay;onthe contrary,therecannotbeanymoralwithoutreason,butitisnotreasontohavethefirstorthelast wordonethicalconduct.Reasonalonedoesnotmoveustoact.Morality,therefore,isgroundedin auniversalsentimentofhumanitydueto‘theoriginalfabricandformationofthehumanmind’ (Hume1975:172).InHumewefindanappraisalofemotionsasthesourceofmorality(andof actioningeneral)inhumannature.Thereasonwhywecareaboutthewelfareoftheotherpersonis becauseofauniversalfeelingofsympathy,‘thehumanityofonemanisthehumanityofeveryone, andthesameobjecttouchesthispassioninallhumancreatures’(idem:273).Thisistheprinciple uponwhichallmoralreasoningmustbefounded. Ontheotherhand,Kantlookssuspiciouslyontheemotionsasapartofoursensiblenatureand thereforenotfittedformorality.Allfeelingsdieoutafterawhile,whereasreasonanditsconcepts standforever(Kant1998b:12930/1578).Truemoralityisgroundedinreason,andisthereforenot subjecttothewhimsofthesubjectorthepressurefromasicksociety.Reasonalonecanguarantee amoralconduct,sinceonlybyfollowingtherulesofreasonarewe,ashewritesin The Metaphysics of Morals ,abletodominateourfeebleanimalisticnatureandbecomemorehumanor,perhapseven moreimportantly,becomeworthyforthehumanitythatharborsinour(rational)nature(Kant1996: 151/387).Thishiddenhumanityinhumannatureisreason,andtheguidingrulesofconductare expressedinthecategoricalimperativesofthemorallawwhich‘isgiven,asitwere,afactofpure reasonofwhichweareaprioriconsciousandwhichisapodicticallycertainthoughitbegranted thatnoexactexampleofitcanbefoundinexperience’(Kant1998b:41/47).Obviously,Kantis wellawarethat‘[n]ohumanbeingisentirelywithoutmoralfeeling,forwerehecompletelylacking inreceptivitytoithewouldbemorallydead;andif(tospeakinmedicalterms)themoralvital forcescouldnolongerexcitethisfeeling,thenhumanitywoulddissolve(bychemicallaws,asit were)intomereanimalityandbemixedirretrievablywiththemassofothernaturalbeings’(Kant

166 1996:160/401).However,thisnaturalandinnategiftmustbecultivatedandeducatedbythefirm principlesofreasonotherwisetheyveryquicklyturnuglyandendupaspathological.SoKantdoes not at all ignore feelings and emotions in his ethics, which one also notice when reading his anthropologicalandpoliticalworksthatarecloselyrelatedtohisethics.Hesimplydoesnotcount onthem(Kant1998a:17/4045).Emotionsarewaytoofutileandinstabletobeconsideredasapart ofaseriousethicalphilosophy.Therefore,theycannotbeamotiveinmoralpsychology.Oneday my conduct may be motivated by the ‘moral feeling’ in my nature and the next day, just as naturally,Imayfeelitbesttothinkmoreofmyownwelfareandlessofthatoftheothers.Without the categorical imperative and the rules of pure (practical) reason my conduct is formed and controlled by ‘the slings and arrows’ of heteronomous forces such as feelings, imagination, contingenteventsandfacts.Feelingarepartofthenaturalworldand,therefore,theycannotbea motivationalfactorforarationalbeingthatcompletesitsautonomyinactinginaccordancewith lawsissuedbyanonnaturalreasonwithwhichallrationalcreaturesareendowed(Kant1998b:59 61/6970), and by means of which they can aspire to become a member and perhaps even a sovereignofthe‘KingdomofEnds’(Kant1998a:41/433). Theconnectionbetweenimaginationandfeelingisimportantsinceitisemployedwithequalforce inbothKantandHume,althoughwithdrasticallydifferentoutcome.WhereasKant(inhisethical writing)mainlypointstoimaginationandfeelinginrelationtothepathologicalphenomenonoflust andotheregoistictendencies(therightuseofimaginationisguidedbyreason),Humeseesfeelings andimaginationasfundamentalfortheconceptofsympathyandtrue(i.e.notselfish)interestin other people. He writes in the Treatise : ‘We blame equally a bad action, which we read of in history,withoneperform’dinourneighbourhoodt’otherday:Themeaningofwhichis,thatwe knowfromreflexion,thattheformeractionwou’dexciteasstrongsentimentsofdisapprobationas thelatter,wereitplacedinthesameposition’(Hume1978:584).Withoutimaginationwecould never reach what Hume calls ‘the common point of view’ (Hume 1975: 272) or ‘the natural sentimentofapprobationandblame’(Hume1978:579);thatis,thepositionfromwhichwelook uponourfeelingsandsentimentswithoutanydirectrelationtoourselves. Ontheotherhand,however,Kantstillrecommends travels,livingina‘cosmopolitan’citylike Königsberg, reading novels, history, biographies, and going to the theatre as ways of gaining important insights into the nature of human beings. Therefore, in some way, he cherishes and approvesofthepowerofthecooperationbetweenimaginationandfeeling(Kant2006:45/1202). But it is different matter in ethics where such a combination cannot be allowed to direct our

167 conduct.Herereasonstandsaloneasthesoledefenderofourhumanity.Notaidedbyimagination orfeelings,orbyacombinationofthetwo. Whatkindofpicturedothesetwometaethicalpositionsgiveofemotions?Well,ontheonehand, Humepresentsatheorythattriestointegrateemotionsasafundamentalpartofethics.Thenature ofhumansubjectivityplaysanessentialroleinwhatwejudgeasa‘good’ora‘bad’action.Hence, theontologicalstatusofmoralvalueissubjective,i.e.,dependentontheparticularconstitutionof humannature.Wecometoknowaboutvaluesbypayingdueattentiontoemotionsandtohowthese emotionsexpressthemselvesinthesocialconductofhumanbeings(theepistemologicalaspect). Reasonalonecanneverdiscernavaluefromafact.Thus,reasoncouldnevermotivateustodo anythingifitwerenotforemotions.Ontheotherhand,Kantstrictlyseparateethicsandemotions. Humansubjectivitydoesnotaffecttheontologicalstatusofmoralvalue.Moralvalueisobjective, notdependentonhumannature(whichisconstitutedbysensiblefeaturessuchasfeelingsandother bodilysensations).Thegoodandthebadactionisnotperceivedbyoureyesorourfeelings,but knownbyreasonaloneinabstractionfromanythingempirical.Theycouldbeunderstoodbyabrain inavatorbyinhabitantsfromanemotionlessTwinEarth,weretheseonlyendowedwithreason. Therefore,emotionscannot,oratleastshouldnot,motivateourconductininteractingwithother persons.Thishasinterestingimplicationsfortherelationbetweensubjectivityandethics. InHumeandKantwehavetwodifferentapproachestothequestionofsubjectivityandethics.In their theoretical works, both philosophers express a quite skeptical view on the question of subjectivity.Hume’sfamouswords,‘Inevercancatchmyselfatanytimewithoutaperception,and never can observe any thingbut theperception itself’ (Hume 1978: 252), tell a story about the missingselfthatisalwayssomethingelse(aperception‘ofheatorcold,lightorshade,loveor hatred,painorpleasure’(idem)).Kant’sviewisnothingbutclear.Thequestionabouttheselfwas thereasonfortherewritingofthe Transcendental Deduction andthe Paralogisms of Reason inthe secondeditionofthe Critique of Pure Reason ,andHeideggerwroteabookonthisproblem,which hethoughttobethefundamentalquestioninKant(1990).Kantseemstoevadethequestionandyet believeittobethemostimportant.Whatistheself?Itisthecommonroot(Wurzel)ofsensibility andreason,thehiddenpowerofthesoul,thelogicalunityofapperception,andthemetaphorsgoes on,butinthesecondeditionheconcludesthat‘Iasintelligenceandthinkingsubjectcognizemy selfasanobjectthatisthought,insofarasIamalsogiventomyselfinintuition,only,likeother phenomena, not as I am for the understanding but rather as I appear to myself’ (Kant 1997: 259/155).Weonlyhaveanindirectknowledgeofsubjectivityinbothphilosophers,andthesubject

168 remainsfragileandobscurewhenwetrytodefineitbyatheoreticalapproach.Itisintheirpractical philosophythatwefindtheirfullblowntheoriesofsubjectivity. InHumethesubjectbecomes a human subjectby means of human sentiments and feelings, and in Kant the subject becomes a subject‘initself’( an sich ),aperson,bylisteningtotheclearvoiceofreasonthatdeclaresthata humansubjectcanneverbetreatedasameans,butonlyasanendinitself,apersonWhatmakesa subjectahumansubjectis,inbothphilosophers,themoraldimensionofsubjectivity. Nevertheless,theirrespectiveethicshavedifferentimplicationsforatheoryofsubjectivity.Kant developsanethicsthatreactsagainstwhathebelievestobethesensibleflawsandinconsistencies of the human subject, whereas Hume grounds his ethics in that same sensibility. Kant sees an irremediablegapbetweensensibilityandreasonthatdemandsanethicsstrictlyseparatedfromthe theoreticalinvestigationsintothenatureofthehumansubject.Thenormativeisofanonnatural nature,andthereforeitdependsuponpracticalandundernocircumstancesontheoreticalreason (Kant1998b:1002/11921) 51 .Hume,bycontrast,claimsthatthenormativedimensioncannotbe approachedwithoutathoroughexplorationofthenaturalnatureofthesubject.Infact,itdependson thatnaturalnature.Thisisnottosaythatthenormativeisthenatural(Humewasthefirsttopointto thenaturalisticfallacy(Hume1978:290)),butasJonathanJacobssays:‘Wecanexplainthesource and basis of moral value and judgement by reference to naturalistic features of human beings’ (2002: 127). Feelings and desires, being an aspect of our sensible nature, are therefore either abandonedaspathologicalorcherishedasfundamentalintheirethics.Wheredoesthisputuswith regardtotherelationbetweenethicsandtheoriesofsubjectivity?Kantputsawatershedbetween the two whereas Hume thinks them inseparable, considering emotions essential to both human subjectivityandethics. In contemporary philosophical debate, we might see ethics as somewhat alien to a descriptive theoryofsubjectivity;theoreticalandpracticalanalysesaredoneondifferentlevelsbyphilosophers whoarespecializedinoneareabutnotintheother.Whatdonormativefeatureshavetodowitha factualdescriptionofthehumansubject?Thismightseemafairobjectiontoanobjective,non

51 ItisworthtonoticethatKant’sethicscanbeapproachedfromanotherperspectivethanthroughhisexplicitlyethical publications.Hispoliticalandanthropologicalwritings(accessiblebothinpublishedworks,manuscripts,andtheso calledreflections)provideamuchmorerefinedviewonthenatureofemotionsandethicalreasoning.Agoodexample ishislongdefenseofsensibilityinthe Anthropology (2006:3454/14367).PeterStrawsonpointstothesamefactinan argumentwherehegivesKant’stheoryofsubjectivitymorecreditthanthatofHumeexactlybecauseKanthasshown, withtheanalysesofthetranscendentalunityofapperceptionandtheparalogisms,thatsubjectidentityneedsnocriteria, neitherempiricalnorrational,toactuallyexist.Subjectidentityisalogicalpresuppositionforexperience,anddespite hisnotorious‘neglectoftheempiricalconceptofasubjectofexperience[…]Thepointis,however,thatnothingin Kant’s account excludes, and everything in it invites, such a supplementation’ (Strawson 1966: 16970; se also Strawson1959:1024).IreturntosomeofStrawson’sargumentsinchaptertwo.

169 natural ethics as the Kantian presented above, but would seem less obvious with regard to a Humeanethics.Andthisisduetothenatureofemotions.Inthefollowingsection,Iwillshowhow subjectiveexperienceisprimarilyethicalexperienceandthatthisisduetotheparticularstructure ofourexperienceasapracticalspaceofreason. The Practical Space of Reason: Values, Concerns, and the Other Thephenomenologicalanalysesofaffectivityshowedthatthesubjectisalwaysinsomekindof feelingstatethatrevealsthebeingintheworldofthesubject,i.e.,existenceisalwaysenvelopedin feelings.Wecannotescapethefeelingswhenanalyzingthenatureofsubjectiveexperience.Froma neurophysiologicalperspective,Pankseepemphasizesthesameprimacyofthefeelingsbypointing tothefactthatalthoughweare‘[d]eeplyculturalcreatureswithacognitiveapparatus,arisingfrom vast neocortical territories that can associate perceptions and ideas with feelings, that remains unmatchedinthelivingworld[…]thoseabilitieswoulddisappear,likeafadingdream,withoutthe solidplatformthatarisesfromsubcorticalabilities we still share with other animals’ (2004: 58). AccordingtoPanksepp,thebasic,nonspecifichuman,affectiveaspectofourbeingisfundamental forourmoreelaboratedpartsofournaturesuchasaesthetics,culture,orethics.Thephilosopher DanZahavipointstothesamebasicaffectivefeatureinsubjectivitywhilediscussingwhyautistic personshaveseriousproblemsinintersubjectiverelations:‘[w]hatweareconfrontedwithhereis notalackofatheoryofmind,butalackofanimmediate,prereflective,orimplicitunderstanding ofemotionalexpressionsandtheunwrittenrulesofsocialinteraction’ (2005:221).Ourbeinga subject cannot be separated from emotions and desires, neither with regards to selfhood nor to intersubjectivity. Itisexactlywiththequestionofintersubjectivitythatsubjectivityandethicsbecomerelated.But oftenthisrelationfirstbecomesevidentatahigher(i.e.lessbasic)levelofintersubjectivity,where wereflectivelyformtheoriesofothermindsandthentrytofindoutwhichkindofconductwe shouldchooseandwhichweshoulddecline.Butanethicsthattakestheemotionsseriouslywould seeitotherwise.Itarguesforthepervasivenessofthenormative.Normativityispresentatevery levelofselfhood,evenintheminimalselfawareness:‘ there is no getting behind ethics .Itcomes unbidden.Itcomeswithliving’(Blackburn1998:2).Weactinaccordancewithnormsalthough thesenormsbecanmoreorlessexplicit,moreorlessarticulated.Therecentneurophysiological discoveryofmirrorneuronsinhigherprimates(monkeysandhumans)seemstoempiricallysupport oratleastenforcethetheoryofpervasivenessof thenormative.Mirrorneuronsare aparticular

170 classofvisuomotorneuronsoriginallydiscoveredinareaF5ofthepremotorcortexinmonkeys. Later,theywerealsoindividuatedinhumansandarenowbelievedtoexistinotherbrainareasas well.Whatmakethemspecialisthattheyareactivatedbybothproperactionandobservationofthe actionofothers.Iunderstandtheactionofanotherbeforecognitivelyrelatingmyselftohisorhers action 52 .Ourrelationtoothersisdeterminedbyaprereflective and automatic understanding of theiractionandtheirconcernsandneeds.Accordingtoahypothesiscalled‘thesharedmanifold hypothesis’,weunderstandourworldasa‘multidimensional,‘wecentric’sharedspace’(Gallese 2003:172)thatsecures,bymeansofanembodiedsimulationattheneuronallevel,animmediate recognitionofotheraspersonswithintentionsandfeelingslikeourselves.Oneofthepioneersin thisresearch,theItalianneurophysiologistVittorioGallese,writes:‘Ourcapacitytoconceiveofthe acting bodies of others as persons like us depends on the constitution of a shared meaningful interpersonalspace[…]Embodiedsimulationconstitutesacrucialfunctionalmechanisminsocial cognition,anditcanbeneurobiologicallycharacterized’(2007:9). The discovery of mirror neurons is interesting, since it promises to break with the otherwise solipsistic tendency in contemporary cognitive neuroscience to study the anatomy and neurophysiologyofthebraininisolationfromtheinteractionwithotherbrains(Gallese2003:172; 2006:156).Ourworldisalreadyaworldofconcernsandneeds,oursandtheothers.Thereappears to exist an ‘unmediated resonance’ among individuals that secures an emotional understanding amongpersons(GoldmanandSripada2004:2078).Withoutexaggeratingtheimportanceofthe discovery,onecanatleastobservethatthepervasivenessofthenormativedoesnotcontrastwith current research. One of Ricoeur’s central points is that most, if not all, actions involve and influencethepresenceofotherpersons(pp.90).Normativityissimplyinstantiatedbythefactthat ourexistenceisdeeplyinterrelatedwiththeexistenceofotherpersons;ifwetakeintoaccountthe basic affective values that Panksepp argued for, we might say that this is so even in the deep subneocorticallayersofthebrain,.Themostbasicstructuresoflivingorganismsarecharacterized bynormativityinformofprimaryfeelingsofpain,anger,care,seeking,andpleasure.Thisis,of course,anextremelymorecomplexprocessinhumans,dueto,amongotherthings,theontological fragilityofournature(thevacillationbetweentobeandappeartobe);however,thereseemstobea

52 A fine and accessible introduction to mirror neurons is found in (Rizzolatti and Sinigaglia 2007), although the presentationissomewhatscaredbyaseriouslackofreservationandperspectiveonthecircumstancesandresultofthe discovery.Amoremodestpresentationofthediscoverywouldbetocharacterizeitasa‘promisingheuristictool’for future empirical investigation, as it is done elsewhere(Rizzolatti,Fogassi,andGallese2001:669). The speculative effortsurrondingtheresearchinmirrorneuronsoftenoutweightstheexactnessandrelevanceoftheempiricaldata.I thankDorothéeLegrandforpointingthisouttome(cf.Legrand2007:47071).

171 phylogenic continuity among mammals that involves the capacity of embodied simulations at a neuronallevelwhichprocuretheexperienceoftheworldthefundamentalfeatureofbeinga‘we centric shared space’ (Gallese and Umiltà 2006: 28). The affective dimension, our feelings, or sentimentsasHumewouldcallthem,revealsthisnormativefeatureofexperience. Thus,ifweaccept(asIdo)thatemotionalexperiencerevealsmanyoftheconcernsandneedsof humansubjects,thenitisthejobofethicalreflectiontounderstand,structure,andevaluatethesein relation to choice and action. Simon Blackburn, deeply inspired by Hume’s sentimentalism, has developedanethicaltheoryfromthiswayoflookingemotionsandethics.Hisviewisknownasa version of expressivism (Ayer, Hare, Gibbard). The theory argues that moral judgements are expressions rather than assertions of facts or beliefs. Moral judgements express feelings and attitudesanddonotdependontherealist’sobsessionwithtruthconditionals(Blackburn1984:191 196) 53 .ThetheoryfollowsHumealongway,butputanemphasisonlanguagethatwerenotpresent inhisethics(Blackburncametoethicsviaphilosophyoflanguage).Iwillnotgointodetailhere, butmainlysketchhowthisethicaltheorydependslargelyuponatheoryofemotion,andviceversa, howatheoryofemotionmusttakeintoaccountthemoraldimensionofemotionsoutlinedinthis theory.Thisinterrelationtellsussomethingabouttherealityofhumanexperiencethatwillhelpus reinforcethenotionofapracticalspaceofreason.Butinordertoshowthis,wewillneedtolookat someofBlackburn’sbasicarguments. Blackburn’sQuasirealismandtheExperienceofValues Blackburninsiststhatemotionsrevealalarge amount of the subject’s concerns and desires and explainshowsomeoftheseareconsideredasvaluesandothersnot.Ourconcernsanddesiresare orderedhierarchically:‘Weshouldthinkintermsofastaircaseofpracticalandemotionalascent [...]Thestaircasegivesusascalebetweenpurepreference,ontheonehand,andattitudeswithall theflavourofethicalcommitment,ontheother’(1998:9).Avaluediffersfromapurepreference orotherkindsofdesireinthat‘[t]oholdavalueistohavearelativelyfixedattitudetosomeaspects ofthings,anattitudewithwhichoneidentifiesinthesenseofbeingsettoresistchange,orsetto feelpainwhenconcernsarenotmet’(1998:68).Valuesare,asinHume,neithernaturalfactsnor supernatural entities, but something that the subject feels towards the world, itself and other

53 Inethicaldiscourse‘[t]heexistenceoftheverdict,ofcourse,dependsontheexistenceofthosecapableofmakingit, theexistenceofthetruthdependsonnothing(externally),andonthosefeaturesthatmakeitwrong(internally)[…] there is no doctrine to express relating the truth of the verdict to the existence of us, of our sentiments, or of rival sentiments’(Blackburn1988:1978).

172 subjects.Thisisnottobemisunderstoodasifvaluesweretodependonemotionsonly.Thisisnot so.Reasonhasalottosayinthestructuringandeducationofvaluesandpreferences.Thetheory onlyinsiststhatwithouttheemotionalaspecttherewouldnotbevaluesinthefirstplace.Emotions qualifythenaturalfactsaspreferences,concernsandvalues 54 .Blackburncallsthiskindofdoing ethicspracticalreasoninginthesensethatethicscannotbesomethingexternal(byareferencetoa naturalornonnaturalrealmofvalues)tohowthesubjectnormallythinks,feels,andacts.Values arepartofhowwethinkinourpracticalrelationtotheworld,ourselves,andothersubjects.Andin thispicture,emotionsplayaprominentrolebecausetheyrevealourconcernsandvalues.Thatis why a theory of emotions is important to this kind of ethics. The more we understand about emotionalexperience(inparticulartheinterrelationofactivityandpassivity,cognitionandfeelings, moodsandaffects),thebetterweareabletostructureourowndesiresandconcernsinaccordance tothoseofothers. Blackburn grounds his ethical analysis in what he calls quasirealism which he positions in between realism and antirealism in ethical debate. Realism (e.g. Kant, Plato, Moore, Nagel, Korsgaard)isthepositionthatunderstandsqualitiessuchasgoodnessandbadnessorrightnessand wrongnessasbeingactualpropertiesintheworld,oratleastcommittedtosomekindoftruth.Said otherwise,ourbeliefthatsomethingisgoodandanotherthingbadmustreflectsomeactualstateof affairs in the world. Our beliefs about the normative qualities of thingsare dependent on truth conditionals.Forexample,ifLouiseisakindperson,thenshemustpossessthetruequalitiesof kindness.ButwheredoIfindthesequalitiesthatmakeupherkindness?Therealistbelievesthatwe can find them independently of what we think or feel, that is, independently of our subjective nature.Theyneednotbeofsomeobscuremetaphysicalorder,but‘ratherjustthetruthaboutwhat weandothersshoulddoandwant’(Nagel1986:139).However,theproblemfortherealistishow toaccountforsuchatruthofvaluesandconduct.IfwearenottosearchforitinGod’sauthoritative commandments,aplatonicidealorder,orintheKingdomofEnds,howisitpossibletoarguefor thetrueexistenceofethicalqualitiesandpropositions? Thereisacommonagreementamong(most)realiststhatwecannotfindthetruthofmoralvalues andconductinthenaturalorderasitisrevealedbytheempiricalsciences.Thereforewe cannot understand moral values in empirical terms, but we would still have to argue for the objective 54 He writes, forexample:‘[The]talkofsomethingbeinggood,orsomethingbeingareasonforaction,isakindof reflectionofamotivationalstateofmind:thefactofsomethingweighingwithyou.Thismotivationalstateofmindis notasimplebelief.Itisnotarepresentationofsomeaspectoftheworld.Itisa reaction torepresentationofthefactof thematter.Itdoesnotitselfpickoutsomefactofthematter.Henceitisnotstrictlyspeakingastateofthemindthatis eithertrueorfalse,anymorethanadesireforcoffeeiseithertrueorfalse’(Blackburn1999:283).

173 existenceofthesesamevalues;otherwiseweslideintoasubjectivepositionwhichmeanstrusting thefragilenatureofourfeelingsandattitudes.Onewaytoavoidthesubjectivetreatistochoosea cognitiveapproachaswesawitinKant.Reasoncantelluswhatiswrongandwhatisright.This hasbeenexpressedas‘aclaimtolaworuniversability’sothat‘Ineedtowilluniversallyinorderto seemyactionassomethingwhich I do […]thefunctionofthenormativeprinciplesofthewill,in particular,istobringintegrityandthereforeunity–andtherefore,reallyexistence–totheacting self’ (Korsgaard 1996: 2289). The normative principles are sovereign because, just like Kant’s categorical imperatives, they govern and hold down selfinterest, disdain, selfishness, pleasing sentiments,andotherbadfeelingsandattitudes.Inestablishingfirmprincipleslikethis,wesecure thatouractionsareguidedbydisinterestedrulesofconductandnotbythewhimsandflawsofour fragilehumannature.IfwewanttoknowifLouiseactuallypossessesthetruequalitiesofkindness, wehavetoseeifher actionsaredoneoutof principles and not just feelings of kindness. The cognitiverealistfindstheobjectivityofmoralvalues(Louise’skindness)intheuniversalprinciples thatareepistemicallyaccessiblebytheworkofreasonalone. This might seem convincing if we exclude the question of naturalism (and that of moral psychology 55 ).Supposewearenaturalists(asIam)andthereforewanttoarguethattheempirical scienceshavesomethingimportanttolearnusaboutourselves,ournature,andthenatureofthe worldinwhichweliveourlife,howdowethenfind‘roomforethics,orofplacingethicswithin thedisenchanted,nonethicalorderwhichweinhabit,andofwhichwearepart’(Blackburn1998: 49)? One option is to be a moral antirealist (e.g. Ayer, Hare, and Mackie). Perhaps the most famous antirealist is the moral skeptic John L. Mackie. He bluntly states that ‘[i]f there were objectivevalues,thentheywouldbeentitiesorqualitiesorrelationsofaverystrangesort,utterly differentfromanythingelseintheuniverse’(1977:38). Whereastherealistiscommittedtosomekindofobjectivity,theantirealistneedsnotto,andcan thereforefreelyoptforsubjectivism,relativism,orevenskepticisminmoraldiscourse.Wecannot lockourcommitmentsontoanyobjectivestandard,becauseeventhoughwenormallythinkthatour claimofrightnessorwrongnesspossessessomekindofobjectivevalidity,thisisshown,oncloser scrutiny,nottobethecase.Mackiecallsthissortofdenial‘anerrortheory’(idem:35),becauseit demonstratesthatweareinerroreverytimeweusemorallanguageasifitreferredtosomereal, objective standards, rules, or principles. The problem about antirealism is that it often leads to 55 Remember Ricoeur’s scepticism regarding Kant’s feeling and desireless account of motivation which he calls ‘ethical dualism’ (pp. 37; FM 79/95). He writes bluntly that ‘no motive can incline me if it odes not impress my sensibility(pp.28;FN122/117)

174 relativism.Iftherearenoreal,objectivestandards,structures,orconditionsinmoraldiscourse,then theslipto‘anythinggoes’isveryeasy.Howarewetodetermineif‘shmoralising’isworseorbetter than‘moralising’inmoraldisagreementsifwehavenostandardstojudgeby (Blackburn1984: 186). Therefore, Blackburn characterizes moral relativism in the following harsh manner: ‘The moralrelativistbelievesthatarguingaboutethicaltruthislikearguingaboutthetruelocationofthe rainbow’(1998:298).Thefactremains,however,thatwhereasweseldomargueaboutthelocation ofrainbows,weveryoftenargueaboutwhatistherightthingtodo.Moraldiscourseisanattempt to solve moral problems, dilemmas, and conflicts; and although our beliefs in the standards by whichwejudgesomethingtobewrongorrightmightbeshowntobeinerror,‘itdoesnotfollow that the error infects the practice of moralizing, nor the concepts used in ways defined by that practice’(1985:150).Thisneedsexplanation.AndthatisexactlywhatBlackburnprovideswithhis argumentforathirdpositionthathehasnamedquasirealism.Basically,thecentralargumentgoes likethis:inordertosolvemoraldisputeordisagreement,weneedtoargueandpractice as though therewereactualmoraltruthtobehad,becauseourvaluesandnormsarepartlydependentupon ourownsentiments,feelings,andattitudes,andpartlyonthefactsthatwefindintheworld.Our valuesareexpressionsofourattitudestotheworld,ourselves,andtheother;inotherwords,we must‘understandtheethicalpropositionasafocusforpracticalthought’(1998:77;cf.1980:2930; 1984:209;1988:167). Thismayseem,intheeyesofsome,aratherweakattempttosqueezeethicsintoanaturalorder while still respecting the peculiar nature of our moral beliefs (McDowell 1997: 15966). Nevertheless,IbelievethatBlackburn’saccountofquasirealismactuallycentersonanimportant featureofourunderstandingoftheworld,namelythatourexperienceisconstitutedbyboththe unquestionableexistenceoftheworldandourpeculiarsubjectivenature.Wemightrememberthat thiswasoneofthebasicstructuresinRicoeur’stheoryofsubjectivity.Theworlddoesnotdepend onourwayoftakingit;itimposesitselfonusthroughourbodyandourbeingsituatedinit.And still,ourinteractionwiththeworld(andtheothersubjects)isalsodeterminedbyhowthatworld appearstousbymeansofourfivesenses,conceptualreasoning,andourfeelings.Weowemuchof whatweknowabouttheworld(thatitisnotflat)andourselves(thatwearenotthecenterofthe universe,andthatsmokingmighteventuallykillyou)totheempiricalsciences;therefore,theseare nottobeconsideredasaobstacleinethics(orasreasonsforethicalskepticismasinMackie’serror theory);onthecontrary,theycanbeahelptofurtherunderstandingthenatureofboththeworld thatweliveinandourownnature.Whatisimportant,however,istounderstandthatourvaluesand

175 normsarestilldifferentfromtheotherpropertiesdiscoveredbytheempiricalsciences,sincethey expresswhatispeculiarabouthumanexperienceoftheworld.Thisdoesnotmeanthattheyare independentofthefactualworld,because,asBlackburninsists,‘moralpropertiesmustbegivenan intelligible connection to the natural ones upon which they somehow depend’ (1984: 187). But thereisnouseinrunningaroundlookingfortruthconditionalsforourconductandvalues,sincewe must leave ‘ethical properties and propositions alone with their own specific identity. They are counters in our transactions with our values, just as a piece of money is a counter in financial transactions.Tounderstandthevalueofapieceofmoneyitisnousestarringatit.Itisnecessaryto understand the processes of human economic behavior […] We need the same eye for whole processesofhumanactionandinteraction.Weneedsynthesis,notanalysis’(1998:50). Now,quasirealismisveryclosetoprojectivisminthesenseitsurmisesvaluesandethicalqualities tobeaproductourattitudestotheworld,ourresponsestothingsandpeoplearoundus;weproject our ‘inner’ feelings, ideas, concerns onto the external world, and thereby the nonethical world becomes the world that we are concerned about; it becomesourworld.This,however,doesnot excludethattheworldatthesametimecanhaveitsownlawsthatourfeelingsandattitudescannot change.Onthecontrary,ourethicaldispositionsareexactlymoldedbythiscausality.Forexample, wedonotblameapersonlosinghismemorybecause he is becoming old or has suffered brain hemorrhage,orhavinghishatblownofonawindyautumnday.Butthenagain,wedoblamehim forpushingandpullinghimselfforwardonacrowdedstreetinJanuarybecausehehasforgottoput onwarmbootssonowhisfeetarefreezing,andhewantsgettoindoorsassoonaspossible.The quasirealistinsiststhattherearefactswhichareindependentofourprojectionsorexpressionsof attitudes, but he also states that some facts cannot be explained only by these facts or by the anonymouslawsgoverningthembecause‘theword‘fact’alsohasanuncorruptedEnglishsense:it isthefactthattherearecolours,andtherearemanyfactsaboutthem’(Blackburn1987:57).What thequasirealistopposesarenottheempiricalsciences,orthevalidityoftheirtheories,itisthe realist’s reduction of reality to an external world untouched by human attitudes, feelings, and perceptualcapacities;aworldinwhichcolorsandtastearecharacterizedas‘secondary’qualities withalesserdegreeofexistencethanthefirmsubstanceofmassandform.Itisevenworsewith moralfeelingssuchasshameorguiltorethicalproperties such as goodness and badness, since theseareveryhardtofitintoa‘squareworld’ofprimaryformsandmasses.Itwasthisproblemthat ledMackietobecomeamoralskepticandKanttoinvent the ‘Kingdom of Ends’ where ethical valuesareindeedprimaryandthe‘unnatural’purereasonthetickettocomealong.

