EEG) Based Neurofeedback Training for Brain- Computer Interface (BCI)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

EEG) Based Neurofeedback Training for Brain- Computer Interface (BCI) Title Electroencephalography (EEG) based neurofeedback training for brain- computer interface (BCI) Kyuwan Choi Rutgers University Psychology Department; Computational Biomedicine Imaging and Modeling, Computer Science Rutgers University Psychology Department (Busch Campus) 152 Frelinghuysen Rd. Piscataway, NJ 08854 1 Abstract Electroencephalography (EEG) has become a popular tool in basic brain research, but in recent years several practical limitations have been highlighted. Some of the drawbacks pertain to the offline analyses of the neural signal that prevent the subjects from engaging in real-time error correction during learning. Other limitations include the complex nature of the visual stimuli, often inducing fatigue and introducing considerable delays, possibly interfering with spontaneous performance. By replacing the complex external visual input with internally driven motor imagery we can overcome some delay problems, at the expense of losing the ability to precisely parameterize features of the input stimulus. To address these issues we here introduce a non-trivial modification to Brain Computer Interfaces (BCI). We combine the fast signal processing of motor imagery with the ability to parameterize external visual feedback in the context of a very simple control task: attempting to intentionally control the direction of an external cursor on command. By engaging the subject in motor imagery while providing real- time visual feedback on their instantaneous performance, we can take advantage of positive features present in both externally- and internally-driven learning. We further use a classifier that automatically selects the cortical activation features that most likely maximize the performance accuracy. Under this closed loop co-adaptation system we saw a progression of the cortical activation that started in sensory-motor areas, when at chance performance motor imagery was explicitly used, migrated to BA6 under deliberate control and ended in the more frontal regions of prefrontal cortex, when at maximal performance accuracy, the subjects reportedly developed spontaneous mental control of the instructed direction. We discuss our results in light of possible applications of this simple BCI paradigm to study various cognitive phenomena involving the deliberate control of a directional signal in decision making tasks performed with intent. Index terms- EEG, Brain plasticity, Neurofeedback training, Motor imagery 2 Introduction Current experimental paradigms using electroencephalography (EEG) as a tool for basic research in cognitive and psychological sciences suffer from a speed and accuracy tradeoff (Stomrud et al. 2010;Liu et al. 2008). The use of external visual signals has several advantageous features. One of them is the ability to harness Evoked Related Potentials (ERP’s) in response to rich visual input of abstract cognitive content whereby the external input can be precisely parameterized to help infer correlations between the neural signal and the stimulus’ features. However visual signal processing is much too slow to allow for fast, spontaneous performance (Maunsell and Gibson 1992). The complex signal also induces eye strain, compounded with habituation effects. The latter are mostly due to long experimental sessions, necessary to average the noisy output over many repeats and extract the signal. An example of visually driven settings is the use of the P300 as steady state visually evoked potentials (SSVEPs). There, the ERP’s decrease over time and the quality of the signal to control an external device using BCI tends to degrade (Wolpaw et al. 2002; Serby et al. 2005; He et al. 2010). The habituation factor and the increase in the noise to signal ratios introduce considerable delays that reach timescales visual awareness. Such delays interfere with the subject’s ability to spontaneously adapt the neural-feedback signal and attain real time control of the external device. Experiments that use SSVEP have recognized that subjects also tend to feel eye fatigue and even admit to the risk of inducing epilepsy (Middendorf et al. 2000; Wang et al. 2006). Experimental paradigms using internally driven motor imagery offer some advantages over externally driven ERP’s (Choi 2012). Motor imagery does not require visual search, so eye straining is not a problem. Users can engage in motor imagery for long periods of time