<<

Grazer PhilosophischeStudien 63(2002)1-26

THEMES INMYPHILOSOPHICAL WORK

Terry HORGAN University of Memphis

This paper is an overview of my philosophical work. It follows closely the structure of the handout Iused asthe basis for atalk on this topic atthe 2000 meeting of the Austro-Slovene Philosophical Association. The section-headings mention major themes, and vari- ous key concepts are indicated byboldface terms in the text.

1. Supervenience, in Relation to Reduction and Materialism

Iinvoked the notion of supervenience in my doctoral dissertation, Microreduction and the Mind-Body Problem ,completed at the Uni- versity of Michigan in 1974 under the direction ofJaegwon Kim. I had been struck by the appeal to supervenience in Hare (1952), a classic work in twentieth century metaethics that Istudied atMichi- gan inacourse onmetaethics taught by William Frankena; and Ialso had been struck by the brief appeal to supervenience inDavidson (1970). Kim was already,in effect, construing the relation between physical and mental properties as asupervenience relation –al- though he was not yet using the word ‘supervenience’. Iassumed that amaterialistic was correct, and that integral to ma- terialism isthe idea that higher-level sciences (including psychol- ogy) are reducible tolower-level ones –ultimately to microphysics. One idea Ipressed in the dissertation was that biconditional “bridge laws”would not suffice for genuine intertheoretic reduction if these inter-level laws were additional fundamental laws of nature along- side those ofthe reducing science; they would bewhat Herbert Feigl and J.J.C. Smart, in their writings on the psychophysical identity theory,called “nomological danglers.”Iargued that the higher-level property inabridge law should bear arelation of strict superve- 2 nience to its correlated lower-level property,rather than merely be- ing nomically correlated with it. The basic idea was that there are no two physically possible worlds w 1 and w2 –where aphysically pos- sible world is, roughly,aworld in which the laws of microphysics obtain and in which there are no nonphysical substances like ente- lechies orCartesian souls –such that the actual-world bridge laws obtain inworld w 1 but not in world w 2.(Thus, the bridge laws them- selves are fixed relative tothe fundamental physical facts and funda- mental laws, rather than being fundamental laws themselves along- side those ofmicrophysics.) Already when writing the dissertation, however, Iwas persistently bothered by the apparent conceivability of possible worlds that are physically just like ours but different with respect tothe way phenomenal conscious properties are instantiated –e.g., worlds in which the color-experiences of humans are system- atically inverted in comparison to the actual world. Irealized that my version of materialism was committed to denying that such worlds are agenuine metaphysical possibility,despite their apparent con- ceivability.Ideas from my dissertation are presented in such papers as Horgan (1976, 1978b, 1981c, 1987d). In subsequent work Imoved away from the idea that materialism requires that the properties posited inpsychology and the other spe- cial sciences, and inordinary discourse, need to becorrelated with (or identical to) physics-level natural-kind properties via universally quantified biconditional bridge laws(or via type-type identity state- ments). Icalled my position aversion of nonreductive material- ism,since such bridge laws and/orproperty-identities were widely considered aprerequisite for intertheoretic reduction; cf. Horgan (1993c, 1994b). Icontinued to stress that inter-level relations be- tween properties should not bemetaphysically sui generis within a materialistic metaphysical view,i.e., should not be fundamental laws alongside those ofmicrophysics. One way Imade this point, in Horgan (1984d), was interms of the idea of cosmic hermeneutics : a LaPlacean intelligence should be able to deduce, from acomplete microphysical history ofthe world plus anunderstanding ofmean- ings ofnon-physics-level terms and concepts, all the facts about the world. In order to accommodate the fact that higher-level facts and properties can sometimes supervene on lower-level facts and prop- erties in away that depends on non-local goings-on, in Horgan 3

(1982b) Iintroduced the idea of regional supervenience (although I only gave itthis name inHorgan 1993b). Later Mark Timmonsand I explicitly argued (Horgan and Timmons 1992a) that naturalism re- quires that supervenience relations be explainable inanaturalisti- cally acceptable way; we articulated aformat for such explanations, and we argued that the supervenience ofmental properties onphysi- cal properties could be explained via this format to the extent that mental properties are functional properties. Istressed the explain- ability requirement in Horgan (1993b), where Iintroduced the term superdupervenience for materialistically explainable superveni- ence. Ihave had ongoing, increasing, worries about the extent towhich higher-order properties instantiated in our world are, or are not, superdupervenient on physics-level properties –and also about what would count as amaterialistically acceptable explanation ofsuper- venience (and why). One source of worry,which as Isaid was al- ready present when Iwas writing my dissertation, isthe conceiva- bility –and hence the presumptive metaphysical possibility –of worlds that are physically just like ours but different with respect to the distribution of phenomenal mental properties. (This is closely related to what Joseph Levine (1983) calls the “explanatory gap” and what (1995, 1996) calls the “hard problem”of phenomenal consciousness.) Another source ofworry,stressed for example in Horgan and Timmons (1993) and in Horgan (1994a), is that intentional mental properties seem to involve semantic norma- tivity,afeature that threatens to prevent their supervenience onthe physical from being explainable in amaterialistically acceptable way.In Horgan (1994a) Iargued that inlight ofthis problem, aposi- tion worthy of serious consideration iswhat Icalled preservative irrealism about mental .Yet athird source of worry is mycurrent belief, stressed in Horgan and Tienson (in press), that oc- current intentional mental states like thoughts and desires have a constitutive phenomenology –which means that the first worry ap- plies to these mental states too. 4

2. Conceptual Austerity and Contextually Variable Parameters of Concepts and Discourse

The idea that philosophically interesting concepts are often rela- tively “austere”in the requirements for their correct application has been apersistent theme inmywork –as have the contentions (i) that often these concepts are governed bycertain implicit, contextually variable, parameters, and (ii) that in certain contexts –including contexts where philosophical puzzles are being raised –the contex- tual parameters tend totake on settings that considerably raise the standards for correct application of the concepts. These ideas are re- flected in my compatibilist approach to the problem of freedom and determinism in Horgan (1979, 1985a); in the defense of folk psy- chology in papers such as Horgan and Woodward (1985), Horgan (1987a, 1993a), Graham and Horgan (1988, 1991), and Henderson and Horgan (in press b); and in my causal compatibilism about mental causation and causal explanation in Horgan (1989b, 1991a, 1993c, 1994b, 1998a, 2001a). Mycollaboration with Jim Woodward that produced Horgan and Woodward (1985) began shortly after Ijoined the Memphis philoso- phy department; Woodward was visiting in the department, before he moved tothe California Institute of Technology.Working with him on this paper convinced me that philosophical collaboration can be both fun and fruitful, and engendered in methe disposition todo philosophy collaboratively when possible. (The collaborative pa- pers cited in the present paper are all thoroughly coauthored; order of authorship inthe citations is alphabetical.)

