DISCIPLINE FILOSOFICHE Anno XXV, Numero 1, 2015

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

DISCIPLINE FILOSOFICHE Anno XXV, Numero 1, 2015 DISCIPLINE FILOSOFICHE Anno XXV, numero 1, 2015 Quodlibet DISCIPLINE FILOSOFICHE Anno XXV, numero 1, 2015 Rivista fondata da Enzo Melandri. Periodicità semestrale. Dipartimento di Filosofia e Aut. Tribunale di Macerata, n. 527/ Comunicazione stampa del 16. 12. 2005 ISSN: 1591-9625 Direttore Stefano Besoli Direttore responsabile Barnaba Maj Comitato scientifico Massimo Barale (Università di Pisa) †, Jocelyn Benoist (Université Paris-I Panthéon- Sorbonne), Giuseppe Cantillo (Università Federico II di Napoli), Jean-François Courtine (Université Paris-IV Sorbonne), Françoise Dastur (Université de Nice Sophia Antipolis), Roberta De Monticelli (Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele di Milano), Bianca Maria d’Ippolito (Università di Salerno) †, Massimo Ferrari (Università di Torino), Gottfried Gabriel (Friedrich Schiller Universität Jena), Gianna Gigliotti (Università Tor Vergata di Roma), Wolfhart Henckmann (Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München), Douglas Hofstadter (Indiana University), John Lachs (Vanderbilt University), Claudio La Rocca (Università di Genova), Eugenio Mazzarella (Università Federico II di Napoli), Ernst Wolfgang Orth (Universität Trier), Renato Pettoello (Università di Milano), Manfred Sommer (Christian-Albrechts-Universität Kiel), Jürgen Stolzenberg (Martin-Luther- Universität Halle-Wittenberg), Francesco Saverio Trincia (Università La Sapienza di Roma), Frédéric Worms (École normale supérieure – ENS , Paris) Comitato di redazione Simona Bertolini, Francesco Bianchini, Roberto Brigati, Vincenzo Costa, Roberto Frega, Sebastiano Galanti Grollo, Michele Gardini, Alberto Gualandi, Luca Guidetti, Barnaba Maj, Giuliana Mancuso, Marina Manotta, Emanuele Mariani, Riccardo Martinelli, Maurizio Matteuzzi, Giovanni Matteucci, Venanzio Raspa, Alessandro Salice, Luca Vanzago, Giorgio Volpe Direzione e redazione Dipartimento di Filosofia e Comunicazione, via Zamboni 38 - 40126 Bologna. Tel 051-2098344. Fax 051-2098355 E-mail Redazione: [email protected] Sito web: www.disciplinefilosofiche.it Copertina: Augusto Wirbel © Copyright 2015 Quodlibet ISBN: 9788874627998 Quodlibet edizioni, via Santa Maria della Porta, 43, 62100 Macerata tel. 0733-264965 fax 0733-267358 www.quodlibet.it; e-mail: [email protected] Finito di stampare nel mese di novembre 2015 dalla Grafica Editrice Romana s.r.l., Roma. Questa Rivista è stata pubblicata con un contributo di fondi R.F.O. dell’Ateneo di Bologna. I saggi che compaiono in questa rivista sono sottoposti a double-blind peer-review. Francesca Ervas, Elisabetta Gola, Antonio Ledda and Giuseppe Sergioli Lexical Ambiguity in Elementary Inferences: an Experimental Study Abstract In this paper we discuss how common meaning ambiguities (homonymy, poly- semy and metaphors) influence the understanding of an elementary argument. In order to understand how, and to what extent, participants’ intuitions on the strength of a syllogism are influenced by meaning ambiguities, we present the results of a pilot study. The study specifically focuses on a fallacy of lexical ambiguity, where the meanings of the middle term diverge in the two premises. We hypothe- size that the evaluation of the strength of an argument of this sort is related to the nature of the ambiguity of its middle term and to the pragmatic process required to disambiguate the ambiguous meanings. We expect the persuasiveness of the syllo- gism to be directly proportional to the degree of semantic superposition of the meanings of the middle term. Keywords : Metaphor, Quaternio terminorum, Lexical ambiguity, Argumenta- tion. 1. Introduction In the informal logic tradition, fallacies are common errors of reasoning (Sergioli 2015). As it has been pointed out, “studies of fallacies in argumen- tation and informal logic have mainly taken a normative approach, by see- ing fallacies as arguments that violate standards of how an argument should properly be used in rational thinking or arguing. However, fallacies also have a psychological dimension ” (Walton 2010, p. 159, our italics). In this perspective, fallacies are arguments that seem valid but are not (Hamblin 1970). In Max Black’s Critical Thinking , the definition of fallacy is tuned up: “A fallacy is an argument that seems to be sound without being so in fact. An argument is ‘sound’ for the purpose of this definition if the conclu- sion is reached by a reliable method and the premises are known to be true” (Black 1946, pp. 129-130, our italics). However little is said in a man- ner of explanation regarding the how and why of “seeming valid” or “seem- ing sound” (Hansen 2002). Introducing lexical fallacies, Cohen and Nagel suggested that “these all seem to conform to valid forms of inference, but on careful examination are seen not to do so the appearance being due to 150 FRANCESCA ERVAS , ELISABETTA GOLA , ANTONIO LEDDA AND GIUSEPPE SERGIOLI an ambiguity, that is, to the use of the same word or verbal sign for