Chapter 2 Elements of Scientific Theories: Concepts and Definitions

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Chapter 2 Elements of Scientific Theories: Concepts and Definitions 11 Part 1 / Philosophy of Science, Empiricism, and the Scientific Method Chapter 2 Elements of Scientific Theories: Concepts and Definitions n this chapter we will discuss the basic building blocks of a scientific theory: the concepts which represent the “real world” phenomena being explained by the theory. The scientific Imethod requires that the nature of these concepts be unambiguously communicated to others. This requirement mandates the creation of theoretical definitions. A theoretical definition explains what is meant by the concept. Concepts must also be objectively observed. This requires that we create operational definitions, which translate the verbal concepts into corresponding variables which can be measured. We will elaborate upon each of these topics in this chapter. In the next chapter, we’ll see how the defined concepts and their associated variables are related to each other to form complete theories. Concepts and Constructs The basic building blocks of theories are concepts. A concept is a verbal abstraction drawn from observation of a number of specific cases. The critical term here is “observed”, because it means that there is a direct link between the concept (the abstraction) and its referents (the reality). For in- stance, we can observe a number of particular instances where individuals receive varying amounts of money for the work they have done over a given period of time. From these particulars we distill an abstraction and label it “income”. Similarly, we observe individuals and find some of them short, some tall and more of them in between; from these observations we generate the concept “height”. Chapter 2: Elements of Scientific Theories: Concepts and Definitions 12 Part 1 / Philosophy of Science, Empiricism, and the Scientific Method A construct serves the same function as a concept, but it is more abstract. It is not characterized by a direct link between the abstraction and its observed manifestations. For instance, “source cred- ibility” is a construct which has been used in studying persuasion. This term can be used in the same way as a concept, but we should recognize that we cannot directly observe different levels of source credibility in individuals. However, we can observe the various parts which make up the construct individually, and then combine them to get some overall summary. Constructs are built from the logical combination of a number of more observable concepts. In the case of source credibility, we could define the construct as the combination of the concepts of expertise, objectivity, and status. Each of these concepts can be more directly observed in an individual. Of course, we might also consider some of these terms to be constructs themselves, and break them down into combinations of still more concrete concepts, as illustrated in Figure 2-1. What we see if we do this is a set of constructs at decreasing levels of abstraction. Only at the bottom of this hierarchy are directly observ- able concepts. From a practical point of view, it matters little whether we call the verbal building blocks concepts or constructs. It is more useful to consider every concept to be at some particular level of abstraction. This level is determined by the distance of the concept from the directly observable ideas at the bottom of the hierarchy. To simplify discussion, in the future we will use the term concepts to refer to either concepts or constructs, recognizing that any concept can really be a very abstract idea built from the combination of many less abstract (more concrete) concepts. Definitions A scientific concept really consists of three parts: a label, a theoretical definition, and an opera- tional definition. We’ll examine each of these elements separately. Concept Labels One of the requirements of a theory is that it be in a form which can be communicated to any interested person in an unambiguous fashion, so that it may be tested and evaluated by others. A great advantage of using concept labels is that they facilitate communication. It is vastly more con- Chapter 2: Elements of Scientific Theories: Concepts and Definitions 13 Part 1 / Philosophy of Science, Empiricism, and the Scientific Method venient and efficient to refer to people’s “income” than to refer to “the amount of money people receive in return for having made their labor or their knowledge available to another”. It is also very easy, at this level of abstraction, to link one concept to another. If we are asked what interests us most in the field of communication, we might answer that our research focuses on the effect of “environmental change” on “task-oriented communication” in organizations. But a label, particularly for abstract concepts like “task-oriented communication”, is usually not sufficient to communicate the full meaning of the concept unambiguously. We need additional explanation. Theoretical Definitions The theoretical definition specifies the verbal meaning which is attached to the concept label. We need this explanation because the scientific method requires that others understand our theory and be able to criticize and reproduce our observations. If we fail to specify the meaning repre- sented by a particular concept label, we leave room for misunderstanding. As we’ll see below, the more abstract the concept that we’re using, the worse this problem becomes. To illustrate this, suppose that you ask a group of people to write down on an index card their explanation of the concept of a person’s “age”. You’ll probably find that most of the definitions mention things like “how long someone has been alive”, “the amount of time which has passed since birth” and other similar statements. The amount of overlap among these definitions probably will be very high, indicating high shared meaning. Now suppose you repeat this procedure, but this time you ask people to define the term “me- dia use”. You’ll