3. Minimalism in (Four Phases)

My work has long been informed by astrong inclination toward a fairly minimalistic ontology.Mypursuit of ontological minimalism has gone through four discernable phases, three of which will be de- scribed in later sections. The first phase involved the pursuit of “paraphrase projects”: ways of systematically paraphrasing or“reg- imenting”discourse about various putative entities into discourse that avoids Quineian “ontological commitment”to those entities – 5 often via appeal tononstandard logico-grammatical constructions like adverbial predicate-modifiers and non-truth-functional sentent- ial connectives. This approach was pursued toavoidevents (includ- ing mental events and actions) inHorgan (1978a, 1981a, 1982a) and Horgan and Tye (1985, 1988); to avoid numbers in Horgan (1984c, 1987c); and toavoid objects ofthe propositional attitudes inHorgan (1989a). But inthe course oftrying tofind ways of “paraphrasing away”discourse about such putative entities as symphonies, corpo- rations, and sentence-types, Icame to believe that paraphrase pro- jects probably could not be successfully carried through for all the various kinds ofputative entities that Iwas disinclined to counte- nance ontologically.Something different, and more radical, seemed needed.

4. Contextual Semantics: Truth as Indirect Correspondence

The idea that came tomind, asaway ofeschewing ontologically problematic entities without either (i) paraphrasing away the dis- course that posits them or (ii) claiming that such discourse isfalse, was to“go soft on truth”– i.e., give up on the idea that truth is always adirect correspondence-relation between language (or thought) and world. Instead, construe truth as semantically correct affirmabil- ity,under semantic standards that involve implicit contextual pa- rameters and often require only indirect correspondence with denizens ofthe mind-independent, discourse-independent, world – rather than direct correspondence. (Direct correspondence is alimit case, in which the contextual parameters are maximally strict.) First Icalled this approach “language-game semantics,”and then “psy- chologistic semantics,”before Mark Timmons and Ibegan to call it contextual semantics .Articulating and defending contextual se- mantics has been an ongoing project for me, and some of mywork on it has been collaborative with Timmons. See Horgan (1986a, 1986b, 1991b, 1995b, 1998c, 2001b), Horgan and Timmons (1993, in press), and Timmons (1999). The turn to contextual semantics ushered in the second stage of my minimalism in ontology.The guiding idea here is that numerous statements have these features: (i) they are true under the semantic standards that normally govern 6 their correct use; (ii) they carry Quineian ontological commitment toentities that are not denizens of the mind-independent, dis- course-independent, world; (iii) they cannot be paraphrased into, or “regimented”by ,statements that eschew apparent ontological com- mitment to the offending entities; and (iv) they are not true under limit-case, direct-correspondence, semantic standards.

5. Metaethical Irrealism

My interest inmetaethics began in the course on this topic Itook with William Frankena when Iwas agraduate student at the Univer- sity ofMichigan. Mark Timmons and Ibegan discussing metaethics during our time together inHilary Putnam’s 1986 summer seminar “Philosophical Problems about Truth and Reality,”sponsored by the National Endowment for the Humanities. Timmons was working on the metaethical dimension of Putnam’s thought, and one project I had underway was Horgan (1987b), apaper tentatively exploring the implications ofcontextual semantics (which Ithen called “psycho- logistic semantics”) for metaethics. That paper of mine staked out a version of moral realism, butongoing discussion with Timmons led me to return tomyearlier inclination toward moral irrealism. After Timmons joined the philosophy department atMemphis, he and I began collaborating on work in metaethics. On the negative side, wehave been attacking various contempo- rary versions of naturalistic moral realism, often deployinga thought experiment wecall Moral Twin Earth .Asarecipe for deconstruct- ing agiven version of moral realism, the basic idea is this: (i) as- sume, for argument’s sake, that humans bear relation Rto natural property P,where Pis whatever natural property the given form of naturalism identifies with moral goodness and Riswhatever rela- tion it claims isthe reference relation linking the term ‘goodness’to P;(ii) assume that some specific normative moral theory (say,some version ofconsequentialism) comes out true if ‘goodness’refers to P;(iii) consider aTwin Earth scenario inwhich people bear relation Rto asomewhat different natural property Q,where adifferent nor- mative moral theory (say,some deontological theory) comes out true if ‘goodness’refers to Q.When one confronts the given version 7 of moral realism with the appropriate kind of Moral Twin Earth sce- nario, we argue, then the view under scrutiny ends upexhibiting one of these two objectionable features: either it is committed to achau- vinistic form of relativism, orelse ityields very little determinate moral truth. See Horgan and Timmons (1991, 1992a, 1992b, 1996a, 1996b, 2000a). On the positive side, Timmons and Ihave been developing and ar- ticulating aversion of metaethical irrealism that we now call nondescriptivist cognitivism .Aversion of the position isset forth in Timmons (1999), and amore recent version appears in Horgan and Timmons (2000b). The basic claim isthat although moral judg- ments are genuine beliefs and moral statements are genuine asser- tions, their overall content is not descriptive content. There isacon- nection to contextual semantics: we hold that the distinction be- tween descriptive and nondescriptive content turns on whether or not agiven judgment or statement is governed by tight semantic standards –that is, semantic standards that conspire with the mind-independent, discourse-independent, world to fix determinate correct affirmability (i.e., truth); cf. Horgan (1996, 2001b), Timmons (1999). Weclaim that moral judgments and statements have nondescriptive content, in the sense that the semantic standards governing them are not tight. Onour view,amoral belief is acertain kind of commitment state –an ought commitment –with respect to what we call a core descriptive content .For instance, the belief that the Tennessee legislature ought topass astate income tax isan ought commitment with respect tothe core descriptive content the Tennes- see legislature passes astate income tax .The overall content of the belief –viz., that the Tennessee legislature ought to pass astate in- come tax –isdistinct from the belief’score descriptive content; and this overall content is not itself descriptive.