and the response signal is immediate. In this context the subjects are unaware of explicit delays between the imagined command and the performance outcome, both attained under latencies that would enable them to attempt the mental control of an external device in real time. However, the motor imagery paradigm also has some drawbacks: (1) accuracy is not as high because a large part of the internal stimuli has to be inferred and cannot be parameterized, (2) it takes longer to train the participant, and (3) a large number of participants cannot control a BCI device through motor imagery alone, even upon training over an extended period of time. Most BCI studies using motor imagery do offline analysis of the cortical activation with an eye for cortical regions that are well known for certain functions (Ramoser et al. 2000; Li et al. 2010). Because the analysis of the signal is off-line and pre-determined in phrenology-like fashion, the 3 participants have no way of knowing whether the motor imagery that they engaged into helped or hindered their performance. The experimenter can also potentially miss neural information from non-targeted cortical areas that may be of relevance for a given context. In general under such off-line and a priori determined settings subjects cannot engage in error-correction loops to try and adapt their motor imagery to eventually exert control over the external device. We propose in this study a simple paradigm that combines visual feedback from the subject’s real-time performance with motor imagery in closed loop so as to engage the subject in a co- adaptation process between the external performance and the internal cortical signal. By relying on the internally driven motor imagery we overcome the delays imposed by the visual processing of complex visual imagery. Motor imagery enables us to provide immediate on-line feedback of the performance based on 125ms sliding window of brain activation. Such a continuous, fast-processing window permits the spontaneous co-adaptation between the neural signal and the instantaneous visual feedback of the desired external cursor direction because the subject is unaware of processing and transmission delays, thus avoiding the types of interference that emerge in the abovementioned SSEVP setups. Lastly, although we cannot entirely parameterize the internal motor imagery, we can track the neural activation across all 64 channels and automatically select the features that maximize performance accuracy. In this way, instead of a priori harnessing the neural signal from pre-defined areas, we let a Bayesian sparse probit classifying algorithm automatically select the regions with highest activation to solve this specific intentional task. We discuss the results of employing this non-trivial modification of the BCI settings in the context of possible usage for future basic research in the cognitive and psychological sciences with translational value for clinical use. Materials and Methods Overview The EEG signal mainly reflects the superposition of the electrical activity created by the ionic charge oscillation due to postsynaptic potentials of neocortical pyramidal cells (Nunez 1995; Nunez and Silberstein 2000). Thus, a large population of neurons beneath an electrode is superimposed to the measureable EEG but relatively little spatial information can be derived from a single channel of EEG. To overcome these problems, studies estimating source currents from EEG channel signals have been steadily conducted in the BCI community. Congedo et al. (Congedo et al. 2004) constructed the first LORETA (low-resolution electromagnetic 4 tomography) tomographic neurofeedback system using source current estimation and conducted a study enhancing the low beta (16-20 Hz) and suppressing the low alpha (8-10 Hz) component of the anterior cingulate cognitive division (ACcd) which is related to attention process. Grave de Peralta Menendez et al. (Grave de Peralta Menendez et al. 2005) introduced a source reconstruction method into an existing motor imagery based BCI field. By using the ELECTRA inverse solution (Grave de Peralta Menendez et al. 2000), they demonstrated the utility of the source reconstruction. Qin et al. (Qin et al. 2004) used single-equivalent-dipole model, and Kamousi et al. (Kamousi et al. 2005) employed two-equivalent-dipole model to classify left and right hand motor imagery. They obtained about 80 % accuracy on it. Furthermore, the use of motor imagery proved useful when Noirhomme et al. (Noirhomme et al. 2008) reconstructed the sources of 400 dipoles and classified motor imagery using frequency power change and Bereitshaft potential as the features. In the present study, source currents over 2,240 vertexes were estimated from EEG signals of 64 channels through a hierarchical Bayesian method introducing a hierarchical prior (Sato et al. 2004; Batenburg et al. 1994) that can effectively incorporate both structural and functional MRI data. In this hierarchical Bayesian method, the variance of the source current at each source location is considered an unknown parameter and estimated from the observed EEG data. Prior information is