probably get very different results. You might find, for instance, that half of the definitions have a central theme of time (for instance, “the amount of time people spend with me- dia”) and that the other half might focus on purpose (for instance, “whether people use media for entertainment, information, escape, etc.”). The amount of overlap among these definitions is much lower than the overlap for “age”. Figure 2-2 illustrates the relationship between abstraction and meaning overlap. “Age” is a more concrete concept, so the concept label itself communicates the meaning of the concept almost as well as the definitions. Thus there is high overlap. “Media use” is more abstract, and can be constructed in many different ways from the combination of a large number of more concrete ideas. This produces many differences in the kinds of definitions which different individuals spontane- ously produce. We call self-defining concepts like “age” primitive terms. Primitive terms are adequately de- fined by their attached concept labels. These are the labels which appear at the bottom of the level of abstraction hierarchy. Probably only a small number of concepts that we are likely to use in commu- nication research have such high degree of shared meaning that they are primitive terms. And even then, the high degree of shared meaning might only exist within a particular group, but may not be shared with other groups. “Communication Apprehension” might be well understood by commu- nication researchers, but poorly understood by psychologists. Consequently, we always risk being on thin ice if we use primitive terms and assume that shared meanings exist. The conservative approach (and therefore the recommended one) is to explicitly specify the meaning associated with each concept, regardless of the extent to which we think the meaning is shared. We do this because the rules of science demand that we use concepts understood by the whole community of researchers. We must have high meaning overlap, particularly for abstract concepts which are not self-defining. To achieve this, we must construct a theoretical definition for each concept in our theory. The procedures for creating theoretical definitions are summarized in Exhibit 2-1, along with an example of the process. We’ve deliberately chosen a concept which is both abstract and not com- monly used in communication research to illustrate the value of theoretical definitions. Operational Definitions We now have a concept label whose meaning is explained by a theoretical definition. But the rules of science demand that this concept be capable of being unambiguously and objectively observed by anyone. This means that we must create another type of definition, called an operational defini- tion. An operational definition translates the verbal meaning provided by the theoretical definition Chapter 2: Elements of Scientific Theories: Concepts and Definitions 14 Part 1 / Philosophy of Science, Empiricism, and the Scientific Method into a prescription for measurement. Although they may be expressed verbally, operational defini- tions are fundamentally statements that describe measurement and mathematical operations. An operational definition adds three things to the theoretical definition.An operational defini- tion describes the unit of measurement (We’ll discuss measurement in much more detail in Chapter Chapter 2: Elements of Scientific Theories: Concepts and Definitions 15 Part 1 / Philosophy of Science, Empiricism, and the Scientific Method EXHIBIT 2-1 Procedure for Creating a Theoretical Definition 1. Select a summary label. the sum of money spent on advertising in media use efficiency media (per capita), subscriptions, and 2. List the labels of all the more concrete con- rentals of media cepts which are encompassed by the label. 6. Continue this process of breaking down more time spent with media abstract definitions into a series of concrete money spent on media definitions, until all terms in the final defini- 3. Combine these labels into a verbal statement tion are concrete, self-defining concepts which which defines the summary label.
Recommended publications
  • PSY 4960/5960 Science Vs. Pseudoscience Human Life
    PSY 4960/5960 Science vs. Pseudoscience •What is science? Human Life Expectancy Why has the average human lifespan doubled over the past 200 years? 1 Quick Quiz • True or false? • Most people use only about 10% of their brain capacity • Drinking coffee is a good way to sober up after heavy drinking • Hypnosis can help us to recall things we’ve forgotten • If you’re unsure of your answer while taking a test, it’s best to stick with your initial answer Common Sense? •Look before you leap. •He who hesitates is lost. •Birds of a feather flock together. •Opposites attract. •Absence makes the heart grow fonder. •Out of sight, out of mind. • •Better safe than sorry. •Nothing ventured, nothing gained. •Two heads are better than one. •Too many cooks spoil the bthbroth. •The bigger the better. •Good things come in small packages. •Actions speak louder than words. •The pen is mightier than the sword. •Clothes make the man. •Don’t judge a book by its cover. •The more the merrier. •Two’s company, three’s a crowd. •You’re never too old to learn. •You can’t teach an old dog new tricks. Lilienfeld et al. (2007) Operational Definition • Science is – “A set of methods designed to describe and interpret observed or inferred phenomena, past or pp,resent, and aimed at building a testable body of knowledge open to rejection or confirmation.” – A toolbox of skills designed to prevent us from fooling ourselves – Learning to minimize your thinking errors – Self‐correcting Shermer (2002) 2 What Makes a Good Scientist? • Communalism –a willingness to share data • Disinterestedness –trying not to be influenced by personal or financial investments • A tiny voice saying “I might be wrong” • “Utter honesty –a kind of leaning over Merton (1942) backwards” Sagan (1995) Feynman (1988) Quick Quiz Write down the names of as many living scientists as you can, including their fields.