176 Ethical properties, feelings, and values are as real as gravity and supersonic airplanes; indeed, sometimestheyevenseemmorerealoratleastmoreactualinourlives,becausetheyeffectively shapethewaywethinkaboutandactintheworld;theyconcernmemorefrequentlythangravity andsupersonicairplanes.Andexperiencesofethicalvaluessuchasgood,bad,guilt,orshameare differentfromexperiencesofmerepreferencesandidiosyncraticpropensitiesbythefactthatthey necessarilyinvolvethepresenceofotherpeople;theymustweightmoreonmythoughtsandaction thanmysecretlittlewhims,becauseitisbymeansofsuchstrongvaluesthatIorientmyselfinmy dailylife.IfIpaytoomuchattentiontomyownprivate feelings and concerns than to those of othersthenIam,rightfully,exposedtootherpeople’sreprobation.This,inturn,normallyleadsto feelingsofguiltandshame,whichisagoodandnaturalthing,because‘[w]ithouttheseemotions, themotivationtoactwellisdiminished’(Blackburn1998:20).Itisinthissensethatourfeelings revealwhatisimportanttous,whatwecareabout.Imaycareaboutmyfreezingfeetinacold Januaryafternoon,but,hopefully,Ialsocareaboutwhatotherpeoplethinkofme,thereforeIknow thatIshouldnotpushandpulltogofaster,andifIhaveactuallydoneso,guiltandshameare natural consequences of such a behavior. To exclude feelings and attitudes from ethics is what Stocker,withhisusualperspicuity,hascalled‘moralschizophrenia’,because‘[n]ottovaluewhat movesonealsobespeaksamaladyofthe’(Stocker1976:454).Itisschizophrenicbecauseof the split between motive and reason. My feeling of kindness or respect cannot be a motive for action,becauseitdoesnotfulfillthecriteriaofarealmoralreason.Bothutilitarianism(Mill)and deontology(Kant)isguiltyofsuchacharge,since‘[w]hatislackinginthesetheoriesissimply–or not so simply – the person. For, love, friendship, affection, fellow feeling, and community all requirethattheotherpersonbeanessentialpartofwhatisvalued’(idem:459). Quasirealism takes the dispositions, attitudes, and feelings of the subject so seriously that it inflatesthestatusofourevaluativepredicatessothatourprojectionsontotheexternalworldare treated as if theywerefactslikegravity,causality,andfreezingfeet. Infact,Blackburnadoptsa minimalistconceptionoftruthforhisquasirealismthat‘allowustoendupsaying´Itistruethat kindnessisgood´.Forthismeansnomorethanthat kindness is good, an attitude that we may properlywanttoexpress’(1998:79).Thefactthatourfeelings,attitudes,andactionscanbetrue and good does not entail an analysis of truthconditionals, but an eye for the workings of our practicalreasoning.Howdoweexperienceandactinaworldthatcontainsbothanonymousevents, whichcannotbeascribedmoralqualities,andmoralactionsthatinfactarecharacterizedbysuch ascriptions?Inaquasirealistpicture,thereisnotensionbetweenanaturalisticworlddescription

177 andamoraldiscourse;theybothtellussomethingaboutthefactsofaworldthatisfullofmany heterogeneousthingssuchanonymouscausality,sexualdesires,unconsciousinheriteddispositions toalcoholismorviolenceinformofDNAstructures,socialoppression,happyfaces,badluck,and, lastbutnotleast,maliciousandkindfeelings.Butwemustnotforgetthateventhoughvaluesand ethicalqualitiesdependsonandareinrelationtothefactsoftheempiricalsciencestheyhavetheir own special kind of identity, their own nature. In this Moore was right, all appropriate ethical reasoning depends on how well we understand that ethical notions are what they are and not somethingelse.Theyaredifferentfromothernotionsthatweareawareof(Moore1903:17).In fact,thedifficulttaskistoretainthecentralandoftenunsurpassableinsightoftherealist’saccounts aboutvaluesandethicalpropertieswithoutslidingintomysticalandinappropriateexplanationsof ideal orders (Platon), parochial virtues and small poleis (Aristotle), infinite Kingdoms of Ends (Kant),solidnaturalutility(Mill),oranintuitionistcapacity(Moore)?Blackburnproposesthatwe considerethicalpropositionsaboutthingsandpersonstobeconstitutedbythefactthattheyreflect ourconcerns;thatis,ourvalues,feelings,dispositions,andattitudesthatcomeswithliving(1998: 80).Tounderstandthemeaningoftheseconcerns,weneedunderstandhowwethink,feel,andact with respect to the concerns that characterize the persons that we are. And here Blackburn introducesanotionthatcomesveryclosetothenotionofthepracticalspaceofreason,whichI proposedinmyreformulationofRicoeur’stheoryofsubjectivity,namely practical reasoning .He does so, because he insists that ‘[e]thics remains essentially practical, a matter of attitude, disposition,andemotion’(idem:65). In the concluding sections, I will pursue this idea of practical reasoning, but no longer with particularattentiontoBlackburn’sanalyses,sinceIamhereprimarilyconcernedwiththerelation betweensubjectivityandethicsandnotwithnatureofethicalreasoningitself.Iwillusehisquasi realismtogetherwithGoldie’sexternalperspectiveonemotionalexperienceinordertogiveafinal articulation of, and hopefully strengthen, my central argument that subjective experience is primordiallyconfiguredasapracticalspaceofreason. ExperienceasStructuredbytheValueoftheOther’sConcerns My reformulation of Ricoeur’s theory of subjectivity developed a central idea that I named the practicalspaceofreason.EventhoughRicoeurneverusedordiscussedasimilarconcept,Ibelieve thathistheoryimplicatesthatsubjectiveexperienceisprimarilystructuredaccordingtoahierarchy ofheterogeneousvaluesorganizedbythepracticaluseofreason.Thesubjectexperiencestheworld

178 asameaningfulorganizationofthingsandeventsthatmatterstothesubjectasaperson.Thingsand eventshaveavalueforthesubjectinthesensethatthesubjectisalways,somehow,concernedwith what it experiences. Experience is never without feeling, and the subject’s sense of agency and ownership,‘theipseityoftheexperientialdimension’or‘aminimalsenseofself’(Zahavi2005: 146),isalwayspermeatedbynormativity.Onemightsaythattobeasubjectisnotonlytoactand experiencethatitisIwhoactandexperience,butalsotofeelthatthissenseofselfmattersinsome wayortheother.Ialways relate myselftotheworld,theother,andmybeingthisperson,although this is often in a prereflective, unmediated sense of the word. Ricoeur individuated this basic relatedness in the nature of the subject as an ‘affective fragility’ in the heart of the subject. Subjectivityisfragileinnatureandcharacterizedbyunrest,oftenevenconflict,betweenvitaland spiritualdesires,betweentheoriginatingaffirmationandtheexistentialdifferencethatcharacterize everysubject.Thisconflictis,firstofall,revealedbytheaffectivedimension,thatis,thefeelings thatcharacterizethebeingofthesubject.Ricoeur,however,isnotveryclearordetailedaboutthe affectivedimension,althoughhecontinuestoemphasize it fundamental importance. Therefore, I havespentconsiderabletimeondevelopingamoreelaborate account of affectivity,both from a philosophicalandneurophysiologicalperspective,inordertosustaintheimportanceoffeelingsina theory of human subjectivity. Feelings reveal values and the pervasive nature of normativity. Panksepp’s account of affective consciousness insists that feelings are constitutive of basic ecologicalvaluesinformofinstinctualaffective behavior that influences the subject both in its reflectiveandprereflectiverelationtotheworld,theother,anditself.DeSousa,Solomon,Strasser, andGoldieclaimedthatfeelingshaveaninformationalimportancethatsurpassesmeresubjective whimsandinclinations.Iusedtheiraccountstodevelopamodelwhichincludesmoodsamongthe feelingsthatrevealthenormativecharacterofpersonhood.Ibelievethatthenotionofpersonhood isimportantinordertofullyunderstandthenormativesignificanceofmorediffuseandatmospheric feelingsinvolvedinmoods.Emotionalexperience(thatisexpressedbytheconceptofemotions) containsbothclearaffectsanddiffusemoods,andweneedamodelthatexplainsbothinorderto understandwhatwemeanbyaffectiveexperience. Inthischaptersofar,Ihavetriedtoshowhowemotionsareimportantfortheethicaldiscussionof valueandconductbasicallybecause,asBlackburnhasshow,emotionsshowuswhatwe actually careabout,ourconcernsaboutandattitudestotheworldandotherpersons.Ethicalreflectionisa practical matter about how we handle our emotions and organize our concern in our daily interactionwithotherpersons.Blackburn’squasirealisminsistsontheimportanceofthesubjective

179 natureofourexperience.Weshouldnotconsiderouraffectiveexperienceaslessinformativeor lessfactualthanour‘cool’,detachedreasoning.Bothhavetheirholdonhumannatureandbothare part of our experience of a world qualified by values. The realist’s sharp distinction between subjectivityandobjectivityintalkingaboutvaluescrumplesinfrontoftheexperientialdimension ofhumanconcerns.Subjectiveexperience,becauseitisemotionalexperience,alwaysinfluencethe waywetalkaboutvalueandethicaldispositions.Ouractionsaredoneoutofreasons,andreasons areconstitutedbydifferentmotives,and,asRicoeur,Blackburn,andStockerpointout,wecannot disregardemotionsasconcretemotiveforactionwithoutendingupinwhatStockercalls‘moral schizophrenia’. In fact, I doubt that any motive canbe completely feelingless. As Humepointed out, emotions arepart of ‘the original fabric andformationofthehumanmind’.Valuesandthe normativedimensionofsubjectivityareasrealandfactualasanyaspectofthesubject.Thevalues andnormativeoutlookbywhichweleadourlifemaybemoredifficulttohandleanddecideonthan abrokenarmortheboilingtemperatureofwater,buttheyexistinthesamefactualmannerassuch things.Ithasrecentlybeenarguedagainstthemetaphysicalrefutationoftherealityoftheself(cf. Strawson 1999 or Metzinger 2003) that ‘why not rather insists that the self is real if it has experientialrealityandthatthevalidityofouraccountoftheselfistobemeasuredbyitsabilityto befaithfultoexperience,byitsabilitytocaptureandarticulate(invariant)experientialstructures’ (Gallagher and Zahavi 2008: 213). The same argument holds for normative experience, since, accordingtomyarguments,theselfisinthemost basic experiential structures an affective and normative being. This is so because subjective experience is primarily structured as a space of practicalconcernsthatareindeedorganizedandhandledbyreason,butprereflectivelyexperienced asvaluesthataffectusthroughourfeelings.Theseconcernsarehierarchicallyorganizedintermsof theheterogeneousvaluesthatweexperienceinourbeingintheworld;or,asBlackburncallsit,‘a staircaseofpracticalandemotionalascent’.WhenIseeapencilinfrontofme,Idonotexperience it as small object with specific physical characteristics, some primary (form and extension) and somesecondaryqualities(colorandtaste),butasathingwithspecificaffordancesthatenablemeto perform certain actions 56 . Things or events are always experienced in some kind of relation to

56 ThishasbeenanalyzedthoroughlybyHeideggeras‘zuhandenheit’and‘vorhandenheit’(Heidegger1996:xx/6676). Hewrites,forexample:‘Again,thesurroundingworldmakesitselfknown.Whatappearsinthiswayisnotitselfone thing[Zuhandenes]amongothersandcertainlynotsomething objectively present [Vorhandenes ]whichliesatthebasis oftheusefulthingathand[zuhandeneZeug].Itis“there”beforeanyonehasobservedorascertainedit[…]Thatthe worlddoesnot“consist”ofwhatisathandcanbeseenfromthefact(amongothers)thatwhentheworldappearsinthe modesoftakingcare which we havejustinterpreted, whatisat handbecomesdeprivedofits worldliness sothat it appearsassomethingmerelyobjective[NurvorhandenseinzumVorscheinkommt][…]Whentheworlddoesnotmake

180 myself that is revealed by the feelings that the thing or event awakes in me. I value what I experiencebeforeIreflectivelyrelatemyselftothatthing.ThevaluesthatIexperiencemaynotbe very clearorarticulate,butthey affectmeonaprereflectivelevel.Itisnotpossibletoseparate clearly between the objectivity and subjectivity of the value, since the experience of values is constituted, as we have seen, by my peculiar subjective, personal nature and the objective, anonymousnatureoftheworld.Buttosaythatavalueisonlyrealifitcanbedetachedfromthe natureofthesubjectiveexperiencethatconstitutesitisabsurd.Therefore,Blackburndevelopedthe notion of quasirealism to save both the reality of values and the importance of subjective experience as a constitutive element of values. If we want to talk about the reality of values as independent of subjective experience, then we should at least concede that there are objective structures in subjective experience that reveal more than just the particular values of individual subjects. The philosopher Lars Christiansen describes beautifully this complex relation between objectivityandsubjectivityofexperience:‘Althoughexperienceinawaycanbesaidtocomefrom ourselves,itisnotselfimposedinanydisqualifyingmanner;wearenotthemastersofexperience, it is in this regard as objective as the thing itself. One could just as well criticize daylight for falsifyingthethings,becauseitdoesnotcomefromthembutfromthesun’;orevenmoreacutely some pages later, ‘Here music can teach us something. A scientific ideologist who overhears someonepraisingthebenevolentsunwouldrefertothefactthatthesunissimplyaglowingbubble of gasses, and how could anyone praise gasses? In the same manner, one could imagine an unmusicalpersonrejectingaviolinconcertwithreferencetothefactthathereitisactuallyjusta matterofrubbinghorsehairagainstthebowelsofacat’(Christiansen1980:71,74.Mytranslation). Experience configured as a practical space of reason means that our experiences are always affectedbyhowwevaluetheexperiencedobjectsandevents.Weperceiveobjectsandeventsas meaningfulthingsandeventsthatsomehowconcernusandrevealthevaluesbywhichweorient ourselvesintheworldthatwelivein.Ourconcernsareexpressedinourfeelings,dispositions,and attitudes.Andourvaluesareexpressedinourconcerns,inthesensethatwe‘cancallthethingsthat mattertousour concerns ’(Blackburn1998:123).Whenwetalkaboutreality,weshouldnotforget that our way ofexperiencingisalsoarealitythatweimmediatelyrelateourselvesto,althoughsome mightfinditalesserrealitythantheonedisclosedbytheempiricalsciences. Nonetheless,thedistinctionbetweensubjectivityandobjectivityisstillessentialforunderstanding thenatureofourvaluesandconcerns.Butwemustunderstandwhatwemeanbysubjectiveand itself known, that is the condition for the possibility of what is at hand not emerging from its inconspicuousness’ (70/75).

181 objective.Tosaythatmyconcernsreflectonlywhat Icareabout,notregardingwhatotherscare aboutiscompletelytomisunderstandthenatureofsubjectiveexperience.Oneofthepointsthat Ricoeur returns to again and again is that ‘[ t]o say self is not to say myself ’ (OSA 180/212). Subjective experience does not only reflect the narrow preferences and predilections of the individualsubject;itisconstitutedbytheworld and especially the other subjects. The practical space of reason is therefore not confined to the point of view of the individual subject. The experienceitselfisofcourseindividualinthesensethatIamtheonewhohastheexperience,but whatisimportantistheexperientialnatureofwhatIexperience.Subjectiveexperienceisstructured asacommonexperientialspaceinwhichIamimmediatelyawareofthepresenceofothersubjects. Myperspectiveisnottheonlyperspective;andIknowthisnotbymeansofreflection,butitisa prereflectiveawarenessthatisdevelopedbysocialexchangesinearlyinfancy(abouttwomonths old)andbecomesanessentialfeatureofhumanexperienceoftheworld.Weexperiencetheworld and our actions in it from both our first person perspective and a ‘ third person or allocentric perspective ’ that together are ‘combined to form new triadic meanings’ (Rochat 2007: 16). I am aware that the chair has a back that I cannot see but is visible to another subject in different position,or,inthesamemanner,Iamprereflectivelyawarethatmyactionhasconsequencesfor otherpersonsbecausemyexperienceandactionissituatedandembeddedinspaceconstitutedby the world, the other, and myself. Hence, the practical space of reason is noninferentially intersubjective,becauseperception,intention,andactionsarestructuredinrelationtoalterity:‘the three dimensions “self,” “others,” and “world” belongtogether,theyreciprociallyilluminateone another, and can be fully understood only in their interconnection’ (Zahavi 2005: 176). The intersubjectivestructureofsubjectiveexperienceissignificant,becauseittellussomethingabout theobjectivenatureofsomeofourconcernsandthequasirealisticnatureofvalues WemetthisideaearlierinGoldie’sanalysesofemotionalresistanceandtheexternalperspective. Whenwedoanactionwemightfeelanemotionalresistancethatcannotbeexplainedbyotherthan ourcapacitytoimmediatelyseethatactionfromanallocentricorexternalperspective.Thisreveals thecompleximportanceoffeelingsinourexperienceoftheworld.Myfeelingsarenotonlyan expressionofmyprivateconcerns,butalsotheexpressionoftheconcernsofothers.Totalkabout concernsinvolvetheothersubject’svaluesaswellasmyown.Theexternalperspectiveindicates thiscomplexityintheconcernsthatstructuremyexperience.Myvaluesaredevelopedandrefined by living in a world that does not obey my will (I do become older no matter what I do, and therefore IperhapslearntocherishthevalueofthingsthatseemedridiculoustomewhenIwas

182 younger, for example sitting in a quiet cornfield counting crows). In the same way, social interactionwithotherpeopleaffectsthewayIamconcernedwithwhatgoesoninmylife.These concerns may be implicit and cognitively impenetrable, but are nevertheless revealed in my attitudes and feelings (my moods and affects). The practical space of reason is constituted by heterogeneousvaluesinthesensethatmyconcernsforthingsandeventsarenotrestrictedtoonly my perspectivebutalwaysaffectedbyalterity.Thisalternityisanessentialpartoftheconstitution of selfhood (involuntariness, passivity, body, time, world, and the other, as we have seen in Ricoeur)andisexpressedinthestructureofourexperience.Theexternalperspectiveisaninherent featureofourexperience,becauseweareprereflectivelyawareofothernesswhenweperceive,act, feel,andthink.Goldiecharacterizedit(inspiredbyWollheim)asacentrallyimaginingtoemphasize that the experience is not egocentrically structuredbutinvolves aperspectivedifferentfromour own. The fact that we experience a phenomenon such asemotionalresistanceindicatesthatthis externalperspectivedoesnotcomeaftertheimmediateexperienceaspartofalaterreflectionupon what happened. We can experience an emotional resistance to our own actions, feelings, and thoughts.Suchfeelingsoftenarisebeforewereflectivelyrelateourselvestowhathashappened.It islayereddeepinourownwayofexperiencingandactinginaworldsharedwithotherpersons.Of course,thisimmediatereactiontothingsandevents,actionsandsufferings,thoughtsandmemories needsareflectiveapproachinordertobefullyunderstood,butthisisnotthepointhere.Whatis essentialisthattheembodiedandsituatednatureofourexperienceisstructuredinsuchawaythat, whetherwelikeitornot,ourconcernsareinherentlyconstitutedbyvaluesthattranscendsourown pointofview,ourownlikesanddislikes.ThisexplainswhyRicoeurcalledvalueaquasiconcept (pp.95).Wecannotdeterminethenatureofavalueapriorioruniversally,asKorsgaarddoesshe when ‘tries to move from the fact that we have reflective distance from our impulses to the requirement that we conceive our reasons as universal, at least in the formal sense’ (Korsgaard 1996:225).Humanvaluesarenotformal.Theydependonthesubjectivenatureofhumanbeings, socialandculturalcontexts(inChinatheyactuallyeatman’sbestfriend),historicaldevelopment (thunderandlightningisnolongerconsideredwrathofthe,butonlybadluckifonehappens tobeoutdoors).However,thisisnotthesametosaythatvalueissubjectiveinarelativisticsense like‘thisisrightbecauseitisrightforme,andyoucannottellmeotherwiseorconvincemethatI amwrong!’Ourvaluesaregroundedintheconcernsofother.WhenIexperiencetheworld,Ipre reflectivelyseethingsandeventsfromdifferentperspectives,andmyownconcernsaretherefore necessarilyinterwovenwiththoseofotherpersons.Thus,ourfeelings,dispositions,andattitudes

183 (i.e. our character) are an essential source of normativity. They reveal how ethical questions are impossibletogetbehindinunderstandingthenatureofsubjectivity.Weareconcernedaboutthe other,whetherwelikeitornot.Ontheotherhand,subjectivityisanecessarypartofanapproachto ethics, because values cannot be understood without taking into account the subjective (quasi conceptualorquasirealistic)constitutionofvalues.Tounderstandwhyweactthewaywedo,we havetounderstandthenatureofourbeinghumansubjects.Blackburnsaysitmuchbetterthanme: ‘Itisonlywhenwehavehumannatureundersomecontrolthathumanethicalnaturecomesunder control’(1998:v). This may seem a somewhat thin argument for the relation between subjectivity and nature. Therefore,inthe concludingsection, I willtryto strengthen the argument by grounding it in a developmentofwhatRicoeurcalledanontologyofcare.Thiswillalsobeofhelpinthelastpart whereIdiscussthespecificproblemsofneuroethics,moralrelativism,theconceptionofnature. An Ontology of Care: Personhood and the Conflictual Nature of Subjectivity Theethicaldimensionofsubjectivityseemstodemandtheuseof‘thick’ethicalconceptssuchas generosity, courage, goodsense, prudence, kindness, cruelty, duty, moderation, and so on. Such thickconceptsdescribethecharacterofaperson,thedispositions,andultimatelyitsethicalstatusas amoralagent.Somethinkthattoreducethickconceptstothinconcepts,suchasgood,bad,right, true,wrong,istodissolveethicalqualitiesintowhattheyarenot.Wecannotexplainwhyaperson isgenerousbyrefereeingtosimpleminimalfacts.Weneedtoseethethickethicalconceptsasbasic irreducibleconceptstoorientourselves‘inmoralspace’(Taylor1989:28).Toknowwhattodo whenfacedwithmoralproblem,Ihavetoknowthebasicthickconceptsofmoraldiscourse.These conceptscannotbyexplainedbyfactsthataredifferent.Crueliscruelandkindiskind,andthese conceptsarefirmreferencepointsnomatterwhatwedo.Theyareprinciplesthatcannotbediluted intomorethinqualitiessuchasgoodandbad.Anethicalminimalistseesitdifferently.Heorshe seesthethicknessas‘overdramatic[…]Itimpliestooreadyatendencytodiagnosethediscussion and reevaluation that are essential of ethical activity as exercise in talking past each other’ (Blackburn1992:299).Thefactisthatmostofthetimewedonottalkpasteachother.Weknow whatwetalkabouteventhoughweneverusethewordskindorcruel;thatis,wedonotneeda special concept to determine the quality of an action. Our ethical disposition (values, rules of conduct,andfirmprinciples)dependsonourattitudesandfeelings,onwhatwecareabout,andnot onourabilitytounderstandthesemanticpropertiesoflexicalexpressions.Wemustlookatthe

184 practical aspect of human life and the basic structure of care in order to understand ethical dispositions. In the previous chapter, I argued that a concept of personhood is essential for understanding human affectivity, since feeling always involve the nature of the beings that experiencethem.Andhumansubjectsarepersons.However,Ricoeurnoticedthatthisfactinvolves thetaskofbecomingaperson.Thesubjectcaresaboutbeingaperson,andveryoftenacertainkind ofperson.Feelingsdirectandfocusourattentiontothingsthatmattertousasaperson,because ‘havingemotionsandnoticingandattendingarecloselyinterrelated’(Stocker1996:85). Inthis way,ourfeelingsandattitudesrevealthisproblematicfragilityintheconceptofpersonhood.One cannotfailtobeaperson,butveryoftenwefailatbeingthepersonthatwewanttobe. Thecentralproblemishowtoexplainthevaluesthatweliveourlifeby.Aretheygroundedina specialmoralontologythatgovernshumanlifeandtheconceptofpersonhood,oraretheysimply expressionsofourfeelings,attitudesanddispositions, and therefore part of a natural world that knowsnothingofkindnessandjustice,goldlitteredcloudsorthevalueofBraque’scubistictrees?I havearguedthatsubjectiveexperienceisconstitutedbykindness,laughter,andgoldlitteredclouds aswellasbyindifferentforcesofphysicsandevolution,becauseourexperienceisconfiguredasa practicalspaceofreasonstructuredaccordingtoheterogeneousvaluesderivedfromboththeworld, theotherandtheself.Ourcrueltyandgoodnessarejustasnaturalasthefallingofraindropsor diarrhea.Idonotthinkthatweneedaspecialmoralontologytothickenourbehaviorinorderto findgenerosity,benevolence,brutality,orevil.Allwehavetodoistorespectthecomplexityofour feelingsandrefinetheontologythatexplainsourbeingintheworld.However,beforeIexplainmy ideaofsucharefinedontology,whichincludesboththefragilityofpersonhoodandnaturalvalues, Iwilltakeabrieflookononeofthemostinfluential and acute defenders of an explicit moral ontology,namelyCharlesTaylor. TheMoralSpaceandStrongEvaluations Firstofall,ImuststartbysayingthatIaminspiredbyTaylor’sworkonsubjectivity,personhood, andmorality.TheonlyproblemthatIhavewithhiswritingsisasmalldetailthatcan,however, haveimportantconsequences.Thisishisviewonnaturalism.Inoverfortyyears,Taylorhaswritten against naturalistic explanations of human behavior, and I am in perfect agreement with his rejectionofreductionistaccountsofagencyandpersonhood.Butnaturalismisnotasynonymfor reductionism. To be a naturalist is not necessarily to hold that all can be explained by the mechanismsofphysicsandchemistry,butthatthesebranchesoftheempiricalsciencescanhelpus