6. Post-Analytic Metaphilosophy

Ibegan collaborating with George Graham during an invited visitto his department atthe University ofAlabama in Birmingham. In Gra- ham and Horgan (1988, 1991) we articulated and defended an anti-eliminativist approach to folk psychology that we whimsically 8 named Southern Fundamentalism .One reason for the name was that wewere both teaching inthe American south. Our key conten- tion was that the concepts of folk psychology are sufficiently non- committal about matters like the type-type reducibility of psychol- ogy to neuroscience, or the existence of language-like mental repre- sentations, that the kinds of scientific scenarios envisioned by eliminativists (e.g., the failure of type-type reducibility,or the repu- diation of the language of thought hypothesis) would not impugn the integrity offolk psychology atall. As we worked toarticulate our reasoning asclearly and explicitly as possible, we came to appreciate that our arguments reflected a certain general conception ofphilosophical methodology –one that we believe isactually at work implicitly in much philosophical theo- rizing past and present, often without being recognized for what itis. In Graham and Horgan (1994), ametaphilosophical paper, we named this methodology Post-Analytic Metaphilosophy . One leading idea isthat philosophical inquiry into the workings of philo- sophically interesting concepts and terms – ideology,as we called it –is abroadly empirical matter, even though often itcan be comfort- ably pursued from the armchair because much of its data is very close at hand ( die vom Armchair aus zuhandenen Daten , as we came to call such data after helpful linguistic consultation with mycol- league Tom Nenon). Another key idea is that intuitive judgments about what isright to say about various concrete scenarios –e.g., Gettier cases ofjustified true belief that seem not to be knowledge, Twin Earth scenarios inwhich the word ‘water’seems to have adif- ferent meaning because people use itto refer tosome clear potable liquid other than H 20, etc. –really have the status ofempirical data for ideological reflection, inmuch the same way that intuitivejudg- ments about grammaticality and grammatical ambiguity count as empirical data for linguists who are constructing theories of natural- language syntax. Graham and Ialso generalized our earlier use of the term South- ern Fundamentalism ,now employing itfor the general ideological hypothesis that philosophically interesting terms and concepts typi- cally are relatively austere intheir ideological commitments, rather than being opulent.Wealso acknowledged, however, that such con- cepts often are philosophically puzzling because they exhibit ideo- 9 logical polarity that involves “opulence tendencies”– something that wesuggested isoften the result of(i) implicit, contextually vari- able, parameters that govern the concepts, and (ii) atendency for these parameters to take on amaximally strict setting in contexts where philosophical problems are being posed. There are close con- nections here with contextual semantics, and specifically with the contextualist versions of compatibilism Ifavor concerning both the freedom/determinism issue and the mental causation issue –and also (although Imyself have not written about this) with contextualist approaches to the problem of Cartesian in epistemology.

6. The Sorites Paradox and its Implications for Semantics and Metaphysics

Ihave long had aserious side-interest in paradoxes, and occasion- ally Ifind myself writing about them. Ihave addressed Newcomb’s problem in Horgan (1981b, 1985b), the Monty Hall problem in Horgan (1995a), and the two-envelope paradox in Horgan (2000b, 2001c) and inwork now in progress. In general Iam inclined to be- lieve that the paradoxes discussed in philosophy are often more dif- ficult, and more philosophically deep, than they initially seem to be. (Iconcur with the memorable closing statement in Quine (1966): “Ofall the ways ofthe paradoxes, perhaps the quaintest is their ca- pacity on occasion toturn out to be sovery much less frivolous than they look.”)Inmy work onNewcomb’s problem, for example, Ire- luctantly came to believe that “one box”reasoning and “two box” reasoning are instalemate with one another, and that this fact re- flects adeep internal tension within our ordinary notion of rational- ityitself. And my work onthe two-envelope paradox led me to the conclusions (i) that epistemic probability is intensional in a way that is widely unappreciated, and (ii) that because of this intensio- nality,there are forms of nonstandard expected utility some of which are rationally appropriate tomaximize and some of which are not. But perhaps the deepest and most philosophically potent paradox on which Ihave worked is the sorites paradox, which evidently 10 arises ubiquitously in connection with vagueness. The paradox and itsmorals are addressed in Horgan (1990, 1993d, 1994c, 1995b, 1997a, 1998b), in Horgan and Potr è (2000, in press), and inwork of mine now in progress. According to my treatment of vagueness, which I call transvaluationism ,vagueness by itsvery nature exhib- itsa certain kind of benign logical incoherence :vague terms and concepts are semantically governed by mutually unsatisfiable se- mantic requirements –afact that surfaces explicitly in the sorites paradox. This kind of incoherence is benign because aform of logi- cal discipline remains inforce with respect to the semantically cor- rect use of vague terms and concepts, and this discipline quarantines the incoherence sothat itdoes not generate malignant results –such as rampant logical commitment tostatements of the form ( F & ~F). Transvaluationism about vagueness has important philosophical consequences, both for semantics and for metaphysics. Regarding semantics, transvaluationism leads to the conclusion that truth, for vague statements and vague judgments, must always beindirect cor- respondence to the mind-independent, discourse-independent, world –rather than direct correspondence. (Here mywork onvague- ness comes together with contextual semantics.) Regarding ontol- ogy,transvaluationism leads to the conclusion that ontological vagueness is impossible –i.e., the correct ontology,whatever it might be, cannot include vague objects, vague properties, or vague relations. This repudiation of ontological vagueness isathird stage in the evolutionof myontological minimalism. Inow find myself eschew- ing not only putative entities like symphonies, corporations, and numbers, but also putative entities like mountains, tables, and per- sons –because the latter, if they were real, would be essentially vague incertain respects (e.g., vague with respect to composition, and/orwith respect to spatiotemporal boundaries). Ido not regard my position as aradical repudiation of common sense, however, be- cause in my view the semantic standards that usually govern dis- course and thought are indirect-correspondence standards rather than direct-correspondence ones. Direct-correspondence standards, the limit case, operate only in fairly unusual contexts, e.g., contexts of serious ontological inquiry.(They do not operate even in scien - tific contexts, insofar as the posits ofscientific theory are vague –as 11 they very often are). Thus, most ofour discourse and thought does not carry ultimate ontological commitment toits vague posits, but only what Icall regional ontological commitment .As such, many of our statements and judgments employing vague terms and con- cepts are indeed true –that is, they are semantically correct, under the contextually operative semantic standards that govern them. What minimal ontology of concrete particulars isthe correct one, given the impossibility of ontological vagueness? Ibelieve that a strong case can be made for the view that there isreally only one concrete particular –viz., the entire physical universe, which Icall the blobject .Ibriefly argued for this position in Horgan (1991b), where Icalled the view “Parmenidean materialism.”But Matja ¾ Potrè persuaded me that this isnot agood name, because evidently the object that Parmenides called “the one”was supposed to been- tirely homogenous –whereas the physical universe surely exhibits enormous spatiotemporal complexity and nonhomogenity.Potr è and Inow call the view blobjectivism ;we defend it inHorgan and Potrè (2000). In Horgan and Potr è (in press) wefurther elaborate the view by addressing certain questions for blobjectivism posed by Tienson (in press). Blobjectivism is the fourth, and most recent, stage in the evolution of my ontological minimalism. Perhaps the only way togoany further inthis minimalist direc- tion would be to repudiate my metaphysical realism and join the ranks of the global irrealists who deny that there isa mind-indepen- dent, discourse-independent, world atall. But Idoubt that Iwill ever take that step, partly because Ifind global metaphysical irrealism unintelligible; cf. Horgan (1991b, 2001b).

8. Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology

When John Tienson joined the Memphis philosophy department, he and Itogether attended the weekly meetings ofaninterdisciplinary cognitive science seminar at the university.There welearned about the newly burgeoning approach incognitive science known as con- nectionism. In 1987 Tienson and Idirected our department’s annual Spindel Conference (named for itsbenefactor Murray Spindel, a great friend ofthe department until his death in 1999), on the topic 12

“Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind.”As usual, the pro- ceedings were published asasupplement tothe Southern Journal of Philosophy:Horgan and Tienson (1988a). Wealso edited acollec- tion, Horgan and Tienson (1991), that included numerous additional papers beyond those from the conference. Tienson and Irealized early onthat we had similar ideas about what was wrong with the classical, computational, paradigm incog- nitive science –and about what was potentially most philosophi- cally interesting about connectionism. Beginning with Horgan and Tienson (1988b), the paper wewrote together for the 1987 Spindel Conference, we produced aseries of collaborative papers and then a book that explained what we took tobe in-principle problems for the classical computational view of cognition, and also described a connectionism-inspired nonclassical framework for cognitive sci- ence that potentially could overcome the problems faced by“classi- cism.”See Horgan and Tienson (1988b, 1989, 1990a, 1992a, 1992b, 1993, 1994a, 1994b, 1995, 1996, 1997, 1998, 1999a, 1999b); Horgan (1997b, 1997c); and Tienson (1997). Our name for the recommended nonclassical framework for cog- nitive science was noncomputable dynamical cognition . Some key ideas are the following. First, human cognitive state-transitions are normally too subtle and complex to conform to any tractably computable transition-function over cognitive states –something that we claimed isa principal lesson of the family ofrelated difficul- ties faced by classicism known collectively asthe “frame problem.” Second, there is aform of mathematics that goes naturally with connectionist modeling, and ispotentially more powerful asabasis for understanding cognition than the discrete mathematics em- ployed in the theory and practice of computation –viz., dynamical systems theory.Third, inprinciple asuitably structured high-dimen- sional dynamical system, implementable by aconnectionist net- work or ahuman brain, could subserve cognitive state-transitions that are too complex to conform toprogrammable representation- level rules. Fourth, in principle such adynamical system could avoid the sources ofthe frame problem by accommodating much relevant information not in the form ofexplicit representations (as inclassi- cism), but instead implicitly in the structure of the dynamical system itself. Such implicit information we called morphological content 13

–the idea being that this kind of content is present inthe standing structure of the system, rather than being explicitly represented by occurrent cognitive states. Ipresented the material later published asHorgan and Tienson (1989, 1990a) ata1989 conference in Dubrovnik on philosophy of mind and epistemology.There Imet Matja ¾ Potrè from Ljubljana. Potrè later spent the academic year 1996-97 in the Memphis philos- ophy department on aFulbright Fellowship, where Tienson and I both had many useful discussions with him about our book, about related work of his, and about various other philosophical matters. He organized aconference on Horgan and Tienson (1996), which took place inLjubljana insummer 1997; the proceedings were pub- lished as Acta Analytica 22, (1999). Since then Ihave had aclose working relationship with him, including the co-authored papers mentioned above and our co-editorship of Acta Analytica 23 (1999), acollection of papers from the 1998 conference on vagueness in Bled.

9. Epistemological Themes

In the wake of mywork with Tienson on connectionism and the phi- losophy of psychology,Ibegan collaborating with myMemphis col- league David Henderson on arange of topics inepistemology.In our first paper, Henderson and Horgan (2000a), wefocused onthe im- portant epistemological distinction between having justification for agivenbelief and being justified in holding that belief –where the latter is amatter of holding the belief because of the justification one has for it. Weargued that much epistemological theorizing effec- tivelypresupposes an empirically questionable conception of this ‘because’-connection, and effectively ignores the role that morpho- logical content very likely plays in the fixation of belief. Weurged a new approach that we called iceberg epistemology ,which empha- sizes that cognitive states that are conscious or consciously accessi- ble are typically only the “tip ofthe iceberg”insofar as the psychol- ogy of belief-fixation isconcerned. Werevisit this theme in Henderson and Horgan (forthcoming), where wespell out our rec- ommended alternative conception of being-justified in more detail. 14