    [Show full text]
  • Language and Definitions
    This asset is intentionally omitted from this text. It may be accessed at Language and Definitions www.mcescher.com. (Waterfall by 1 Language Functions M.C. Escher) 2 Emotive Language, Neutral Language, and Disputes 3 Disputes and Ambiguity 4 Definitions and Their Uses 5 The Structure of Definitions: Extension and Intension 6 Definition by Genus and Difference 1 Language Functions When people reason, they typically do so using language, manipulating proposi- tions in a logical or informative spirit. But language is used in a great variety of ways, only some of which are informative. Without the intention to inform, we may express ourselves using language: “That’s really great!” we may say; and the poet, overcome by the beauty of an ancient city, channels his emotions in writing these lines: Match me such marvel, save in Eastern clime— A rose-red city—“half as old as time.”1 Of course, some expressive discourse also has informative content, and may express attitudes as well as beliefs. Grow old along with me! The best is yet to be, The last of life for which the first was made.2 Moreover, some discourse is directive, with or without expressive or informa- tive elements. It seeks to guide or to command. “Step on the scale, please,” we may be told, or we may receive this good advice: Drive defensively. The cemetery is full of law-abiding citizens who had the right of way. A mixture of functions is a natural feature of almost all our uses of language. We can see this in our own speech and writing.
    [Show full text]
  • FURTHER REMARKS on DEFINITION and ANALYSIS 19 Cf
    FURTHER REMARKS ON DEFINITION AND ANALYSIS 19 Cf. C. G. Hempel and Paul Oppenheim, "The Logic of Explanation," Philosophy of Science, vol. 15 (1948). While this definition is adequate for many purposes, it is oversimplified in some ways. Theorem 1 depends on the form of this definition, but our general approach is consistent with any explieatum of 'explain.' 1~ Cf. footnote 6. i~ For example, T'~ may state that T~ holds under specified conditions. le Cf. H. Feigl's contribution to the symposium on operationism in the Psychological Review, vol. 52, no. 5 (September 1945). Further Remarks on Definition and Analysis by IRVING M. COPI UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN A NUMBER of acute criticisms have been directed against some of the views presented in my essay "Analytical Philosophy and Analytical Propositions" (this journal, December 1953). I welcome them as providing stimulation and opportunity for penetrating more deeply into the issues involved. The central notion in my discussion is that of a theoretical de/init/on. A theoretical definition of a term is intended to formulate a theoretically adequate characterization of the objects to which that term applies. One gives a theoretical definition of a term to attach to the term, as intension, that property which in the context of a given theory is most useful for understanding or predicting the behavior of those entities which comprise the (usual) extension of that term. In his "Definitions in Analytical Philosophy" (this journal, April 1954) Michael Scriven has correctly observed that a given theoretical definition is compatible with a wide range of different theories (p.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 5 Measurement Operational Definitions Numbers and Precision
    5 - 1 Chapter 5 Measurement Operational Definitions Numbers and Precision Scales of Measurement Nominal Scale Ordinal Scale Interval Scale Ratio Scale Validity of Measurement Content Validity Face Validity Concurrent Validity Predictive Validity Construct Validity Thinking Critically About Everyday Information Reliability of Measurement Test–Retest Reliability Alternate Form Reliability Split-Half Reliability Factors That Affect Reliability Case Analysis General Summary Detailed Summary Key Terms Review Questions/Exercises 5 - 2 Operational Definitions An essential component of an operational definition is measurement. A simple and accurate definition of measurement is the assignment of numbers to a variable in which we are interested. These numbers will provide the raw material for our statistical analysis. Measurement is so common and taken for granted that we seldom ask why we measure things or worry about the different forms that measurement may take. It is often not sufficient to describe a runner as “fast,” a basketball player as “tall,” a wrestler as “strong,” or a baseball hitter as “good.” If coaches recruited potential team members on the basis of these imprecise words, they would have difficulty holding down a job. Coaches want to know how fast the runner runs the 100-yard dash or the mile. They want to know exactly how tall the basketball player is, the strength of the wrestler, the batting average of the hitter. Measurement is a way of refining our ordinary observations so that we can assign numerical values to our observations. It allows us to go beyond simply describing the presence or absence of an event or thing to specifying how much, how long, or how intense it is.
