Happiness and Superlative Value in the Eudemian Ethics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Happiness and Superlative Value in the Eudemian Ethics Happiness and Superlative Value in the Eudemian Ethics Giulia Bonasio Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy under the Executive Committee of the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2019 © 2018 Giulia Bonasio All rights reserved ABSTRACT Happiness and Superlative Value in the Eudemian Ethics Giulia Bonasio In my dissertation Happiness and Superlative Value in the Eudemian Ethics, I analyze dimensions of the Eudemian Ethics (EE) that, as I see it, make the EE a distinctive contribution to ethics. The EE discusses a superlative excellence called kalokagathia, the virtue of being-beautiful-and-good, which does not figure in the Nicomachean Ethics (NE). The agent who possesses kalokagathia is the best agent of Aristotle’s EE. Scholars tend to hold that the practically wise person, the phronimos, or the theoretically wise person, the sophos, are the best agents of the NE. If my reading of the EE is right, then the EE and the NE conceive differently of the best agent. This is salient in both treatises’ construals of the unity of the virtues. In the NE, the unity of the virtues includes the character virtues and phronêsis. In the EE, it additionally includes the virtues of theoretical thinking, or so I argue. The EE starts with what I call the Superlative Thesis (ST): happiness is what is best, most beautiful, and most pleasant of all. I take this beginning to be programmatic. Aristotle aims to show how these three kinds of value combine in the best human life, rather than coming apart. The Pleasure Thesis (PT) is the most contested aspect of ST: happiness is the most pleasant thing of all. On my reading, Aristotle fully embraces PT. In laying out his proposal for the best human life, the Aristotle of the EE develops a distinctive kind of naturalism, which I call Natural Goods Naturalism. I reconstruct this position in two steps: by interpreting the EE’s function argument; and by exploring the notion of natural goods, which is central to the EE, but does not figure in the NE. In sum, my dissertation argues that the EE contains a distinctive and under-appreciated option within ancient ethics, and that it contains ideas that are relevant to today’s virtue ethics and ethical naturalism. TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER ONE: Introductory remarks on happiness and the Superlative Thesis 1 1 The state-of-the-art 5 2 Happiness: a substantive account 11 3 Happiness: a formal account 17 4 The Superlative Thesis 20 5 Theognis’ quote 25 6 Happiness and three kinds of values 29 7 Complete virtue 37 8 Chapter outline 46 CHAPTER TWO: Kalokagathia and the unity of the virtues in the EE 49 1 Kalokagathia and its relation to particular virtues 52 2 Kalokagathia as unified and complete virtue 56 3 Unity of the virtues and unity of the soul 59 4 Mutual entailment of practical wisdom and the character virtues 64 5 Intelligence as part of the unity of the virtues 69 6 Sophia and epistêmê as part of the unity of the virtues 72 7 Theoretical and practical wisdom 75 !i Conclusion 80 CHAPTER THREE: Natural goods in the EE 82 1 Natural goods and simpliciter-goods 85 2 Natural goods, dependent goods and external goods 88 3 Who are natural goods good for? 93 4 Good-for vs relative-goodness 101 5 A minimal notion of the standard state 104 6 For the most part and by nature 108 7 Formulation of Natural Goods Naturalism 111 Conclusion 113 CHAPTER FOUR: Function, human nature and contemplation in EE and in the NE 115 1 The Function Arguments 118 2 Subject and purpose of the Function Arguments 120 3 Structure of the Function Arguments 124 4 Parts of the soul and the human good 127 5 Virtue in the Function Arguments 130 6 Use in the Function Arguments 134 7 Fulfilling the function 137 !ii 8 Human function and the divine in the EE 140 9 Function, limit, and contemplation 149 10 Function and contemplation in the NE 154 Conclusion 156 CHAPTER FIVE: Pleasure in the EE. Against the view that pleasure is the apparent good 158 1 The Superlative Thesis and the Pleasure Thesis 162 2 What pleasure is 163 3 Pleasure by nature 168 4 The contingent identity: pleasure and happiness 172 5 The apparent good 174 6 Pleasure and the good 177 7 Apparent and true pleasure 184 8 Pleasure and the best agent 191 9 Pleasure and the divine 194 Conclusion 196 CONCLUSION 198 BIBLIOGRAPHY 202 !iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS My deep thanks goes to my advisor, Katja Vogt, for precious, timely, and insightful feedback on my work during all these years at Columbia University. I owe her immense thanks for her direction. I am grateful