185 understandthenatureofhumanbeings.Tayloriswellawareofthisandwouldnotdisagreewithan ambition to find a convergence between, for example, neurophysiology and human subjectivity (1971:1789).Theproblemisthathemakessuchaconvergencequitedifficult.Heholdsastrong realistideaofmoralityandanevenstrongeraversiontoantirealistorquasirealistideasaboutthe projectivenatureofethicalvalueinadisenchantedphysicaluniverse(1989:59,78).Hemaintains thatwecannotexplainmoralexperiencebyotherthanrealmoralvaluesthathavenothingtodo withthenaturalisticinspired‘gutreactions[…]similartothoseofbaboons’(idem:15;cf.6)or ‘weakevaluations’(1976:116).Realmoralvaluesareexpressednotbyourfeelings,butbystrong evaluations that secures a ‘subject who strongly evaluates desires, goes deeper, because he characterizeshismotivationatgreaterdepth.Tocharacterizeonedesireorinclinationasworthier, ornobler,ormoreintegrated,etc.thanothersistospeakofitintermsofthekindofqualityoflife which it expresses and sustains’ (1977: 25). Any attempt to naturalize or dilute these strong evaluationsinaquasirealistpictureistounderminemorality(1989:6). Ibelieve,onthecontrary,thatwecanmaintainethicalcommitmentandthequalityofhumanlife withoutnecessarilyadoptingthestrongvocabularythatTaylorarguesfor.Althoughitmayseema contradiction,Isurmisethathisanalysescanbeusedinalower,i.e.,lessantagonistic,tonetoargue forthenaturalisticnatureofvalues.Hisperceptiveinsightsintotherelationbetweenpersonhood, emotions,andvaluescanbeusedtoargueforapracticalspaceofreasoninsteadofamoralspace. Thenotionofamoralspacestructuredbystrongevaluationsandthickconceptsputmoreweighton thereflectivenatureofhumanvaluesthanthesecanbear.Thevaluesbywithweliveourlifeare tooheterogeneousanddiscordanttobeenvelopedinconsciouslyendorsedmoralprinciples.Many of our less noble and more selfish concerns affect ourthoughts,feelings,andactionsinamuch strongerwaythanisallowedinamoralspace.Itisnotjustamatterofpurifyingmypersonforsuch nonmoralconcerns.Myidentityactuallydependsonthosemore‘dirty’evaluationsjustasmuchas onthemorestrongqualitative(clearlymoral)ones.AsRicoeurobserved,ourexistenceisorganized by practices that are basically more ethical than moral; that is, the idea of living well is not primarilyamoralone,butabouthavingagoodlife.Thecharacterizationof‘good’isnotonlya matterofmoralnormsandobligations,butbeingabletoliveaccordingtothevaluesthatinclude suchmoralnormsasa part ofmyownconcerns.Myhierarchyofvaluesmustofcoursereflectthe normsthatgovernmyinteractionwithotherpersons,buttheyareintrinsicallyintermingledwithmy ownideasandnastylittledesiresthatmaybeindirectcontrasttothenorms,whichIholdtobepart ofthepersonthatIam.Myexistenceismorethanmoralbehavior,andoftenmoralbehavioris

186 moreawishthanafactbecause,asBlackburnwrites,‘JagoisjustasnaturalasMotherTheresa, andonaheadcountperhapsmoreso’(1998:48).Tobeanaturalististorelyontheempirical sciencesforimportanthelpinunderstandinghumanbehavior,feeling,andthought,butitisalsothe temperateobservationofourselvesandothersinthedailyroutinesofhumanlife.Here(alas!)we seldomfindactionsdoneoutofconsciouslyendorsedmoralprinciplesbutoutofaheterogeneous variety of motives and values (from the most depraved aggression to the most warmhearted unselfishdeed). ThereareseveralreasonswhyIhavechosentoanalyzesubjectivitybymeansofapracticalspace ofreasoninsteadof‘theselfinmoralspace’.Asmentionedabove,Ithinkthattherearemanynon moralsourcesoftheself.Further,thereformulationofRicoeurpointedinthatdirection.Fordespite allhisemphasisonmoralconstitutionofthesubjectivity,Ricoeurhaskeeneyefortheself(ish)in theconceptofaperson,thetensionbetweenself(theI)andselfhood(theperson).Thisisthenon coincidenceintheheartofthesubjectthatmakespersonhoodfragileandvulnerable.Tobeaperson isataskofbecomingaperson;thesubjecthastobalancetheheterogeneousvaluesthatorientits existenceinordertoliveasapersontogether, with,andforotherpersons 57 .Thepracticalspace explainssuchheterogeneousvaluesandthemeanstoendreasoningthatcharacterizessomanyof ourconcerns.And,atthesametime,itfulfillstheformalcriteriaofTaylor’smoralspace.Taylor argues that we need a moral space to explain our (modern) moral thinking, which has three principleaxes:1)senseofrespectofothers,2)afulllife,and3)dignity(attitudinal)(1989:15). These three axes make up the three dimension of the moral space, which is the ‘background, explicit or implicit, for our moral judgements, intuitions or reactions (idem: 26). This space is constitutive of human agency because ‘stepping outside these limits would be tantamount to stepping outside what we would recognize as integral, that is, undamaged human personhood’ (idem:27).ThedifferencebetweenTaylor’sspaceandmineisthatIdonotthinkthatwehaveto include strong evaluations as a basic constitutional feature of what explains human agency or personhood.Thisisnottobeunderstoodasifwecouldexistwithoutstrongevaluations.Onthe contrary,theyareacentralpartofwhatitistobeahumanperson.Ionlysaythatthepracticalspace ofreasoncanaccountforsuchevaluationsintermofamore‘weak’explanation,i.e.,intermsof 57 ThisisthecentralpointinhiscriticismofLévinas,namelythatanontologyofsubjectivitycannotbegroundedinan asymmetricalconceptionof selfandother.Therefore,he writesthat ‘Selfimputation[…]is nowinscribed withina asymmetrical dialogic structure whose origin lies outside me’ which means that ‘No middle ground, no between, is securedtolessentheutterdissymmetrybetweentheSameandtheOther’(OSA336/388,338/390).Thisdissymmetry resultsina‘hyperboleofseparation’that‘rendersunthinkable[…]thedistinctionbetweenselfandI,andtheformation ofselfhooddefinedbyitsopennessanditscapacityfordiscovery’(idem339/391).

187 concern or care and practices. I found this idea on the affective dimension of personhood. Our feelingsaretooheterogeneousandpervasivetobeheldwithinthearmorofmorality.Evenourmost consciousendorsedprincipleisrootedinfeelings,althoughthismightnotbetheclearintentional emotions that we usually associate with emotional experience (fear as well as benevolence). Feelingshavemanyexpressions(consciouslyandunconsciously),whichIhavetriedtoshowbymy extendedanalysisofmoodsandaffects.Ouridentityhingesonourfeelings,becausethecomplexity of personal identityis,aswehaveseen,oftencognitivelyimpenetrable.Myidentityisnotonlya matterofhowIconsciouslyrelatemyselftothepersonthatIam.Sometimesfeelingsrevealwhatis hiddenbeneathmyactions,emotionalreactions,dispositions,orcharacter.Icannotunderstandwhat iswrongwithme,andthatthatabsenceofunderstandingisaconstitutivepartofmyidentityasa person. Further,asTaylorrightlyobserves,feelingsarewhatsecuresthesignificanceofthethingsforme (Taylor1981:1079).Infact,Taylor’sanalysesoftheemotionalaspectofsignificance,whichhe calls ‘the import of a given situation’ (1977a: 49), is critical for my own account about the irreduciblyinformativenatureofemotionalexperience.Taylorcallsthisthe‘fullbloodedactivity’ thatmakesahumanbeingandafrogdifferentfromacalculator,because‘things matter toliving beings’ (Taylor1988:450).Ourfeelingsreveal whatwecareabout,andwedocareaboutmore thanjuststrongevaluations.Wecareaboutgettingthekidtoschool,smokingourcigarettes,our (lackof)hair,thepersonallifeofBritneySpears,thesizeofourtelevision,ourfather’sbadhealth, thebalanceofourbankaccount,andsoon.Theseareallpartofwhatmakesusthepersonsthatwe are. Naturally, dignity, fullness of life, and respect of others are more important than a new beautifully expensive sweater, and therefore these strong issues should instantiate the supreme compassbywhichweorientourselvesinlife.Nevertheless,theidentitycrisisthatTaylordescribes as‘anacuteformofdisorientation,whichpeopleoftenexpressintermsofnotknowingwhothey are,butwhichcanalsobeseenasaradicaluncertaintyofwheretheystand’(1989:27)isnotonly thelackofframeworkof‘stablesignificance’,whichisinitselfararephenomenon,butalsodueto thestructuralfragilityofsubjectivity.IbelieveTayloriscompletelyrightwhenheemphasizesthe moralaspectofthefragilityofmodernidentity,butIdonotthinkthatheisrightwhenheargues thatanaturalisthumanismisdefectiveinthesensethatithindersuniversalbenevolencebecauseit doesnotidentifyitwiththeChristianagapē(idem:5168).Ifwewanttounderstandthenormative constitutionofhumansubjectivity,wecannotapproachitasa moral questionaboutorientationin terms of strong evaluations. Normativity is present in every action, feeling, and thought of the

188 subject,butweneedamoredeflatedformofmoralityinordertoseehowmoralityissomething thatwecannotleaveoutofafactualdescriptionofthehumansubject.Idonotdoubtthatstrong evaluationsaresomeofthemostfirmandreliable supportsforourfragilenature,andthatthey cannot be left out of any serious account of subjectivity. Nonetheless, I am convinced that the practical space of reason can account for such evaluations without excluding the naturalistic understanding of values. Subjective experience is configured by a hierarchy of heterogeneous valuesthatcomeswithlivinginaworld,whichdoesnotchangebecauseIwantitto,andtogether with other human subjects that demand that I recognize their personhood. But these values themselves are not clear and neither is my hierarchy, because, somehow, that world and other peoplearestillwhatItakethemtobe.Myexperienceoftheworldisalwaysconstitutedbythis difficult relation between my self and alterity (body, world, and other). I sometimes (too often) valuethingswrongly,andthisisrevealedbecausemyexperienceandmyownbeingapersonis constitutedbythatwhichisnotme(theworldandotherpersons).Myexperientialandinteractive relationtotheworldisprimarilypracticalinthesensethatmyexistencedependsonhowIinteract withtheworldandotherpeopleonpracticallevel.Thus,Ihavearguedthatsubjectiveexperienceis primarilyconfiguredasapracticalspaceofreasonaccordingtoheterogeneousvaluesexpressedin myconcernsorratherinwhatIcareabout. Now,myfinalargumentwillbeabouttheontologicalsignificanceofpersonhoodinrelationtothe notionofcareandtheconflictualnatureofhumansubjectivity.Hopefully,theseconcludingpages willreinforcemyargumentfortheirreduciblerelationbetweensubjectivityandethics. OntologyandPersonhood:TheConflictualNatureofSubjectivity Thenotionofapracticalspaceofreasonhasbeenthecentralthemeupuntilnowandthenotionthat bindsthedifferentanalysestogether.Subjective experienceisprimarily configuredas apractical spaceofreasonthatisstructuredbytheheterogeneityofvaluesgeneratedandshapedbytheworld, theother,andtheself.Humanexperiencealwaysimpliesanexperienceofvaluesrevealedbywhat wecareabout,ourconcerns.Experienceandactionaresointerlacedthatexperienceofobjectsand eventsisbasicallypractical.Weperceiveobjectsandeventsas things and situations thatconcern us;inshort,wecareaboutwhatweexperience. Theaffectivedimensionisaprimarysourceofinformation,sinceourfeelingsmaketheworld,the other, and our existence in general matter to us. Experience without feelings is unthinkable, because,asStockerputsit,‘humanlifeisthroughandthroughaffectiveandinlargeandimportant

189 waysconstitutedorperfectedbyaffectivity.Further,humanlife,initsvariousforms,isjudgedin terms of affectivity – importantly, by whether and how it succeeds or fails in developing, expressing, and satisfying affective needs’ (Stocker 1996: 325). There is no getting behind our feelingsifwewanttounderstandhumansubjectivity.Infact,affectivityisanimportantpartofthe basic structure of subjective experience (receptivity), and as such it influences all our capacities (perception,reason,will,andaction).Toseparatereasonandfeelingistomisunderstandthenature of human experience, since human experience is always emotional experience. Further, it is an expressionofmistrusttohowweactuallythinkabouttheworldandourselves,andareductionof the heterogeneity of feelings to ‘mere bodily’ induced phenomena. All experience is embodied experience, which means that we reason in terms of our bodily constitution, so excluding mere feelingsistowanttogetridofafundamentalpartofournature.Thereisnosuchthingasamere bodily feeling without meaning or relevance to our existence. It may be just as relevant to care aboutinvoluntarysweatingpalmsastorespectmycollege’scoffeecup.Feelingscan,however,be moreorlessappropriateandevenmoreorlessrightaccordingtothesituationthatIfindmyselfin. SaythatIlaughwhenIseeaseriousaccidentjustbecauseitwasironicthatthecarhitaladywho wereadjustingherhairandcaringaboutherlooks;‘nowshewillneverhaveabadhairdayagain’. Thatisnotjustaninappropriatereaction,itisa wrong reaction. It goes against all that human societystandsforandcherishes.Thereply‘Butyoucannotneglectthefactthatitwasironicanda damnfunnything,ifwe,foramoment,supposethatnobodygothurt’willnotchangethefactthatit wasawrongreaction because apersongothurt.Fortunately,personsnormallydonotfindsucha tragic event funny, which tells us something not trivial about the nature of human care. Care expresses the nature of subjectivity; to imagine a subject who does not care about anything is difficult,ifnotimpossible.Ricoeuralignedthiscaretheoriginatingaffirmationorattestation(the willtolive,thewilltosayyes),buthealsostressedthatsubjectivecareisneverconfinedtoour own concerns, because we live together with other persons who care about things as we do. Feelingsexpressourcareabout…,andtounderstand the heterogeneous nature of feelings (from moodstoaffects)istounderstandhowcareholdstogetherourexperienceandactionintheworld;it bindstogetherthebeingoftheworldandourbeingpersonswhocareaboutthatworld.Careisthe ontologicalgroundfromwhichweunderstandwhatitisliketobeahumansubject.Ourexperience andexistenceispracticalinthesensethatweexperience,feel,think,andactaccordingtowhatwe careabout.Ourcareexpressesthevaluesbywhichweliveourlives,justasfeelingsexpressour care.Feelings,care,andvaluesareinseparablyinterrelatedinsubjectiveexperience,whichiswhyI

190 havestressedtheaffectivedimensionsomuchinmyanalyses.Emotionalexperienceisthestarting point in understanding both the experiential and ontological nature of subjectivity. Reason and rationality is fundamental in our relation to the world, the other, and to ourselves, because we understand,develop,andrefinewhatwecareaboutintermsofmakessenseandwhatdoesnot.But reasonworksinandwithaffectivitylikethesculptorworkswiththeamorphousstone.Therewould benoreasontoreasonifwedidnotcareaboutreasoning;andwecareaboutreasoning,becausewe wanttoknowbetterwhatwecareaboutandwhattodowiththings,events,andpersonsthatwe care about. Reason and rationality are fundamental to our life, nobody denies that, but it is importanttounderstandthat‘thestrictandcategoricalcontrastbetweenrationalityandemotionality ismisleadingandtendentious’(Stocker1996:104). Toseehowcareexpressestheontologicalconditionofsubjectivity,weneedtobringintheconcept of personhood. First of all, the notion of care covers both the biological and the psychological dimensionofsubjectivity.Wecare aboutourbasic biologicalneedsjustaswecare aboutlove, kindness,beauty,andfriendship.Wecannotseparateourpersonhoodfromthebiologicalnatureof ourbeing.ThiswasoneofPanksepp’scentralpoints.Basicaffectiveinstinctsarepresentevenin ourmostrefinedspiritualthought(ithasalwaysbeenconsideredasacrificetobecomeamonkor joinahungerstrike;infact,thatisexactlywhatsuchchoiceswanttodemonstrate).However,as arguedrepeatedly,affectivityisnotconfinedtosuchinstinctualneeds.Feelingsarealsointentional. Theydonotonlycharacterizemybeing,butalsothebeingoftheobjectsorpersonsthattheyare feelings for and about. They characterize me not only asabiological being,butalsorevealthe natureofthepersonthatIam(whetherIlikeitornot);orbetteryet,theyshowthatmypersonhood isinseparablyrootedinmybiologicalnature.Thisbringsusbacktothefirststructuraldiscovery about the nature of human subjectivity, namely that it is constituted by both reason and body (spontaneityandreceptivity).Aswesawinthefirstpart,thiswastheessenceofKant’sCopernican revolution. Human experience, and therefore human reality, is not a passive registration of the external world, but the product of a cooperation of reason and body. Although I agree with Strawsonthatthearchitecturalelaborationoftheideais‘baroque’(Strawson1966:24),Ithink,as he himself did, that the basic idea is worth following. In fact, Strawson’s seminal work on the conceptofapersondoescomeclosetowhatRicoeurcallsthesecondCopernicanrevolution 58 .I

58 Themovefromtheselftoanontologyofsubjectivitythatgroundsbeingoftheselfinthebeingofworld.Thisis carriedoutbyanontologicalphenomenologywhich‘isinitsturnasortofconversionthat“decentres”theontological concernfromtheSelf”(PW233/86;cf.FN32/35,446/448).

191 thinkthatRicoeurdismissedStrawson’sanalysestooquickly 59 ,andthatafurtherclarificationof personhoodcanbefoundexactlyinhiswork.Strawsonwas,asknown,deeplyinspiredbyKant and,althoughheobservedthatKant’sseparationofthecognitiveandpracticalsideofournature was too strict and categorical (idem: 272), he nevertheless maintained that human experience depends on the particular combination of human sensibility and reason. Human experience is peculiar and must not be identified with the notion of a detached and impersonal reality: ‘The boundsofthereal.Wemaysay,areindeednotcoextensivewiththetypesofsensibleexperience we in fact enjoy. We must not suppose that the nature of reality is exhausted by the kinds of knowledgewhichwehaveofit’(idem:267).Heisinterestedinthenatureofhumanpeculiarity, andthereforehisanalysesofhumanexperiencefocusonthebasicstructuresandconceptsofsuch an experience. On line with the Kantian esthetics, heindividuatestimeandspaceasthegeneral structure (Strawson 1959: 223) in which material bodies ‘secure us a one single common and continuously extendable framework of reference’ (idem:54).Whatisofparticularinteresttous hereisthatinthiscommonframeworkofreference,theconceptofpersonhasaparticularstatus becauseit‘islogicallypriortothatofanyindividualconsciousness.Theconceptofapersonisnot to be analyzed as that of an animated body or of an embodied anima’ (idem: 103). Human experience has twobasic and commonpoints of reference, namely material bodies (things) and persons. They are both fundamental in the constitution of our understanding of the world. Personhoodisnotthesameasselfhood,and‘itiseasiertounderstandhowwecanseeeachother, andourselves,aspersons,ifwethinkfirstofthefactthatweact,andactoneachother,andactin accordancewithacommonhumannature’(idem:112). Now, Strawson’s individuation of the concept of a person as a constitutive element of human experienceisimportanttotheconceptionofcareastheontologicalgroundofsubjectivitybecauseit tells us something about the complexity and, at the same time, structural unity involved in the notionofcare.Ourexperienceof,relationto,andinteractionwiththeworld,theotherpersons,and ourselves are rooted in care for the world, the other, and ourselves. This care involves the heterogeneity of our values that are themselves both bodily and spiritual. I care for my health, 59 Justas Ricoeur, Strawsonisnot mainlyinterested inthe objectivevalidityofexperience,butin ‘ordinaryhuman experience’(Strawson1959:88),andalthough‘personsinStrawson’ssensearemoreonthesideofsubstance’(OSA 83/104),itdoesnotmeanthat‘thattheagentassuchisnotyetaself,inthestrongsenseI[Ricoeur]amattributingto thisterm,butonlyasoneofthe“things”aboutwhichwespeak(idem).TheemphasisinStrawson’sanalysesisonthe basicnatureofpersonhoodinourmostdispassionateexperienceofanotherhumanbeing.Thispersonisaself,withall thefragilitythatRicoeurattributestothatterm,butStrawsonismoreinterestedinshowingthatthepersonhoodofthat selfisasobjectivelyfirmandinalienableasthematerialnatureoftheself.ForStrawson,asforRicoeur,thefragilityof thehumanselfisaccessibleonapracticallevel,thatis,inconsideringtheselfasanagent,because‘ourpracticesdonot merelyexploitournatures,theyexpressthem’(Strawson1962:80).

192 career,ambitions,economicalsecurity,myloveones,ketchuponmyfries,Brague’sstrangetrees, the hope for freedom, equality, a better world, and so on. Therefore, care is a very broad and confuseconceptthatmayatfirstseemcompletelyuselessbecauseitencompasseseverythingand nothing. Nonetheless, there is a structural unity incarethatmakesita biteasiertohandleand thereforeuseinanalysesofhumansubjectivity.Humancareisboundtothestructuralnatureof humanexperience,ofwhichwehaveseenthattheconceptofapersonisaconstitutivefeature.The subject’scareforpersonhoodisconstitutiveofitsbeing,becausethatiswhatdefinesthe‘common rootsinourhumannatureandourmembershipofhumancommunities’(Strawson1962:72).The efforttomaintainourpersonhood(andnotjustbeaselfishbastardoramoralidiot)isinscribedin most of our actions by the simple fact that our interaction with other people is constituted by practicesthatbuildonacommonconceptionofpersonhood.Myrecognitionoftheotherandthe other’s recognition of me as a person is a presupposition for our existence in a world that is constitutedbyme and theotherpersons.However,personhoodisnotonlyconstitutedbysucha mutualrecognition.Italsoinvolvesthesenseofselfhood.Thepersonisanindividualotherthana socialbeing(Strawson1959:1125).Myconcernsaremarkedbythistwofoldnatureofcare.Icare abouttheotherandaboutmyself(oftenmoreaboutmyselfthantheother).ThiswaswhatRicoeur stressedwhenheindividuatedtwoprincipledesires(vitalandspiritual)insubjectivityandargued thatthe(affective)fragilityofhumannatureoriginatesintheconflictualconstitutionofitsbeing (bodyandreason).Heconcludedthatthisnoncoincidence,thisconflict,couldonlybedealtwithin thepatheticdimensionofsubjectivity,i.e.,theconcreteactingandsufferingofhumannature.Our affectivefragility,thatis,theheterogeneousnatureofourcare,becomesapracticalprobleminhow wedealwithnormativeconflicts,problems,anddilemmas.Anontologyofcareexplainsthebeing of the human subject better than a strict materialistinspired ontology that analyzes human subjectivity in terms of either disembodied reason (functional computation) or impersonal embodiment(evolutionarytheories),sinceacceptsthefactthatthesubjectisrootedinbiologythat itcannevercompletelycontrolorunderstand(basicaffectivevalues),andstillitmakesroomfor theotherfact,namelythatthesubjectalsocareaboutbeingapersonandbeingpartofahuman community(humanity). Itistheresultof what Strawson has named a ‘descriptive metaphysics’ (1959:9)inthatitisgroundedinconceptualandexperientialanalysesofwhatitistobeahuman subject.

193 Conclusion: Subjectivity and Ethics The subject is a biological being and a person. In fact, we cannot separate one aspect from the other. A phenomenological analysis of subjectivity can only distinguish between the two by disregardingtheemotionalaspectofexperience.This,aswehaveseen,cannotbedoneunlesswe stripthesubjectofwhatmakesitahumansubject,namelythefeelingsthatqualifyexperienceas myexperienceofthingsthatmattertome.Ifwewanttounderstandwhatisparticularlyhumanin subjectiveexperience,wemustincludefeelingsinouranalyses.Andoncewedothis,personhood becomes a constitutive element of subjectivity. Things matter to the subject in virtue of its personhood.Despitethisfactualqualityofpersonhood,beingapersonismoreaproblemthana fact.Subjectivityisnormativeinnature,andpersonhoodmakesthisnormativityafactualproblem intheexistenceofthesubject.Normativityisbasicinthesensethatitisgroundedintheprimitive feelingofembodiedpleasureandpain.Weseekpleasureandavoidpainbeforewethinkofwhat pleasureandpainisreallyabout.Thereisalwaysastrongelementofinvoluntarypassivityinour normativeexperienceofgoodandbad.Wedonotchoosenormativity.Itcomeswithliving.We could call this the first passivity involved in the embodied nature of subjectivity. Personhood, however, accentuates the normativity of existence, sinceouractionsandsufferingsareboundto personhood,ourownandthatoftheother.Mylifeisnotjustaboutthethrivingofmyselfhood.My feelings reveal the basic nature of my being in that they orient my experience according to the heterogeneityofvalues.Thisisthesecondpassivityofsubjectivityinvolvedinmybeingaperson. MycareinnotconfinedtowhatIcareabout.Mycareisconstitutedbymycoexistencewithother persons; it involves their being, their happiness, and their suffering, as a qualification of my existence,sinceIexperiencetheworldasapracticalspaceofreasonconfiguredbythevaluesthat donothavetheirorigininme.Alterityisexpressedinbothmyselfhood(body)andinmybeinga person(theother).Subjectivityisnotconstitutedonlybyselfhood,whichbecomesevidentinthe feelingsofthesubject.Thesubjectalsocaresaboutbeingaperson;orsaiddifferently,thesubject feelsethical.Feelingethical,myfeelingofbeingapersonamongpersons,isabasicconstitutional featureinsubjectivity,sincethisfeeling,orratherdiffuseamalgamoffeelings,isaffectsprofoundly theactionsandthestateofbeingofthesubject.Theconflictualnatureofsubjectivityoriginatesin thiscomplexnatureofitsbeing:subjectivityisarelationbetweenselfhoodandalteritybythefact ofbeingapersonembeddedinanimpersonalnature. Theanswertothequestionoftherelationbetweensubjectivityandethicsmustconsiderthetwo sidesofthatquestion.Whathasethicstodowithatheoryofsubjectivity?And,doesthenotionof

194 subjectivityhaveimplicationsforethicaltheory?Ihavepartlyansweredthesequestionswithmy analysesinthischapter,butforthesakeofclarityIwillconcludebyarticulatingmyconsiderations intwofinalformulations.First,therelevanceofethicsforatheoryofsubjectivity. Theethicalnatureofsubjectivityis expressed inthepervasivenessof normativity.Atheory of subjectivitycannotneglectthis.Theexperienceandbeingofthesubjectisinherentlyintertwined withtheexperienceandbeingofothersubjects.Wecannotcompleteouranalysesofsubjectivity without clarifying that complexity. And, what is perhaps more pertinent, our structural analyses must consider that this normative feature affects and qualifies every aspect and capacity of the subject. Sensation, perception, feeling, knowledge, will, and action must all be analyzed on the backgroundofnormativity.Wecannotunderstandsubjectivityasontologicallyneutral.Thisisnot to say that structural and functional analyses that do not consider the ontological nature of the subject are unwarranted; on the contrary, they may help us understand better the ontology that groundsthosestructuresandfunctions,whichisinagreatmeritinitself.However,theycannotbe said to explain the nature of subjectivity, the sense of being a human subject. Further, the phenomenologicaldistinctionbetweenminimalself(selfawareness, ownership, and agency) and personhood(Zahavi2005:12932)becomessomewhatcomplicatedandblurredwhenweconsider thattheexperientialdimensionofsubjectivityas amatteroffactinvolvethecomplexnotionof feelings.Althoughwecandistinguishbetweenpersonhoodandanexperientialcoreselfbytalking aboutanarrative(cognitive)senseofselfandan experiential self (Gallagher and Zahavi 2008: 205),thisisnottheonlypossibleapproach.Feelingsarepartoftheexperientialcoreself,andthe normativityexperiencedbymeansofthefeelingsispersonalinthesensethatitrevealspersonhood intheexperientialself.Theselfisfeelingethicaleveninthemoststrippedsenseofsubjectivity. Thisbringsmetotheothersideoftherelation.Subjectivityisrelevantforethicaltheoryinmany ways.Humanbeingsaresubjectiveinnature.Wemightevensaythatethicaltheoriesarenecessary simplybecausehumansarebeingswithindividualsubjectivenatures.ButhereIwillfocusonlyon theaffectivedimensionofsubjectivitybecausethatoftenseemstobewhatdividesthewatersin ethicaltheory.Theforegoinganalyseshaveemphasizedtheirreducibleaffectivenatureofhuman valuesandpractices.Emotionsarefundamentalintheethics,andinordertounderstandwhythe subjectthinksandacts ethically, wemust‘focusontheemotions–on,thatis,theemotionsas affective,as emotional’ (Stocker1996:124).This isbasicallythe conclusionofmy analyses.A thorough analysis of the structures and capacities of subjectivity reveals the pervasive nature of affectivity.Thesubjectexperiencesandactsinapracticalspaceofreasonthatisrevealedbythe

195 emotional import of the feelings. Things and persons matter to us through our feelings, and to disregardthesefeelingfor‘cold’reasoningistomisunderstandthecomplexityofhumanaffectivity. Ourfeelingsrevealourvalues;andourvaluesareexpressedinwhatwecareabout,ourconcerns. Anyethicaltheoryhastoacceptthatthisisabasicfactofhumannature,whichcanberatifiedby bothdispassionate(neutral)observationofhumanbehaviorandstructuralanalysesofsubjectivity. Human feelings do not only involve my (egoistic) self, since the nature of human affectivity includes personhood as a basic element in emotional experience. We care about being persons, becauseourinteractionwithotherpersonsispermeatedbyethicalfeelingsotherthanselfishand perverse one. This is a fragile combination of feelings, which is rooted in the vulnerable constitutionofthesubject.Butwedonotsecureethicalbehaviorbyexcludingthefragilityofthe feelings,becausefeelingsarenotsomethingthatwechoose.Inourfeelingswefindthevulnerable constitutionofselfhood(voluntary)andalterity (involuntary)inourbeingpersons. Iproposeda deflated ethical theory that considers ethics to be a matter of practical reasoning and not about morality .Wehavetofindtheethicalconceptsthatguideourbehaviorinwhatwecareaboutinour practicallife,andnotina‘moralspace’.Iargueforanaturalisticconceptionofbothsubjectivity andethicsthatfindthevaluesofhumanlifeinthepervasivenormativitythatcharacterizehuman nature. Care, feelings,practices, andpersonhood arethekeyconceptsinsuchaninterrelationof subjectivityandethics,andtheforegoinganalyseshaveonlybeenaclarificationoftheseconcepts, notasystematicemployment. The final part of the dissertation is a further clarification of what I mean by a ‘naturalistic’ conceptionofsubjectivityandethics.Idosobyexaminingthecontemporaryformofnaturalization thatgoesunderthenameofneuroethics.Thisisa very relevant example of what I believe that naturalizationshouldnotbe.Mycriticismiscarriedoutonthebackgroundofthepreviousanalyses inthesensethatIlookathowthisformofnaturalizationusestheconceptsofnormativity,values, subjectivity,andpersonhood.Imaintainthatthecentralproblemofthiskindofnaturalizationisits complete lack of a coherent theory of subjectivity. This will hopefully clarify my view on the relationbetween subjectivity and ethics. Secondly, I clarify my conception of a naturalization of human personhood by looking at different conceptions of what we mean by nature and distinguishingmypositionformarecentattempttousetheprocessofnaturalizationtoarguefor moralrelativism.