    [Show full text]
  • Developing an Operational Definition of Intellectual Disability for the Purpose of National Health Surveillance
    Developing an Operational Definition of Intellectual Disability for the Purpose of National Health Surveillance Prepared by: Alexandra Bonardi OTR/L, MHA Emily Lauer, MPH In cooperation with: Steven Staugaitis PhD Julie Bershadsky PhD Sarah Taub MS Courtney Noblett MPA November 2011 A 2010 Research Topic of Interest (RTOI): Health Surveillance of Adults with Intellectual Disability, awarded by the Association of University Centers on Disabilities (AUCD) and funded through a cooperative agreement with the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC) National Center on Birth Defects and Developmental Disabilities (NCBDDD) ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The RTOI Project team would like to thank all participants at the April 13th, Operational Definition of ID Summit for their clear and compelling arguments, their engaged and respectful sharing of opinion and expertise, and for their dedication to enhancing surveillance as a means to improve the health of people with an intellectual disability. A complete list of the Summit Participants and their affiliations are included in Appendix A The RTOI Project Advisory Group provided valuable input into the planning and interpretation of the outcomes from the summit: Robert Baldor, Mary Blauvelt, Val Bradley, Mike Fox, Matt Janicki, Christine Linehan, Chas Moseley, Deirdra Murphy, Susan Parish, Ismaila Ramon, Steven Staugaitis. Others who offered advice, especially Max Barrows and Karen Topper of Self Advocates Becoming Empowered (SABE) and those self advocates, family members, and researchers who committed
    [Show full text]
  • Operational Definition Refinement: A
    From: AAAI-92 Proceedings. Copyright ©1992, AAAI (www.aaai.org). All rights reserved. Operational definition refinement: a Jan M. iytkow Jieming Zhu obert Zembowicz Department of Computer Science Wichita State University, Wichita, KS 67208 Abstract that high quality data are obtained from a user or a simulation. In true science, however, the requests for Operational definitions link scientific attributes to ex- data are based on empirical knowledge. For instance, perimental situations, prescribing for the experimenter measurements must be made at concrete times. If a the actions and measurements needed to measure or measurement is made too early, before a reaction is control attribute values. While very important in real completed or before a measuring device stabilizes, the science, operational procedures have been neglected in results will be systematically wrong or the error may machine discovery. We argue that in the preparatory be large. If the measurements are made too late, the stage of the empirical discovery process each opera- interference of a disturbing phenomenon may cause an- tional definition must be adjusted to the experimental other systematic error. The exact timing of “too early task at hand. This is done in the interest of error re- and too late” may vary. A reaction may be completed duction and repeatability of measurements. Both small at different times for varying amounts of chemicals. error and high repeatability are instrumental in theory Similarly, the time after which a measuring device will formation. We demonstrate that operational proce- stabilize may depend on the mass added and other cir- dure refinement is a discovery process that resembles cumstances.