two dif- ferent terms” (1934, p. 376). In classical argumentation theory, metaphors usually lead to fallacies of reasoning (Sergioli and Ternullo 2014; Tindale 2006), by exacerbating problems of ambiguity (Barnden 2012; Camp 2006; Fischer 2015). A sen- tence where a metaphor occurs is literally false.1 However, the context of its usage might create a perception that it is true, or at least plausible. From a literal point of view a metaphor is false, but from a non-literal point of view it may appear plausible. Fischer (2015) argues that a range of varied disci- plines have demonstrated the productive usage of metaphors in deductive reasoning: physics (Hesse 1996), biology (Keller 1995), psychology (Gentner and Grudin 1985) and problem solving (Keefer et al. 2014; Thibodeau and Boroditsky 2011). At the same time, metaphors are gov- erned by heuristic rules that never guarantee the preservation of truth, thus giving rise to systematic fallacies (Fischer 2011, 2014). This might be the reason why metaphors are highly persuasive by nature. Thus, the persua- siveness of an argument would eventually be influenced by the presence of metaphors. Following this intuition, we aim to understand the effect of metaphors in arguments with the structure of a quaternio terminorum, sometimes re- ferred to as four term fallacy , where the nature of the middle term plays a fundamental role and might influence its persuasive strength. Quaternio terminorum relies on the intrinsic ambiguity of the middle term, which is used in the premises with two different meanings. The middle term can be ambiguous either because the term has two different literal meanings (the case of homonymy and polysemy ), or because it has both a literal and a non- literal meaning (the case of lexicalized metaphor and live metaphor ). We claim that the persuasiveness of an argument varies as the ambiguity of the middle term moves through such a spectrum. In order to test our claim on a real representative sample, we set up an experimental design. Usually, argumentation theory does not employ an experimental approach and relies on a priori notions, according to which figurative language renders premises literally false and the overall argument unsound. However, an experimental approach may tell us something more about argumentation in common language and the divergences between speakers’ and scholars’ intuitions on the strength of arguments – in particu- 1 In this paper we will be exclusively concerned with literally false metaphors. However, it should be observed that there are cases of twice-true (Cohen 1976, p. 254) and twice-apt (Hills 1997, p. 130) metaphors, such as “No man is an island” and “George Bush is a primate”. See Camp (2008) for an extensive discussion. LEXICAL AMBIGUITY IN ELEMENTARY INFERENCES 151 lar, on the reason why a fallacious argument may appear strong, even if it is not. More specifically, the results of this study indicate a consistency be- tween the psychological and the normative aspects (Walton 2010; Tversky and Kahneman 1974) of quaternio terminorum. The semantic intuitions leading to the disambiguation of the middle terms allow participants to cor- rectly evaluate the arguments. This is so with participants bearing no specif- ic training in logic nor in argumentation theory. Interestingly, this con- sistency seems to weaken in case of metaphors as middle terms. This is per- haps due to the fact that the presence of metaphors renders natural lan- guage ambiguous. The structure of the paper is the following. In the first section we pro- vide the basic notions required to define quaternio terminorum and clarify the different pragmatic phenomena involved in the gamut of lexical ambi- guities. In the second section we present the experimental design of a pilot study that aims to understand whether, and to what extent, lexical ambigui- ty influences the persuasiveness of a quaternio terminorum. In the third section we present the methodology of the experimental study and describe the participants involved, either in the norming or the pilot study, the mate- rials that were presented to them and the procedure that was followed. In the fourth section we present the results of the experimental study. Finally, in the fifth section we discuss the results in the light of the aims of the over- all paper. 1.1. Basic notions In order to keep the paper self-contained, we introduce in this section all the required basic notions from argumentation theory and lexical prag- matics. 1.1.1. Argumentation theory A sentence is a declarative statement to which a truth-value (true or false), in classical logic, can be assigned
Recommended publications
  • Western Logic Formal & Informal Fallacy Types of 6 Fallacies