Iceberg epistemology has numerous potential implications, includ- ing the capacity to accommodate aspects of erstwhile competing epistemological theories like foundationalism, coherentism, and structural contextualism. In Henderson and Horgan (2001), we argue that there is animpor- tant and insufficiently appreciated aspect of objective epistemic jus- tification, over and above abelief’shaving been produced by areli- able belief-forming process. Wecall it robustness of reliability (or just robustness, for short). The basic idea isthis: for abelief-forming process to berobustly reliable isfor itto bereliable in avery wide range of“epistemically relevant”possible worlds –roughly,worlds in which the epistemic agent undergoes appearances much like the appearances experienced inthe agent’s actual world. The empirical beliefs of someone who is deceived by aCartesian evil demon, for example, could be the products of belief-forming processes that are robust inthis sense, and hence such beliefs could beobjectively very well justified –even though those belief-forming processes happen to be thoroughly unreliable in the agent’s actual world. In Henderson and Horgan (2000b, in press a), we draw upon and extend the methodological ideas that George Graham and Ihad set out under the rubric ‘post-analytic metaphilosophy’. Weoffer a nonclassical reconception ofapriori reasoning and apriori knowl- edge –with aparadigm case being ideological inquiry within philos- ophy itself. The low-grade apriori ,as we call it, isaform ofinquiry and knowledge that isbroadly empirical, and yet nonetheless is suf- ficiently distinctive –and sufficiently similar tothe apriori as classi- cally conceived –tostill warrant the label ‘apriori’. Such inquiry typically seeks todiscover conceptually grounded necessary truths, and ittypically relies heavily upon empirical data (including intu- itions about how to apply key concepts to concrete thought-experi- mental scenarios) readily available by armchair reflection.

10. The Limits of Systematizability

Tienson and I,inour work on connectionism and the philosophy of psychology,argued that human cognitive state-transitions evidently are not fully systematizable by exceptionless, general, psychologi- 15 cal laws that take the form of programmable rules. Once this claim is taken toheart, one begins toappreciate that cognitive states need not be –and probably are not –fully systematizable by exceptionless psychological laws of any kind. This is consistent with their being partially systematizable by psychological generalizations that we called soft laws –that is, psychological laws that have ineliminable ‘ceteris paribus’clauses adverting not only to lower-level excep- tions like external interference orinternal physical malfunction, but also to same-level exceptions characterizable at the psychological level of ; cf. Horgan and Tienson (1990b, 1996). Atheme that has been much on mymind lately,although not yet much articulated inmywritten work, isthis: just asthere are appar- ent limits to the systematizability ofhuman cognitive processing by way ofgeneral laws, sotoo there could well be –and probably are – significant limitsto the systematizability of various kinds of normativity to which humans are capable of conforming in their cognitive, linguistic, and behavioral practices –notably semantic normativity,epistemic normativity,and moral normativity.This idea is articulated and explored with respect to epistemic norma- tivityin Potr è (2000). The same general theme also is explored inthe work oftwo former doctoral students from Memphis: inthe case of epistemic normativity,Stark (1993, 1994, 1999); and inthe case of moral normativity,Haney (1999). One way that this theme affects my current thinking iswith re- spect tothe further articulation and defense ofcontextual semantics. One might think that anadequately worked out version ofcontextual semantics should provide, atleast in rough outline, ageneral and systematic formulation of the semantic normative standards that govern correct affirmability –in particular, correct affirmability of the indirect-correspondence variety.But increasingly Ihave come to think that such aformulation probably isnot possible –not because contextual semantics ismistaken, butrather because semantic normativity is probably too subtle and too complex to be thus systematizable. Toinsist on such systematizability,onthe grounds that otherwise human thought and human linguistic behavior could not conform tothese semantic standards, would beto underestimate the capacities of human cognition. 16

11. The Whole Hard Problem inPhilosophy of Mind

Ever since Iwrote my doctoral dissertation, Ihave been worried about whether anadequate materialistaccount ofphenomenal con- sciousness could be given, and about what it would look like. Things would gosmoother ifsome version offunctionalismwere correct –perhaps aversion that incorporates typical cause connec- tions betweeninnerstates oftheorganism andfeatures ofthedistal environment. AsIremarked insection 1above, itappears that ma- terialisticallyacceptable explanations are available for the super- venience relations linking physical properties tofunctional prop- erties. But for the phenomenal aspects ofmentality,atleast, func- tionalism hasalways seemed tomeimplausible. Onefamiliar way tomake the point isinterms ofthe apparent conceivability of“in- verted qualia”and “absent qualia”scenarios, atopicIhave written about myself; cf. Horgan (1984a, 1987d). Also very potent dialectically is Frank Jackson’s famous thought experiment about Mary the colorblind neuroscientist. Although I wrote one of the first replies to Jackson onbehalf ofthe materialist (Horgan 1984b), Istillsuspected that his thought experiment proba- bly could be deployed somewhat differently than he had, to produce aserious challenge to materialist treatments of phenomenal con- sciousness. George Graham and Itook upthis gauntlet in Graham and Horgan (2000). Wefocused specifically on the account ofphe- nomenal consciousness in Tye (1995), but we argued that our argu- ment looks generalizable. The key line of reasoning was as follows. Let Mary Mary (the daughter of Jackson’s Mary) be acolorblind sci- entist/philosopher who not only knows all there isto know about the physics of color and the neurobiology ofcolor perception, butalso believes aspecific materialist account of phenomenal concepts and the properties to which they refer –say,Tye’s account. She under- stands well what the materialist account says about the nature of color experiences, about the nature of phenomenal concepts, about the nature of the physical/functional properties these concepts sup- posedly refer to, and about the need to undergo color experiences in order to actually possess phenomenal concepts. (Basically,posses- sion of such concepts is supposed to be amatter of being able to color-categorize things solely on the basis ofseeing them, without 17 relying on collateral information.) Given her scientific knowledge and her philosophical beliefs, she has no rational reason toexpect to be dramatically surprised should she begin to undergo color experi- ences inthe future; for, she already knows that those experiences will allow her tobegin color-classifying things just by looking at them. But of course, she will be dramatically surprised (and de- lighted) by color experiences –not because of the new classicatory capacities they provide her, but because of their intrinsic phenomen- ology.Such surprise, which evidently ought to be irrational given the philosophical theory she has accepted prior tohaving color experi- ences, isnot irrational at all. Some materialists, seeking to show full respect for the intrinsic phenomenology of phenomenal consciousness, advocate atype of position that John Tienson and Ihave dubbed “new wave material- ism.”This view asserts that although “inverted qualia”and “absent qualia”scenarios are not metaphysically possible, they are indeed conceivable; italso maintains that although Jackson’s Mary deploys new concepts and acquires new knowledge upon first experiencing color vision, the properties she learns about are physical/functional properties that she knew about already.New wave materialists also claim that experience-based phenomenal concepts –for instance, the new color-concepts that Mary first acquires when she begins to have color vision –pick out their referents not via any accidental ref- erence-fixing features of the referent, but instead via something es- sential about the referent-property.But in Horgan and Tienson (2001), itis argued that new wave materialism faces atheoretical problem that threatens todeconstruct the view.The problem isto ex- plain intelligibly how the following three claims, each of which the view embraces, can besimultaneously true: (i) when phenomenal properties are conceived under phenomenal concepts, they are con- ceived essentially,as they are in themselves; (ii) when phenomenal properties are conceived under phenomenal concepts, they are con- ceived otherwise than as physical properties; (iii) phenomenal con- cepts refer to physical properties. Prima facie, it appears that the conjunction of claims (i) and (ii) is incompatible with claim (iii), given the plausible further claim (also embraced by new wavers) that when phenomenal properties are conceived under physical con- cepts, they are conceived essentially,as they are in themselves. 18