    [Show full text]
  • Kuhnian Incommensurability Between Two Paradigms of Contemporary Linguistics
    Kuhnian Incommensurability Between Two Paradigms of Contemporary Linguistics Philip Smith Ph.D. Thesis School of English Literature, Language and Linguistics The University of Sheffield March 2011 Slowly we are learning, We at least know this much, That we have to unlearn Much that we were taught, And are growing chary Of emphatic dogmas; Love like matter is much Odder than we thought. From 'Heavy Date' by W.H.Auden I must review my disbelief in angels. Brian Patten - Angel Wings Abstract This dissertation proposes a theory of reference for the language of scien- tific theories. This theory of reference looks at the nature of postulation in scientific theories, and shows that mental posits are metaphorical in na- ture. It is a hybrid of internalist and extensive reference theories. This, allied with the competing epistemological assumptions of competing schools of ltngutsttcs, can account for the existence of incommensurability across two paradigms of ltngutsttcs, The relationship between transformational generative grammar and socio- linguistics is vexed. Both claim the same object of study, but with radi- cally different methods and aims. This dissertation shows that the meta- phorical nature of the posits used in each leads to incommensurable vo- cabularies. Thomas Kuhn's notions of paradigms and incommensurability are used to elucidate this relationship. Chapter one proposes and explains the theory of reference. Chapter two defines the major areas of the thesis. Chapter three explores the history of linguists claiming that a particular area of linguistics instantiates a Kuhnian paradigm, and looks at arguments concerning the possibilities for studying language scientifically. Chapter four explores the epistemological bases of TGG and sociolinguistics, starting from Chomsky's claims to do 'Cartesian linguistics', and concludes that opposing epistemological com- mitments lead to incommensurability.
    [Show full text]
  • Developing a Theoretical Framework of Responsiveness In
    DEVELOPING A THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK OF RESPONSIVENESS IN EDUCATIONAL INSTITUTIONS AND NON-PROFIT ORGANIZATIONS by DIVYA NARENDRA BHEDA A DISSERTATION Presented to the Department of Education Studies and the Graduate School of the University of Oregon in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy June 2013 DISSERTATION APPROVAL PAGE Student: Divya Narendra Bheda Title: Developing a Theoretical Framework of Responsiveness in Educational Institutions and Non-Profit Organizations This dissertation has been accepted and approved in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Doctor of Philosophy degree in the Department of Education Studies by: Dr. Ronald Beghetto Co-Chair Dr. Joanna Goode Co-Chair Dr. Mia Tuan Member Dr. Patricia A. Curtin Outside Member and Dr. Kimberly Andrews Espy Vice President for Research & Innovation/Dean of the Graduate School Original approval signatures are on file with the University of Oregon Graduate School. Degree awarded June 2013 ii © 2013 Divya Narendra Bheda iii DISSERTATION ABSTRACT Divya Narendra Bheda Doctor of Philosophy Department of Education Studies June 2013 Title: Developing a Theoretical Framework of Responsiveness in Educational Institutions and Non-Profit Organizations A number of education institutions and non-profit organizations seek to be responsive toward the stakeholders they serve. They engage in numerous organizational and evaluative processes to be perceived as responsive. They consider evaluating and improving responsiveness, important to their practice. Unfortunately, such efforts are often impeded because there is a lack of clear understanding regarding what “responsiveness” means. One reason is that the current professional literature on responsiveness provides fragmented, ambiguous, and limited definitions of responsiveness.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Scientific Research
    Part I Introduction CHA1pTER Introduction to Scientific Research Introduction to Scientific Research Science Traditional Methods of Pseudoscience Acquiring Knowledge Assumptions Characteristics Role of Role of Objectives Theory Scientist Intuition Uniformity Control Logic of Curiosity Describe Discovery Authority Reality Operationalism Patience Explain Logic of Rationalism Discoverability Replication Justification Objectivity Predict Empiricism Change Control Learning Objectives • Explain what knowledge is and how it is • Describe the characteristics of scientific re- obtained. search and understand why each of these is • Describe the current conception of science necessary. and describe its history. • Explain the difference between logic of dis- • Understand the basic assumptions underlying covery and logic of justification. scientific research. 1 M01_CHRI1252_12_SE_C01.indd 1 08/05/13 6:40 PM 2 | Introduction to Scientific Research • Describe the characteristics that typify the per- • Describe the objectives of scientific research. son who is adept at pursuing scientific • Differentiate pseudoscience from scientific research. research. Introduction In our daily lives, we continually encounter problems and questions relating to thoughts and behavior. For example, one person might have a tremendous fear of taking tests. Others might have problems with alcoholism or drug abuse or problems in their marriage. People who encounter such problems typically want to eliminate them, but often need help. Consequently, they seek out professionals, such as psychologists, for help. Likewise, business professionals might enlist the assistance of psychologists in understanding the thinking and behavior of others. For example, salespeople differ greatly in their ability to understand customers and sell merchandise. One car salesperson might be ca- pable of selling twice as many cars as another salesperson.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical Analysis of the Concept of Time in Physics