Recommended publications
  • Things and Places the Jean Nicod Lectures Franc¸Ois Recanati, Editor
    Things and Places The Jean Nicod Lectures Franc¸ois Recanati, editor The Elm and the Expert: Mentalese and Its Semantics, Jerry A. Fodor (1994) Naturalizing the Mind, Fred Dretske (1995) Strong Feelings: Emotion, Addiction, and Human Behavior, Jon Elster (1999) Knowledge, Possibility, and Consciousness, John Perry (2001) Rationality in Action, John R. Searle (2001) Varieties of Meaning, Ruth Garrett Millikan (2004) Sweet Dreams: Philosophical Obstacles to a Science of Consciousness, Daniel C. Dennett (2005) Reliable Reasoning: Induction and Statistical Learning Theory, Gilbert Harman and Sanjeev Kulkarni (2007) Things and Places: How the Mind Connects with the World, Zenon W. Pylyshyn (2007) Things and Places How the Mind Connects with the World Zenon W. Pylyshyn A Bradford Book The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England ( 2007 Massachusetts Institute of Technology All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form by any elec- tronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or information storage and retrieval) without permission in writing from the publisher. MIT Press books may be purchased at special quantity discounts for business or sales promotional use. For information, please e-mail [email protected] or write to Special Sales Department, The MIT Press, 55 Hayward Street, Cambridge, MA 02142. This book was set in Stone Serif and Stone Sans on 3B2 by Asco Typesetters, Hong Kong, and was printed and bound in the United States of America. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Pylyshyn, Zenon W. Things and places : how the mind connects with the world / by Zenon W. Pylyshyn. p. cm.—(The Jean Nicod lectures) ‘‘A Bradford book.’’ Includes bibliographical references and indexes.
    [Show full text]
  • Author Title 1 ? Mennyi? Szamok a Termeszetben 2 A. DAVID REDISH
    Author Title 1 ? Mennyi? Szamok a termeszetben 2 A. DAVID REDISH. BEYOND THE COGNITIVE MAP : FROM PLACE CELLS TO EPISODIC MEMORY 3 Aaron C.T.Smith Cognitive mechanisms of belief change 4 Aaron L.Berkowitz The improvising mind: cognition and creativity in the musical moment 5 AARON L.BERKOWITZ. THE IMPROVISING MIND : COGNITION AND CREATIVITY IN THE MUSICAL MOMENT 6 AARON T. BECK. COGNITIVE THERAPY AND THE EMOTIONAL DISORDERS 7 Aaron Williamon Musical excellence: strategies and techniques to enhance performance 8 AIDAN FEENEY, EVAN HEIT. INDUCTIVE REASONING : EXPERIMENTAL, DEVELOPMENTAL, AND COMPUTATIONAL APPROACHES 9 Alain F. Zuur, Elena N. Ieno, Erik H.W.G.Meesters A beginner`s guide to R 10 Alain F. Zuur, Elena N. Ieno, Erik H.W.G.Meesters A beginner`s guide to R 11 ALAN BADDELEY, Michael W. EYSENCK, AND Michael MEMORYC. ANDERSON. 12 ALAN GILCHRIST. SEEING BLACK AND WHITE 13 Alan Merriam The anthropology of music RYTHMES ET CHAOS DANS LES SYSTEMES BIOCHIMIQUES ET CELLULAIRES. ENGLISH. BIOCHEMICAL 14 ALBERT GOLDBETER OSCILLATIONS AND CELLULAR RHYTHMS : THE MOLECULAR BASES OF PERIODIC AND CHAOTIC BEHAVIOUR 15 Albert S Bregman Auditory scene analysis: the perceptual organization of sound 16 Albert-Laszlo Barabasi Network Science 17 Alda Mari, Claire Beyssade, Fabio del Prete Genericity 18 Alex Mesoudi Cultural Evolution: how Darwinian theory can explain human culture and synthesize the social sciences 19 Alexander Easton The cognitive neuroscience of social behaviour. 20 ALEXANDER TODOROV Face Value the irresistible influence of first impression 21 ALEXANDER TODOROV, Susan T. FISKE & DEBORAHSOCIAL PRENTICE. NEUROSCIENCE : TOWARD UNDERSTANDING THE UNDERPINNINGS OF THE SOCIAL MIND 22 ALEXANDRA HOROWITZ INSIDE OF A DOG : WHAT DOGS SEE, SMELL, AND KNOW 23 Alfred Blatter Revisiting music theory: a guide to the practice 24 Alison Gopnik Bolcsek a bolcsoben: hogyan gondolkodnak a kisbabak 25 Alison Gopnik A babak filozofiaja 26 ANDREW DUCHOWSKI EYE TRACKING METHODOLOGY : THEORY AND PRACTICE 27 Andrew Gelman Bayesian Data Analysis 28 ANDREW GELMAN ..