196 PartThree TheBrainandHumanValues Ethicalbehaviorisafactjustasdeliciousredapplesoranannoyingheadache.Weallhaveapretty clearideaofwhatisethicalandwhatisnot.Wedonotthinkofethicswhenweseeawoman stumbleandfallinthestreet.Badluck,distraction,lousypavements,clumsiness,andsoon,butnot assomethingthatiswrongormean.However,ourreaction(orlackofsame)tothesituationfalls underwhatweconsiderasethical.Imightruntohelporthinkthatitisnotmyproblemthatsheis clumsyorunlucky.Ihaveatraintocatch,worktodo,moneytoearn,buyapairofshoesormet someonethat Icareabout.Ethicalbehaviorshapes theworldasweknowit,andethicalvalues influencehowweexperiencesituationsthatwefindourselvesin. Ihavearguedforadeflatedethicaltheorythatunderstandsethicalvaluesandbehaviorasanatural part of the constitution of the human subject. Ethical values are part of nature as we humans experienceit.Ethicsisnotsomethingthatwesuperimposeonhumannatureoronanotherwise nonethicalworld.Ethicalvaluessimplycomewithexperienceof andinteractionwiththeworld andothersubjects.Ihavefurtherarguedthatthismightbeaccountedforbyconsideringsubjective experienceconfiguredasapracticalspaceofreason.Ourexperienceisstructuredbyhowwevalue andinteractwiththeworldbymeansofhumanpractices.Onthisview,ethicaltheoryisanattempt toorganize,andperhapsimprove,thevaluesthatwenaturallyexperienceinvirtueofbeinghuman persons.So,ifethicalvaluesareanaturalandfactualpartofbeingahumanperson,thentheymust revealsomethingabouthumannature.Ithinkthatoursubjectivefeelingsofvaluesshowthatthe humansubjectisanormativebeingthatcannotbeclarifiedwithoutconsideringthisnormativityat theheartofsubjectivity.Atthesametime,Iclaimthatsuchaconceptionofhumansubjectivityis nottobeconsideredahindrancetotheattempttonaturalizehumanpersonhood;onthecontrary,a clarified notion of the normative structure of subjectivity can be a help for the process of naturalization.However,theprocessofnaturalizationhastoacceptthepeculiarnatureofhuman experienceandaction,andnottrytomakeitintosomethingthatitisnot.Therefore,inthisthird partIwilltrytoclarifymynaturalisticpositionbycriticizingtwodifferentattemptstonaturalize human personhood, namely neuroethics and a recent argument for moral relativism on the backgroundofstrongempiricalnaturalism.Further, Iwillclarifywhat Imeanbytheconceptof natureandnaturalism.Thispartisshorterthanthetwopreviousones.Thisisduetotheexplanative nature of the presentation. It is meant as a clarification and not as a further argument, and will thereforebuildontheargumentspresentedinthetwomoresubstantialparts.

197 ChapterOne NeuroethicsandSubjectivity

Aclarificationoftherelationbetweensubjectivityandethicsisparticularlyimportanttoday,since subjectivitycaneasilybeforgotteninthesensationalistclamorsurroundingsomeneuroscientific resultsandhypothesesconcerninghumannature.Inrecentyearstherehasbeenagrowingtendency, inneuroscienceaswellasamongphilosophers,psychologists,andsociologistsworkingwithinthe framework of ‘neurophilosophy’, to deal with the question of ethics. What was first sproradic attempts has now grown into the founding of a new multidisciplinary research field named ‘neuroethics’(ratifiedin2002withabigtwodayconferenceinSanFrancisco;seeMarkus2002). Neuroethicsisadistinctbranchofbioethicswhose‘missionistoexaminetheethical,legal,and socialimplicationsofneurosciencetoday’(Illes2006:IX) 60 .Thisisalargegroundtocover,andthe disciplineisonlyjustgettingstarted,buttheexpectationsareboldandhigh:‘Wecanimproveour understandingofthenatureofmoraltheoryanditsplaceinmoraljudgmentifwebetterunderstand justwhatmoralityconsistsin.Suchanunderstandingwillbestbeinformedbytreatingmoralityasa natural phenomenon subject to constraints from, influenced by, and ultimately reduced to the sciences,particularlythecognitivesciencesandbiology. Treating morality as a matter ofproper function,biologically construed(e.g. atleastpartially fixed by our evolutionary history), with a concomitant emphasis on skillful action in the world, will also shed light on just what kind of creatures we must be (cognitively speaking) if we are to possess knowledge about morality so taken’(Casebeer2003a:3;seealsoChurchland2006:3;Pinker2003:270;Metzinger2006:69; Farah2005:3839;Greene2003:84950). Theattempttoreducemoralitytonaturalfactsisnotanewone.Ithasbeenacentralissueinmoral philosophyatleastsinceHumedismissedanyattempttodragan‘ought’outofan‘is’.Moreover, ethicalnaturalismwasconsideredaclosedchapterafterMoore,inthebeginningofthelastcentury, carefullypointedoutthatthequestionofwhatis good (or bad, for that sake) remains an ‘open question’,thatis,itcannotbesettledbyscrutinizing natural facts. Nevertheless, with the newly gainedstrengthandsupportofneuroscientificresults.Ethicalconceptssuchasmorality,value,and normnowseemtoberootedinthenaturalsoilofgood,solidscience.Thenewtechniquesandthe firm progress of empirical science have finally made it possible to substitute the ‘first guesses,’

60 Neuroethicsisdividedintwomainfields:theethicsofneuroscienceandtheneuroscienceofethics(Roskies2002: 21).HereIwilldealonlywiththelatter.

198 ‘stories,’and‘talesfromthepast’toldbyAristotle,Descartes,HumeorHobbes(toputitwiththe wordsoftheprominentneuroscientistMichaelGazzaniga(2006a:164,178))withseriousscientific insightcapableofdismantlingourerroneousimageofhumannature.Ofcourse,thisnewimageis metbyheavycriticism fromthehumanitiesingeneral and philosophers in particular; therefore, whenneuroscientistsdebateethicalissueswithphilosophersandordinarylaypeopletheymustbe aware,accordingtothejustquotedGazzaniga,that‘NoonehastoldthekidsyetthereisnoSanta Claus’(idem:163). Thisnewbiologicallyinformedethicsisadirectconsequenceoftheneuroscientificimageofman. Ethicalnaturalismhasonceagainbecomeaseriousissue,becauseourknowledgeofhumanbiology hasexplodedwithnewinsightsintothehithertofirmlyconcealed‘blackbox’thatweknowasthe brain.Aroundfiftyyearsago,behaviorismwascriticized,becauseitsoughttobypassthebrainby relyingonlyonobservablebehaviorandthusdeliberatelyignoringthecognitivecapacityofhuman beings. Today, on the contrary, the ‘black box’ has become transparent by means of various imaging techniques, and neuroscience can, allegedly, pin down the neural correlates of almost everything, cognitive as well as affective capacities, from selfreferential reflection over deliberationtoemotionalexperience(Roskies2006:18).Hence,itfollowsasanaturalconsequence thatneurosciencealsohassomethingtosayaboutethics,sinceitgivesusthepossibilitytoregister the subpersonal components of our ethical life and practices. Finally we could say something concreteandexactaboutthisannoyinglyimpalpableandconflictualdimensionofhumannature. Some neuroethicists seem think that all we have to do is to show how the nonnormative, empiricallyverified,structuresanddynamicsof neuronalnetworkscometogethertoproducethe normativeexperiencethatwe,ashumanbeings,haveofourselves,theother,andtheworld.Thus, ‘the beginnings of a new paradigm in ethics can be seen emerging. Owing to the natural and biologicalrootsofmorality,thisnewapproachtoethicsmaybereferredtoas‘naturalizedethics’, ormoresimply,‘asneuroethics’’(Churchland2006:3). Now,whyinclude anewly formeddisciplinesuchasneuroethicsinadiscussionoftherelation betweenethicsandsubjectivity?Idothisforthreereasons. Thefirstofall,Idonotthinkthatneuroethicsdeliverswhatitpromises;thatis,itdoesnotexplain neither why people act the way they do and nor how they evaluate when they act ethically. Furthermore,itdoesnotexplain what moralityisorhowwecometothinkofethicsinthe first place.Oneofthemainreasonsforthis,Ithink,isthatneuroethicscompletelybypassesthenotion ofsubjectivityindealingwithethics.Justlikebehaviorismexcludedeverythingmental,neuroethics

199 deliberately ignores the firstperson dimension of ethical experience. It relies exclusively on a combinationofsubpersonaldataandenvironmentalfactors,andupontheseitadvanceshypotheses thatdonotconsiderthedispositions,feelings,anddeliberationsexperiencedbythesubjectwhois registered to undergo these various stimuli. Subjective experience of, for example, being a particularpersonwithcertaindesiresandwishesisgenerallyconsideredassecondary(Zoloth2006: 68)orevenasanillusion(Farah2007:40).Thisisaproblem:Canweaccountforhumanethical dispositionsandmoralitywithoutpayingattentiontohumansubjectivity?Isthenew,naturalized paradigmthatneuroethicsissupposedtoprovideinethicaldebateactuallyalegitimateone? Secondly,inmy critiqueofneuroethics, Ihopeto strengthen my argument for the necessity of theory of subjectivity in ethical theory. Neuroethics emphasizes that human nature is critical to ethics. I agree perfectly with this claim. In order to make a legitimate ethical theory, we must understand how people come about to think and act ethically. Ethics requires an attentive metaethical investigation into the normative dimension of human nature. Such an investigation dependsonneutralandpatientobservationofhowvaluesandnormsaregeneratedinhumanaction and experience, and how they influence perception ofandactionintheworld. Ithinkthatitis importanttodistinguishbetweenneuroethicsandneuroscientific research. Ibelieve neuroscience cantellusmuchabouthumannaturethatisimportanttoethicalreasoning.WhatIopposeisthe tendencyinneuroethicstogoforreductiveconclusionsabouthowhumans should behaveandthink accordingtoneuroscientificfindings.Thereoftenisasilenttransitionfromdescriptiveanalysesto normativeconclusions,whichimpairthelegitimacyoftheirsocalled‘ethicalfacts’. Finally,IsurmisethatbyrelatingthepreviousanalysisofsubjectivityandethicstoneuroethicsI might clarify my own naturalistic position. How can I be a naturalist and still not accept the arguments of neuroethics? As I said in the introduction, ethical dispositions such as moral sentiments (e.g. love, care, anger, benevolence, and desire) and principles fit badly into the scientificimageoftheworld.They areconsideredstrangeandsuspiciousphenomenainaworld madeupbydisinterested,swirlingmassesofparticles.Nonetheless,wecannotdenyethicsaplace inthispicturebecauseourbeingdependsonthesestrangephenomena.Blackburnputsitlikethis: ‘wenearlyallwanttobenaturalistsandweallwantatheoryofethics’(Blackburn1998:49).Now, in the attempt to place ethics in the nonethical nature of the world, we might not just learn somethingaboutthenatureofethics,butperhapsethicsmightalsoclarifyproblematicaspectsof someversionsofnaturalization.Thepracticalnecessityoffindinganappropriateethicaltheorythat accountsforhowweactuallythinkandactintheworldmakesitreasonabletopresumethatethics

200 shouldhavealegitimateclaimonthe‘big’questionabouthumannature.Actually,thefactthatwe needtofindroomforethicsinthedisenchantedworldisconfirmedpreciselybyaphenomenonas neuroethics. Even the most hardcore eliminativist wants to legitimize his or hers (im)personal conduct. Ethics stresses the problematic relation between fact and normativity. Neuroethics performsa rapidstraightforwardtranslationfromfacttonorm,inscribedinalargerevolutionary context.Oftenitgoessomethinglikethis:whenweanalyzetheconstitutionofthehumansubject wefindoutwhatitisandhowitreactsincertaincircumstances,thereforewecanprescribethatone kind of cognitive constraint is more scientifically based than others; for example a principle of utility instead of a deontological principle (Farah and Heberlein 2007: 46). However, a good translationmustpayattentiontobothsidesoftheequation,thatis,boththe‘is’andthe‘ought’.If wewanttofindthebesttranslation,wemustlookforatheorythatincludesasmanydimensionsas possible. Thus,thefollowingcriticismwilltrytoarguefortheclaimthatneuroscientificfindingsmustrely on more than evolutionary theories to provide an adequate ethical theory; it must pay equal attention to, for example, the dimension of subjectivity, sociocultural factors, history, logic, institutions,andeconomics.Ethicscannotbedealtwithonlyfrom,tosayinasimplisticmanner,a synapticperspective.AsMoorewrites:‘[if]weoncerecognizethatwemuststartourEthicswithout adefinition,weshallbemuchmoreapttolookaroundus,beforeweadoptanyethicalprinciple whatever;andthemorewelookaboutus,thelesslikelyarewetoadoptafalseone’(Moore1954: 20). In this open search for an adequate ethical theory, we may have to modify the process of naturalization.Anadequateethicaltheoryisadescriptivenotionthatshouldfunctionasaheuristic toolinourunderstandingofnormativity.Ifweacceptthatthereexistboth‘is’and‘ought’inthe human world, then we should try to describe both aspects as carefully as possible in order to procure the most adequate picture of human nature. Humans are individual subjects with their peculiar ideas, sentiments, principles, and perspective on things. We cannot dismiss a person’s benevolencebyreferringtoaselfishgenethatonlystrivesforsurvival.Andwe cannot explain altruisticbehaviorwiththefactthatsurvivalismorelikelyinlargergroupsthanbyoneself.Values areheterogeneousphenomenathatcannotbeboileddowntoonesingleprinciplesuchassurvival. Valuesarefelt,thought,andwishedforbythesubjectconsideredasanindividualperson(madeup ofidiosyncratictendenciesandsocioculturalfactorsaswellasbiologicallydefinedtraits);andthis

201 subjectivedimensionofvaluescannotbeeliminatedasirrelevant,byproducts,orillusions,ifwe wantfindareasonableaccountofvalues. In neuroethics, the neuroscientific findings are commonly interpreted in terms of a ‘neuroessentialism’ that states that ‘our brains define who we are’ (Roskies 2002: 22), and that ‘[a]dvances in neuroscientific research in relevant areas may change the very fabric of our philosophicaloutlookonlife(idem).Onthefollowingpages,Iwilladvocatethataninversemodel may be needed if we want to understand what neuroscientific research might contribute to our understandingofethics.Aphilosophicalconsiderationonthenatureofethicaldispositions,values andnormsmaybeausefulforthewayweapproachthequestionofnaturalization.Ethicscanbe seenasacounterweightto‘neuroessentialism’becauseitemphasizesthecomplexityofnormativity andthusclarifythedifficultiesinvolvedintranslating‘is’to‘ought’orreducing‘ought’to‘is’. Further,onmyownviewofethics,theproblemofneuroethicsliesmainlyinitsreductivestance toward subjectivity. ‘Ought’ is a subjective experience of a world that can be described as non ethicalbythemethodsusedbythenaturalsciences.However,thisnormativefeatureoftheworldis notsomethingthatweshouldtrytoreducetowhatitisnot,namelynonnormativefacts.Metaethics is an objective approach to the subjective experienceofnormativityinthesensethatitseeksto clarify,objectively,thenatureandworkingsofourvalues,principles,andnorms.Ournormative experienceoftheworldisaslegitimateasourdistancedandneutralapproachtothatworld.The problemishowtoreconcilethetwowithoutreducingtheonetotheother.Thiswillbethetopicof thefinalchapter. But first I shall present some of the arguments proposed by William D. Casebeer whose book Natural Ethical Facts provides,tomyknowledge,themostcoherenttheoretical background for neuroethicalproposals.Iconcentrateonthequestionofvalues.ToavoidthatIgiveanarrowview ofthediscipline,IintegratesomeotherauthorsinthepresentationofCasebeer’sarguments. The Case of Casebeer and Some of his Allies: Impersonal Ethical Facts Casebeerwantstoexplainourethicalbehaviorinnaturalterms,whichinitselfisnotabadthing. Wemust,however,understandwhathemeansbynatural.Heusesthreeapproachestoclarifyhis natural ethical facts: neurophysiology, cognitive sciences (especially connectionism) and evolutionary biology (2003a: 11). Although Casebeer only rarely goes into more specific neurophysiological considerations (2003b: 8434), he nevertheless builds his theory on connectionismbecausethisunifiesneurobiologyandcognitivepsychologyinafunctionalmodel

202 that,accordingtohim,explainsmoralreasoning(2003a:6).Roughlydefined,connectionismisa variation of the older computational approach to human cognition. But whereas computational theoriesdonotaspire(orevenintend)tomodeltheneurophysiologicalanatomyandworkingsof thebrain,connectionismwantstodoexactlythat.Byusingtheneuralnetworksofthebrainasa model,thiskindofcomputationsaspirestotellussomethingabouttheway wehumansreason. Thereare,however,manyincompatibilitiesbetweenconnectionismandtheactualneurophysiology ofthebrain,sincethemodeloffersmorethanisanatomicallypossible,forexampleinformationis allowedtoflowinbothdirectionsalongtheaxon(Pinker1999:114).Butthisisnotthequestion here. In short, connectionism is an attempt to understand the workings of the brain (mental processessuchasthoughts,deliberation,decisions,ideas,associationsetc.)byassumingthatmental processesarecomputationalprocessesdefinedbysimplesyntacticspecifiedentitiesthat,whenthey areaccumulatedinarecursivesystem,functionsasrepresentationsoftheworld.Inotherwords,the brain functions as computer. However, I think that Casebeer’s theory (and consequently many neuroethicaltheories)canbepresentedfaithfullybyadoptingamoregeneralpointofview,namely withregardtohisaccountofnaturalvalues. His basic idea goes something like this: if we connect a sufficiently large amount of neural networks (artificial or natural), we could eventuallydemonstratethatthemorenetworksthatare combinedinanorganism,thesmallertheactualdifferencebetweenlearningandjudgingwouldbe. Inarecursivesystem,inwhichinputandoutputareregulatedbyorganism’sabilitytoadapttothe factualsurroundings,thecapacitytojudgesimplyconsistsintheabilitytocreatethebestpossible optionsforexistinginthosesurroundings:‘Inasufficientlycomplexneuralnetworks–exhibiting sufficient recurrence, coping with the world, and interacting with the environment – ‘comportmental’behaviorwouldarisenaturally’(Casebeer2003a:86).Thequestionabout how the organismshouldbehaveisreducedtoaquestionabout what isbestforthelifeoftheorganism. Casebeer is very clear about the fact that his functionalist account of behavior is grounded in evolutionary biology. The life of biological organisms is characterized according to what is consideredtobe‘ecologicalvalid’behaviors‘thatletthemadaptrulesandregulationstosituations inamannerthatpromotesflourishing’(145).Hechallengesthetraditionalviewthatmoralityisa particular human quality (75) by emphasizing that all organisms act according to values simply because‘moralfactsarefunctionalfacts’(53). He distinguishes between three kinds of moral agents (923): 1) minimal moral agents (plants, viruses,bacteria,andsomeinsects),2)standardmoralagents(insectsandmostotheranimals,3)

203 robustmoralagents(humansandperhapsdolphinsorhigherprimates).Humansareonlydifferent fromtheamoebabecauseofthemorecomplexneuralnetworksworkinginthehumanbrain.This complexityallowustohaveplans,projects,anddesiresthatarenotdirectlyrelatedtoimmediateor proximatesatisfaction;infact,Casebeerventuresthat‘possessionofnumeroussuchprojectsisin factthesingularmarkofhumanity’(93).Ontheotherhand,moralqualificationscanbeextendedto viruses,because,ashepointsout,wedoinfactsay:‘Lo!A flourishing Virus!’(92).Thus,Casebeer preparesagroundonwhichwecanspeakofmoralvaluesjustlikewespeakofanythingelseinthe biologicaluniverse. This is one of the main principles in neuroethics. If we understand the evolutionary and physiologicalaspectofthebrain,wewillbeabletosee‘the very largeextenttowhichinformation processingtakesplaceautomatically,belowthelevel of conscious experience’ (Levy 2007: 20). Andthatwhichactuallydependsonconsciousexperience,ourdecisionmaking,issomehowalso nottobetakenpersonally:‘we are thesetofoursubpersonalmechanisms,andnothingelse,and ourintelligencejust is theproductofthesuccessfulcombinationofthesedumbmachines[…]for themechanismsthatmakethedecisionareneverthelessours,us;theyhaveourvalues,theyhave our beliefs, our goals (we have them by them having them), and when they decide, we decide’ (idem:243).Natureisnotpersonal.Thisisobviouseventothosewhoarenotneuroscientistor biologists.Alreadythe Great LisbonEarthquakein 1755 diffused this austere reality among the intellectuals in that time, and in a time of wars, torture, natural catastrophes, and desperate immigration who would today maintain otherwise. Nature is heartless and indifferent. The distinction between human agency (e.g. war, terror, and immigration) and anonymous events is made difficult by such a functional account, because humans are, in virtue of being nature’s progeny,deeplyimmergedinthisimpersonalmatter.Andtoassumepersonhoodtobepartofthe natural world is the same as to think that the stick is broken in the water just because we are ignorant of the physical laws of optical reflectionthatunderliethisvisualillusion.Ourideasof personhoodaremerelyduetoa‘misleadingsystemforpersonrepresentation’thatshouldbeleftout ofethicaldebate,because‘personhoodisnotreallyintheworld’(FarahandHeberlein2007:45). If we return to Casebeer, we can see that just as we naturally select the most flourishing and beautifulorchidintheflowershop,afunctionalevolutionaryethicssecuresvaluesthat‘remaintrue totheneurobiologyofmoralcognitionandtheempiricalfactsaboutsuccessfulwaystoproduce humanflourishing’(2003a:137).Inordertorejectwhatheconsiderstobeimplausiblenormsand values, we must understand that ‘[n]orms to which cognition is ultimately responsive would be

204 pragmatic“fitfunctional”norms’(90),andthereasonwhywehumanssooftenendupinmoral disagreementsandconflictsis‘becausewehaveconstructedafaultymodelthatdoesnoteffectively linkthedemandsofourfunctionalnaturetothestructure of the world’ (93). The fitfunctional normsandvaluesoforchidsinaflowershop are tobeflourishingandbeautiful,thereforethey shouldbesootherwisetheydonotfittheproperfunctionoforchidsandwill naturally endinthe dumpster.Casebeerdoesnotbelievethatsucharadicalapproachtohumanethicalbehaviorisin contrastwithsomeofthegreatmoralphilosophersofthepast.Heclaimstodevelopa‘robustly naturalizedAristotelianethics’thatcombinedwithDewey’spragmatismguardsthenaturalnature ofmoralityagainst‘allegationsabouttherelativityandqueernessofobjectivevalues’(49).Values areobjectiveandtravelcrossnature’smanyspeciesbecauseifwesticktosolidscientificevidence, it is difficult to distinguish what is particularly human behavior from that of a vampire bat (Kennedy2002:199200). Theontologythatsustainsandnourishesthispictureofnatureandhumanvaluesiseasilyidentified as a strong materialist ontology that emphasizes the epiphenomenal nature of our subjective experience of the world and ourselves. What counts is the impersonal constitution of such experiences,andtheonlyhopetofindrealvaluesthatescapetheimplausibleclaimsofbothnon naturalist realists such as Plato, Kant, and Moore and antirealists or skeptics such as Hare, Blackburn,andMackie istodigdeeperintotheconstitution of humannature, and let the most sophisticatedofourbodilymembers,ourbrain,speakforitself.Researcherhaveactuallylocated the utilitarian center in the brain (Moll and OliveiraSouza 2007), which seems to confirm that neurobiologymayhaveanimportantroleindiscussionofmoraljudgments;forexample,itcan showusthat‘moralmotivationandmoraljudgmentare functionally separable and depend upon distinctbrainsystems’,whichmayhave‘radicalimplications’formoraleducation(Roskies2006: 29)thatintheendcanallowustodevelop‘amoremorallyresponsivecitizenry’(idem:30).Such insightswilleventuallyhelpus‘livefullyfunctional lives’ and ‘structure characterdevelopment institutionssuchasschoolsandcolleges’(Casebeer2003a:145). Thus,thebestwaytosolvetheconflictualnatureofhumansocietyistolookforsomethingmore stabile and solid than the fragile and vulnerable nature of human subjectivity. It is, in fact, a characteristic feature of many publications in neuroethics that they very easily jump from descriptive metaethical investigations to normative moral policy, educational and institutional proposals. Neuroethics is an urgent help to the society that all too long has suffered under the hopeless and utopian regime of folklore and philosophy. Instead of spending useless time and

205 energyonMoore’sirreducible‘ought’andonhowitisconnectedtothefactualworld’s‘is’,we shouldratherunderstandthatourbiologicalnature,factualenvironment,andevolutionarytheory hasalreadygivenusthetoolstocommence‘ourownnewenlightenment’ofethicalvalues(Saphire 2002:5). ProminentphilosopherssuchasDennett,Metzinger,andPaulandPatriziaChurchlandattemptto providetheyoungdisciplinewithphilosophicalargumentsagainstmoralphilosopherswhoclaim thatsuchethicalreasoningisunfoundedorsimplewrong.Dennett,forexample,recommendsthat wesubstituteourelusiveidealofgenuinealtruisticbehaviorwithamorenatural‘ benselfishness ’ (Dennett 2003: 194) 61 , which is found in all species and confirmed by evolutionary research. Therefore instead of chasing Kant’s deontological fantasy (idem: 213), we should put a lot of computerstodo‘simulationsofevolutionaryscenarios’ofpossibleactionsandfindoutwhatwould bethebestbehaviorinthefuture(idem:218). TheDisobeyingSubject:SubjectiveValuesandPersonhood ‘Histhoughtswanderedagain.Almostunconsciouslyhetracedwithhisfingerinthedustonthe table:2+2=5 […]Butitwasallright,everythingwasright,thestrugglewasfinished.Hehad wonthevictoryoverhimself.HelovedBigBrother’ (Orwell 1989: 303, 311). These are words fromtheconcludingpagesofGeorgeOrwell’snovelNineteen Eighty-Four .Afterhavingsecretly fought Big Brother’s inhumane norms and values (peace is war, truth is manipulation, love is torture,sexisimpersonalreproduction)withhissmallpersonalrevoltssuchasconstantlythinking about the history that it is his job to rewrite, drinking too much gin, turning his back to the telescreen and making love to Julia, Winston Smith finally, with heavy help from brutal prison guardsintheMinistryofLove,reachestotheconclusionthattheywererightandhewaswrong:2 +2isindeed5. Now,Idonotwanttoinsinuatethatneuroethicsaspirestotheterrifyingaccountofimpersonal functionalismthatwefindinOrwell’sbook.Idothink,however,thatbyrejectingthesubjective aspectofhumannatureweendupwithadistortedaccountofnormsandvaluesthatdisregardthe complexity of human nature. The values and norms of humanity are reduced to the impersonal forcesofgenes,synapses,distantevolutionarydrives,andfitfunctionalsocieties.Toarguethatwe

61 Dennett has, with his usual astuteness, coined this neologism from an old anecdote, which tells that Benjamin FranklinsaidthefollowingwordstoJohnHancock,atthesigningoftheDeclarationofIndependence:‘ We must indeed all hang together, or, most assuredly, we shall all hang separately ’(Dennett2003:1993).Heplayswiththedouble meaningof‘Ben–’:Ben(jamin)andBen(e)asintheLatinwordforgood.