    A critical analysis of the concept of time in physics Claudio Borghi Liceo Scientifico Belfiore, via Tione 2, Mantova, Italy Abstract. This paper puts forward a broad critical analysis of the con- cept of physical time. Clock effect is conceived as a consequence of the variation of the gravitational or pseudo gravitational potential, and it is remarked that only some real clocks measure durations in agreement with the predictions of general relativity. A probable disagreement is ex- pected between radioactive and atomic clocks, in the light of Rovelli’s thermal time hypothesis. According to the recent contributions by Rugh and Zinkernagel, the relationship between time and clocks is investigated in order to found on a physical basis the concept of cosmic time. In the conclusive section is argued the impossibility of reducing thermal time to relativistic time. Key words: Time, Relativity, Thermodynamics, Cosmology 1 Introduction The following points resume the main concepts: 1) analysis of the operational definition of time in Newton and Einstein; 2) distinction between time dilation effect and clock effect in Einstein’s theory; 3) considerations about the nonequivalence between atomic clocks and radioac- tive clocks in the light of the clock hypothesis; 4) remarks about the existence, in nature, of thermal clocks that do not behave as relativistic clocks, and about the consequent nonequivalence between ther- mal and relativistic time, in the light of the thermal time hypothesis; 5) reflections about the operational definition of cosmic time in relation to the physical processes, then to the clocks that can be used for measuring it; arXiv:1808.09980v2 [physics.gen-ph] 2 Sep 2018 6) conclusive remarks about the need of a revision and a consequent refounda- tion of the concept of time in physics.
    [Show full text]
  • About the Conventionality of Simultaneity and Synchronization
    20th IMEKO TC4 International Symposium and 18th International Workshop on ADC Modelling and Testing Research on Electric and Electronic Measurement for the Economic Upturn Benevento, Italy, September 15-17, 2014 About the conventionality of simultaneity and synchronization Luigi Maxmilian Caligiuri1, Alfonso Nastro2 1 Department of Chemistry and Chemical Technology, University of Calabria, Arcavacata di Rende (CS), Italy, [email protected] FoPRC – Foundation of Physics Research Center, Celico (CS), Italy, [email protected] 2 Department of Chemistry and Chemical Technology, University of Calabria, Arcavacata di Rende (CS), Italy, [email protected] Abstract – The conceptual and operative definition of possible inertial frames [1], whose origin is substantially simultaneity is fundamental not only from a purely “electrodynamics” because it describes a specific theoretical point of view but also in order to ensure property of light arising from Maxwell equations and it is the correctness of metrological practices, because of not required by the internal consistence of STR itself [1]. its implication upon synchronization procedures. In It has been shown, in fact, that it is possible, by this paper we’ll critically analyze the main possible considering only homogeneity of empty space and time definitions of simultaneity, discussing the consequence and the Relativity Principle (RP), to build “alternative” of each of them upon the synchronization process and versions of Special Theory of Relativity (STR), without how the choice of the right method is far from assuming the invariance of light velocity in vacuum [1]. obvious. When these alternatives are considered they give rise to different conceptual and operative versions of definition I.
    [Show full text]
  • The Epistemology of Measurement: a Model-Based Account
    The Epistemology of Measurement: A Model-Based Account by Eran Tal A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © Copyright by Eran Tal 2012 The Epistemology of Measurement: A Model-Based Account Eran Tal, Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, University of Toronto, 2012 Thesis abstract Measurement is an indispensable part of physical science as well as of commerce, industry, and daily life. Measuring activities appear unproblematic when performed with familiar instruments such as thermometers and clocks, but a closer examination reveals a host of epistemological questions, including: 1. How is it possible to tell whether an instrument measures the quantity it is intended to? 2. What do claims to measurement accuracy amount to, and how might such claims be justified? 3. When is disagreement among instruments a sign of error, and when does it imply that instruments measure different quantities? Currently, these questions are almost completely ignored by philosophers of science, who view them as methodological concerns to be settled by scientists. This dissertation shows that these questions are not only philosophically worthy, but that their exploration has the potential to challenge fundamental assumptions in philosophy of science, including the distinction between measurement and prediction. ii The thesis outlines a model-based epistemology of physical measurement and uses it to address the questions above. To measure, I argue, is to estimate the value of a parameter in an idealized model of a physical process. Such estimation involves inference from the final state (‘indication’) of a process to the value range of a parameter (‘outcome’) in light of theoretical and statistical assumptions.
    [Show full text]