    9/17/2021 Western Logic Formal & Informal Fallacy Types of 6 Fallacies- Examrace Examrace Western Logic Formal & Informal Fallacy Types of 6 Fallacies Get unlimited access to the best preparation resource for competitive exams : get questions, notes, tests, video lectures and more- for all subjects of your exam. Western Logic - Formal & Informal Fallacy: Types of 6 Fallacies (Philosophy) Fallacy When an argument fails to support its conclusion, that argument is termed as fallacious in nature. A fallacious argument is hence an erroneous argument. In other words, any error or mistake in an argument leads to a fallacy. So, the definition of fallacy is any argument which although seems correct but has an error committed in its reasoning. Hence, a fallacy is an error; a fallacious argument is an argument which has erroneous reasoning. In the words of Frege, the analytical philosopher, “it is a logician՚s task to identify the pitfalls in language.” Hence, logicians are concerned with the task of identifying fallacious arguments in logic which are also called as incorrect or invalid arguments. There are numerous fallacies but they are classified under two main heads; Formal Fallacies Informal Fallacies Formal Fallacies Formal fallacies are those mistakes or errors which occur in the form of the argument. In other words, formal fallacies concern themselves with the form or the structure of the argument. Formal fallacies are present when there is a structural error in a deductive argument. It is important to note that formal fallacies always occur in a deductive argument. There are of six types; Fallacy of four terms: A valid syllogism must contain three terms, each of which should be used in the same sense throughout; else it is a fallacy of four terms.
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER XXX. of Fallacies. Section 827. After Examining the Conditions on Which Correct Thoughts Depend, It Is Expedient to Clas
    CHAPTER XXX. Of Fallacies. Section 827. After examining the conditions on which correct thoughts depend, it is expedient to classify some of the most familiar forms of error. It is by the treatment of the Fallacies that logic chiefly vindicates its claim to be considered a practical rather than a speculative science. To explain and give a name to fallacies is like setting up so many sign-posts on the various turns which it is possible to take off the road of truth. Section 828. By a fallacy is meant a piece of reasoning which appears to establish a conclusion without really doing so. The term applies both to the legitimate deduction of a conclusion from false premisses and to the illegitimate deduction of a conclusion from any premisses. There are errors incidental to conception and judgement, which might well be brought under the name; but the fallacies with which we shall concern ourselves are confined to errors connected with inference. Section 829. When any inference leads to a false conclusion, the error may have arisen either in the thought itself or in the signs by which the thought is conveyed. The main sources of fallacy then are confined to two-- (1) thought, (2) language. Section 830. This is the basis of Aristotle's division of fallacies, which has not yet been superseded. Fallacies, according to him, are either in the language or outside of it. Outside of language there is no source of error but thought. For things themselves do not deceive us, but error arises owing to a misinterpretation of things by the mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Stephen's Guide to the Logical Fallacies by Stephen Downes Is Licensed Under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike 2.5 Canada License
    Stephen’s Guide to the Logical Fallacies Stephen Downes This site is licensed under Creative Commons By-NC-SA Stephen's Guide to the Logical Fallacies by Stephen Downes is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike 2.5 Canada License. Based on a work at www.fallacies.ca. Permissions beyond the scope of this license may be available at http://www.fallacies.ca/copyrite.htm. This license also applies to full-text downloads from the site. Introduction ............................................................................................................................................ 3 How To Use This Guide ............................................................................................................................ 4 Fallacies of Distraction ........................................................................................................................... 44 Logical Operators............................................................................................................................... 45 Proposition ........................................................................................................................................ 46 Truth ................................................................................................................................................. 47 Conjunction ....................................................................................................................................... 48 Truth Table .......................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Tel Aviv University the Lester & Sally Entin Faculty of Humanities the Shirley & Leslie Porter School of Cultural Studies