to the members of my committee, Francesca Masi, Karen Margrethe Nielsen, Dhananjay Jagannathan, Gareth Williams, who commented on this project along the way and provided helpful and encouraging advice. The time and resources granted by the DAAD Fellowship and by the Chateaubriand Fellowship allowed me to work on my project for a year in Munich and in Paris. Thanks to Evan Jewell, Charles McNamara, Sam McVane, Mariana Beatriz Noé, and Joe Sheppard, for reading parts of the dissertation and providing comments. I am grateful to all my friends in New York, Italy, France, Germany and the Netherlands, who made my life more pleasant during all these years. Deep thanks to my parents who supported me and encouraged me from the beginning. Last, my deepest gratitude goes to my husband, Daniele, who taught me how to be patient and supported me in all possible ways. He followed me in New York too many times to count them and he allowed me to work on my project in all the beautiful places where life took us in these years. !iv To my husband To my parents !v CHAPTER ONE Introductory Remarks on Happiness and the Superlative Thesis A perennial question has been raised in antiquity and continues to be on our minds: how can we be happy? The answer to this question is difficult and there is no general agreement. What is more, it is not even clear that happiness is a unified and agreed upon notion. For Aristotle, eudaimonia - happiness, literally “to have a good daimon” - is the highest goal of human life.1 Aristotle’s philosophical proposal in the Nicomachean Ethics (NE) has received considerable attention from antiquity on. Conversely, the Eudemian Ethics (EE) is still largely unexplored. It is my aim in this work to shed light on some aspects of Aristotle’s philosophical proposal in this treatise. Is the ethical theory of the EE largely the same as the theory of the NE, or are there important differences? Specifically, does the Aristotle of the EE propose a different view on happiness? Does he discuss a well-lived human life in terms that are familiar from the NE, or does he employ conceptual tools that are distinctively Eudemian? If we look at how the two treatises begin, something strikes us as profoundly different. From the very first lines of the work, the NE focuses on the good, while three value- properties take center stage in the EE: the good, the beautiful, and the pleasant. All three kinds of values are presented as immediately connected to happiness. Aristotle says that 1 Eudaimonia is translated “happiness” for lack of a better term: I use this translation for the sake of clarity insofar as it is ingrained in the literature on the topic. Other possible translations are “flourishing,” “well-being,” etc. Some important contributions on Aristotle’s notion of happiness are: W.F. R. Hardie, Aristotle ethical theory (Oxford, 1968); J. Cooper, Reason and the human good (Cambridge, 1975); J. McDowell, “The role of eudaimonia in Aristotle’s ethics,” in Essays on Aristotle's ethics, A.O. Rorty (ed.) (Berkeley, 1980); J. Dybikowski, “Is Aristotelian Eudaimonia happiness?”, Dialogue, 20, 1981, pp. 185-200; T. Nagel, “Aristotle on eudaimonia,” in Rorty; J.L. Ackrill, “Aristotle on eudaimonia,” in Rorty; R. Kraut, Aristotle on the human good (Princeton, 1989); A. Kenny, Aristotle on the perfect life (Oxford, 1992); S. Broadie, Ethics with Aristotle (Oxford, 1994); N. Sherman (eds.), Aristotle’s Ethics: critical essays (Oxford, 1998); P. Destrée, Aristote, Bonheur et vertus (Paris, 2003); G. Lear, Happy lives and human good (Princeton, 2006); M. Pakaluk, G. Pearson, Moral psychology and human actions (Oxford, 2011); C.D.C. Reeve, Action, contemplation and happiness (Cambridge, 2012); P. Destrée, M. Zingano (eds.), Theoria, (Paris, 2015). For a history of happiness, F. De Luise, G. Farinetti, Storia della felicità. Gli antichi e i moderni (Torino, 2001). !1 happiness is the best, the most beautiful, and the most pleasant thing of all. Throughout this dissertation, I argue that the EE can be read as an extended argument. Aristotle aims to prove that happiness is the best, the most beautiful, and the most pleasant thing of all. I investigate the relation of the best agent to these three kinds of value. Aristotle calls this agent the kalos kagathos. The kalos kagathos is the agent who has kalokagathia, the complex virtue of being-beautiful-and-good. And on account of this high-level excellence, she lives a life that deserves to be called happy. Her happiness displays the superlative value mentioned in the first sentence of the EE: it is the best, the most beautiful, and the most pleasant thing of all. The route to happiness, I argue, admits a lot of variability regarding the specifics of a given person’s good life.