    [Show full text]
  • (CGE Marcoussis), G. Huet
    The FINITE STRING Newsletter Announcements Announcements The Program Committe consists of: James Allen, Norm Badler, Mike Bauer, Wayne Davis, Mark Fox, Bill Havens, Hector Levesque, Charles Morgan, John NELS Meeting and Workshop Mylopoulos, Zenon Pylyshyn, Reid Smith, and Doug The Twelfth Annual Meeting of the North-Eastern Skuce. The Proceedings Editor is Brian Funt. Linguistic Society will be held November 6-8, 1981, at Correspondence should be addressed to: the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Plans are Gordon McCalla, General Chairman also being made to hold a workshop immediately be- CSCSI/SCEIO Conference fore the Meeting on the topic "Free Word-Order and Department of Computational Science Syntactic Configuration". Questions to be addressed University of Saskatchewan at the workshop include: what are the functions of Saskatoon, Sask. CANADA S7N 0W0 word-order in syntax and semantics? what degrees of freedom are there of word-order? how should the Nick Cercone, Program Chairman different functions and degrees of word-order be ex- CSCSI/SCEIO Conference pressed within a theory of universal grammar? Computing Science Department Simon Fraser University For further information contact: Burnaby, B.C. CANADA V5A 1S6 NELS Committee Department of Linguistics and Philosophy M.I.T., 20C-128 ECAI-82: Call for Papers Cambridge, Massachusetts 02139 The 1982 European Conference on Artificial Intel- ligence will be held July 12-14, 1982, in Orsay, France CSCSI/SCEIO: Call for Papers (just after COLING-82). The conference is sponsored by the Society for the Study of Artificial Intelligence The Fourth National Conference of the Canadian and the Simulation of Behavior (AISB), and succeeds Society for Computational Studies of Intelligence/ to the AISB meetings on Artificial Intelligence held at Soci6t6 Canadienne pour Etudes d'intelligence par Brighton (1974), Edinburgh (1976), Hamburg (1978), Ordinateur will be held at the University of Saskatche- and Amsterdam (1980).
    [Show full text]
  • Things and Places: How the Mind Connects with the World
    Things and Places: How the Mind Connects With the World Zenon W. Pylyshyn Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science Forthcoming, 2007, MIT Press (Jean Nicod Lecture Series) i 11/26/2006 Table of contents Preface & Acknowledgements Chapter 1. Introduction to the Problem: Connecting Perception and the World 1.1 Background 1.2 What’s the problem of connecting the mind with the world? Doesn’t every computational theory of vision do that ? 1.3 The need for a direct way of referring to certain individual tokens in a scene 1.3.1 Incremental construction of representations (and a brief sketch of FINSTs) 1.3.2 Using descriptions to pick out individuals 1.3.3 The need for demonstrative reference in perception 1.4 Some empirical phenomena illustrating the role of Indexes 1.4.1 Tagging/marking individual objects for attentional priority 1.4.2 Argument binding 1.4.3 Subitizing 1.4.4 Subset selection 1.5 What are we to make of such empirical demonstrations? Chapter 2. Indexing and tracking individuals 2.1 Individuating and tracking 2.2 Indexes and primitive tracking 2.3 What goes on in MOT? 2.3.1 FINSTs and Object Files 2.3.2 The explanation of tracking 2.4 Other empirical and theoretical issues surrounding MOT 2.4.1 Do we track by keeping a record of locations? 2.4.2 Can we select objects voluntarily? 2.4.3 Tracking without keeping track of labels 2.4.4 Nonconceptual individuation without reference? 2.5 Infants capacity for individuating and tracking objects 2.6 Summary and Implications for the Foundations of Cognitive Science 2.6.1 Review: Nonconceptual functions and Natural Constraints 2.6.2 Summary: Why are FINSTs needed? Chapter 3.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE John Bickle December 2020