206 cannotdoethicslikethis,Iwilllookmorecloselyonthenotionofvalueasitisconceivedand employedbyatleastsomeofthespokesmenofneuroethics,andarguethatwecannothopetosolve the problems involved in this notion without paying attention to the subjective nature of personhood. Casebeernoticesthathedoesnotdistinguishbetweenethicsandmorality,because,althoughhe obscurely agrees that such a distinction ‘might be eminently useful’ in other contexts, it is not relevantforhisprojecttonaturalizeethical/moralreasoning(2003a:13).AlthoughIagreethata sharpdistinctionisfutile,Idobelievethatsometimessuchadistinctioncanpreventconfusionwith regard to another distinction that we cannot permit ourselves to confuse, namely that between factual description of normativity (metaethics) and normative claims (moral debate). Metaethics dealswiththenatureofmoralvalue,moralmotivationandthestatusofmoraljudgments,whereas moral debate can be seen as the (important) discussion of actual rules and norms (written and unwritten)ofagivenperson,society,orevenhumanityingeneral.Theoneisnotmoreimportant than the other, but they involve different kinds of analyses. Metaethics begins without any normativeclaimsandattemptstoclarifythenatureoftheclaimsthatarebeingdiscussedinmoral debate.Ithinkthatneuroethicalanalysesoftenconfusesthetwobecausetheybuilttheiranalyseson anormativeclaimthatfactsandnaturearereducibletowhatarerevealedbytheempiricalsciences andevolutionarytheory.Thereisnodoubtthattheyarerightalongpartoftheway.Neuroscientific research can help us understand many relevant facts about how our brain works, and this is necessary information that any metaethical analysishastopaydueattentionto.Butitissimply wrongtouseneuroscientificresultstojustifybluntstatementslike:‘moralfactsarefunctionalfacts’ (Casebeer2003a:53);orthatwemustoptforautilitarianethicsbecausepersonhoodisanillusion (FarahandHeberlein2007:45);orthatmoralitydependsonintuitionsbecause‘moraljudgments arenotrational’(Levy2007:293)andtherefore‘perhapssomekindofconsequentialismisthebest normativetheory’(idem:306);orthat‘[t]hegeneralcognitivistpictureofmoralityiscorrect:moral judgmentsareasubspeciesofjudgment;moralreasoningisatypeofreasoning;moralconceptsare an ordinary type of concept, and there are nothing intrinsically motivating about either moral concepts or moral judgments’ (Roskies 2006: 28). The reason why it is wrong is that these researchersusetheneuroscientificresultstosettledebatesthatinvolvemorethanneurosciencecan deliver.Itislikesayingthatjustbecauseahammeristhebesttool,ifwewanttofixthebroken wood frame of our favorite picture, then it is also the best tool to fix our ragged marriage. Neuroscienceisagoodtool,butitisnottheonlytooltocopewithhumannatureandvalues.The

207 problemisthatneuroethicsis,perdefinition,groundedinanontologythathaveastrictnormative criteriaforwhatisrealandwhatisnot.Ireturntothediscussionoftheconceptofnatureinthe next,concludingchapter,butfornowIlimitmyselftothenatureofvalues. Forneuroethics,realvaluedoesnotdependonsubjectiveexperience.Subjectivityishardlyever mentioned or discussed in the literature, and when it is it is not considered as a firstperson perspective on the world and the other in their phenomenological givenness, but in relation to constructivistaccountssuchasnarrativeethics(e.g.Zoloth2006:689;Levy2007:1757).Ifwe dismissthesubjectivenatureoftheagent,howdo we then decide on the nature of values? The answerisstraightforward:thegoodvaluesaretherealandtruevaluesthatmustbediscoveredand ratified by objective empirical sciences. This will then show us what is best for human beings accordingtotheirbiologicalnatureandthefunctionofsocialinteraction.Thesubjectdoesnothave anythingtosayaboutthevaluesbywhichitleadsitslife,becauseitswholeexistenceisspunupby theillusionthatpersonhoodcountsinhumaninteraction.Whereaspersonsexperiencedoubtsand confusionwithregardtovalues(whataremyvalues?HowdoIknowifIadopttherightones?Why are my values better than the idiot who sleeps until noon every day of his useless life?), the neuroscientifically good values are stable and clear simply because they ‘are discovered by examinationofthebiologicalworldoforganismenvironmentinteraction:theyarefacts,empirical mattersinanyreasonablesenseofthephrase’(Casebeer2003a:33).Casebeer,whoisoneofthe few neuroethicists who actually deal with Moore’s openquestion, rejects the possibility that the natureofvaluesismoreaproblemthanafact,sinceweallhavedifferentattitudes,opinions,and feelingsconcerningthevaluesthatgovernhumaninteraction. He is convinced that if we let the nature of value be an open question, then ‘it can legitimize armchair metaphysics’ (idem: 32), whichwilleventuallyhinderany‘moralprogress’and‘fruitfullives’(idem:161). EvenwithoutconsideringthelogicalaspectofMoore’squestion(theanalyticalnatureofthenotion ‘good’), we easily see how such a functional accountofvalues goesagainsteverythingthatwe normally understand by human values. Values are a factual problem because individual persons actuallydohavedifferentvaluesthatsometimescontrast,sometimesconcur,andsometimesstart wars.Apartofthejobofmetaethicsistoinvestigateintothenatureofthesedifferentvaluesandtry toarguerationallyforwhysomevaluesaremoreinaccordancewithwhatweknowabouthuman nature, the nature of the world, and human interaction. In (most of) the western world today, homophobia, repression of women, child labor, extreme nationalism, death penalty, race discrimination,andviolencearecriticizedbecausesuchbehaviorsandattitudesexpressvaluesthat

208 donotrespectthesovereignrightoftheindividualperson.Thepersonisanindividualpersonand hasarighttohisorherindividuality(feelings,opinions,principles,dreams,andattitudes).Ethics comes into the picture because often this individuality compromises the individuality of other persons.Andmetaethicaltheoryistheattempttoclarifytheconceptsandargumentsweusewhen wethink,act,anddiscussethically. Ourbiologicalnature,asithasbeenuncoveredbytheempiricalsciencesinthelast150years,isa functionalorganismthatisbornanddevelopedbyspecific(althoughmanyyetunknown)lawsand processes.Thesescienceshaveenabledustodissipatemanyabsurdmythsandurbanlegendsabout humannature(thereisnosuchthingasracialinferiority,paleskinisnotmorenoblethandarkskin, womenarenotmadeintheimageofman,wearenotthecenteroftheuniverse,lefthandedpeople are not just being obnoxious, greed is not only Jewish, and tuberculosis is not cured by fresh mountainair).Functionalanalysesofnature(humanasnothuman)doalotofgood.Butalthough the normative dimension of existence can find precious help in such analyses, it remains a categoricalmistaketothinkthatvaluescanbeexplainedorevencharacterizedasmerefunctional facts.Thisistoexplainandinstructhumannaturebymakingitintosomethingthatitisnot,namely impersonal. We saw in the discussion about the evolutionary approach to emotions that intentionalitycannotbeexplainedbydistantevolutionaryforces,sincehumanbeingscareabout individuals (Hintentionality) in difference to other mammals. Our rationality is governed by something more than efficiency and functionality. Most of us do find it wrong to sacrifice an individualtosavethousandhumanbeings.Anditisamisunderstandingofrationalitytosaythatit would be more rational to do so, because then we save many other lives. But in this way of thinking,itwouldperhapsbemorerationaltosaveone,sincetheearthisbecomingoverpopulated, which is a bad thing, rationally speaking, because then humanity will eventually die of lack of oxygen,food,andwater.Ourrationalitydoesnotworkinavacuum,butisstrictlyinterconnected with the rest of our human nature, that is, our feelings, sensations, memory, and cognitively impenetrabledesires.Andonepertinentfeatureofhumanbeingsisthattheydocareaboutbeing individualpersonswithallthatthisinvolves.ItwasDeSousawhoinlastchapterbroughtattention to this feature of human evolution by emphasizing the particular individual nature of human intentionality.Hehasrecentlywrittenaninterestinglittlebookabouttheevolutionarydevelopment ofrationalityandindividualitywherehepointstothefactthat‘[w]ithoutthepowerofthought, whateverIdoandwhateverhappenstome,theultimate why ofmybehaviorcanonlyreside outside me,inthevestigialteleologyofmygenes[…]Bymeansoftheexplicitresourcesoflanguage,

209 humans became conscious of themselves as individuals and empowered to invent new values transcending the vestigial values embedded in our biology’ (de Sousa 2007a: 86) 62 . Ricoeur’s conceptionofvaluesstressedthiscomplexityinthenatureofwhatwevalue,ofwhatwecareabout, by defining value as a quasiconcept. The concept of value encompasses many heterogeneous aspectsabouthumancareorconcernsthatwecannotunderstand,onlyfeel.Valuesarepersonal, impersonal, spiritual, biological, historical, traditional, uniting, separating, universal, parochial, firm,changing,fragile,pure,nasty,transparent,obscure,andsoon.Humannatureisexpressedin thevaluesbywhichweinteractwithoneanother.Wecannevercompletelydecideonwhattocare about, although we can reflectively learn to controlsomeofwhatisnotappropriateorrightto value.Thevalueoferoticloveisagoodexample.Blackburnwrites:‘apartnerwhocandecideat willwhethertofeeldesireisnotquitetherealthing.Wedon’twantcontrol.Wewanttofeelswept awayourselves,andespeciallywewanteachothertobesweptaway,justaswerequireblushesto beinvoluntary,anditisnosignofshamethattheyare’(Blackburn2004:61).Theexperienceof beingboundtoourvaluesisanexpressionofthecognitivelyimpenetrablenatureofwhatwecare about.Thereareinvoluntaryaspectsofvaluesthatcannotbedisregardedwithoutendinguptalking aboutwhatistherightandwrongvalues(i.e.,normativeclaims),andnotaboutthenatureofvalues. IknowthatPeterisbadcompanybutIcannothelpwantingtobenearhim.Itislikeexplaining homosexualitywithreferencetothefactthatnature(andyourmother)wanteditotherwise;or,that weshouldnotusepreservativesbecausesexisjustreproductionandtohinderreproductionwhile

62 Another recent and important publication is the collection of essays by neuroscientists, psychologists, and philosophers: Tall Tales about the Mind and Brain. Separating fact from fiction .Thebookismeantasanattemptto dissipatethemythsandlegendsconcerningneuroscience,bothamongtheresearchersinsidethedisciplineitselfandon part of the public. For example, with respect to the present discussion, the neurophysiologist, Giovanni Berlucchi, arguesthatitishardtodisposeofindividualityforimpersonalfunctionevenatmicroscopiclevel,because‘[a]person’s identity, individuality is the result of that person’s genome as much as of his our hers unique and unrepeatable life history, including prenatal development in the intrauterine environment. Further, in addition to genetic and environmental influences, there is an independent third source of phenotypic variation which has a major role in ensuring the uniqueness of each individual organism and particularly of each individual brain. Independent of their genetic makeup, persons have different minds arguably because the have different nervous systems, and they have differentnervoussystemsbecauseeachnervoussystemistheunique,irreproducibleresultofthreefactors:thegenes, theenvironmentanddevelopmentalnoise’(Berlucchi2007:337).Thiscanbeusedagainsttheargumentsthatsome neuroethicistsusewhentheywanttodefendthemselvesagainstaccusationsofbiologicaldeterminism.Theyoftenstate thataperson’sbehaviourisnotonlyinhisorhersgenes,because‘[c]ontextiseverything–andthis,quitesimple,isthe lessonofneuroscience’(Gazzaniga2006b:143).Apersonishisorhersbiologicalconstitution and theenvironment. Butthisisto missthepoint,namelythatasubstantialamountof neuroscientific studiesshowthatourindividuality depends on, at least, a third feature, developmental noise, which is best explained by the fact ‘that chance events occurringduringontogenesiscontributetotheproductionofuniquebody/braincomposites,eachofwhichwillinteract withtheenvironmentinitsownidiosyncraticmanner’(Berlucchi2007:345).Anindividualpersonismorecomplex, evenatamicroscopicbiologicallevel,thanjustthecombinationofgenesandenvironment.Thereforewecannotrely on biology and a good functional society to envisage the functional character of human nature. Every human being functionsinhisorhersuniqueway.

210 havingsexisirrational.Tounderstandandexplainwhathumanvaluesareisactuallytoexplain muchofwhatistobeahumanbeing,andviceversa.Whensomeresearchesclaimthattheproblem withhumanbeingsisnotthattheyhavetoolittlemoralitybuttoomuch(Pinker2003:269),then thisreflectsaratherundisturbedideaofwhathumannaturereallyis.Valuesareapproachedwitha veryclearideaofwhatishumanandwhatisnot.Weshouldnotthinkthatmoralityisacomplex and multilayered question, because ‘[t]he modern sciences of mind, genes, and evolution are increasinglyshowingthatitisnottrue’(idem:421).Theonlyproblemisthatpeopledohaveso muchmoralityandcareaboutwhattheyarenotsupposedtocareabout,andunlessweusethesame ‘wellmeant’methodsastheMinistryof Love,wewillneverchangepeople’sattitudes,feelings, andrationalityinsuchadramaticwaythat2+2willeventuallybecome5.Ourvaluesspringfrom oursubjectiveexperienceoftheworld,and,asIhavebeenarguingforallthistime,thisexperience is a fragile constitutionof the voluntary and involuntary aspects of human nature, selfhood and alterity,spontaneityandpassivity.Andwhen,forexample,Casebeerwritesthat‘[w]hetherornot certainpersonsareirredeemablyevilisanempiricalquestion,amenabletoinquiry’(2004:450),I would not disagree that this is in part true. Evil is empirical. It is a tragic fact about human intercourse and society. Too many people suffer from mischiefs so cruel and horrifying that we cannotbutconsiderthepersonswhodosuchthingsirredeemablyevil.Butthisisonlypartofthe story.Therealdifficultyariseswithourexperienceofevil.Howandwhydoweexperienceevil? Whatmakesuscharacterizeactionsandpersonsasevil?Itistheexperientialdimensionbehindthe empirical fact, the values that structure our normative responses, which is more complex than expressedinthebiologicalfunctionalaccountofvaluesandfacts 63 .

63 Ricoeur’sworkonthesymbolicnatureofevilremainsanimportantsourceofclarificationwithregardtothecomplex relationoflanguage,concretesedimentationofdailyroutines,myth,andinourexperienceofevil.Whenwe lookattheexperientialdimensionofevil‘[t]hentheproblemwillarise,howthequasibeingandthequasinothingness ofhumanevilarearticulateduponthebeingofmananduponthenothingnessofhisfinitude’(SE357/488).Evilisa fact. However, this factuality continuously subtracts itself from our comprehension because of the nature of our experienceofevil,whichcomesinendlessforms,degrees,andphysicalmanifestations.Evilisaproblemin(human) nature.Andtherealproblemishowtoconfrontthatevilandhowtolevitatethesufferingthatevilbringsabout.In ordertodoso,weneedtounderstandthefragilityofourknowledgeofevil.Isitoutsideofme,partofme,partofthe world,intheother,inthetracesoftraditionandreligion,andcanwewashitawaylikeastainonourconscience?Are myvalues,mycare,causingevilwithoutmyintentiontodoso?Ifwelookattheexperientialdimensionofevil,then this‘irredeemable’factlosesitsempiricalclarityandworksitswayintoourownpersonhood.IfIrealizethatIcannot separatemyselffromevil,maybeIwillcometo‘understandthatevilisnotsymmetricalwiththegood,wickednessis notsomethingthatreplacesthegoodnessofman;itisthestaining,thedarkening,thedisfiguringofaninnocence,a light,andabeautythatremain.However radical evilmaybe,itcannotbeas primordial asgoodness’(SE156/306).I neverconsidermyself‘irredeemableevil’,andifIseetheevilinmyownbeing,perhapsIwillseethatitisnotsomuch afactaboutevilpersonsasaproblemaboutourbeinghumanthat‘pointstowardtherelationofradicaleviltothevery beingofman’(SE156/305).

211 Therelationofethicsandvaluesdemandsmorethansubjectivity.Thisisobvious.Ethicalvalues cannotjustexpressthesubjectivenatureofpersonhood,sinceweallhavedifferentvaluesthathave to be somehow reconciled if we want to live together in a world that we all share. Therefore, functionalityshouldnotbeconsideredabadwordinourethicalreasoning.Onthecontrary,human values must reflect the demand of a certain degree of functionality which I have tried to show earlierbyemphasizingthepracticalnatureofourexperienceofandrelationtotheworldandother subjects. However, I do not believe that we reach this degree of functionality by excluding the subjectivenatureofourbeing.Withoutarespectforthesubjectivecharacterofhumanpersonhood, thenotionoffunctionalitycanendupdestroyingthepersonthatethicalreasoningwantstoprotect. Factandvalueareintrinsicallyinterwovenbecausethehumanpersonisconstitutedbyboth,andas suchtheycannotbedividedinwhatisfactandwhatisvalue,orvaluereducedtowhatisfact,or factexcludedfromvalue.Tosaythattoassessandunderstandevilorgoodisbasicallyanempirical inquiryistodecideonwhatisgoodandevilbeforestartingtheinquiry,whichnormallywouldbe consideredawrongwaytoproceed. Asimilarkindofreasoningsometimesaffectsthelegalsystem.ThepoliticalphilosopherBrian Barrycriticizesthefunctionallogicofincapacitationofhabitualoffendersthathauntsthe U.S. legalsystem(Barry2005:95105).Thesocalled‘TreeStrikesOut’lawspermituptolifesentence forathirdfelonyconviction.Theselawsaresupposedtoincapacitatehabitualviolentcriminalsand therebymakethesocietymoresafe,buthaveinlongerperiodsresultedinlifesentencesfortwice asmanymarihuanauserthankidnappers,rapists,andmurderersalltogether.Andin2000,ablack maninTexaswassentencedto16yearsimprisonmentfortheftofa1$Snickersbar.Explaining thehardsentencetothepublicafterwards,thedistrictattorneysaidthatbesidesthefactthathewas ahabitualoffenderthiswasn’tjustacandybar,butakingsizecandybar(idem:99).Thiswasof coursemeantasaverybadjoke,butthefactremainsthat85%oftheconvictionsmadebythe ‘threestrikes’lawsinthe1990’sinvolvednonviolentcrimes,oftenminormisdemeanor. Thefunctionalnatureoflegalsystemsisobviouslydifferentfromthosegoverningethicalconduct, butifwelookatthefrighteningproceduresofmanylegalcases,wemightgetanideaofhowstrict functionalism lead to inhumane treatment of human beings. When we forget (or purposely disregard) that the accused is an individual person and instead see him or her as a certain type (habitualoffender,poor,male,black),thenouractionorfinalsentencewillnecessarilylosewhat normallyqualifiesitashuman(thatwecareforindividuals).

212 Weshouldnot,however,deludeourselvesbythinkingthatthisfunctionallogicisrestrictedtoan unjust(NorthAmerican)legalsystem.Anotherpoliticalphilosopher,GiorgioAgamben,hasargued that this intentional negation of the individual for the sake of the state is deeply rooted in the tradition of western politics. Ever since Aristotle characterized man as a political animal, the distinctionbetweenlifecommontoalllivingbeings(zoê)andparticularkindoflife,i.e.,qualified life,(bíos)havegrownmoreandmoreindistinctandthebarelife‘graduallybeginstocoincidewith thepoliticalrealm,andexclusionandinclusion,outsideandinside,bíosandzoê,rightandfact, enterintoazoneofirreducibleindistinction’(Agamben1998:9/12).Thebarelife(vitanuda)is neitheranimalnorhumanlife,butsimplylifeasunqualifiedbiologicalexistence.Notpersonhood orhumanityisthefundamentofpoliticsbutthenakedbiologicalfactofexistence.Agambentraces, in his dense and complicate writings, this tendency to define the bare life up through western ethicopoliticalthoughttowhathe(withArendtandFoucault)callsthebasisofbiopolitics.Human natureisincludedintoworkingsofbiologicalnaturebymeansof‘theanthropologicalmachineof the moderns’, which ‘functions by excluding as not (yet) human an already human being from itself,thatis,byanimalizingthehuman,byisolatingthenonhumanwithinthehuman:Homoalalus, ortheapeman […]Whatwouldthusbeobtained,however,isneitherananimallifenorahuman life,butonlyalifethatisseparatedandexcludedfromitself–onlyabarelife’(Agamben2004: 37/43).Agamben’spointisradical.Heseesthisreductionofhumanlifetobarelifeasthecriterion with which modern western democracies gain the legitimacy of their sovereign power over the individualhumanbeinginordertopromotetheflourishingofthestate.Whentherighttohumanity isnolongerconsideredafactoftheindividualpersonbutadecisiontobemadeonpartofthestate, thenthechoiceisopentoexcludefromhumanitythatwhichisnotconsideredhumaninthehuman being (the animal or simply the different). Once westarttopoliticizehumanlife,arguingabout whatishumanandwhatisnot,theincludingexclusionofbarelifebecomesareality.Thisisthe paradoxinthemodernhumanrights:‘Inmodernbiopolitics,sovereignishewhodecidesonthe valueornonvalueoflifeassuch.Life–which,withthedeclarationofrights,hadassuchbeen investedwiththeprincipleofsovereignty–nowitselfbecomestheplaceofasovereigndecision’ (Agamben1998:142/158).Thecontemporarypoliticalemphasisofthevalueofbarelifedissolves theprimordialhumanityoftheindividualperson,becausethehumanvaluesarequestionedinthe firstplace.Itbecomespossibletoexcludewhenwewanttoincludesometraitsandnotothersin whatmakesalivingbeinghuman(idem:78/101).

213 Thismaybeanecessaryfunctionofapoliticalorlegalsystem.Ethics,however,isneitherpolitics nor jurisprudence. Ethical values should protect the individual person from the objectifying, impersonalreasoningthatcharacterizesmanylegalandpoliticalprocedureswherepersonsaretobe ‘managedorhandledorcuredortrained’(Strawson1962:66).Insuchprocedures,personscanbe strippedoftheirhumanityandsufferfromthe‘intuitionoffittingness’that,whenliberatedfrom humansentiment,isfreetoworkout‘anadequatebasisforcertainsocialpracticesincalculated consequences’(idem:79).Agamben’spictureofthe mechanisms of western democracy may be glooming and radical, but not distorting with respect to factual state of world politics today. Biopoliticshasbeenthehorrifyingagendaformuchpoliticsinthetwentiethcentury,andtodaythe acceleratingfocusonbodilywelfare,socialaesthetics,andthematerialistobsessionexpressedin consumer directed policies have a strong hold on the political agenda in the majority of contemporarywesternsocieties.Thisthreatenstounderminethevaluesthatmademoralandsocial progresspossibleinthefirstplace.Theproblemwithfunctionalistaccountsofvaluesisthatthey tend to forget the concrete historical consequences of past realizations of functionalism (e.g. HolocaustandtheGulags).Agamben’sanalysesshowusthatwithhumanreasonthereisalwaysthe riskofcategorizingandexcludingthatwhichdoesnot‘fit’intowhatotherstellusisrightandgood. Humanvaluesarefragile.Andwemustbecarefulwiththetheoretical(philosophical,economical, or political) conclusions that we draw from our account of values, because such theoretical conclusionsdoactuallyaffectourownlivesandthatofothers 64 .

64 Idonotthinkthatweshouldconsiderthisadistantpossibilitythat might occurordoesoccurinlessenlightened societiesthanthewestern.Itisriskthatlives,andsometimesevenflourishes,attheheartofourown‘civilized’values. The economist and social thinker Robert C. Reich has in his latest book argued that what he calls ‘democratic capitalism’ is rapidly transforming itself into ‘supercapitalism’, which suppresses the ‘citizen’ in favour of the ‘consumer’.Heseesthisasadangerousshiftinmentality,becauseitthreatenstounderminethehumanityofsocialand politicalstructuresinthenameofeconomics.Hewrites,forexample:‘Economics,asadiscipline,focusesonadomain ofpersonalconcernstrictlyboundedbywhatanalystsingovernmentstatisticalagenciesdefineasone’s“family”or “household.” But such categories are arbitrary. The capacity of human beings to emphasize – feel responsibility, loyalty, and simple human connection – extends far beyond them […] Standard economic models have little to say aboutanyofthesealtruisticsentiments.Yetascitizenswemaycareagreatdealifmostpeople’sjobsareinsecureand wagesstagnant,andifarelativelysmallnumberofpeoplehavecorneredmostofthenation’swealth’(Reich2007:98). ReichmainlydealswithUSpoliticsanddemocracy,buthestressesthatthisisnotalocalphenomena:‘Peoplearound theglobearemoreabletopursuetheirowndesiresandprofitfromtheirinvestmentswithincreasingfervor.Yetdespite the satisfaction they feel as consumers and investors, many are frustrated in their capacities as citizens. Their democracies,too,arefindingitmoreandmoredifficulttoarticulateandactuponthecommongood.Voterssurveysin Britain,Italy,Spain,Belgium,theNetherlands,Norway,Sweden,Ireland,andJapanshowcitizenswhohavegrownto feelalmostasdisempoweredasAmericans’(idem:9).Reich,however,thinksthatitistooeasyjusttoblamelarge companiesandcorruptpoliticiansforthissadchange:‘YouandIarecomplicit.Asconsumersandinvestors,wemake thewholeworldrun.Marketshavebecomeextraordinarilyresponsivetoourwishes–moresoallthetime.Yetmostof usareoftwo minds,anditisthecitizenin us thathasbecomerelativelypowerless.Supercapitalismistriumphant. Democratic capitalismisnot’(idem:99)

214 Theneurobioethicalfocusonthebiologicalandsocietalnatureofhomosapienstendstoforgetthat what makes us human is not an unqualified amalgam of the pure beating of our heart, our ‘specializedsystemsof representations,suchasmathematicalorchemicalsymbols’(Levy2007: 43),andafitfunctionalsociety.WhenCasebeerarguesthatheisactuallyjustupdatingAristotle withtheneuroscientificinsightsofpresentday,hefailstomentionthathisAristotlehascompletely forgottenthatheoncewrotethe10 th bookofthe Nicomachean Ethics wherehedescribedhuman contemplation as the highest form of human happiness. The fundament of humanity is not the impersonalbodilymaterialofhumanwork,anundefinedhumanflourishing,ortheproceduresof lawandpolitics,‘fortodonobleandgooddeedsisathingdesirableforitsownsake’(Aristotle 1984: 1859 [1176b78]). This kind of contemplation is not functional reasoning, since it is not directedatanythingelse.Itisthelibertyofeveryhumanbeingtothink,dream,feel,value,and understand the world in his or hers own personal way. Ethics is our way of conditioning this subjective basis of human personhood by finding the most appropriate actions according to our individualnatures.Ifwedestroyorobjectifythis subjective fundament of human intercourse by makingour ethicsfunctional,then2+2can eventually become 5 and the absurdity of ‘Arbeit machtfrei’canonceagainbejustifiedbyagreatermeaning 65 . Thiscritiqueofneuroethicsshouldnotbereadasnewversionoftheoldcriticismofrationalityand scientificandtechnologicalprogress.AsIhavesaidbefore,Idobelievethatafurtherscientific clarification of human nature can help us make a better ethical theory. What I oppose is blind enthusiasmandquicksolutionstodifficultproblems.Aristotle,Hume,Kant,andMoorewereall cautious, almost enigmatic, with regard to human nature. Ricoeur joined this attitude by emphasizing the fragile constitution of subjectivity. We know that human nature is a part of physicalnatureandstillsomehowautonomousofthatsamenature.Humansareselfcentered,need company,seekhappiness,andreasonabouthowtoliveandhowtoactinthebestpossibleways. Buttosaythathumanbeingsareonlyreasonableoronlyverycomplexbiologicalorganismsor madeintheimageoftranscendinggodsistosaymorethanweactuallyknow.Wecanchooseto saylikeChangeux,whenRicoeurconfrontshimwiththisfragilityofourknowledge,thatthiswill all be completely different in 2500, where we can finally rewrite Spinoza’s Ethics on 65 Agambendescribesthecontemplativenatureasthefundamentforselfhoodandtherebyhumanactionandlife:‘The life,whichcontemplatesits(own)powertoact,makesitselfnonworkableinallitsoperations–itlivesthe(personal) life.Iwrite“own”and“personal”inparenthesisbecauseonlythroughthecontemplationofpower,whichmakesnon workableeveryspecific energeia ,somethingliketheexperienceofan“own”anda“self”becomespossible.Theself, thesubjectivity,isthatwhichopensitselfasanonworkabilitycentralineveryoperation,asthelivability [vivibilità ] ofeverylife.Inthisnonworkability,thelifethatweliveisonlythelifethroughwhichwelive,onlyourpowertoact andtolive,ouractability [agibilità ]andourlivability ’(Agamben2007:274.MyTranslation).

215 neurobiological terms (WT 201/211). Then we will eventually understand that ethics is just an extendedpartofalargerneurobiologicalaccountofthelivingorganism.Suchoutcries,however, areneglectingthefactthataneurobiologicalaccountofethicswillalwaysremainfunctional‘from senselessatomstofreelychosenactions’(Dennett2003:306),sinceitisembeddedinanobscure evolutionarytheorythatenhances‘benselfishtypes’and‘punishtoopure“altruists”’becausethese ‘helpfreeloadersflourish’(idem:200).Humannatureisfragileandvulnerablebecauseitisrooted inacomplexsubjectivitythatmakespersonssodifferentfromoneanother.Therealwayshasbeen andalways willbe‘tooaltruist’persons andcoldheartedpersons,butisshouldneverbeupto otherpeopletodecideontheirhumanityonbasisoftheirabilitytofitintoahuman(alltoohuman) accountofwhatishuman.Ifthevalueswithwhichwecharacterizehumanactiondonotreflectthe subjectiveattitudes,feelings,andthoughtsofhumanpersonhood,thentheyloosewhatevercould makethemhumaninthefirstplace. Faulknerwritesinhis As I Lay Dying abouttheindestructiblesubjectivityineveryperson,inthis casethequeernatureofDarlwho,albeithisprofound‘naturalaffection’forotherhumanbeings, continuestodefythenormalreasoningoftheDeepSouthfamily:‘ButIain’tsoshothatereaman hasrighttosaywhatiscrazyandwhatain’t.Itisliketherewasafellowineverymanthat’sdonea pastthesanityortheinsanity,thatwatchesthesaneandtheinsanedoingsofthatmanwiththesame horrorandastonisment’(Faulkner1996:226).