    Tel Aviv University The Lester & Sally Entin Faculty of Humanities The Shirley & Leslie Porter School of Cultural Studies "Mischief … none knows … but herself": Intrigue and its Relation to the Drive in Late Seventeenth-Century Intrigue Drama Thesis Submitted for the Degree of "Doctor of Philosophy" by Zafra Dan Submitted to the Senate of Tel Aviv University October 2011 This work was carried out under the supervision of Professor Shirley Sharon-Zisser, Tel Aviv University and Professor Karen Alkalay-Gut, Tel Aviv University This thesis, this labor of love, would not have come into the world without the rigorous guidance, the faith and encouragement of my supervisors, Prof. Karen Alkalay-Gut and Prof. Shirley Sharon-Zisser. I am grateful to Prof. Sharon-Zisser for her Virgilian guidance into and through the less known, never to be taken for granted, labyrinths of Freudian and Lacanian thought and theory, as well as for her own ground-breaking contribution to the field of psychoanalysis through psycho-rhetoric. I am grateful to Prof. Alkalay-Gut for her insightful, inspiring yet challenging comments and questions, time and again forcing me to pause and rethink the relationship between the literary aspects of my research and psychoanalysis. I am grateful to both my supervisors for enabling me to explore a unique, newly blazed path to literary form, and rediscover thus late seventeenth-century drama. I wish to express my gratitude to Prof. Ruth Ronen for allowing me the use of the manuscript of her book Aesthetics of Anxiety before it was published. Her instructive work has been a source of enlightenment and inspiration in its own right.
    [Show full text]
  • Categorical Syllogism
    Unit 8 Categorical Syllogism What is a syllogism? Inference or reasoning is the process of passing from one or more propositions to another with some justification. This inference when expressed in language is called an argument. An argument consists of more than one proposition (premise and conclusion). The conclusion of an argument is the proposition that is affirmed on the basis of the other propositions of the argument. These other propositions which provide support or ground for the conclusion are called premises of the argument. Inferences have been broadly divided as deductive and inductive. A deductive argument makes the claim that its conclusion is supported by its premises conclusively. An inductive argument, in contrast, does not make such a claim. It claims to support its conclusion only with some degrees of probability. Deductive inferences are again divided into Immediate and Mediate. Immediate inference is a kind of deductive inference in which the conclusion follows from one premise only. In mediate inference, on the other hand, the conclusion follows from more them one premise. Where there are only two premises, and the conclusion follows from them jointly, it is called syllogism. A syllogism is a deductive argument in which a conclusion is inferred from two premises. The syllogisms with which we are concerned here are called categorical because they are arguments based on the categorical relations of classes or categories. Such relations are of three kinds. 1. The whole of one class may be included in the other class such as All dogs are mammals. 2. Some members of one class may be included in the other such as Some chess players are females.
    [Show full text]
  • Lexical Ambiguity in Elementary Inferences: an Experimental Study
    Lexical ambiguity in elementary inferences: an experimental study Francesca Ervas, Elisabetta Gola, Antonio Ledda, Giuseppe Sergioli (University of Cagliari) Abstract In this paper we discuss how common meaning ambiguities (homonymy, polysemy and metaphors) influence the understanding of an elementary argument. In order to understand how, and to what extent, participants’ intuitions on the strength of a syllogism are influenced by meaning ambiguities, we present the results of a pilot study. The study specifically focuses on a fallacy of lexical ambiguity, where the meanings of the middle term diverge in the two premises. We hypothesize that the evaluation of the strength of an argument of this sort is related to the nature of the ambiguity of its middle term and to the pragmatic process required to disambiguate the ambiguous meanings. We expect the persuasiveness of the syllogism to be directly proportional to the degree of semantic superposition of the meanings of the middle term. 1. Introduction In the informal logic tradition, fallacies are common errors of reasoning (Sergioli 2015). As it has been pointed out, «studies of fallacies in argumentation and informal logic have mainly taken a normative approach, by seeing fallacies as arguments that violate standards of how an argument should properly be used in rational thinking or arguing. However, fallacies also have a psychological dimension» (Walton 2010, p. 159, our italics). In this perspective, fallacies are arguments that seem valid but are not (Hamblin 1970). In Max Black’s Critical Thinking, the definition of fallacy is tuned up: «A fallacy is an argument that seems to be sound without being so in fact.