    CURRICULUM VITAE John Bickle December 2020 Mailing Address: Department of Philosophy and Religion P.O. Box JS Mississippi State University Mississippi State, MS 39762 (662) 325-2382 fax: (662) 325-3340 E-mail Addresses: [email protected] URLs: http://www.philosophyandreligion.msstate.edu/faculty/bickle.php https://www.umc.edu/Education/Schools/Medicine/Basic_Science/Neurobiology/John_Bi ckle,_PhD.aspx ___________________________________________________________________________ CURRENT ACADEMIC POSITIONS Professor (Tenured) of Philosophy Mississippi State University Affiliate Faculty Department of Neurobiology and Anatomical Sciences University of Mississippi Medical Center EDUCATION B.A. University of California, Los Angeles, June 1983 M.A., Ph.D. University of California, Irvine, June 1989 Field: Philosophy; Scientific Concentration: Neurobiology. Doctoral Dissertation: Toward a Scientific Reformulation of the Mind-Body Problem AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION Philosophy of Neuroscience, Philosophy of Science (especially Scientific Reductionism), Cellular and Molecular Mechanisms of Cognition and Consciousness AREAS OF COMPETENCE Moral Psychology and the Moral Virtues, Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI). Logical Positivism (especially the Philosophy of Rudolph Carnap), Libertarian Political Philosophy ______________________________________________________________________________ PROFESSIONAL PUBLICATIONS (94) BOOKS (4) 2014 Engineering the Next Revolution in Neuroscience. (Co-authors: Alcino J. Silva and Anthony Landreth).
    [Show full text]
  • Pylyshyn: Mental Imagery
    BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2002) 25, 157–238 Printed in the United States of America Mental imagery: In search of a theory Zenon W. Pylyshyn Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science, Rutgers University, Busch Campus, Piscataway, NJ 08854-8020. [email protected] http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/faculty/pylyshyn.html Abstract: It is generally accepted that there is something special about reasoning by using mental images. The question of how it is spe- cial, however, has never been satisfactorily spelled out, despite more than thirty years of research in the post-behaviorist tradition. This article considers some of the general motivation for the assumption that entertaining mental images involves inspecting a picture-like object. It sets out a distinction between phenomena attributable to the nature of mind to what is called the cognitive architecture, and ones that are attributable to tacit knowledge used to simulate what would happen in a visual situation. With this distinction in mind, the paper then considers in detail the widely held assumption that in some important sense images are spatially displayed or are depictive, and that examining images uses the same mechanisms that are deployed in visual perception. I argue that the assumption of the spatial or depictive nature of images is only explanatory if taken literally, as a claim about how images are physically instantiated in the brain, and that the literal view fails for a number of empirical reasons – for example, because of the cognitive penetrability of the phenomena cited in its favor. Similarly, while it is arguably the case that imagery and vision involve some of the same mechanisms, this tells us very little about the nature of mental imagery and does not support claims about the pictorial nature of mental images.
    [Show full text]
  • Return of the Mental Image: Are There Really Pictures in the Brain?