Recommended publications
  • Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Version 1.1 (Last Updated : Apr
    - Institute for scientific and technical information - Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Version 1.1 (Last updated : Apr. 05, 2018) This resource contains 4435 entries grouped into 89 collections. Controlled vocabulary used for indexing bibliographical records for the "Philosophy" FRANCIS database (1972-2015, http://pascal-francis.inist.fr/ ). This vocabulary is browsable online at: https://www.loterre.fr Legend • Syn: Synonym. • →: Corresponding Preferred Term. • FR: French Preferred Term. • DE: German Preferred Term. • SC: Semantic Category. • DO: Domain. • URI: Concept's URI (link to the online view). This resource is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International license: LIST OF ENTRIES List of entries English French Page • 10th century Xe siècle 176 • 11th - 13th centuries XIe - XIIIe siècles 176 • 11th century XIe siècle 176 • 12th -13th centuries XIIe - XIIIe siècles 176 • 12th century XIIe siècle 176 • 13th - 14th centuries XIIIe - XIVe siècles 176 • 13th - 15th centuries XIIIe - XVe siècles 176 • 13th century XIIIe siècle 176 • 14th - 15th centuries XIVe - XVe siècles 176 • 14th - 16th centuries XIVe - XVIe siècles 176 • 14th - 17th centuries XIVe - XVIIe siècles 176 • 14th century XIVe siècle 176 • 15th - 17th centuries XVe - XVIIe siècles 176 • 15th century XVe siècle 176 • 1656-1658 1656-1658 176 • 16th - 17th centuries XVIe - XVIIe siècles 176 • 16th - 18th centuries XVIe - XVIIIe siècles 176 • 16th - 20th centuries XVIe - XXe siècles 176 • 16th century XVIe siècle 176 • 1735-1985 1735-1985
    [Show full text]
  • Beauty on Display Plato and the Concept of the Kalon
    BEAUTY ON DISPLAY PLATO AND THE CONCEPT OF THE KALON JONATHAN FINE Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2018 © 2018 Jonathan Fine All rights reserved ABSTRACT BEAUTY ON DISPLAY: PLATO AND THE CONCEPT OF THE KALON JONATHAN FINE A central concept for Plato is the kalon – often translated as the beautiful, fine, admirable, or noble. This dissertation shows that only by prioritizing dimensions of beauty in the concept can we understand the nature, use, and insights of the kalon in Plato. The concept of the kalon organizes aspirations to appear and be admired as beautiful for one’s virtue. We may consider beauty superficial and concern for it vain – but what if it were also indispensable to living well? By analyzing how Plato uses the concept of the kalon to contest cultural practices of shame and honour regulated by ideals of beauty, we come to see not only the tensions within the concept but also how attractions to beauty steer, but can subvert, our attempts to live well. TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements ii 1 Coordinating the Kalon: A Critical Introduction 1 1 The Kalon and the Dominant Approach 2 2 A Conceptual Problem 10 3 Overview 24 2 Beauty, Shame, and the Appearance of Virtue 29 1 Our Ancient Contemporaries 29 2 The Cultural Imagination 34 3 Spirit and the Social Dimension of the Kalon 55 4 Before the Eyes of Others 82 3 Glory, Grief, and the Problem of Achilles 100 1 A Tragic Worldview 103 2 The Heroic Ideal 110 3 Disgracing Achilles 125 4 Putting Poikilia in its Place 135 1 Some Ambivalences 135 2 The Aesthetics of Poikilia 138 3 The Taste of Democracy 148 4 Lovers of Sights and Sounds 173 5 The Possibility of Wonder 182 5 The Guise of the Beautiful 188 1 A Psychological Distinction 190 2 From Disinterested Admiration to Agency 202 3 The Opacity of Love 212 4 Looking Good? 218 Bibliography 234 i ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS “To do philosophy is to explore one’s own temperament,” Iris Murdoch suggested at the outset of “Of ‘God’ and ‘Good’”.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical and Historical Analysis of Cosmology from Copernicus to Newton