All of this underscores, and fleshes out in different ways, the so-called “hard problem”of phenomenal consciousness. Ionce thought, as many in philosophy of mind still do think, that the phe- nomenal and the intentional aspects of mentality are largely separa- ble from one another.But lately,largely asaresult ofongoing dis- cussion with John Tienson and George Graham, Ihave come tobe- lieve that this “separatist”doctrine about phenomenology and inten- tionality isthoroughly mistaken. InHorgan and Tienson (in press) it isargued that phenomenology and intentionality are thoroughly and essentially intertwined –and in particular, that there isanessential “what it’s like”of having an occurrent thought, orof having an oc- current desire. This means that the whole hard problem – that is, the overall problem ofexplaining the phenomenal aspects ofmen- tality –extends to paradigmatically intentional states too, thereby encompassing virtually the whole of human conscious (as opposed to unconscious) mental life. Iremain deeply attracted tomaterialism in philosophy of mind; I would like to believe that the mental is superdupervenient on the physical. But the whole hard problem looks very hard indeed, and I see no prospects currently in sight for dealing with itsatisfactorily. Theories ofmind that claim todo justice to phenomenology,and yet would besatisfiable by zombies who lack phenomenal conscious- ness altogether, do not seem credible. Much asIwould like to be a materialist, at present Ido not know what anadequate materialist theory of mind would look like.

Acknowledgements and Dedication

My sincere thanks toMatja ¾ Potrè for initiating the Horgan Sympo- sium that took place at the 2000 Austrian-Slovene Philosophical Euroconference, to Wolfgang Gombocz for organizing the confer- ence, and to Johannes Brandl and Olga Marki è for co-editing this collection. My deep thanks too to all the participating philosophers, for their very stimulating presentations. David Henderson and Mark Timmons each gave useful overview talks about their collaborative work with me. Others who gave presentations butdid not submitpa- pers to this volume were John Bickle, Bojan Borstner, Johannes 19

Brandl, Bo¾ idar Kante, Friderik Klampfer, Nenad Mi šè eviæ , and Di- ana Raffman. Thanks also toDavid Henderson, Mark Timmons, and John Tienson for discussion and feedback as Iprepared the present paper and my reply to the papers in this volume. Mywife Dianne and Ilost our son Alexander William Horgan on July 30, 2001. He died of suicide, at age 23. Alec was enormously talented inmany ways, including as amusician, asong writer, and a fiction writer.Hehad agigantic intellect, and was asbrilliant aper- son as Ihave ever known. He suffered from severe depression from his teen years onward, and inthe end itovercame him. Idedicate this volume tohis memory.

REFERENCES

Chalmers, D.1995.The Puzzle ofConscious Experience, Scientific American 273, 80-86. Chalmers, D.1996. TheConscious Mind .OxfordUniversity Press. Davidson,D. 1970.Mental Events.In L.Forsterand J. W.Swanson,eds., Experience andTheory (Universityof Massachusetts Press),79-101. Reprintedin D. Davidson, Essayson Actions andEvents (Oxford, 1980). Graham,G. andHorgan, T .1988.How to beRealistic AboutFolk Psy- chology, PhilosophicalPsychology 1, 69-81. Graham,G. andHorgan, T .1991.In Defenseof SouthernFundamental- ism, PhilosophicalStudies 62, 107-34. Graham,G. andHorgan, T .1994.Southern Fundamentalism and the End ofPhilosophy, PhilosophicalIssues 5, 219-47. Graham,G. andHorgan, T .2000.MaryMary, Quite Contrary, Philosophi- cal Studies 99, 59-87. Haney,M. 1999.Dynamical Cognition,Soft Laws, and Moral Theorizing, Acta Analytica 22, 227-40. Hare,R. M.1952. TheLanguage of Morals .OxfordUniversity Press. Henderson,D. andHorgan, T .2000a.Iceberg Epistemology, Philosophy andPhenomenolog ical Research 61,497-535. 20

Henderson,D. andHorgan,T .2000b.What is APrioriand Whatis ItGood For?, SouthernJournal of Philosophy 38,SpindelConference Supple- ment,51-86. Henderson,D. andHorgan,T .2001.Practicing Safe Epistemology, Philo- sophicalStudies 102,227-58. Henderson,D. andHorgan, T .Inpress a. TheA PrioriIsn’ t All That It’s CrackedUp to Be, But ItIsSomething, PhilosophicalT opics , issue honoringAlvin Goldman. Henderson,D. andHorgan, T .Inpress b. What Does It TaketoBe aTrue Believer? Againstthe OpulentIdeology of Eliminative Materialism. In C.Ernelingand D. Johnson,eds., Mindas aScientific Object: Between Brainand Culture .OxfordUniversity Press. Henderson,D. andHorgan, T .Forthcoming.Morphological Content and Justified Belief. Horgan,T .1976.Reduction and the Mind-BodyProblem. In M.Marxand F.Goodson,eds., Theoriesin Contemporary Psychology ,2ndedition (Macmillan), 223-31. Horgan,T .1978a.The Case AgainstEvents, PhilosophicalReview 87, 28-47. Horgan,T .1978b.Supervenient Bridge Laws, Philosophyof Science 45, 227-49. Horgan,T .1979.‘ Could’, PossibleW orlds,and Moral Responsibility, SouthernJournal of Philosophy 17, 345-58. Horgan,T .1981a.Action Theory Without Actions, Mind 60, 406-14. Horgan,T.1981b.Counterfactuals and Newcomb’ s Problem, Journal of Philosophy, 331-56. Horgan,T .1981c.T okenPhysicalism, Supervenience,and the Generality of Physics, Synthese 49,395-413. Horgan,T .1982a.Substitutivity and the Causal Connective, Philosophi- cal Studies 42, 47-52. Horgan,T .1982b.Supervenience and Microphysics, Pacific Philosophi- cal Quarterly 63, 29-43. Horgan,T .1984a.Functionalism,Qualia, andthe InvertedSpectrum, Phi- losophyand Phenomenolo gical Research 44, 453-69. Horgan,T .1984b.Jackson on Physical Informationand Qualia, Philo- 21