    Opinion TRENDS in Cognitive Sciences Vol.7 No.3 March 2003 113 Return of the mental image: are there really pictures in the brain? Zenon Pylyshyn Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science, Rutgers University, New Brunswick, NJ 08903, USA In the past decade there has been renewed interest in The picture theory of mental images the study of mental imagery. Emboldened by new find- Despite the problem of stating clearly what it means for ings from neuroscience, many people have revived the imagistic thought to be pictorial, claims that mental idea that mental imagery involves a special format of images have a special picture-like (or depictive) format thought, one that is pictorial in nature. But the evidence have persisted. One of the few explicit statements and the arguments that exposed deep conceptual and concerning what this means ([3], p. 5), defines a depictive empirical problems in the picture theory over the past representation as ‘…a type of picture, which specifies the 300 years have not gone away. I argue that the new locations and values of configurations of points in a space. evidence from neural imaging and clinical neuro- … [in which] each part of an object is represented by a psychology does little to justify this recidivism because pattern of points, and the spatial relation among these it does not address the format of mental images. I also patterns… correspond to the spatial relations among the discuss some reasons why the picture theory is so parts themselves.’ For obvious reasons I refer to such resistant to counterarguments and suggest ways in theories as ‘picture theories’.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE Brian Patrick Keane October 2020
    CURRICULUM VITAE Brian Patrick Keane October 2020 University of Rochester Medical Center www.keanelab.com Department of Psychiatry ORCID: 0000-0002-7011-3380 601 Elmwood Avenue, Box 603 [email protected] Rochester, NY 14642 Twitter: @BrianKeaneLab ACADEMIC APPOINTMENTS University of Rochester, Rochester, NY. • Asst. Professor of Psychiatry with a secondary appointment in Neuroscience (tenure track), 2/2020 – present, University of Rochester Medical Center. • Member, Center for Visual Science, 6/2020 – present, University of Rochester. Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey, Piscataway, NJ • Asst. Professor of Psychiatry (tenure track), 3/2015 – 1/2020, Robert Wood Johnson Medical School. • Research Associate, 11/2011 – 3/2015, University Behavioral Health Care. • Postdoctoral Fellow, 10/2009 – 10/2011, University Behavioral Health Care, Center for Cognitive Science. EDUCATION University of California, Los Angeles, CA from 2004–2009 (degree awarded 12/2009). Doctor of Philosophy: Psychology. Dissertation: Beyond phenomenological connectedness: Functional consequences of filling-in during contour interpolation. Committee: Philip Kellman (Chair), Hongjing Lu, Dario Ringach, Ladan Shams, Joaquin Fuster (outside). Rutgers University, New Brunswick, NJ from 1999–2004 (degree awarded 05/2006). Doctor of Philosophy: Philosophy. Certificate in Cognitive Science. Dissertation: Visual objects: Philosophical and cognitive science perspectives. Committee: Brian McLaughlin (Chair), Zenon Pylyshyn, Jerry Fodor, Alvin Goldman. University of Pittsburgh, PA, University Honors College, from 1995–1999 (degrees awarded 08/1999). Bachelor of Arts, Triple Major: Physics & Astronomy, Spanish, Philosophy (Intensive). Bachelor of Philosophy: Philosophy. Thesis: Constructive empiricism and minimal epistemic realism: A critical comparison. Advisors: Wesley Salmon and John Earman. G.P.A.: 3.85/4.00. RESEARCH INTERESTS • Visual perceptual abnormalities in schizophrenia: contour grouping and 3D shape perception deficits.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Vision Continuous with Cognition? the Case for Cognitive Impenetrability of Visual Perception
    BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1999) 22, 341–423 Printed in the United States of America Is vision continuous with cognition? The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception Zenon Pylyshyn Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science, Rutgers University, New Brunswick, NJ 08903 [email protected] ruccs.rutgers.edu/faculty/pylyshyn.html Abstract: Although the study of visual perception has made more progress in the past 40 years than any other area of cognitive science, there remain major disagreements as to how closely vision is tied to cognition. This target article sets out some of the arguments for both sides (arguments from computer vision, neuroscience, psychophysics, perceptual learning, and other areas of vision science) and defends the position that an important part of visual perception, corresponding to what some people have called early vision, is prohibited from accessing relevant expectations, knowledge, and utilities in determining the function it computes – in other words, it is cognitively im- penetrable. That part of vision is complex and involves top-down interactions that are internal to the early vision system. Its function is to provide a structured representation of the 3-D surfaces of objects sufficient to serve as an index into memory, with somewhat differ- ent outputs being made available to other systems such as those dealing with motor control. The paper also addresses certain concep- tual and methodological issues raised by this claim, such as whether signal detection theory and event-related potentials can be used to assess cognitive penetration of vision. A distinction is made among several stages in visual processing, including, in addition to the inflexible early-vision stage, a pre-per- ceptual attention-allocation stage and a post-perceptual evaluation, selection, and inference stage, which accesses long-term memory.