216 ChapterTwo PersonhoodinNatureandCulture Moralfactsandvaluesexistandarepersonal.Wefeelthem,weactuponthem,andwedisagree aboutthem.Thisiswhatintuitive,Humeanbackgammonplayingexperiencetellsus.But,asKant onceobserved:‘Thereissomethingsplendidaboutinnocence;butwhatisbadaboutit,inturn,is thatitcannotprotectitselfverywellandiseasilyseduced’(Kant1998a:17/4045).Weliveina worldthatdoesnotknowanythingaboutourethicaldoubt,convictions,andconflicts.Sothejobof philosophymustbetotrytounderstandhowmoralvaluesarefactsandhowtheyfitinwiththerest of what we know about nature. This is not just another futile theoretical investigation of little interesttoothersthanacademicphilosophers.Onthecontrary,ithasimportantpersonal,social,and evenpoliticalimplications,sinceourwaytothinkaboutvalueandethicsinfluencesourdecisions, attitudes,andbehaviorwithregardtotheother,both those we care about and disagree with and thosethatwedonotcareaboutandstilldisagreewith. IntheforegoingpagesIhaverepeatedlysaidthatIamnaturalist.Now,bywayofconclusion,I wanttoclarifywhatIexactlymeanbythis.Further,Ihavepromisedtoexplainhowtherelation betweenethicsandsubjectivitymightshedsomelightontheprocessofnaturalization.Iapproach thesetwoissuesinthreemovesthattogether,hopefully,willclarifymyposition.First,Ispecify what I mean by naturalism by positioning it with regard to other kinds of naturalism. Then I questiontheintuitiverelationbetweensubjectivityandmoralrelativismandarguethattherelation betweensubjectivityandethicsisnotapleaformoralrelativism.Andfinally,Iconcludewitha brief summary of some central arguments of the dissertation about the natural status of ethical personhoodinanonethicalworld,andwhichis,atthesametime,amodestsuggestionforfurther processofnaturalization. Thisconcludingclarificationis,asmentionedearlier,obviouslynotanattempttosettlethelong standingandverycomplicatedebateaboutthefactvaluedistinction.Thisexceedsbothmycapacity andthescopeandaimofthiswork.Theworkismeantasanargumentfortheirreduciblerelationof subjectivityandethicswithrespecttoanaturalizedconceptionofhumanpersonhood,andIbelieve thatthisneedsafinaldiscussionofbothnaturalismandrelativism.Thepreviouschaptercriticized neuroethicsforexcludingsubjectivityinitsattempttonaturalizeethics.Thischaptercanbeseenas anextensionofthatargumentbyshowingthatthenotionofsubjectivitydoesnotblocktheprocess of naturalization nor lead to moral relativism, which is a common objection to the notion of subjectivityinethics.Onthecontrary,aclarifiednotionofsubjectivitycanbeseenasapartofthis

217 process,becauseitcanhelptogiveamoresolidaccountofanaturalizedethicsthanisproposedby theneuroethicalexclusionofsubjectivity.

Which Sort of Naturalism? Mycriticismofneuroethicsstressedthenotionofsubjectivityandtriedtoarguefortheimplausible and sometimes even dangerous solutions offered by an ethics controlled by impersonal functionalism. Subjectivity matters, or rather, subjectivity is fundamental to ethical reasoning. Whenanethicsignorestheindividualnatureofthepersonor‘thespecificcontingenciesofone’s creaturelypointofview’(Nagel1986:9),i.e.,subjectivity,andwantstoexplainwhattheperson shoulddoandthinkwithreferencetoneurophysiologicalmechanismsandamythicaltransparent fitfunctionalsocietythatarebothincomprehensibleandfarfromtransparentformostpersons(if not all), then it stops being an ethical theory and transforms into bad moralizing. Many neuroethicists(andperhapsevenmorescientisticphilosophers)abhorreligionandtalkaboutthe soulbecausesuchaccountsaregroundedinanobscuremetaphysicsthatignorestheactualstateof the universe and the biological being of the human person. Sometimes, however, they adopt a patronizingtoneexplainingthatreligiousbeliefsarejustasnaturalasanythingelseintheuniverse, becausethebrainneedstoformreligiousbeliefsjustasitneedsapaniccentertoavoiddanger.This isallduetothesimplefactthat‘[h]umansarebeliefformationmachines’(Gazzaniga2006a:161). Infact,manycreativepersons(e.g.Socrates,Dostoevsky,Flaubert,andVanGogh)andreligious leaders (Moses, Buddha, Muhammad, and Paul) may very well all have been suffering from temporallopeepilepsy,whichcausedthemtoformtheirartandreligioussystems(idem:15660). Butoftenreligionandmetaphysicsaresimplyconsideredasdangerousfiction.Thedangeristhat such accounts can inspire us to act on false beliefs about the world and human nature. This is possiblytrue,butthereissomethingcraftyaboutthiskindofreasoning,sincethetruthsproposed byneuroethicsandscientisticphilosophersoftencontainthesamesortofobscuredogmatismthat they accuse religion and metaphysics for. Evolutionary theory comes in all kinds of flavor, explanations for physicalistic determinism in even more, brain imaging techniques still only penetratetheupperlayersofthebrainlopes,andthecomplexityofthebrainmindbodyunitythat wecallthinkingistodaynotmoretransparentthanthatoftheuniverse.Andtheconstantpledge that in a (near or distant) future we will eventuallydiscoverthisorthatwhichcanfinallysolve traditional philosophical problems sounds a lot like the futuredirected explanations of some (waitandseewhatshallcome!).

218 Thisis,ofcourse,puttingthingsontheedge.Thevastmajorityofseriousempiricalscientistsisof courseverycautiouswiththeirconclusionabouthumannatureandremainswithintheirrespective (local)fieldsofinvestigation.However,thetensionbetweennaturalsciencesandthehumanities canbestrong,andIthinkthatthisisduetoanimplicitdichotomyintheconceptionofnature.A dichotomy that has existed since the birth of modern science but recently grew into an intense publicdebate. Thelastdecadeofthe20 th centurywastormentedbythesocalled‘sciencewars’betweendifferent academic cultures. On the one side, we had the ‘postmodernists’ who, backed up by Thomas Kuhn’sfamousbookfrom1962,arguedthat‘scientifictheoriesarepurelysocialconstructionswith nomoreclaimtothelabel“truth”thanothersociallyconstructedideas’(Baringer2001:9).Onthe other,thescientistswhoretortedthatthescientificmethodistheonlywaytoavoidmysticismand personalbiaseswhichwilldivertusfromlogicandrationalismandputusontheroadtodogmatism (idem:57;foragooddiscussionofthesciencewars,seeAshmanandBaringer2001).Thiswaris stillfoughttoday,althoughpostmodernismissubstitutedwithreligion. Thepublic and academic discussionisnolongeraboutpostmodernismandscientism,butmoreabouthowscientificprogress and(Christian)religionarethetwopillarsofwesterncivilization.Thequestionaboutnaturalization istoooftenseen asachoicebetweeneitherthecold world of science or the colorful world of religion. A naturalist has to confess complete adherence to the impersonal account of science otherwiseheorsheisconsideredaslogicallyinconsistentorsimplysuperficial.Ontheotherhand, areligiouspersonmustaccountfortheparadoxofcreationandafterlifeifheorsheisnottobe labeledaconformistandintellectuallylazy.Andalthoughtalkaboutreligionmayseemirrelevant forthepresentdiscussionaboutsubjectivity,ethicsandnaturalization,Ithinkthatthefearofbeing called mystic, idealistic, or even religious affects the way much discussion about nature is conducted. I will go so far as to say that one of the most difficult issues in the process of naturalizationisanimplicitdichotomyintheconceptionofnature: either objective, certain, and realistic or subjective,uncertain,andidealistic. This has recently been discussed by Hans Fink in a thorough and clear article about ethical naturalism and the concept of nature (2006). In a discussion of McDowell’s famous distinction betweentwosortsofnaturalism,‘neoHumeannaturalism’or‘baldnaturalism’(natureasrevealed bythenaturalsciences)andMcDowell’sown‘acceptablenaturalism’or‘Greeknaturalism’(nature understood in a broader sense that include all human potentials, e.g. virtues, skills etc.), Fink introducesathirdsortofnaturalismthathecalls‘unrestrictedorabsolutenaturalism’(idem:205).

219 WhilebeingingeneralagreementwithMcDowell’sviewonamoreacceptableethicalnaturalism, Finkbelievesthatthethirdsortofnaturalismisbetter,becauseitcan‘pointusintherightdirection whenitcomestotheunderstandingofapositivenaturalismprovidingaconvincingalternativeto baldnaturalism’(idem).HereIwillnotdealwithhiscommentsonMcDowell,butfocusonhis argumentsabouttheunderlying conceptionofnatureinvolvedinthedifferentunderstandingsof naturalism. Finkpointstotheambiguityinouruseoftheconceptofnature.Ontheoneside,wetalkabout‘the natureofsomething–e.g.mynature,humannature,thenatureofacertainmineral,something beinginthenatureofthings’and,ontheother,wetalkabout‘nature asarealmofitsown,the world of nature’ (idem: 206). The first way of talking about nature must include absolutely everything,and‘[i]twouldbewrongtoleaveanythingout’(idem:207),sinceeveryaspectofthe beingxispartofthenatureofx.Allthatweeventuallycancometoknowaboutthenatureofa certainbeingisreleveanttothenatureofthatbeing.Say,forexample,thatsomedayanattentive scientistdiscoversabutterflythatcanactuallyswimunderwater,thenthisdiscoverywillbevery importanttoourunderstandingofthenatureoftheLepidopteraorderofinsects.Finkcallsthisa ‘non-contrasting conceptionofthenatureofxopentoanyfutureadditionalinformationaboutx’ (idem: 208). In contrast to such an unrestricted understanding of nature, we have the other conceptionthatwantstounderstandthenatureoftheworldwelivein.Sincewewanttofindthe basic and constant structure of the world that we try to understand, such a general conception quicklyleadstocontrastsandrestrictionsthat‘wouldthenidentifynaturewithcertainpartsorsides oftheworld’(idem:209). This is, I would claim, what happens in the neuroethical account of values. Moral facts are functional facts, because the world is functional in nature. The body is a complex functional machine,anautumnleafinthewindisjustasmechanical as the words of Shakespeare and my kitchen blender; the society has to reflect this functionality and the person simply fit into the machinery.Inthiswaywecansolvethetediousissuesofmoraldisagreementandpreventthatthe byproductsofevolution(anunfunctionalmoralfeelinglike‘purealtruism’)comeinthewayofthe progressofevolution,otherwisethisinsatiateprogresswillsweepusawaylikeinsignificantcrumbs onatable.Neuroethicscomestothisconclusiononthebackgroundofarestrictedandfragmentary conceptionofnature.Sincethephysiologicalconstitutionofhumannatureandthegenerallawsof physics and biology are functional, the basic structures and dynamics of nature have to be

220 functional, and explanations of nature must conform to these basic features if they are to be consideredvalidandtrueto real nature. Fink’sargumentforanunrestrictedorabsoluteconceptionofnaturecontestssucharestrictedview onwhatisrealnature.Wecannotoperatewithasimplisticconceptionofwhatisnatureandwhatis not,because‘[n]atureisnever mere nature.Thatwhichis more than mere isnature,too[...]thefact thattherearesomanyincompatiblecontrastingandrestricted conceptionsofnature andthe fact thateachofthemcreatesformidabledifficultiesinaccountingforthatwhichisregardedasnon naturalprovidesastrongmotivationfortryingtoexplicateanabsoluteconception.’(idem:217). Finkiswellawarethatsuchaconceptiondoesnotsolvetheproblemsofnaturalism,butitisaway toavoid‘theotherwiseendlessoscillation’betweenthedifferentconceptionsofnature:‘Natureis thatwhichallpossibledomainsaredomainsof.Natureisallthereis,allthatisthefact,allthat happens’(idem:218).Hence,whenIdefinemyselfasanaturalist,itisthissortofnaturalismthatI referto. However,IneedtobemorespecificifIwanttopositionmyselfproperlywithregardtotheprocess ofnaturalization.MyprimaryinteresthereistoclarifywhatImeanbenaturalismwithregardto ethicsandsubjectivity.This,Iwillclaiminthe conclusivesection,bearsaconsequenceforthe moregeneralconceptionofnaturalization. InFink’sabsoluteorunrestrictedconceptionofnaturethereisnocontradictioninspeakingofthe natureofGodorofthesupernatural(idem:206,218).Thisiscertainlytrueonatheoreticallevel. The Christian God, Odin, Demeter, E.T., and golden mountains all have a nature and therefore belongtoanunrestrictedconceptionofnature.Theytellussomethingaboutnatureingeneral,as the sum of what is actually experienced,withoutdisqualifyingsomeexperiences of nature on a theoreticallevel. Onapracticallevel,thingsareabitmoredifficult,sincethedifferentexperiencesofnatureoften disagreeandconflict.Andanimportantaspectofmyconceptionofethicalreasoningisthatsuch disagreementsmustremainonapracticallevel,andnotbesettledwithspeculativeorideological arguments.WithspeculativeandideologicalImeanungroundedargumentsandblindconvictions thatpresupposeorimpelmorethancanbeaccountedforwithregardtocommonhumanconcerns. This, however, does not imply that we can do ethics without theoretical arguments. But such argumentsaredifferentfromspeculationsandideologies,sincetheyare(orshouldbe)impartial and rooted firmly in the nature of human practices (our care, interest, and concerns). This distinction between speculative/ideological and theoretical arguments is important in order to

221 understandmyconceptionofethicalnaturalism.Thismeans,forexample,thatourconceptionof God or other supernatural natures must not a priori restrict other conceptions of nature. In the naturalisticperspectivethatIproposeitwouldbewrong,i.e.,badpracticalreasoning,tosaythatit isthewilloftheChristianGodthatmissionariesremovepreservativesfromcommunitiesinKenya becauseitisasintohaveprotectedsex.Suchpracticalreasoningdisregardsthefactthatcommonly people do want to have sex without thinking about children and even less about dying from a terrifying virus. The same argument holds for neuroethics and other restrictive kinds of naturalizations. We cannot use one conception of nature, in this case a functionalevolutionary account,todeterminehowweshouldthink aboutethical questions that involve the concerns of personswhoconsiderthemselvestobemorethanjustobjectsofimpersonalfunctions.Conceptions of nature that a priori exclude religious phenomena or what, in their conception of nature, is considered to be unnatural phenomena such as personhood, pure altruism, or protected sex are making one aspectofnatureintoan absolute conceptionofnature.Fink’sthirdsortofnaturalism arguesthatsuchamoveisimplausibleandrestrictivebecauseitwantstoexplainthewholeby isolatingapartandcontrastingittothewhole.Instead of using specific scientific methods and insightstodefinearestrictedconceptionofnature,Finkproposesthat‘unrestrictednaturalismtakes ittobedefiningofsciencethatallthingsarethemeasureofscience’(idem:218). Therefore,myconceptionofethicalnaturalismclaimsthatsubjectiveexperiencematters,because theethicalqualitiesthatthesubjectexperiencesinitsinteractionwiththeworld(goodness,badness, love,shame,resentment,wrongness,rightness,courage,virtue,commitment,etc.)areanaturalpart ofwhatitmeanstobeahumansubject,aperson.ThedeflatedethicaltheorythatIproposeassures theexistenceofsuchthickmoralconcepts,sincetheyareasubstantialpartofhumanexperience, butarguethattheycanbeexaminedanddiscussedwithoutframingaspecificmoralspacesevered from the rest of what we know about human nature. Our thick personal concepts that regard religious experiences, fragile identity, vulnerable personhood, esthetic experience and the cold insights from the empirical sciences such as our mammal kinships, evolutionary past, neurophysiological structures and mechanisms, social behavior and statistics, economic and politicaldimensionsare,togetherwithaninfinityofothers,allpartofhumannature.Andtoneglect orintentionallydisregardanyoftheseaspectsofhumannatureistoimpairethicalreasoning.And thisiswhatIbelievehappensifourconceptionofnatureisinfectedwiththeimplicitdichotomy thathauntsmuchethics(andphilosophyingeneral)today.

222 AsImentionedinthebeginningofthissection,I think that this dichotomy (objective, certain, realisticvs.subjective,uncertain,ideological)hasbeenstressedbytheturmoilofthe‘sciencewars’ of the last century. Subjective experience becomes associated with introspective, unscientific idealismwithatwistofmysticism,whichhasnothingtodowithrealsolidscience.Itbecomesan either/or,andnotabothand.Wecanhaveasubjectivetasteofwineandasubjectivefeelingofart, butnotasubjectivefeelingaboutethics,becausethenweendupwithmoralrelativismthatdoesnot helpusinourexistencewithotherpeople.Ontheotherhand,ifweconsultempiricalsciencessuch asneuroscienceandbiologythenwenecessarilyendupwithacoldandimpersonalaccountofour warmethicalrelationtootherpeople. Such ways of positioning oneself to the dichotomy can be seen in the writings of Taylor, Blackburn,andRicoeur.Althoughallthreethinkershaveworkedmuchwiththenaturalstatusof humanpersonhoodandtherebythedichotomyitself, their work somehow reflects the excluding tendencythataffectsmuchwritingaboutnaturalism.Taylor’sconstantrejectionofnaturalismtout courtandofdeflatednaturalistictheoriesofethicssuchasBlackburn’squasirealistexpressivism revealsageneralconceptionofnaturalismasimpersonalizingthesubjectandstrippingitofallthat whichmakesitahumansubject.AndalthoughBlackburn’saccountofpracticalreasoning,whichI follow,placessubjectiveexperiencesinthecenterofthetheory,hedoesnotconsiderreligionor religiousexperiencetohaveanythingtodowithethics.Ibelieveboththeseattitudestobewrong, sincetheyneglecttworichsourcesofinformationabouthumannature.AndalthoughIhavenot consideredreligioninthiswork,sincemyprimaryfocuswasonthenaturalrelationbetweenethics and subjectivity, I believe it to be an indispensable aspect of any ethical theory, since religious experience reveal something about human nature, for example, the experience of transcendent alterity in subjective experience. Ricoeur’s writings, although more openstructured, suffers from thesamedichotomy.Hisphilosophicalandtheologicalanalysesarestrangelysegregated,andhis discussion of naturalization is only peripheral. Nonetheless, I think that Ricoeur’s theory of subjectivity, because of its deep and openstructured analyses, offers, when reformulated, an adequateframeworkforanunrestrictedconceptionofnatureandanaturalisticapproachtoethics andsubjectivityinthesensedescribedabove. Thus,saidroughly,ourconceptionofwhatisnatureandwhatisnotaffectstheontologyinwhich we ground our ethical practices and argue for our ethicalvalues.Theontologythat Ihavebeen arguedforisconstitutedbycare.Thisis,ofcourse,ahumanwayoftalkingaboutit,becauseitis hardlylikelythatatickcaresaboutitsexistenceinthesamewaythatwehumansdo.However,

223 everylivingorganism‘cares’aboutlivinginthesensethatitinteractswiththeenvironmentinorder toliveandreproducelife,fromthefunctionalsplittingofthecelltohumancarefortheotherin eroticandparentallove.Humanethicalvaluesarerootedinandgeneratedbythisbasiccarethat characterizesalllivingorganisms,althoughhumancareisnotgovernedbythesamefunctionality thatqualifyothermammaliancare.Tounderstandthisnaturalconceptionofhumancareandnot reduceittowhatitisnot,wehavetomakeourconceptionofnatureasbroadaspossiblesothatwe donotstartonawrongontologicalfooting.Atthesametime,itisimportanttoarguewhysucha conceptionofanaturalisticontologyisnotthesameastosaythateverythinggoes,andthatwe cannot exclude anything from our conception of human nature. As I said, ethics is a practical matter,andaseverybodyknowsthatnotallpracticesaregoodpractices,andthatsomearebetter thanothers.Therefore,toargueforanunrestrictedconceptionofnatureinethicalreasoningisnot to argue for moral relativism. The relation of subjectivityandethicshassomethingtosayabout whatisliketobeahumanperson. So,beforeconcludingwithafinalsummaryofthenatural relationbetweensubjectivityandethics andwhythisrelationisimportanttothegeneralprocessofnaturalization,wehavetolookatone lastdangerwhentalkingaboutanaturalisticconceptionoftherelationbetweensubjectivityand ethics,namelytheaccusationofopeningadoorforrelativism.Iwilldefendtheethicalrelevanceof notionofsubjectivitybycriticizingverybrieflysomemethodologicalaspectsofarecentattemptto argue for relativism on the background of a extensive account of emotions, subjectivity, and naturalization. Not a Plea for Relativism Subjectivitymustnotbeconfusedwithsubjectivism.Subjectivismhasabadreputationinmoral philosophyandisoftenassociatedwithrelativism,idealism,andegoism.Ifethicsweretodepend onthevaluesoftheindividualsubject,howcouldwethenpossiblyavoidthateverybodyactson whatthatpersonthinksorfeelsisbestforhimorher?Orevenworse,howcouldweprescribeor demandthatthepersondidotherwise?Questionslikethesetroubleeveryattempttoputthesubject atthecenterofmoralreasoning,andthatwithgoodreason.Fewphilosopherswouldrecommend strong moral relativism, since the sense of doing moral philosophy is to find the best way for differentpersonstointeractwithoneanother.Andrelativismmakesthisdifficult.IfIcannotsayto another person that he or she has treated me wrong,insultedmeorhurtme,humanintercourse becomesdifficult,ifnottosayimpossible.Humanlivesareinterwoven,andpeoplecareaboutone

224 another.Thisisa factthateventhemostsubtlespeculation cannot dissolve. Why, then, would anybodyrecommendsomethingasnonsensicalasrelativism?Thereare,however,goodreasonsfor this.Aswesawabove,moralitycanturnuglyandbecomebadmoralizingthatdoesnotrespectthe individualpersonhoodofeveryhumanbeing.Moralizingisdifferentfrommoralitybecauseitrelies onanauthoritythatclaimstoknowwhatisbestforapersonoracommunitywithoutregarding whatthepersonorcommunitythinkthemselves.Historyandpresentdayarefullofexamplesof badmoralizingandofpeoplesayingwhatotherpeopleshouldthink,feel,ordo.Iammakinga normativeclaimwhenIsaythatsomeneuroethicistsdobadmoralizing,orthatsomereligionsand communities do bad moralizing systematically, make it a policy, and cause dismay and terror aroundthem.Suchaclaimcaneasilyturnintobadmoralizingitself,ifitisnotsupportedbygood arguments.Thequestionofwhatisagoodargumentandwhatisnotisalsoanormativeclaim.So, asIhavetriedtoargueforearlier,therenowayofgettingbehindnormativity.Wearetetheredto normativityinvirtueofbeingahumansubjectwholivesasapersonamongotherpersons.And,on thisview,ethicaltheoryisbasicallytheattempttoargueforwhatisconsideredagoodargumentor reasonwhenjudging,acting,andarguingmorally.Inshort,howdowelegitimizethevaluesand normsbywhichweinteractwithotherpeople? ThepicturethatIhavelaidoutintheforegoinganalysesfocusesonsubjectivityand,inparticular, on feelings as the source of normativity. And I have argued, from within the framework of Ricoeur’stheoryofsubjectivity,thatthisdoesnotqualifyasrelativism.Onthecontrary,relativism isnotanoption,becauseselfandsubjectivity cannotbereducedto egoismorskepticismwith regardtothevaluesoftheother.Mysubjectivefeelings arenotconstitutedbymyownlimited understandingandexperienceoftheworldorrestrictedtoaconcernformyownwellbeing.Ihave arguedforthisintermsofthepracticalspaceofreasonandanontologyofcare.Mybasicclaimis thatvaluesareconstitutedbysubjectivefeelings,andIhavearguedthatthesefeelingscannotbe understoodwithoutconsideringthatthesubjectisapersonotherthanbeingabiologicalbeing.But beforeconcludingwithashortoutlineofhowIseeasuccessfulnaturalizationofpersonhood,Iwill confronttheproblemofrelativismbypresentingsomeaspectsofarecentphilosophicalargument formoralrelativismthatreferstonotionsthatImyselfhavebeenstressing,namelyhumanconcerns andsubjectivity. Whendiscussingdifferenttheoriesofemotionsinthelastpart,Ibrieflymentionedacontemporary variantoftheJamesLangefeelingtheoryproposedbytheJesseJ.Prinz(page121,note24).Prinz isveryproductiveandhas,since2002,publishedthreebooksthatheconsiderstobeoneextensive

225 argumentforaHumeanempiricism,whichparallelsthestructureofthethreebooksof Hume’s Treatise :concepts,emotions,andmorality.Modestly,hecharacterizeshisbooksas‘footnotes’and yet‘atributeandmodestextensionofHume’smasterwork’(Prinz2007:vii).Prinz’workhasan impressive interdisciplinary scope, comprising cognitive science, cultural anthropology, neuroscience,andevolutionarypsychology,andhisprovocativeandclearstylemakeshisbooks excitingandaccessibleforreaderscomingfrommanydifferentfields.Frommyownpointofview hispositionisinteresting,becausehedefendsafeelingtheoryinemotionalresearchand,further, seesemotionsasessentialtoethicaltheory.Thus,myownframeworkissimilartohis,andyetI completelydisagreewithmostofwhathehastosayaboutbothemotionsandethics.Ithinkthat thiscanbeexplainedbyourcontrastingunderstandingofthenotionofsubjectivity.Thisdifference makeshistheoryofemotionsandhisethicaltheoryutterlydifferentfromwhatIhaveproposedin thisdissertation.Obviously,IcannotgivePrinz’elaborateaccounttheextensivetreatmentthatit merits,butwillonlydealbrieflywithsomemethodologicalaspectsthatseparatehisapproachfrom mineandmakeshisfinalresult,moralrelativism,a logical conclusionthatIdisagreewith. Prinz has an apparently clear agenda. Empiricism can answer most philosophical questions 66 . Therefore a philosophical theory must work conceptually with what we learn from biology and culturalstudies.Forexample,thestudyofemotionsshouldnotfocusononeofthetwo,butrealize that ‘[a]dult emotions are both cultural and biological. One needs a notion of compatibilism to capturethisinteraction’(Prinz2004:158).Andhearguesforthesame ‘bioculturalapproachto morality’(2007:270),because‘moralrulesarenotinnate.Rather,theyemergethroughinteraction betweenbiology andculture[…]Biologically based behaviors arenot quitea constraintonthe genealogyofmoralrules,becauseculturecanoverridethem.Wecanunderstandmanymoralnorms asculturallyspecificvariationsonthesamebiologicalthemes’(idem:274).However,hewantsto reject biological reductionism, because the innate gut reactions (sadness, fear, surprise, panic, disgustetc.)encodedinourgenesisoverriddenby culture that ‘does not merely activate innate programs; it rewires our moral software […] One might put the point by saying that humans instinctivelytaketheircluesfromculture.Culturealsoconvertsourbiologicalnormsintomoral norms–normsthataregroundedinsentimentsandextendedtothirdparties’ (idem:286).This clarification gives him an empirical framework whereinheemploystheconceptualanalysesthat werepreparedbyhisfirstwork Furnishing the Mind: Concepts and their Perceptual Basis (2002).

66 Hewrites,forexample:’Ithinkthatenduringphilosophicalquestionscanbeilluminatedbyempiricalresults,and, indeed,theymightnotenduresolongifweusetheresourcesofscience’(2007:9).