sophicalQuarterly 34, 147-52. Horgan,T .1984c.Science Nominalized, Philosophyof Science 51, 529-49. Horgan,T. 1984d. Supervenience and Cosmic Hermeneutics, Southern Journalof Philosophy 22,SupplementIssue on Supervenience,19-38. Horgan,T .1985a.Compatibilism andthe ConsequenceArgument, Philo- sophicalStudies 47, 339-56. Horgan,T .1985b.Newcomb’ s Problem:A Stalemate. InR.Campbell and L.Sowden,eds., Paradoxesof Rationality andCooperation (U. of Brit- ishColumbia Press), 223-34. Horgan,T .1986a.Psychologism, Semantics, andOntology, Nous 20, 21-31. Horgan,T .1986b.Truth and Ontology, PhilosophicalP apers 15, 1-21. Horgan,T .1987a.Cognition is Real, Behaviorism 15, 13-25. Horgan,T .1987b.Psychologistic Semantics andMoralTruth, Philosoph- ical Studies 52, 357-70. Horgan,T .1987c.Science Nominalized Properly, Philosophyof Science 54, 281-82. Horgan,T. 1987d. Superven ient Qualia, Philosophical Review 96, 491-520. Horgan,T. 1989a. Attitudin atives, Linguistics andPhilosop hy 12, 133-65. Horgan,T .1989b.Mental Quausation, PhilosophicalP erspectives 3, 47-76. Horgan,T .1990.Psychologistic Semantics, RobustV agueness,and the Philosophyof Language.In S.L.Tsohatzidis,ed., Meaningsand Pro- totypes:Studies in Linguistic Categorization (Routledge),535-57. Horgan,T .1991a.Actions, Reasons, and the ExplanatoryRole ofCon- tent. InB.McLaughlin,ed., Dretske andHisCritics (Basil Blackwell), 73-101. Horgan,T .1991b.Metaphysical Realism andPsychologistic Semantics, Erkenntnis 34,297-322. Horgan,T .1993a.The Austere Ideology of FolkPsychology. Mind and Language 8, 282-97. 22

Horgan,T .1993b.From Supervenience to Superduperve nience: Meeting the Demandsof aMaterial World, Mind 102,555-86. Horgan,T. 1993c. Nonreductive Materialism andthe ExplanatoryAuton- omyof Psychology.In Wagner& Warner,eds., Naturalism:A Critical Appraisal (NotreDame), 295-320. Horgan,T .1993d.On WhatThereIsn’t, Philosophyand Phenomenologi- cal Research 50,693-700. Horgan,T .1994a.Naturalism andIntentionality, PhilosophicalStudies 76, 301-26. Horgan,T .1994b.Nonreductive Materialism. InR. Warnerand T . Szubka,eds., TheMind-Body Problem (Blackwell), 236-41. Horgan,T .1994c.Robust V aguenessand the Forced-MarchSorites Para- dox, PhilosophicalP erspectives 8,Logicand Language , 159-88. Horgan,T .1995a.Let’ s Make aDeal, PhilosophicalP apers 24, 209-22. Horgan,T .1995b.Transvaluationism: A DionysianApproach to V ague- ness, SouthernJournal Philosophy 33,Spindel Conference Supple- ment,97-125. Horgan,T .1996.The Perils ofEpistemic , Philosophyand Phenomenological Research 66, 891-97. Horgan,T .1997a.Brute Supervenience,Deep Ignorance, and the Prob- lem ofthe Many, PhilosophicalIssues 8, 229-36. Horgan,T .1997b.Connectionism and the PhilosophicalFoundations of CognitiveScience, Metaphilosophy 28, 1-30. Horgan,T .1997c.Modelling the Noncomputational Mind: Reply to Litch, PhilosophicalPsychology 10, 365-71. Horgan,T .1998a.Kim on Mental Causation andCausal Exclusion, Philo- sophicalP erspectives 11, 165-84. Horgan,T .1998b.The Transvaluationist Conception of Vagueness, The Monist 81, 316-33. Horgan,T .1998c.Actualism, Quantification,and Contextual Semantics, PhilosophicalP erspectives 12, 503-09. Horgan,T .2000a.Facing Up tothe SoritesParadox. In A.Anamori,ed., Proceedingsof the 20 th WorldCongress of Philosophy.V olume6: Ana- lytic PhilosophyandLogic (PhilosophyDocumenta tionCenter), 99-111. 23