    [Show full text]
  • Visual Indexes and Nonconceptual Reference1
    Notes for the NYU Language and Mind Seminar: Please do not quote (I reserve the right to change my mind!) Visual Indexes and Nonconceptual Reference1 Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science (Notes for NYU’s Language and Mind Seminar, March 2, 2004) First a little historical background Just as Moliere's Monsieur Jourdain discovered that he had been speaking prose all his life without realizing it, so I discovered not too long ago that what I had been doing without realizing it occupied a position in the philosophical landscape. It turns out that coming from a very different perspective I had taken a position on a set of questions that philosophers had been worrying about for much of the past 30 or more years. My clandestine involvement in philosophical issues began when a computer science colleague and I were trying to build a model of geometrical reasoning that would draw a diagram and notice things in the diagram as it drew it [1]. One problem we found we had to face was that if the system discovered a right angle it had no way to tell whether this was the intersection of certain lines it had drawn earlier, and if so which particular lines. Moreover, the model had no way of telling whether this particular right angle was identical to some bit of drawing it had earlier encountered and represented as, say, the base of a particular triangle. There was, in other words, no way to determined the identity of an element (I will use this neutral term until I discuss what qualifies as an element) at two different times if it was represented differently at those times.
    [Show full text]
  • Semantic Properties and the Computational Model of Mind
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1990 Semantic properties and the computational model of mind. Randall K. Campbell University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Campbell, Randall K., "Semantic properties and the computational model of mind." (1990). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2062. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2062 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. UMASS/AMHERST 312Qt,bQ13S7t.lDS S) (j DATE DUE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS AT AMHERST LD 3234 M267 1990 C1895 SEMANTIC PROPERTIES AND THE COMPUTATIONAL MODEL OF MIND A Dissertation Presented by RANDALL K, CAMPBELL Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY September 1990 Department of Philosophy Copyright by (7) Randall K. Campbell 1990 All Rights Reserved SEMANTIC PROPERTIES AND THE COMPUTATIONAL MODEL OF MIND A Dissertation Presented by RANDALL K. CAMPBELL Approved as to style and content by: Gareth Matthews, Chair Bruce Aune, Member Fred Feldman, Member Neil Stillings, Member! ABSTRACT
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Systematicity
    Systematicity: An Overview John Symons1 and Paco Calvo2 1 University of Kansas 2 Universidad de Murcia Introduction In 1988 Jerry Fodor and Zenon Pylyshyn published “Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis.” Their article presented a forceful and highly influential criticism of the explanatory relevance of neural network models of cognition. At the time, connectionism was reemerging as a popular and exciting new field of research, but according to Fodor and Pylyshyn, the approach rested on a flawed model of the human mind. Connectionism is the view that the mind can be understood in terms of an interconnected network of simple mechanisms. Its proponents contend that cognitive and behavioral properties can be modeled and explained in terms of their emergence from the collective behavior of simple interacting and adaptive mechanisms. According to Fodor and Pylyshyn, connectionist approaches neglect an essential feature of thought – its systematic nature. On their view, the basic psychological fact that thoughts are intrinsically related to some other thoughts in systematic ways becomes inexplicable if one denies that representations are structured in a syntactically and semantically classical combinatorial manner. 1 Connectionism, they argued, inevitably fails to provide a meaningful explanation of cognition insofar as it confuses the intrinsically systematic nature of thought with a system of associations.2 Connectionism might shed some light on the way that cognitive architectures happen to be implemented in brains, but the explanation of cognition does not take place at the level of biology or hardware. A cognitive architecture must be systematic to the core in order to shed light on the intrinsically systematic character of cognition.
    [Show full text]