226 Here I will focus on his understanding of the generation and status of human values on the backgroundofthisbioculturalframework. Whereasafunctionalunderstandingofvaluesinducedneuroethicstosuppresssubjectivity,Prinz cares very much about defending the individual subject’s right to ‘privacy, free expression, and diversity’,eventoanextendthatsecures‘isolationism’(idem:212).Inthissense,hisagendaisthe completeoppositeofCasebeer’sversionofneuroethics.Andstill,therearemanysimilaritiesinthe ways they construct their notion of values. We have two sources of information about human values,biologyandculture.Andasagoodempiricist,Prinzdoesnotacceptotherfoundationsof values. This is basically the same reasoning that we found in neuroethics only that Prinz’ naturalisticapproachstartswithadifferentassumption.Contrarytoneuroethicalfunctionalismthat coinsourvaluesontheworkingsofbiologyand society ,Prinzseesvaluesasconstructedbybiology and individuality .Wecannotassumethatmoralvaluespossessthestabilitythatneuroethicsorother ethical theories presume them to hold. Nonetheless, ‘moral properties are perfectly real’, since ‘wrongnessinducesemotionsinus,andthoseemotionsimpactourbehavior’(2007:167),butstill ‘[m]oralpropertiesarenotobjectiveinanyinterestingsense’(idem).Moralvaluesarefacts,since theyare‘causallyefficacious’andbringaboutobservablechangesintheenvironment.Buttheyare differentfromphysicalfacts,becausetheydependonthesubjectswhodealwiththem.Amountain doesnotdisappearjustbecausewewantitto,norwillthesunpiercethroughtheskyonarainyday, becauseIdesparatelyneedsomelight.Thesearefactsthatexistinanotherwaythanmoralvalues, becausetheyareabsolutelyindependentoftheconstitutionandwillofthesubject.Thefactualityof moralityandnormsaredifferent,because‘[m]oralfactsarelikemoney.Theyaresocialfactsthat obtaininvirtueofourcurrentdispositionsandpractices.Theyareasrealasmonetaryvaluesand even more important, perhaps, in guiding our lives’ (idem). So, if values are facts but still not objective facts, then what kind of moral theory does Prinz argue for? He calls his position ‘constructive sentimentalism’, since ‘the members of different cultures can have different fundamentalvalues’(195).Valuesareconstructedbytheculturethattheyaresupposedgovern. Prinzconjoinsthesentimentalisttraditioninsaying that subjective feelings are fundamental for ethicalthought.Infact,‘moralvaluesaresentiments’(120),whichmeansthattheyareexpressedby theemotionsofthesubjectwhojudgessomethingaswrongorright.Sofarhefollowsthekindof reasoning that I have been arguing for. Sentiments represent our basic concerns, i.e., human dispositions to experience different emotions (84). And he gives many examples of moral

227 sentiments(i.e.moralvalues)suchasanger,contempt,resentment,fear,sadness,happiness,liking, disliking,loving,hating,andsoon. Thisallfitswellwithmyownaccountofhumanvalues.Wecannotneglectthesubjectiveaspectof values,andwesawthatalsoBlackburnusedthemetaphorofmonetaryvaluestoexpressthatwe cannotfindmoralvaluesbutinthewaythathumansubjectsinteractwithoneanother.Buttherethe similaritiesstop.Prinz’hasastrictempiricalframeworkthathemustrespect.WhereasBlackburn andthesentimentalisttraditionthatIadheretoretainthatmoralvaluescannotbeaccountedforwith truthconditionalsandreferenceto‘hard’empiricalfacts,Prinzseesitotherwise.Heisconvinced thatwehavetosticktowhatweknow.Ifmoralityshallnotbecompletelyunnaturalinaperfectly naturalworld,thenweneedsomethingtoholdonto when we discuss moral disagreements and practical issues about how human beings should judge one another’s behavior. Prinz therefore spendsalotoftimecriticizingtheviewthatIhavebeendefending,namelythathumanvaluesdoes not depend on truthconditionals in the same way that functional logic does (e.g. 100). On the contrary,heclaimsthatmoralvaluesdoindeed‘refertorealfacts’(108).Wehavetobeableto pointoutempiricallywhyoneactioniswrong,whileanotherisright,otherwiseit‘wouldbehardto makesenseofmoraldiscourse’(idem).Wecannotretortthatpracticalhumanreasoningisnota matteroftruthinthesensethatarealistsemanticsaccountsfortruth(i.e.byreferencetoempirical facts and logical deduction), since this goes against the naturalism that Prinz defends, i.e., the facticityofempiricalfindings(from‘neuroscience,psychology,psychiatry,anthropology,cultural history,andethology)thatmake‘philosophyascontinuouswithscience’(10). AsImentionedearlier,Prinzisinterestingbecausehisempiricalframeworkreachesthecomplete opposite result of Casebeer’s functionalism, although they work with the same confidence in empiricalsciencesandlogic(biology,culture/society,andconceptualanalysis).Prinzarguesfora strongrelativismthatsecurestherightofthevaluesystemoftheindividualagentinfrontofother agents(Prinzoftenusesthetermagentinsteadofpersonasiftoemphasizethelogicalnatureofhis analyses).Forexample,theevaluativepropositionssuchas‘killingiswrong’isbothcontentand truthrelativeinthesensethatthepropositiondependsontheindividualagentwhouttersitandis notnecessarilywrongfortheagentwhoisinfactkillinganotherhumanbeing(17583).Thisseems tobethelogicalimplicationofadoptinganethicaltheorythatputstheindividualsubjectandhisor hersfeelingsatthecenterofmoralvalues.HowcanIsaythatanotherperson’svaluesarewrongifI claimthathumanvaluesareconstitutedbysubjectivefeelings?Prinzthinksthathisargumentfor relativism is evident, because it is backed by the empirical fact that different persons do feel

228 differentlyinfrontofthesamethingorevent,andthus‘the existenceofdifferencesinpeople’s sentimentsentailsadifferenceinmoralfacts’(175).Therefore,heusesmanypagestoargueforthe implausible justification of the common western conviction that cannibalism and female circumcisioniscategoricallywrong.Obviously,hedoesnotappraisesuchpracticesbutquestions ourfirmbeliefthatnobodywantstobeeatenorhavetheir genitalsmutilated.Heobservesthat ‘cannibalismmaybethedefaulthumanpractice’(224),andhethenreferstomanystudiesfrom culturalanthropologythatconfirmthisstrange fact .Withregardtofemalecircumcision,heargues thatmanygirlsarewillinglyacceptingthisritual,and‘[a]sfarasIknow,mostwomenwhohave cometoacceptcircumcisionhavenotundergoneanyunusuallycoercivemethodsofindoctrination’ (210).Weneedunderstandthat‘[r]elativismpromotestoleranceincaseswherethe“victims”are trulywilling’(211). However,IbelievethattheevidenceofPrinz’argumentsformoralrelativismthatdependsonthe theoryofsubjectivitythatoneadopts.And Ithinkthathisevidencebecomeslessevidentifwe considerhowheaccountsforthe‘subjective’natureofhumancareandconcerns:‘Emotions,asI haveargued,representconcerns.Concernsareorganismenvironmentrelationsthatbearonwell being’(85).Ourconcernsareconstitutedbythetwo basic reference points that make up Prinz’ empiricalframework:biologyandempiricalenvironment.Thesearethesourcesofthefirmfacts that we need to refer to if we want to understand human values. The only problem is that the individual subject that Prinz cares so much about does not have much to say in this account, because he or she is characterized by what we know about the biology and the environment in whichthesubjectlives.Ourvaluesaresubjectiveandreal,butthenotionofsubjectivityremainsa somewhatfrozenobjectof‘angry’emotionalforcesthatreflectthemammalian‘altruistic’behavior thatisneverreallymoral,butanexpressionofageneticallyencodedseekingofpleasureandproper wellbeing in a specific environment. Thus, Prinz does not think that ‘concern is the most fundamental moral emotion; the emotions that figure in moral judgments express blame for the wrongdoer,notsympathyforthevictim’(98).Andthisbecause he iscertain that ‘there are two fundamental classes of otherdirected moral emotions (moral anger and moral disgust) and one derived class (moral contempt)’ (76). He supports such convictions on his empirical study of emotions,wherehumanemotionsareseenas‘naturalextensionsofbasicemotionsthatariseinthe contextsoftransgression[…]Rightsviolationsarethreatstopersons.Sexualmoresinvolvethreats tothenaturalorder.Rankviolationsarethreatstothenaturalorderofpersons’(idem).Therefore, when Prinz argues that he performs a descriptive analysis of normativity in contrast to the

229 ‘imperialisticambition’ofKant,Mill,andAristotlewhosenormativeagendaignoresthefactthat ‘everyrulehasitsownbioculturalhistory’(305),hecompletlyforgetsthathistheoryofbiocultural sentimentgroundsinauniversalandverynormativeclaim:thehumansubjectiscontrolledbybasic emotionsthattogether withfactualenvironmentalinput creates a human person whose concerns andcaresarejustvariations(metaemotionsandmetasentiments)ofamorefundamentalbiological urge(gutreactions)forhomeostaticwellbeing. If we go back to Prinz’ argument for the reduction of the phenomenological variety of human emotionstogutreactionsbasedon‘corerelationalthemes’that‘aredirectlyrelevanttoourneed andinterest’(2004:66;jf.pp.121note24),wecanseethathedoeseffectuateareduction,although heclaimsnotto.Prinztriestocamouflagethiscovertbiologicalreductionismbyarguingforthe limits of evolutionary ethics and the priority of the individual moral sentiment, but it seems somewhat crafty when he has a very clear idea of thebiologicaloriginofsuchsentiments.The subjectisfreetoactaccordingtoitsownindividualmorality,butthisfreedomisconstructedbyless freefeelingsaboutwhatitshouldcareabout.Onemightbetemptedtosaythattheindividualitythat Prinzarguesforisrootedinhisconvictionthateverysubjectisbiologicallywiredtocareprimarily forhisorhersownwellbeing. Now,Idisagreewiththisnaturalizedpictureofhumanfeelingsofconcernsandcare,becauseIfind his empirical account of subjectivity reductive with respect to what I consider the (f)actual subjectiveexperienceoffeelingsofcareandconcern.Tosaythathumancareandconcernoriginate inbasicmammalianaffectprograms(whichIagreedtointhelastchapter)doesnotevidentlylead to the conclusion that human values and human care and concern are restricted to the basic emotionalreactionsthatwefindinothermammals.Ifweusetheembodied(biological)natureof ouremotionalexperiencetodisqualifythesubjectivenatureofsuchexperiences,thenwelosewhat makestheseexperiencesparticularlyhuman 67 . IsimplythinkthatPrinzmissessomethingfundamentalinhis‘compatibilist’attempttoaccount forthebiologicalandculturalconstitutionofhumansubjectivity.Humannatureisnotconstituted by nature and culture,but is aperson who is embedded in both nature and culture. To deduce humanvaluesfromaconceptualanalysisofbiologicalandculturalnormsistoleavethesubjectout ofthepicture.Ifeveryonecouldremainwithintheirownisolatedsystemofvalues,wewouldnot 67 Goldie points to the same problematic reduction if his otherwise favorable review of Prinz’ book on emotions: ‘Whatever one’s view of the expressive properties of music, it does seem a distortion of our notion of what makes sadnessappropriatetosaythatweare‘inerror’whenwefeelsadlisteningtoBeethoven’slatestringquartets.Thisis justanexampleofthekindsofdifficultiesfacedbyaccountsthatreducetheappropriatenessofanemotionalexperience toitsbeinginaccordwithwhatweare‘setup’ordesignedfor(Goldie2006:457).

230 needanethicaltheory,oranideaofpersonhoodforthatsake.Apartfrommypersonaldoubtthat anyoneactuallylikestobeeatenormutilated“willingly”,thenthefactremainsthatsubjectscares aboutbeingapersonwhocaresaboutotherpersons,althoughthesedonotsharethesamevalues. Justbecausemoralrelativismisalogicalpossibilityconsideringsomeaccountsofthebiological constitutionandculturaldiversityofhumanbeings,thisdoesnotmakesuchatheoryeithermore true(descriptively)orattractive(normatively).AsBlackburnwrites:‘Animmature,unimaginative, unsympathetic, anduncultivatedethicmightbequite coherent, in the way that the Decalogue is quite coherent. But the people who embody the attitudes it commends will not be particularly admirable’(1998:310).Anattempttonaturalizepersonhoodcannotfallforthefunctionalistor relativist temptation, if it wants to account for the fact that the subject cares about being an individualperson and apersonwholivestogetherwithpersonswithdifferentvalues. Iwillnowconcludewithashortoutlineofmybasicargumentsandamodestsuggestiontowecan naturalizehumanpersonhoodwithoutlosingthecomplexrelationbetweensubjectivityandethics. Conclusion: Naturally the Subject is a Person It might appear somewhat unorthodox to use Ricoeur in relation to the question of naturalizing personhood.Ithink,however,thatRicoeur’stheoryofsubjectivityhassomethingimportanttosay abouttheprocessofnaturalization.Inparticular,theirreduciblerelationbetweensubjectivityand ethics that was emphasized in my reformulation of his theory is relevant for the contemporary debateaboutthenaturalstatusofthehumansubject.Ibelievethatitisso,becausenaturalization oftenseemstowanttogetridofthesubjectorreduceethicstosomethingthatitisnot.Ricoeur analysesshowthattherealityofhumanvaluesismultilayered andconstitutedbyheterogeneous aspectsofhumanlifesuchasself,body,historicity,world,practices,andtheothersubject.Ibelieve thatthistheoreticcoreofhistheoryisfirstfullydisclosedinareformulationthatfocusesonthe complexnotionofsubjectivity.Ihavemuchconfidenceintheimportanceofthepeculiarnatureof subjectiveexperience.Iamconvincedthatourconceptionofnatureand,consequently,ofethicsis incomplete if we do not clarify the experiential dimension of the nature in and through which human beings live. At the same time, Ricoeur’s analyses are precious because of the strong emphasis on the alterity in human experience and being. The notion of subjectivity becomes incomprehensiblewithoutanexaminationofthatwhichisnottheself:body,world,other. In this part I have tried to clarify my basic argument for the irreducible relation between subjectivityandethicsbyshowingthatanaturalizationofethicsnecessarilyinvolvesthequestion

231 ofhumansubjectivity,ifitisnottodistortthenotionofhumanvalues.Andparttwoarguedthatthe question of subjectivity cannot be separated from the notion of personhood, because the human subjectischaracterizedbyfeelingsthatrevealabasiccareforbeingapersonamongotherpersons. Ihavethusarguedthatthenotionsofsubjectivity,ethics,andpersonhoodareirreduciblyrelatedto oneanother.Wecannotunderstandoneoftheconceptsinisolationfromtheothertwo.Thisisdue totheparticularontologicalstatusofthehumansubject. Inordertounderstandsubjectiveexperienceandaction,wehavetoformulateanontologyofcare thatrespectsthefragilityofhumanexistenceinaworldthatdoesnotcareaboutthefactthatthe subjectcaresabouttheworldandotherpersons.Humanexperienceisaffectedbythisfragilityis thesensethatthesubjectexperiencestheworldandtheotherpersonsasbothdifferentfromand,at thesametime,partofitsownbeing.Thecareofthesubjectivepersonaffectstheexperienceofthat person.Subjectiveexperienceoftheworldisnotanindifferentregistrationofthings,events,and persons,butconfiguredbytheheterogeneousvaluesthatthesubjectharborsintheinteractionwith theexperiencedthings,events,andpersons.Thisinteractiveconfigurationofsubjectiveexperience iswhatIhavetriedtocapturewiththenotionofthepracticalspaceofreason.Humanexperienceis primarily practical and enveloped in the affective dimension of these practices. Care, interest, concern,desire,fear,insecurity,panic,joy,hopelessness,absurdity,love,hate,hope,andsoforth areallaffectiveexperiencesthatariseinthisinteractionbetweentheselfandthatwhichisnotthe self(world,body,otherperson). Thisrelationbetweenselfhoodand alterity inhumansubjectivityisthecoreoftheframeworkthat IhaveconstructedbymyreformulationofRicoeur’stheoryofsubjectivity.Ricoeur’stheoryisa lifelongdevelopmentofthisrelationbetweenthevoluntaryandinvoluntaryaspectsofthehuman subjectintermsofspontaneityandreceptivity,reasonandbody,presenceanddistance,immediacy andhistoricity,selfandother.Thefragileaffectivityintheheartofthesubjectischaracterizedby thisstructuralnoncoincidenceinthebeingofthesubject.Thesubjectdoesnotexistbutinthat whichisnotself,andsubjectiveexistenceisaconstantaffirmationofselfhoodthroughthisalterity. Selfhood,however,cannotbeaffirmedinthebareexistenceoftheself,butneedsthepresenceof othersubjects,otherselves,thatrecognizethepersonhoodoftheself.Thisisduetothefactthatthe world of the subject is constituted by the coexistence with other subjects. The alterity that the subjectencountersintheheartofitsbeingisthereforeprimarilyconstitutedbythe active alterityof otherselves.Whenthesubjectaffirmsitselfinthealterityofitsexistence,itdoessothroughthe presence of other subjects who experience, evaluate,andsuffertheseactions.Theactionsofthe

232 subject express the personhood that the subjects care about, because these actions inscribe themselvesinacommonworldsharedtogetherwithotherpersons,ahumanworld. We cannot abstract from this humanity without losing sight of what makes the subject human. Humanthoughts,words,actions,andpracticesareallcharacterizedbythepersonalqualification thatdifferentiatesthesefromnonhumanactionsandmereanonymouseventsofimpersonalnature. The normative dimension of subjectivity is rooted in this particular nature of the subject. The subjectisapersonbythesimplefactthatitexists,andyetthisfactisaquestionofhowthesubject relatesitselftothefactthatitisapersonwhodependsontherecognitionofotherpersons.Thus, Ricoeursaysthattobeapersonisatask.Thesubjectcaresaboutbeinga(certain)person,andthis caremakesthesubjectsee‘itselfasanother’,becausepersonhoodisprimarilyconstitutedbythe presenceofotherpersons. Therearehowevermoretothebeingofthesubjectthanselfandthealterityotherpersons.The subjectisembeddedinandconstitutedbythealterityofthenaturalworldwhoselawsandrulesdo notrespectpersonhoodorhumanvalues.Wecannotunderstandthebeingofthesubjectwithout consideringthisaspectofhumannature.Weexperiencethisalterityindifferentdegrees,through our embodiment (perspective, physical constitution, limited actions) and through the absolute passivityinfrontofcosmologicaltimeandeventuallydeath.Weareborn,weage,andwedie. The reformulation of Ricoeur stressed these two fundamental aspects of human experience of alterity.Wearepersons and biologicalbeings.Humansubjectsareconstitutedbytheimpersonal workingsofthenaturalworld and bythepersonalnatureofhumanity.ThisiswhatIhavearguefor inthisdissertationbyexaminingtheethicalandbiologicalbeingofsubjectivity.Ricoeur’stheory remains the theoretical framework for my further analyses, although I have developed his argumentsindirectionsthatmightseemdistantfromhis.This,however,isoneofthevirtuesofhis theory.Hisargumentsandconclusionsremainopenstructuredwithoutbeingsuperficial.Heisclear aboutwhathethinks,buthisanalysesinvitetofurtherreflection.Ihavedonesobyexaminingthe natural relationbetweensubjectivityandethics. Ihavespentmuchtimeonarguingforthenaturalstatusofhumanvalues.Humanexperienceis affective experience. We experience the world as qualified by our feelings. And these feelings revealthevaluesbywhichweexperience,think,andact.ThisiswhyIhaveinsistedthatsubjective experienceisconfiguredasapracticalspaceofreasonthatisstructuredbyheterogeneousvalues generated and refined by the world, other, and the self. Human values cannot be examined in isolationfromthesubjectiveexperienceofsuchvalues.Thenaturalstatusofhumanvaluesdoesnot

233 suffer from this subjective aspect of their constitution, because this subjectivity is not a disqualificationoftheirstatusasbeingpartofnature.Humanvaluesarenaturalfactsabouthuman naturejustastheconstitutionofhumanbones,railroads,andcellphones.Theymaybemorefragile anddifficulttohandle,buttheirexistenceisfactualinthesensethattheyaffecttheworldandthe beingsinthatworldinaveryconcretemanner.Ourexperienceofvaluesplaysanactiveroleinthe constitutionoftheworldinwhichweandothercreatureslive.Therefore,todisregardorabstract fromthisexperienceofvaluesistotransformthevaluesthatweallwanttounderstand. ThiswasthecentralpointinmycritiqueofbothneuroethicsandPrinz’versionofmoralrelativism. Intheirattempttomakeethicalvalueslessdifficulttohandle,theymadethemintowhattheyare not,functionalandstronglyrelativistic.Neuroethicsneglectedthefactthathumanpersonsaremore thanthesocietyinwhichtheylive.Humanpersonsareindividualswithalltheblessingsandthe problemsthatthisimplies.Prinzcompletelymissestheotherfactthatindividualsubjectarealso persons. The subject’s values express more than the individual nature of the subject (desires, preferences,inclinations,upbringingetc.).Valuesexpressthehumanityinwhichthissubjectexists as a person among other persons. The subject cares about being more than an individual, or as Strawsonputsit,weareindividualsbecausewearepartofthecommonrootsofhumanpersonhood. Theindividualdifferencesofhumanvaluesareonlypossibleonacommonagreementofwhatitis tobeahumanperson.Valuesvaryfrompersontoperson,andevenmoredrasticallyfromcultureto culture, but they are still human values that characterize human behavior (i.e. care, love, hate, interest, and concerns). The job of a descriptive ethical theory is not to make the different expressionsofthevaluesincomprehensibletooneanother,buttomakethesecapableofinteracting inwaysthatdonotcompromisethecoexistenceofthehumanpersonswhohavedifferentvalues. This is what I mean by the natural existence of moral values. And an understanding of human natureisimpairedifitdonotrespectthatthefactual existence of moral attitudes, feelings, and behaviorisirreducibletoanythingotherthanmoralvalues.AsIrisMurdochwrites:‘Theauthority ofmoralsistheauthorityoftruth,thatisofreality.Wecanseethelength,theextension,ofthese conceptsaspatientattentiontransformsaccuracywithoutintervalintojustdiscernment.Heretoo wecanseeitasnaturaltotheparticularkindofcreaturesthatwearethatloveshouldbeinseparable fromjustice,andclearvisionfromrespectforthereal’(Murdoch1967:901). Therefore,Iconsiderhumanvaluestobebothpersonalandbiological,andanaturalpartofhuman nature.Theprocessofnaturalizationisnotathreattoneitherpersonhoodnorethicsifthenatural relationofsubjectivityandethicsistakenintoaccount.Thefactthathumanbeinglivebyvalues

234 that depend upon the subjective nature of those beings must give the notion of subjectivity a legitimateclaimonbeingpartoftheprocessofnaturalizinghumanpersonhood.Ontheotherhand, subjectivityandethicscannotexcludethemselvesfromthisprocessbyassertingthe‘unscientific’ natureofthehumanperson.Myclaimthathumanvalues are natural implies that the empirical sciencescanclarifyimportantaspectsoftheembodiednatureofhumanpersonhood. Therelationbetweensubjectivityandethics emphasizesthenecessityofatheorythatdoesnot exclude,butemphasizeapatientinterdisciplinaryapproachtohumannaturethatacceptsthemany layersofourconceptionofwhatisrealandnatural.

235 References

TheabbreviationsusedforRicoeur’sworks Books CR : The Course of Recognition . Trans. D. Pellauer. Cambridge, Mass.: Havard University Press 2005; Parcours de la reconnaissance. Trois études .Paris:ÉditionsStock2004.

FM : Fallible Man: Philosophy of Will .Trans.C.A.Kelbley.NewYork:FordhamUniversityPress1987; Philosophie de la volonté II. L’homme faillible .Paris:Aubier1960.

FN : Freedom and Nature. The Voluntary and the Involuntary . Trans. E. V. Kohák. Evanston, III: Northwestern University Press 1966; Philosophie de la volonté I. Le volontaire et l’involontaire . Paris: Aubier1950.

FP : Freud and Philosophy: Essay on Interpretation .Trans.D.Savage.NewHaven:YaleUniversityPress 1977; De Interpretation. Essay sur Freud .Paris:ÉditionduSeuil1965.

OSA : Oneself as Another .Trans.K.Blamey.Chicago:UniversityofChicagoPress1992; Soi-même comme un autre .Paris:ÉditionduSeuil1990.

SE : The Symbolism of Evil .Trans.E.Buchanan.NewYork:BeaconPress1969;Philosophie de la volonté II. Symbolique du mal .Paris:Aubier1960. TN3 : Time and Narrative, III .Trans.K.BlameyandD.Pellauer.Chicago:University of Chicago Press 1988; Temps et Récit, t. 3 .Paris:ÉditionduSeuil1991(1thed.1985). WT: (with JeanPierre Changeux) What Makes Us Think? Trans. M. B. DeBevoise. Princeton: Princeton UniversityPress2000; Ce qui nous fait penser. La nature et la regle .Paris:ÉditionsOdileJacob2000(1th ed.1998).

Articles APH : Husserl’s Ideas II: Analyses and Problems. In P. Ricoeur: Husserl. An Analysis of His Phenomenology .Trans.E.G.BallardandL.E.Embree(3581).Evanton,Illinois:NorthwesternUniversity Press 2007; Analyses et problèmes des Ideen II de Husserl (1952). In P. Ricoeur: A l’école de la Phénoménologie (87140).Paris:Vrin1986.

EH : Exisitence and Hermeneutics. Trans. K. McLaughlin (324). In P. Ricoeur: The Conflict of Interpretations , ed. Don Ihde. New York: Continum 2004; Existence et Hérméneutique (1965). In Paul Ricoeur: Conflit des l’interprétations (728).Paris:ÉditionduSeuil1969.

IDA : L’imagination dans discours et dans l’action. In P. Ricoeur: Du texte à l’action. Essais d’herméneutique II (237262).Paris:ÉditionduSeuil1986.

KH :KantandHusserl.InP.Ricoeur: Husserl. An Analysis of His Phenomenology .Trans.E.G.Ballardand L.E.Embree(175201).Evanton,Illinois:NorthwesternUniversityPress2007;KantetHusserl(1955).In P.Ricoeur: A l’école de la Phénoménologie (227250).Paris:Vrin1986.

LS: LeSentiment(1959).InP.Ricoeur: A l’école de la Phénoménologie (251265).Paris:Vrin1986.

236 MT: Themodelofthetext:meaningfulactionconsideredasatext.InPaulRicoeur: Hermeneutics and the human sciences ,ed.J.B.Thompson(197221).NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress1981;Lemodèledu texte: l’action sensée considérée comme un texte (1971). In P. Ricoeur: Du texte à l’action. Essais d’herméneutique II (205236).Paris:ÉditionduSeuil1986.

NPH : Narrativité, Phénoménologie et Herméneutique (1989). In André Jacob (ed.): Encyclopédie Philosophie Universelle I: L’univers philosophique (6371).Paris:PUF1989.

NA :NegativityandPrimaryAffirmation.InP.Ricoeur: History and Truth (305328).Trans.Ch.A.Kelbley. Evanton, Illinois: Northwestern University Press 2007; Négativité et affirmation originaire (1956). In P. Ricoeur: Histoire etVerité(378405).Paris:ÉditionduSeuil1967.

PD : The Problem of Double Meaning as Hermeneutic Problem and as Semantic Problem. Trans. K. McLaughlin.InP.Ricoeur: The Conflict of Interpretations ,ed.D.Ihde(6176).NewYork:Continum2004; Leproblèmedudoublesenscommeproblèmeherméneutiqueetcommeproblèmesémantique(1966).InP. Ricoeur: Conflit des l’interprétations (6479).Paris:ÉditionduSeuil1969.

PH :PhenomenologyandHermeneutics.Trans.J.B.Thompson.InP.Ricoeur: Hermeneutics and the human sciences ,ed.J.B.Thompson(101128).NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress1981;Phénomenologieet hermémenutique(1975).InP.Ricoeur: Du texte à l’action. Essais d’hermeneutique II (4381).Paris:Édition duSeuil1986.

PW:MethodsandTasksofaPhenomenologyoftheWill.In Husserl. An Analysis of His Phenomenology . Trans.E.G.BallardandL.E.Embree(213233).Evanton,Illinois:NorthwesternUniversityPress2007; Méthode et tâche d’une phénoménologie de la volonté (1951). In Paul Ricœur: A l’école de la Phénoménologie (5986).Paris:Vrin1986.

QS :TheQuestionoftheSubject:TheChallengeofSemiology.Trans.K.McLaughlin.In The Conflict of Interpretations (23262). Ed. D. Ihde. New York: Continum 2004; La question du sujet: le défi de la sémiologie.InPaulRicoeur: Conflit des l’interprétations (pp.23362).Paris:ÉditionduSeuil1969.

SP :SurlaPhénoménologie(1953).InP.Ricoeur: A l’école de la Phénoménologie (266283).Paris:Vrin 1986.

SR :Sympathieetrespect(1954).InP.Ricoeur: A l’école de la Phénoménologie (141159).Paris:Vrin1986.

TFA :TrueandFalseAnguish.In History and Truth .Trans.Ch.A.Kelbley(287304).Evanton,Illinois: NorthwesternUniversityPress2007;Vraietfausseangoisse(1953).InP.Ricoeur: Histoire et Verité (357 377).Paris:ÉditionduSeuil1967. Otherreferences

Agamben,G.(1998/1995). Homo Sacer. Sovereign Power and Bare Life .Trans.D.HellerRoazen.Stanford, CA:StanfordUniversityPress; Homo sacer. Il potere sovrano e la nuda vita .Torino:Einaudi. Agamben, G. (2004/2002). The Open. Man and Animal . Trans. Kevin Attell. Stanford, CA: Stanford UniversityPress;L’aperto. L’uomo e l’animale .Torino:BollatiBoringhieri. Agamben,G.(2007). Il Regno e la Gloria. Per una genealogia teologica dell’economia e del governo. Homo sacer, II, 2 .Vicenza:NeriPozzaEditore.

237 Aristotle (1984). Nichomachean Ethics. Trans. W. D. Ross (rev. J. O. Urmson). In J. Barnes (ed.): The Complete Works of Aristotle. The Revised Oxford Translation .Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress. Barry,B.(2005). Why Social Justice Matters .Cambridge:PolityPress. Bear, Connors and Paradiso (2006). Neuroscience: Exploring The Brain. Third Edition . Baltimore: LippincottWilliams&Wilkins. Beedie, C. J., Terry P. C, Lane A. M. (2005). Distinctions between emotion and mood. Cognition and Emotion vol.19 , no.6:847878. Berlucchi,G.(2007).Themythoftheclonablehumanbrain.InDellaSala,S.(ed.): Tall Tales about the Mind and Brain. Separating fact from fiction (336347).Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. Blackburn, S. (2006). Must We Weep for Sentimentalism? In J. Dreier (ed.): Contemporary Debates in Moral Theory (144159).Oxford:BlackwellPublishing. Blackburn,S.(2004). Lust .Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. Blackburn,S.(1999). Think . A compelling introduction to philosophy .Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. Blackburn,S.(1998). Ruling Passion. A Theory of Practical Reasoning .Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. Blackburn,S.(1995).PracticalTortoiseRaising. Mind, NewSeries,vol.104,no.416:695711. Blackburn,S.(1988).HowToBeanEthicalAntiRealist.InS.Blackburn: Essays in Quasi-Realism .(166 181)Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress1993. Blackburn, S. (1987). Morals and Modals. In S. Blackburn: Essays in Quasi-Realism . (5274) Oxford: OxfordUniversityPress1993. Blackburn,S.(1985).ErrorsandthePhenomenologyofValue.InS.Blackburn: Essays in Quasi-Realism . (149165)Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress1993. Blackburn, S. (1984). Spreading the Word . Groundings in the Philosophy of Language . Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress. Brezzi,F.(2006). Introduzione a Ricoeur .RomaBari:EditoriLaterza. Cannon,W.B.(1927).TheJamesLangeTheoryofEmotions: A critical examination and an alternative theory. The American Journal of Psychology ,vol.39:106124. Casebeer, W. D. (2003a). Natural Ethical Facts: Evolution, Connectionism, and Moral Cognition . Cambridge,Mass.:TheMITPress. Casebeer,W.D.(2003b).Moralcognitionanditsneuralconstituents. Nature Reviews Neuroscience ,vol.4: 840047. Casebeer, W. D (2004). Knowing Evil When You See It: Uses for the Rhetoric of Evilin International Relations. International Relations ,vol.18,no.4:441451. Churchland, P. (2006): Moral decisionmaking and the brain. In J. Illes (ed.): Neuroethics: Defining the issues in theory, practice, and policy (316).NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress.