    University of Central Florida STARS Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019 2017 Scientific transformations: a philosophical and historical analysis of cosmology from Copernicus to Newton Manuel-Albert Castillo University of Central Florida Part of the History of Science, Technology, and Medicine Commons Find similar works at: https://stars.library.ucf.edu/etd University of Central Florida Libraries http://library.ucf.edu This Masters Thesis (Open Access) is brought to you for free and open access by STARS. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019 by an authorized administrator of STARS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. STARS Citation Castillo, Manuel-Albert, "Scientific transformations: a philosophical and historical analysis of cosmology from Copernicus to Newton" (2017). Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019. 5694. https://stars.library.ucf.edu/etd/5694 SCIENTIFIC TRANSFORMATIONS: A PHILOSOPHICAL AND HISTORICAL ANALYSIS OF COSMOLOGY FROM COPERNICUS TO NEWTON by MANUEL-ALBERT F. CASTILLO A.A., Valencia College, 2013 B.A., University of Central Florida, 2015 A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the department of Interdisciplinary Studies in the College of Graduate Studies at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Fall Term 2017 Major Professor: Donald E. Jones ©2017 Manuel-Albert F. Castillo ii ABSTRACT The purpose of this thesis is to show a transformation around the scientific revolution from the sixteenth to seventeenth centuries against a Whig approach in which it still lingers in the history of science. I find the transformations of modern science through the cosmological models of Nicholas Copernicus, Johannes Kepler, Galileo Galilei and Isaac Newton.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy As a Path to Happiness
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto Philosophy as a Path to Happiness Attainment of Happiness in Arabic Peripatetic and Ismaili Philosophy Janne Mattila ACADEMIC DISSERTATION To be publicly discussed, by due permission of the Faculty of Arts at the University of Helsinki in auditorium XII, University main building, on the 13th of June, 2011 at 12 o’clock. ISBN 978-952-92-9077-2 (paperback) ISBN 978-952-10-7001-3 (PDF) http://ethesis.helsinki.fi/ Helsinki University Print Helsinki 2011 2 Abstract The aim of this study is to explore the idea of philosophy as a path to happiness in medieval Arabic philosophy. The starting point is in comparison of two distinct currents within Arabic philosophy between the 10th and early 11th centuries, Peripatetic philosophy, represented by al-Fārābī and Ibn Sīnā, and Ismaili philosophy represented by al-Kirmānī and the Brethren of Purity. These two distinct groups of sources initially offer two contrasting views about philosophy. The attitude of the Peripatetic philosophers is rationalistic and secular in spirit, whereas for the Ismailis philosophy represents the esoteric truth behind revelation. Still, the two currents of thought converge in their view that the ultimate purpose of philosophy lies in its ability to lead man towards happiness. Moreover, they share a common concept of happiness as a contemplative ideal of human perfection, merged together with the Neoplatonic goal of the soul’s reascent to the spiritual world. Finally, for both happiness refers primarily to an otherworldly state thereby becoming a philosophical interpretation of the Quranic accounts of the afterlife.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical Inquiry Into the Development of the Notion of Kalos Kagathos from Homer to Aristotle