Horgan,T .2000b.The T wo-EnvelopeParadox, Nonstandard Expected Utility, andthe Intensionalityof Probability, Nous 34,578-602. Horgan,T .2001a.Causal Compatibilism andthe ExclusionProblem, Theoria 16, 95-116. Horgan,T .2001b.Contextual Semantics andMetaphysical Realism: Truthas IndirectCorresponden ce InM. Lynch,ed., TheNature of Truth:Classic andContemporary P erspectives (MITPress),67-95. Horgan,T .2001c.TheT wo-EnvelopeParadox and the Foundationsof Ra- tional DecisionTheory. In B.Brogaardand B.Smith,eds., Rationality andIrrationality: Proceedings of the 23 rd InternationalWittgenstein Symposium (öbv &hpt),172-91. Horgan,T .andPotr è ,M.2000.Blobjectivism andIndirect Correspon- dence, FactaPhilosophica 2, 249-70. Horgan,T .andPotr è ,M.Inpress. Addressing Questions for Blobjec- tivism, FactaPhilosophica . Horgan,T. and Tienson, J., eds.1988a. SpindelConference 1987:Con- nectionismand the Philosophyof Mind . SouthernJournal of Philoso- phy 26,Supplement. Horgan,T .andTienson,J. 1988b.Settling intoa NewParadigm, Southern JournalofPhilosophy 26,Supplement,97-114. Reprintedin T .Horgan andJ. Tienson,eds., Connectionismand the Philosophyof Mind (Kluwer,1991). Horgan,T. and Tienson, J. 1989.Representations withoutRules, Philo- sophicalT opics 17, 27-43. Horgan,T .andTienson,J. 1990a.Connectionism and the KuhnianCrisis inCognitive Science, Acta Analytica 6, 5-17. Horgan,T .andTienson, J. 1990b.Soft Laws, Midwest Studiesin Philoso- phy 15, 256-79. Horgan,T .andTienson, J., eds.1991. Connectionismand the Philosophy of Mind. Kluwer. Horgan,T .andTienson, J. 1992a.Cognitive Systems as Dynamical Sys- tems, Topoi 11, 27-43. Horgan,T .andTienson, J. 1992b.Structured Representations inCon- nectionist Systems?,In S. Davis.,ed., Connectionism:Theory and Practice (Oxford),195-228. 24

Horgan,T .andTienson, J. 1993.Levels ofDescriptionin Nonclassical CognitiveScience, Philosophy 34,Royal Institute ofPhilosophySup- plement, 159-88. Horgan,T .andTienson, J. 1994a.Representations Don’t NeedRules: Re- plyto James Garson, Mindand Language 9, 38-55. Horgan,T .andTienson, J. 1994b.A Nonclassical Frameworkfor Cogni- tive Science, Synthese 101,305-345. Horgan,T .andTienson,J. 1995.Connectionism and the Commitments of FolkPsychology, PhilosophicalP erspectives 9, 127-52. Horgan,T .andTienson, J. 1996. Connectionismand the Philosophyof Psychology. MIT Press. Horgan,T .andTienson,J. 1997.Pré cis of Connectionismand the Philos- ophyof Psychology , PhilosophicalPsychology 10, 337-56. Horgan,T .andTienson, J. 1998.Resisting the Tyrannyof Terminology: TheGeneral Dynamical Hypothesisin Cognitive Science, Behavioral andBrain Sciences 21, 643. Horgan,T .andTienson, J. 1999a.Authors’ Replies, Acta Analytica 22, 275-87. Horgan,T .andTienson, J. 1999b.Short Precis of Connectionismand the Philosophyof Psychology , Acta Analytica 22, 9-21. Horgan,T .andTienson, J. 2001.Deconstructing New W aveMaterialism. InC. Gillett andB. Loewer,eds., Physicalism andIts Discontents (Cambridge),307-18. Horgan,T .andTienson, J. Inpress. The Intentionality ofPhenomenology andthe PhenomenologyofIntentionality.In D.Chalmers, ed., Philos- ophyof Mind:Classical andContemporary Readings (Oxford). Horgan,T .andTimmons, M. 1991.New Wave Moral Realism Meets Moral TwinEarth, Journalof PhilosophicalResearch 16,447-65;and inJ. Heil, ed., Rationality, Morality, andS elf-Interest: Essays HonoringMark C. Overvold (Rowmanand Littlefield, 1993). Horgan,T .andTimmons, M. 1992a.Troubles on Moral TwinEarth: Moral QueernessRevived, Synthese 92, 221-60. Horgan,T .andTimmons, M. 1992b.Troubles for New Wave Moral Se- mantics: The‘ OpenQuestion Argument’ Revived, PhilosophicalP a- pers 21, 153-75. 25

Horgan,T. and Timmons, M. 1993.Metaphysical Naturalism, Semantic Normativity,and Meta-Semantic Irrealism, PhilosophicalIssues 4, 180-203. Horgan,T .andTimmons, M. 1996a.Troubles for Michael Smith’s Metaethical Rationalism, PhilosophicalP apers 25,203-231. Horgan,T .andTimmons,M. 1996b.From Moral Realism toMoral Rela- tivism inOne Easy Step, Critica 28, 3-39. Horgan,T .andTimmons, M. 2000a.Copping Out on Moral TwinEarth, Synthese 124,139-52. Horgan,T. and Timmons, M. 2000b.Nondescrip tivist Cognitivism: Frameworkfor a NewMetaethic, PhilosophicalP apers 29, 121-53. Horgan,T .andTimmons, M. Inpress.Conceptual Relativity andMeta- physicalRealism, PhilosophicalIssues. Horgan,T .andT ye,M. 1985.Against the TokenIdentity Theory. In E. LePoreand B. McLaughlin,eds., Act andEvent: ThePhilosophy of DonaldDavidson (Basil Blackwell), 427-43. Horgan,T .andT ye,M.1988.Braving the Perils ofanUneventfulW orld, GrazerPhilosophische Studien 31,179-186. Horgan,T .andWoodward, J. 1985.Folk Psychology is Hereto Stay, PhilosophicalReview 94,197-226. Levine,J. 1983.Materialism andQualia: TheExplanatory Gap, Pacific PhilosophicalQuarterly 64, 354-61. Potrè ,M.2000.Justification Havingand Morphologica lContent, Acta Analytica 24, 151-73. Quine,W .V.O.1966.The W aysof Paradox.In his TheW aysof Paradox andOther Essays (RandomHouse). Stark,H. 1993.Rationality is NotAlgorithmic, Kinesis 20, 16-30. Stark,H. 1994.Connectionism and the formof Rational Norms, Acta Analytica 12, 39-53. Stark,H. 1999.What the Dynamical CognitiveScientist Saidto the Epis- temologist, Acta Analytica 22, 241-60. Timmons,M. 1999. Morality without Foundations:A Defense ofEthical Contextualism .OxfordUniversity Press. Tienson,J. 1997.What the DifferencesAre: Reply toHardcastle, Philo- 26

sophicalPsychology 10, 385-9. Tienson,J. Inpress.Questions for Blobjectivism, FactaPhilosophia . Tye,M. 1995. TenProblems of Consciousness: A Representationalist Theoryof the PhenomenalMind . MIT Press.