238 Crane,T.(1998).IntentionalityastheMarkoftheMental.InA.O’Hear(ed.): Current Issues in Philosophy of Mind (22951).Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress. Christiansen,Lars(1980). Naturfilosofi. Et essay om de tavse humaniora .Købehavn:G.E.C.Gadsforlag. Damasio,A.R.(2004).EmotionsandFeelings:ANeurobiologicalPerspective.InA.S.R.Manstead,N. Frijda, A. Fischer (eds.): Feelings and Emotions. The Amsterdam Symposium (4957). Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress. Damasio,A.R.(2003). Looking for Spinoza. Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain .NewYork:Harcourt. Damasio, A. R. (2000). A Second Chance for Emotion. In R. Lane and L. Nadel (eds.): Cognitive Neuroscience of Emotions .Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. Damasio,A.R.(1999). The Feeling of What happens. Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness . NewYork:Harcourt. Damasio,A.(1994). Descartes’ Error . Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain .NewYork:Putnam. Dennett,D.C.(1991).LovelyandSuspectQualities. Philosophical Issues ,vol.1,Consciousness:3743. Dennett,D.C.(2003).FreedomEvolves.NewYork:Putnam. deSousa,R.(1987). The Rationality of Emotions .Cambridge,Mass.:MITPress. deSousa,R.(2005).TheArtofthePossibleinLifeandLiterature.InM.E.ReicherandJ.C.Marek(eds.): Experience and Analysis (347356).KirchbergamWechsel,Wien:öbv&hpt. deSousa,R.(2007a). Why Think? Evolution and the Rational Mind .Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. deSousa,R.(2007b).Truth,Authenticity,andRationality. dialectica ,vol.61,no.3:323345. Edelman,G.M.(2003).NaturalizingConsciousness:ATheoreticalFramework. Proceedings of the National Acadamy of Sciences of the United States of America,vol.100,no.9:55205524. Ekman,P.(1992).AnArgumentforBasicEmotions. Cognition and Emotion ,vol.6,no.34:169200. Ekman, P. (2003). Emotions Revealed: Understanding Faces and Feelings. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson. Farah, M. J. and Heberlein, A. S. (2007). Personhood and Neuroscience: Naturalizing or Nihilating? American Journal of Bioethics ,vol.7,no.1:3748. Farah,M.J.(2005).Neuroethics:thepracticalandthephilosophical. TRENDS in Cognitive Sciences ,vol.9, no.1:3440. Faulkner,W.(1996/1935). As I Lay Dying .London:Vintage(RandomHouse). Fink,H.(2006).ThreeSortsofNaturalism. European Journal of Philosophy ,vol.14,no.2:202221. Franfurt,H.G.(1971).FreedomoftheWillandtheConceptofaPerson. Journal of Philosophy vol.68,no. 1:520.

239 Fuchs,T.(2000). Leib, Raum, Person. Entwurf einer phänomenologischen Anthropologie .Stuttgart:Klett Cotta. Fuch, T. (2002a). Melancholie als Desynchronisierung. Ein Beitrag zur Psychopathologie der intersubjektiven Zeit. In T. Fuchs, Zeit-Diagnosen. Philosophisch-Psychiatrische Essays (111134). Kusterdingen:DieGraueEdition. Fuchs,T.(2002b).Maske,Selbst,Selbsentfremdung.ZurAnthropologieundPsychopathologiederPerson. In T. Fuchs, Zeit-Diagnosen. Philosophisch-Psychiatrische Essays (135163). Kusterdingen: Die Graue Edition. Gallagher,S.andMarcelA.J.(1999).TheSelfinContextualizedAction. Journal of Consciousness Studies vol.6,no4:430. Gallagher,S.andZahavi,D.(2008). The phenomenological Mind: An Introduction to Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science .London:Routledge. Gallese, V. (2003). The Roots of Empathy: The Shared Manifold Hypothesis and the Neural Basis of Intentionality. Psychopathology ,vol.36:171180. Gallese,V. (2006). Intentional Attunement: A neurophysiological perspective on social cognition andits disruptioninautism. Brain Research ,vol.1079:1524. Gallese,V.(2007).Embodiedsimulation:frommirrorneuronsystemstointerpersonalrelations. Novertis Foundation Symposium ,vol.278:319. Gallese,V.andUmiltà,M.A.(2006).CognitiveContinuityinPrimateSocialCognition. Biological Theory , no.1,vol.1:2530. Gazzaniga, M. S. (2006a). The Ethical Brain. The Science of Our Moral Dilemmas . New York: Harper CollinsPublishers. Gazzaniga, M. S. (2006b). Facts, fictions, and the future of neuroethics. In J. Illes (ed.): Neuroethics: Defining the issues in theory, practice, and policy(141148).NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress. Goldie,P.(2000a). The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration .Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. Goldie,P.(2000b).ExplainingExpressionsofEmotion. Mind ,NewSeries,vol.109,no.433:2538. Goldie,P.(2002a).Emotion,PersonalityandSimulation.InP.Goldie(ed.): Understanding Emotions: Mind and Morals (97109).Aldershot:AshgatePublishing. Goldie,P.(2002b).Emotions,feelingsandintentionality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences ,vol.1: 235254. Goldie,P.(2003a).One’sRememberedPast:NarrativeThinking,Emotion,andtheExternalPerspective. Philosophical Papers ,vol.32,no.3:301319. Goldie,P.(2003b).Narrative,Emotion,andPerspective.InM.KieranandD.Lopes(eds.): Imagination and the Arts (5468).London:Routledge.

240 Goldie,P.(2003c).Narrativeandperspective:ValuesandappropriateEmotions.InA.Hatzimoysis(ed.): Philosophy and the Emotions (201220), Royale Institute of Philosophy Supplements Series. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress. Goldie,P.(2004). On Personality .London:Routledge. Goldie,P.(2005).ImaginationandtheDistortingPowerofEmotion. Journal of Consciousness Studies ,vol. 12,no.810:12739. Goldie,P.(2006). Review of Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotions by J. Prinz. Mind,vol.115: 453457. Goldie, P. (2007). There are Reasons and Reasons. In D. Hutto and M. J. Ratcliffe: Folk Psychology Reassessed (103114).DordrechtNetherlands:KluwerAcademicPress. Goldman, A.I. and Sripada, C. S. (2005). Simulationist models of facedbased emotion recognition. Cognition ,vol.94:193213. Greene,J.(2003).Fromneural“is”tomoral“ought”:whatarethemoralimplicationsofneuroscientific moralpsychology? Nature Reviews Neuroscience ,vol.4:847850. Greisch,J.(2000). Le Cogito herméneutique. L’herméneutique philosophique et l’héritage cartésien .Paris: LibrairephilosophiqueJ.Vrin. Greisch,J.(2001). Paul Ricoeur. L’itinérance du sens .Grenoble:J.Milton. Grøn,A.(2004a).TheEmbodiedSelf:ReformulatingtheExistentialDifferenceinKierkegaard. Journal of Consciousness Studies ,vol.11,no.1011:2643. Grøn,A.(2004b).SelfandIdentity.InD.Zahavi,T.Grünbaum,J.Parnas:The Structure and Development of Self-Consciousness . Interdisciplinary perspectives (123156). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins PublishingCompany. Heidegger, M. (1990/1998). Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics . Trans. R. Taft. Indiana: Indiana UniversityPress; Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik .FrankfurtamMain:VittorioKlostermann. Heidegger,M.(1996/1993). Being and Time .Trans.J.Stambaugh.Albany,NY:StateUniversityOfNew York; Sein und Zeit .Tübingen:MaxNiemeyerVerlag. Hume, D. (1751/1975). Enquiries concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals .Oxford:ClarendonPress. Hume,D.(1739/1978). A Treatise of Human Nature .Oxford:ClarendonPress. Jacobs, J. (2002). Dimensions of Moral Theory. An Introduction to Metaethics and Moral Psychology . Oxford:Blackwell. James,W.(1884).WhatisanEmotion? Mind ,vol.9,no.34:188205. Jervolino,D.(1993). Il cogito e l’ermeneutica. La questione del soggetto in Ricoeur .Genova:Marietti. Jervolino,D.(1995). L’amore difficile .Roma:Studium.

241 Kant, I. (1996/1914). The Metaphysics of Morals . Trans. M. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Die Metaphysik der Sitten .ImmanuelKantsSchriften.AusgabederkönglichPreussischenAkademie derWissenschaften,band6.Berlin:W.deGruyter. Kant, I. (1996/1914). The Metaphysics of Morals . Trans. M. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Die Metaphysik der Sitten .ImmanuelKantsSchriften.AusgabederkönglichPreussischenAkademie derWissenschaften,band6.Berlin:W.deGruyter. Kant, I. (1997/1904). Critique of Pure Reason .Trans.PGuyer.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress; Kritik der reinen Vernunft .ImmanuelKantsSchriften.AusgabederkönglichPreussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften,band3.Berlin:W.deGruyter. Kant,I.(1998a/1903).Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals .Trans.PGuyer.Cambridge:Cambridge UniversityPress;Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten .ImmanuelKantsSchriften.Ausgabederkönglich PreussischenAkademiederWissenschaften,band4.Berlin:W.deGruyter. Kant,I.(1998b/1908). Critique of Practical Reason .Trans.M.Gregor.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press; Kritik der praktischen Vernunft . Immanuel Kants Schriften. Ausgabe der könglich Preussischen AkademiederWissenschaften,band5.Berlin:W.deGruyter. Kant, I. (2006/1917). Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View . Trans. R. B. Louden. Cambridge University Press; Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht . Immanuel Kants Schriften. Ausgabe der könglichPreussischenAkademiederWissenschaften,band7.Berlin:W.deGruyter. Kenny,A.(1963). Action, Emotion and Will .London:Routledge. Kennedy, D. (2002). Are There Things We’d Rather Not Know? In Marcus, S. J. (ed.): Neuroethics: Mapping the Field (196206).NewYork:DanaFoundation. Kierkegaard,S.(1983/1920). The Sickness unto Death .Trans.H.V.HongandE.H.Hong.Princeton,NJ: Princeton University Press; Sygdommen til Døden . SørenKierkegaards Samlede Værker, Anden Udgave, bind11.København:GyldendalskeBoghandel. Korsgaard,C.M.(1996). The Sources of Normativity .Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress. LeDoux, J. (1996). The Emotional Brain: The Mysterious Underpinnings of Emotional life . New York: SimonandSchuster. Legrand, D. (2007). Naturalizing the Acting Self: Subjective vs. Anonymous Agency. Philosophical Psychology ,vol.20,no.4:457478. Levy,N.(2007). Neuroethics . Challenges for the 21 st Century .Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress. Mackie,J.L.(1977). Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong .Harmondsworth,Middx.:PenguinBooks. Marcus,S.J.(ed.)(2002). Neuroethics: Mapping the Field .NewYork:DanaFoundation. McDowell,J.(1997).ProjectionandTruthinEthics.InJ.McDowell: Mind, Value, and Reality (151166). Cambridge,Mass.:HarvardUniversityPress. Metzinger,Th.(2005).UnterwegszueinemneuenMenschenbild. Gehirn&Geist ,no.11. Mongin,O.(1994). Paul Ricoeur .Paris:ÉditionduSeuil.

242 Moore,G.E.(1903). Principia Ethica .Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress. Murdoch,I.(1967):TheSovereigntyofGoodoverOtherConcepts.InI.Murdoch: The Sovereignty of Good (77104).London:Routledge1970. Nagel,T.(1986). The View from Nowhere .NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress. Nietzsche, F. (1986/1954a). Human, all too human . Trans. R.J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress; Menschliches, Allzumenschliches .WerkeindreiBänden.Hrsg.vonKarlSchlechta,Band 1.Münschen:CarlHanserVerlag. Nietzsche,F.(2007/1954b).The Dawn .Trans.J.M.Kennedy.NewYork:DoverPublications;Morgenröte . WerkeindreiBänden.Hrsg.vonKarlSchlechta,Band1.Münschen:CarlHanserVerlag. Nussbaum,M.(2001). Upheavals of Thought .Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress. Overgaard, S. (2007). Wittgenstein and Other Minds. Rethinking subjectivity and intersubjectivity with Wittgenstein, Levinas, and Husserl .London:Routledge. Orwell,G.(1989/1949): Nineteen Eighty-Four .London:PenguinBooks. Panksepp, J. (1991). Affective Neuroscience: A conceptual framework for the neurobiological study of emotions.InK.Strongman(ed.): International Reviews of Emotional Research (5999).Chichester:Wiley. Panksepp, J. (1998). Affective Neuroscience: The Foundations of Human and Animal Emotions . Oxford: OxfordUniversityPress. Panksepp,J.(2001).OntheSubcorticalSourcesofBasicHumanEmotionsandthePrimacyofEmotional Affective ActionPerception Processes in Human Consciousness. Evolution and Cognition , vol. 7, No. 2: 134140. Panksepp,J.(2003).Attheinterfaceoftheaffective,behavioural,andcognitiveneuroscience:Decodingthe emotionalfeelingsofthebrain. Brain and Cognition ,vol.52:414. Panksepp,J.(2004a).AffectiveConsciousnessandtheOriginsofHumanMind:ACriticalRoleofBrain ResearchonAnimalEmotions. Impuls ,no.3:4760. Panksepp,J. (2004b). Basic Affects and the InstinctualSystemsoftheBrain. InA.S.R.Manstead,N. Frijda,A.Fischer(eds.): Feelings and Emotions. The Amsterdam Symposium ,eds.(175193).Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress. Panksepp,J.(2005a).Towardascienceofultimateconcern(GuestEditorial). Consciousness and Cognition , vol.14:2229. Panksepp, J. (2005b). Affective Consciousness: Core emotional feelings in animals and humans. Consciousness and Cognition ,vol.14:3080. Panksepp,J.(2005c).OntheEmbodiedNeuralNatureofCoreEmotionalAffects. Journal of Consciousness Studies ,vol.12,no.810:15884. Panksepp, J. (2006). Emotional endophenotypes in evolutionary psychiatry. Progress in Neuro- Psychopharmacology & Biological Psychiatry ,vol.30:774784.

243 Panksepp,J.(2007).Neuroevolutionarysourcesoflaughterandsocialjoy:Modellingprimalhumanlaughter inlaboratoryrats. Behavioural Brain Research ,vol.182:231244. Phelps,E.A.(2004).TheHumanAmygdalaandAwareness:InteractionsBetweenEmotionandCognition. InM.S.Gazzaniga(ed.): The Cognitive Neurosciences III (10051015).Cambridge:TheMITPress. Pinker,S.(1999). How The Mind Works .NewYork:PenguinBooks. Pinker,S.(2003). The Blank Slate. The Modern Denial of Human Nature .NewYork:PenguinBooks. Preuss,T.M.(2004).WhatisitliketobeaHuman?InM.S.Gazzaniga(ed.): The Cognitive Neurosciences III (519).Cambridge:TheMITPress. Prinz,J.J.(2002). Furnishing the Mind: Concepts and their Perceptual basis .Cambridge,MA:MITPress. Prinz,J.J.(2004). Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotion .NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress. Prinz,J.J.(2005).AreEmotionsFeelings?. Journal of Consciousness Studies 12 ,no.810:925. Prinz,J.J.(2007). The Emotional Construction of Morals .NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress. Ratcliffe,M.(2005).TheFeelingofBeing. Journal of Consciousness Studies 12 ,no.810:4360.

Reich,R.B.(2007). Supercapitalism. The Transformation of Business, Democracy, and Everyday Life .New York:AlfredA.Knoff. Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, L. and Gallese, V. (2001). Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the understandingandimitationofaction.NatureReviews,vol.2:661669. Rizzolatti,G.andSinigaglia,C.(2007). Mirrors in the Brain. How our Minds share Action, Emotions, and Experience .Trans.F.Anderson.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. Rochat,P.(2007).Intentionalactionarisesfromearlyreciprocalexchanges. Acta Psychologica ,vol.124,no. 1:825. Rosfort, R. and Stanghellini, G. (forthcoming). The Person in between Moods and Affects. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology . Roskies,A.(2002).NeuroethicsfortheNewMillinium. Neuron ,Vol.35:2123. Roskies,A.(2006):Acasestudyofneuroethics:thenatureofmoraljudgment.InJ.Illes(ed.): Neuroethics: Defining the issues in theory, practice, and policy(1732).NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress. Rudrauf,D.andDamasio,A.(2005).AConjectureRegardingtheBiologicalMechanismofSubjectivityand Feeling. Journal of Consciousness Studies vol.12 ,no.810:2642. Russell,B.(1960). An Outline of Philosophy.Cleveland:TheWorldPublishingCompany. Russell, J. A. (2005). Emotion in Human Consciousness Is Build on Core Affect. In Journal of Consciousness Studies vol.12,no.810:2642.

244 Russell,J.A.(2003).CoreaffectandthePsychologicalConstructionofEmotion. Psychological Review vol. 110,no . 1:145172. Ryle,G.(1949). The Concept of Mind .London:Hutchinson. Safire,W.(2002):VisionsforaNewFieldof“Neuroethics”.InMarcus,S.J.(ed.): Neuroethics: Mapping the Field (39).NewYork:DanaFoundation. Sartre,JeanPaul(1971/1939). Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions. Trans.PhilipMairet.London:Methuen &CoLtd; Esquisse d’une théorie des émotions .Paris:Hermann. Scheler, M. (1973/1912). Wesen und Formen der Sympathie . Max Scheler. Gesammelte Werke. Band 7. Bern:FranckeVerlag. Scheler, M. (1966/1916). Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die Materiale Wertethik . Max Scheler. GesammelteWerke.Band2.Bern:FranckeVerlag. Searle,T.(2000). Mind, Language and Society .London:Phoenix,OrionBooksLtd. Siemer,M.(2005). Moodsasmultipleobjectdirectedandasobjectlessaffectivestates:Anexaminationof thedispostionaltheoryofmoods. Cognition and Emotion vol.19,no.6:815845. Smith,Q.(1986). The Felt Meanings of the World. A Metaphysics of Feeling .Indiana:PurdueUniversity Press. Solomon,R.C.(1976). The Passions .NewYork:AnchorPress. Solomon,R.C.(1977).TheLogicofEmotion. Noûs ,vol.11,no.1:4149. Solomon,R.C.(2001).ThoughtsandFeelings:Whatisa“CognitiveTheory”oftheEmotions,andDoesIt NeglectAffectivity?InR.Solomon:NotPassionsSlave(178194).Oxford:OxforduniversityPress2003. Solomon,R.C.(2007). True to Our Feelings. What Our Emotions are really telling Us .NewYork:Oxford UniversityPress. Simpson,G.G.(1966).TheBiologicalNatureofMan. Science ,no.152:4728. Spinoza,B.(1955). The Ethics .Chiefworksvol.2.Trans.R.H.M.Elwes.NewYork:DoverPublications. Stanghellini,G.(1997). Antropologia della vulnerabilità .Milano:Feltrinelli. Stanghellini, G. (2004). Disembodied Spirits and Deanimated Bodies: The Psychopathology of Common Sense .Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. Stanghellini,G.(2006). Pscicopatologia del senso comune .Milano:RaffaelloCortinaEditore. Stanghellini,G.andBallerini,A.(1992). Ossessione e rivelazione. Riflessione sui rapporti tra ossessività e delirio .Torino:BollatiBoringhieri. Stocker,M.(1976).TheSchizophreniaofMoralEthicalTheories. The Journal of Philosophy,vol.73,no. 14:453466.

245 Stocker, M. (1983). Psychic Feelings: Their Importance and Irreducibility. Australasian Journal of Philosophy ,vol.61,no.1:526. Stocker,M.(1996),withHegeman,E. Valuing Emotions .Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress. Strasser,S.(1977/1956). Phenomenology of Feeling: An essay on the Phenomena of the Heart .Trans.R.E. Wood. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press; Das Gemüt: Grundgedanken zu einer Phänomenologische Philosophie und Theorie des Menschlichen Gefühlsleben .Freiburg:VerlagHerder. Strawson,G.(1999).TheSelfandtheSESMET. Journal of Consciousness Studies ,vol.6,no.4:99135. Strawson,G.(2004).AgainstNarrativity. Ratio (new series) ,vol.16,no.4:428452. Strawson,P.F.(1959). Individuals. An Essays in Descriptive Metaphysics .London:Methuen&Co.Ltd. Stawson,P.F.(1962).FreedomandResentment.InG. Watson (ed.): Free Will (5980). Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress1982. Strawson, P. F. (1966). The Bounds of Sense. An Essay on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason . London: Methuen&Co.Ltd. Taylor,C.(1977a).Selfinterpretinganimals.InC. Taylor: Human Agency and Language. Philosophical Papers 1 (4576).Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress1985. Taylor,C.(1977b).Whatishumanagency?InC.Taylor:Human Agency and Language. Philosophical Papers 1 (1544).Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress1985. Taylor, C.(1981).Theconcept of a person. In C. Taylor: Human Agency and Language. Philosophical Papers 1 (97114).Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress1985. Taylor,C.(1988).ReplytoSousaandDavis. Canadian Journal of Philosophy ,vol.18,no.3:449458. Taylor,C.(1989). Sources of the Self. The Making of Modern Identity .Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity. Teichert,D.(2004). Narrative,IdentityandtheSelf. Journal of Consciousness Studies ,vol.11,no.1011: 175191. Watson,J.D.andCrickF.H.(1953):MolecularStructureofNucleicAcids. Nature ,vol.171,no.4356:737 738. Wollheim,R.(1984). Thread of Life .Cambridge,Mass.:HavardUniversityPress. Wollheim,R.(1999). On the Emotions .NewHaven:YaleUniversityPress. Zahavi,D.(2005). Subjectivity and Selfhood. Investigation the First-Person Perspective .Cambridge,Mass.: TheMITPress. Zahavi,D.(2007).Killingthestrawman:Dennettandphenomenology. Phenomenology And The Cognitive Sciences ,vol.6,no.12:2143. Zoloth,L.(2006).Beingintheworld:Neuroscienceandtheethicalagent.In J.Illes(ed.): Neuroethics: Defining the issues in theory, practice, and policy(6173).NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress.

246 DissertationAbstract Subjectivity and Ethics. Ricoeur and the Question of Naturalizing Personhood

This dissertation argues for the irreducible relation between subjectivity and ethics. To deny subjectivityaplaceinethicsistomisunderstandthenatureofethicaltheoryandtoexcludeethics fromatheoryofsubjectivityistodisregardacriticalfeatureofsubjectiveexperience,namelythe questionofnormativity.Humanexperienceoftheworldisnormative.Wedonotexperiencethe worldasavaluefreespaceofindifferenteventsandmovements,butasmeaningfulsituationsand actionsthatinscribethemselvesinacommonworldofinterest,care,andvalueforthesubject.The human subject is characterized by what it cares about, and subjective experience is primarily structuredinaccordancewiththevaluesthatareexpressedinthebasicnotionofcare.Itherefore beginthedissertationbyperformingasystematicreformulationofRicoeur’stheoryofsubjectivein ordertoprovideaconceptualframeworkformyfurtheranalysesofsubjectivityandethics. Ethical experience is critical in the structure of subjective experience, since subjective values, albeit they origin in the self, are never restricted to the sole being of the individual subject. Subjective experience is constituted by selfhood and alterity. I do not experience the world or myselfascreationsofmywill.Thus,mybeingisaffectedbythepresenceofalterityinthesense thatselfhood,world,andtheotherareallactivepartsintheconstitutionofthevaluesbywhichI leadmylife.Icannotneglectthisalterityintheconstitutionofmybeing,sincemyexperienceis continuallyaffectedbythatwhichisnotme(mybirth,myfragmentaryperspective,myphysical body,time,space,andotherpersonswhoreacttomydoingandsaying). Further,subjectiveexperienceischaracterizedbyhowthesubjectinteractswiththeworldthatit experiences.Consciousexperienceisnotmereregistration,buttheresultoftherelationbetween activityandpassivity,actionandsuffering.Hence,Iarguethatsubjectiveexperienceisstructured as a practical space of reason according to a hierarchy of heterogeneous values generated and shaped by the interaction of the world, the other, and the self. We experience the world as a configurationofthings,events,andsituationsthatwecareabout. Subjectivityandethics isirreducibly related,becausethesubjectisapersonotherthan amere physicalbeing.Personhoodiswhatmakesthesubjectabeingwhocaresaboutmorethanitsown survivalandwellbeing,andIarguethatwecannotunderstandthenatureofsubjectivityinisolation frompersonhood.Thefactthathumansubjectscareabouttheworld,theother,andthemselvesis whatleadsmetoargueforanontologyof carethat is capable of explaining the complexity of humannature.Weneedtoaccountforboththephysicalandpersonalnatureofsubjectivityifwe wanttogiveacomprehensiveandsatisfyingexplanationoftheexistenceofahumanbeingina worldthatisnothuman.Feelingsarefundamentalforunderstandingthestructureandvalueloaded natureofsubjectiveexperienceandbeing.Therefore,Ispentconsiderabletimeonanalyzingboth theneurophysiologicalandpsychologicaldimensionsofhumanaffectivity. Ifinallyexaminethenatureofhumanvaluesinordertoaccountfortheparticularpersonalvalues thatcharacterizehumancare.Iargueforanaturalistconceptionofhumannatureandvaluesand hownaturalismisnottobeconsideredathreattotheparticularnatureofhumanfeeling,action,and personhood.Iclarifymyconceptionofnaturalismbycriticizingthenewlyborndisciplinecalled neuroethicsandanaturalisticbasedmoralrelativism.Theprocessofnaturalizationmustrespectthe subjectiveandpersonalnatureofhumanbeings. Theanalysesarestructuredinthreeparts: 1) AReformulationofRicoeur’sTheoryofSubjectivity(aconceptualframework:ca.100pages) 2) FeelingEthical(analysesofhumanaffectivityanditsrelationtoethicalexperience:ca.100) 3) TheBrainandHumanValues(neuroethicsandtheProcessofnaturalisation:ca.30)

247 Afhandlingsresumé SubjektivitetogEtik.Ricœurogspørgsmåletompersonbegrebetsnaturalisering Afhandlingen argumenterer for det ikkereducerbare forhold mellem subjektivitet og etik. At benægte subjektivitet en plads i etikken er at misforstå etisk teori og at udelukke etik fra en subjektivitetsteorieratsebortfraetvigtigtaspektafsubjektiverfaring,nemligspørgsmåletomdet normative.Menneskeligerfaringafverdenernormativ.Vierfarerikkeverdensometværdifritrum afbegivenhederogbevægelser,mensommeningsfyldtesituationeroghandlinger,derindskriver sig i en fælles verden af interesse, omsorg/bekymring (care) og værdi for subjektet. Det menneskeligesubjekterkarakteriseretvedhvaddetbekymrersigom,ogsubjektiverfaringerførst ogfremmeststruktureretioverensstemmelsemeddeværdier,somerudtryktidetfundamentale begreb omsorg/bekymring (care).Jegbegynderderforafhandlingenmedatforetageensystematisk reformulering af Ricœurs subjektivitetsteori, der således danner en begrebslig ramme for mine videreanalyserafforholdetmellemsubjektivitetogetik. Etiskerfaringerafgørendefordensubjektiveerfaringsstruktur,fordisubjektiveværdier,selvomde harderesoprindelseiselvet,eraldrigbegrænsettildetindividuellesubjektseksistens.Subjektiv erfaringerkonstitueretafselv(selfhood)ogfremmedhed (alterity). Jeg erfarer ikke verden eller migselvsomskabelserafminegenvilje.Minværenerderforberørt(affected)affremmedhedens nærværdiogmed,atselv,verdenogdetandetmenneskealleeraktivefaktorerikonstitutionenaf deværdier,hvorvedjeglevermitliv.Jegkanikkesebortfradennefremmedhediminværen,fordi minerfaringkonstanterberørtafdet,somikkeermig(minfødsel,mitfragmentariskeperspektiv, minfysiskekrop,tid,rumogandrepersoner,somreagererpåminehandlingerogord). Dertilersubjektiveerfaringiskarakteriseretveddenmåde,subjektetinteragerermeddenverden, somdeterfarer.Bevidsterfaringerikkeensimpelregistrering,menetresultatafforholdetmellem aktivitet og passivitet, handling og lidelse. Derfor argumenterer jeg for, at subjektiv erfaring er struktureretsometfornuftenspraktiskerum(apracticalspaceofreason)ioverensstemmelsemed ethierarkiafheterogeneværdierskabteogbearbejdedeietsamspilafverden,selvetogdenanden person. Vi erfarer verden som en konfiguration af ting,begivenhederogsituationer,somvihar omsorgfor/bekymrerosom. Subjektivitetogetikeruløseligtforbundet,fordisubjekteterenpersonudoveratværeetfysisk væsen.Atsubjekteterenpersonbetyder,atdetbekymrer sig om andet og mere end dets egen overlevelseogvelvære,ogsubjektiviteteruforståeligudenpersonbegrebet.Detfaktumatsubjektet bekymrer sig om verden, den anden og sig selv fører mig til at argumentere for en omsorgens/bekymringensontologi(care),dereristandtilatforklaremennesketskompleksenatur. Vi er nødt til at forklare både subjektets fysiske og personlige natur, hvis vi vil give en fyldestgørende forklaring på den menneskelige eksistens i en verden, der ikke er menneskelig. Følelserne er fundamentale for forståelsen af den værdiladede natur, der kendetegner subjektets erfaringogværen.Jegbrugerderforbetydeligtidpåatanalyserebådedenneurofysiologiskeog psykologiskedimensionafmenneskeligefølelser. Jegsluttermedatundersøgedemenneskeligeværdiersnaturforatforklaredepersonligeværdier, somkendetegnermenneskeligbekymring.Jegvælgerennaturalistiskforståelse afmenneskelige værdierogviser,hvordannaturaliseringikkeerentrusselmoddensærligenatur,derkendetegner menneskeligfølelse,handling,ogpersonbegreb.Jegklargørminforståelseafnaturalismevedat kritiserehenholdsvisneuroetikogennaturalistisk baseret moralsk relativisme. En naturalisering mårespekterermennesketssubjektiveogpersonligenatur.Analyserneerstruktureretitredele: 1) EnreformuleringafRicœurssubjektivitetsteori(enbegrebsligramme) 2) Følesigetisk(analyserafmenneskeligefølelserogforbindelsentiletiskerfaring) 3) Hjernenogmenneskeligeværdier(neuroetik,moralskrelativismeognaturalisering)

248