    The University of Notre Dame Australia ResearchOnline@ND Theses 2006 A philosophical inquiry into the development of the notion of kalos kagathos from Homer to Aristotle Geoffrey Coad University of Notre Dame Australia Follow this and additional works at: https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses Part of the Philosophy Commons COMMONWEALTH OF AUSTRALIA Copyright Regulations 1969 WARNING The material in this communication may be subject to copyright under the Act. Any further copying or communication of this material by you may be the subject of copyright protection under the Act. Do not remove this notice. Publication Details Coad, G. (2006). A philosophical inquiry into the development of the notion of kalos kagathos from Homer to Aristotle (Master of Philosophy (MPhil)). University of Notre Dame Australia. https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses/13 This dissertation/thesis is brought to you by ResearchOnline@ND. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of ResearchOnline@ND. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY INTO THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE NOTION OF KALOS KAGATHOS FROM HOMER TO ARISTOTLE Dissertation submitted for the Degree of Master of Philosophy Geoffrey John Coad School of Philosophy and Theology University of Notre Dame, Australia December 2006 TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract iv Declaration v Acknowledgements vi INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER 1: The Fish Hook and Some Other Examples 6 The Sun – The Source of Beauty 7 Some Instances of Lack of Beauty: Adolf Hitler and Sharp Practices in Court 9 The Kitchen Knife and the Samurai Sword 10 CHAPTER 2: Homer 17 An Historical Analysis of the Phrase Kalos Kagathos 17 Herman Wankel 17 Felix Bourriott 18 Walter Donlan 19 An Analysis of the Terms Agathos, Arete and Other Related Terms of Value in Homer 19 Homer’s Purpose in Writing the Iliad 22 Alasdair MacIntyre 23 E.
    [Show full text]
  • 7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul
    7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul Roger Crisp n the recent revival of interest in Aristotelian ethics, relatively little attention has been paid to the virtue of greatness of soul (megalopsuchia). This is partly Ibecause of the focus on the more structurally central concepts of Aristotle’s theory, in particular happiness (eudaimonia) and virtue (aret¯e). But in fact a study of greatness of soul can reveal important insights into the overall shape of Aristotelian ethics, including the place of external goods and luck in the virtuous life, and the significance of “the noble” (to kalon). Further, Aristotle describes the great-souled person in more detail than any other, and calls greatness of soul a “sort of crown of the virtues” (NE IV.3.1124a1–2). Many have found aspects of the portrait of the great-souled person in the Nicomachean Ethics repellent or absurd, but that is no good reason for the student of Aristotle to shy away from it. In this chapter, I shall elucidate Aristotle’s account of greatness of soul, addressing some puzzles internal to that account and bringing out its place in, and implications for, the ethics of Aristotle and of those modern writers influenced by him. Greatness of Soul as a Virtue To understand greatness of soul as an Aristotelian virtue requires first understand- ing Aristotle’s conception of virtue itself. Aristotle distinguishes virtues into two classes – intellectual virtues and virtues of character – corresponding to distinct aspects of the human soul (NE I.13). Greatness of soul is a virtue of character, though, like all such virtues, it requires its possessor to have the intellectual virtue of practical wisdom (phron¯esis; NE VI.13).
    [Show full text]
  • Interpv3issue2 5/5
    Volume 30 Issue 2 Spring 2003 119 Jules Gleicher Moses Dikastes 157 Eric Buzzetti New Developments in Xenophon Studies 179 George Thomas The Parasite as Virtuoso: Sexual Desire and Political Order in Machiavelli’s Mandragola 195 Roslyn Weiss Oh, Brother! The Fraternity of Rhetoric and Philosophy in Plato’s Gorgias 207 Kalev Pehme Book Review: Outline of a Phenomenology of Right, by Alexandre Kojève Editor-in-Chief Hilail Gildin, Dept. of Philosophy, Queens College General Editors Seth G. Benardete (d. 2001) • Charles E. Butterworth • Hilail Gildin • Leonard Grey • Robert Horwitz (d. 1978) • Howard B. White (d. 1974) Consulting Editors Christopher Bruell • Joseph Cropsey • Ernest L. Fortin (d. 2002) • John Hallowell (d. 1992) • Harry V. Jaffa • David Lowenthal • Muhsin Mahdi • Harvey C. Mansfield • Arnaldo Momigliano (d. 1987) • Michaeal Oakeshott (d. 1990) • Ellis Sandoz • Leo Strauss (d. 1973) • Kenneth W. Thompson International Editors Terrence E. Marshall • Heinrich Meier Editors Wayne Ambler • Maurice Auerbach • Robert Bartlett • Fred Baumann • Amy Bonnette • Eric Buzzetti • Susan Collins • Patrick Coby • Elizabeth C’de Baca Eastman • Thomas S. Engeman • Edward J. Erler • Maureen Feder-Marcus • Pamela K. Jensen • Ken Masugi • Carol M. McNamara • Will Morrisey • Susan Orr • Michael Palmer • Charles T. Rubin • Leslie G. Rubin • Susan Meld Shell • Devin Stauffer • Bradford P. Wilson • Cameron Wybrow • Martin D. Yaffe • Michael P. Zuckert • Catherine H. Zuckert Copy Editor Maria Kent Rowell Designer Wendy Coy Subscriptions Subscription rates per volume (3 issues): Individuals $29 Libraries and all other institutions $48 Students (four year limit) $18 Single copies available. Postage outside U.S.: Canada: add $4.50; all other countries add $5.40 for surface mail (8 weeks or longer) or $11 for airmail.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume's Chief Argument
    Chapter 6 Hume’s Chief Argument Peter Millican I Skepticism, Empiricism, Naturalism, and Irreligion David Hume’s philosophy is complex and multifaceted, generating considerable debate over which themes within it should be seen as dominant. Historically, most of his crit- ics have viewed him as a negative skeptic who either deliberately sets out to show the weaknesses and contradictions in human reason,1 or else is driven to do so by follow- ing through the logical implications of his philosophical premises.2 Prominent among these premises is the concept-empiricist assumption inherited from Locke, which Hume expresses as his Copy Principle, that all ideas are derived from impressions (T 1.1.1.7/4; EU 2.5/19). But this is not in itself a skeptical principle, and some interpret- ers have seen it as providing the keystone of a more constructive philosophy.3 Another very prominent theme in Hume’s work is his “Attempt to introduce the experimental Method of Reasoning into Moral Subjects.” In accordance with this ambitious subtitle, the Treatise aspires to lay the groundwork of a science of human nature that can explain cognitive operations (such as factual belief and the apprehension of external objects) in terms of the association of ideas, enabling Hume to be seen as an associationist or early cognitive scientist.4 Although the associationism fades in his later works,5 Hume’s epis- temic-empiricist commitment to the “experimental” science of man remains a pervasive theme in virtually all of his philosophy, including the two Enquiries and Dissertation on the Passions, the essays on politics, economics, and aesthetics, and his various contribu- tions to the philosophy of religion.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle and the Value of Tragedy Malcolm Heath
    Aristotle and the Value of Tragedy Malcolm Heath This article explores Aristotle’s understanding of the value of tragedy. The primarily technical analyses of the Poetics are not sufficient for this purpose: they must be read in the context of Aristotle’s philosophical anthropology. An outline of Aristotle’s understanding of the structure of human motivation provides a framework within which to interpret his discussion of the uses of music, and in particular of music’s status as an intrinsically valuable component of cultivated Downloaded from leisure. Applying that model to tragedy requires an explanation of what motivates engagement with drama that evokes distressing affects. Aristotle’s account of musical katharsis, if read with sufficient attention to its structure and interpreted in the light of his analysis of pleasure, provides a solution. If the importance which Aristotle attaches to intrinsically valuable leisure activities is overlooked, it http://bjaesthetics.oxfordjournals.org/ is not possible to understand his conception of a good human life, or his aesthetics. What motivates human beings to invest time and effort in producing and consuming trag- edies? And how does that investment contribute to a characteristically human way of life? That is, what value attaches to the production and consumption of tragedies? Though Aristotle touches briefly on poetry’s roots in human nature at the beginning of Poetics 4, for the most part the existence of poetry and its diverse kinds is treated in the Poetics, not as an explanandum, but as the starting point for technical analyses of how poems, in their various kinds, are best composed.
    [Show full text]
  • UC Davis UC Davis Previously Published Works
    UC Davis UC Davis Previously Published Works Title The anthropology of incommensurability Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/3vx742f4 Journal Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 21(2) ISSN 0039-3681 Author Biagioli, M Publication Date 1990 DOI 10.1016/0039-3681(90)90022-Z Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California MARIO BIAGIOLP’ THE ANTHROPOLOGY OF INCOMMENSURABILITY I. Incommensurability and Sterility SINCE IT entered the discourse of history and philosophy of science with Feyerabend’s “Explanation, Reduction, and Empiricism” and Kuhn’s The Structure of Scient$c Revolutions, the notion of incommensurability has problematized the debate on processes of theory-choice.’ According to Kuhn, two scientific paradigms competing for the explanation of roughly the same set of natural phenomena may not share a global linguistic common denominator. As a result, the possibility of scientific communication and dialogue cannot be taken for granted and the process of theory choice can no longer be reduced to the simple picture presented, for example, by the logical empiricists. By analyzing the dialogue (or rather the lack of it) between Galileo and the Tuscan Aristotelians during the debate on buoyancy in 1611-1613, I want to argue that incommensurability between competing paradigms is not just an unfortunate problem of linguistic communication, but it plays an important role in the process of scientific change and paradigm-speciation. The breakdown of communication during the
    [Show full text]
  • Catalogue of Titles of Works Attributed to Aristotle
    Catalogue of Titles of works attributed by Aristotle 1 To enhance readability of the translations and usability of the catalogues, I have inserted the following bold headings into the lists. These have no authority in any manuscript, but are based on a theory about the composition of the lists described in chapter 3. The text and numbering follows that of O. Gigon, Librorum deperditorum fragmenta. PART ONE: Titles in Diogenes Laertius (D) I. Universal works (ta kathalou) A. The treatises (ta syntagmatika) 1. The dialogues or exoterica (ta dialogika ex terika) 2. The works in propria persona or lectures (ta autopros pa akroamatika) a. Instrumental works (ta organika) b. Practical works (ta praktika) c. Productive Works (ta poi tika) d. Theoretical works (ta the r tika) . Natural philosophy (ta physiologia) . Mathematics (ta math matika) B. Notebooks (ta hypomn matika) II. Intermediate works (ta metaxu) III. Particular works (ta merika) PART TWO: Titles in the Vita Hesychii (H) This list is organized in the same way as D, with two exceptions. First, IA2c “productive works” has dropped out. Second, there is an appendix, organized as follows: IV. Appendix A. Intermediate or Particular works B. Treatises C. Notebooks D. Falsely ascribed works PART THREE: Titles in Ptolemy al-Garib (A) This list is organized in the same way as D, except it contains none of the Intermediate or Particular works. It was written in Arabic, and later translated into Latin, and then reconstructed into Greek, which I here translate. PART FOUR: Titles in the order of Bekker (B) The modern edition contains works only in IA2 (“the works in propria persona”), and replaces the theoretical works before the practical and productive, as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • The Lesson of Plato's Symposium
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 2005 Eros, Paideia and Arête: The Lesson of Plato’s Symposium Jason St. John Oliver Campbell University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the American Studies Commons Scholar Commons Citation Campbell, Jason St. John Oliver, "Eros, Paideia and Arête: The Lesson of Plato’s Symposium" (2005). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/2806 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Eros, Paideia and Arête: The Lesson of Plato’s Symposium by Jason St. John Oliver Campbell A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Masters of Arts Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Joanne B. Waugh Ph.D. Charles Guignon, Ph.D. Martin Schöenfeld, Ph.D. Date of Approval: April 14, 2005 Keywords: Ancient Greece, Socrates, Education, Pedagogy, Sunousia © 2005, Jason St. John Oliver Campbell Acknowledgments I wish to extend a debt of gratitude to Professor Joanne B. Waugh for her continued dedication throughout the completion of this thesis. Table of Contents Abstract ii General Introduction 1 Chapter One 4 Introduction 4 Mousikē: The First Component
    [Show full text]