    [Show full text]
  • 6.4 Syllogistic Rules and Syllogistic Fallacies
    M06_COPI1396_13_SE_C06.QXD 10/16/07 9:17 PM Page 244 244 CHAPTER 6 Categorical Syllogisms 3. Some mammals are not horses, for no horses are centaurs, and all centaurs are mammals. 4. Some neurotics are not parasites, but all criminals are parasites; it follows that some neurotics are not criminals. *5. All underwater craft are submarines; therefore no submarines are pleasure vessels, because no pleasure vessels are underwater craft. 6. No criminals were pioneers, for all criminals are unsavory persons, and no pioneers were unsavory persons. 7. No musicians are astronauts; all musicians are baseball fans; conse- quently, no astronauts are baseball fans. 8. Some Christians are not Methodists, for some Christians are not Protestants, and some Protestants are not Methodists. 9. No people whose primary interest is in winning elections are true liber- als, and all active politicians are people whose primary interest is in win- ning elections, which entails that no true liberals are active politicians. *10. No weaklings are labor leaders, because no weaklings are true liber- als, and all labor leaders are true liberals. 6.4 Syllogistic Rules and Syllogistic Fallacies A syllogism may fail to establish its conclusion in many different ways. To help avoid common errors we set forth rules—six of them—to guide the reasoner; any given standard-form syllogism can be evaluated by observing whether any one of these rules has been violated. Mastering the rules by which syllogisms may be evaluated also enriches our understanding of the syllogism itself; it helps us to see how syllogisms work, and to see why they fail to work if the rules are broken.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography
    BIBLIOGRAPHY [Adams, 1954] E. M. Adams. The Fundamentals ofGeneral Logic. Longmans , Green & Co., New York, 1954. [Allport, 1958] Gordon W. Allport. The Nature ofPrejudice. Doubleday An­ chor Books, Garden City, New York" 1958. [Atherton, 1993] Catherine Atherton. The Stoics on Ambiguity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1993. [Atlas, 1989] Jay David Atlas. Philosophy Without Ambiguity: A Logico­ Linguistic Essay. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1989. [Barth and Krabbe, 1982] E. M. Barth and E. C. W. Krabbe. From Axiom to Dialogue. De Gruyter, New York, 1982. [Barth and Martens, 1977] E. M. Barth and J. L. Martens. Argumentum Ad Hominem : From chaos to formal dialectic. Logique et Analyse, 77-78:76­ 96, 1977. [Beardsley, 1950] Monroe C. Beardsley. Practical Logic. Prentice-Hall, New York,1950. [Beardsley, 1956] Monroe C. Beardsley. Thinking Straight. Prentice-Hall, En­ glewood Cliffs, 1956. [Bentham, 1969] Jeremy Bentham. The book of fallacies (1824) . In Mary P. Mack, editor, A Bentham Reader, pages 331-358. Pegasus, New York, 1969. [Bertin, 1995] Oliver Bertin . Poor communication cited in ship mishaps . The Globe and Mail, B2, 18 October 1995. [Black, 1946] Max Black. Critical Thinking . Prentice-Hall, New York, 1946. [Blair, 1988] J. Anthony Blair. What is bias? In Trudy Govier, editor, Selected Issues in Logic and Communication, pages 93-103. Wadsworth , Belmont, 1988. [Brinton, 1986] Alan Brinton. Ethotic argument. History ofPhilosophy Quar­ terly, 3:245-257, 1986. [Broad and Wade, 1982] William Broad and Nicholas Wade. Betrayers ofthe Truth: Fraud and Deceit in the Halls ofScience. Simon & Schuster, New York,1982. 281 282 FALLACIES ARISING FROM AMBIGUITY [Burtt, 1931] Edwin Arthur Burtt.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Reasoning in Constructing a Persuasive Argument
    THE ROLE OF REASONING IN CONSTRUCTING A PERSUASIVE ARGUMENT RICHARD R. ORSINGER [email protected] http://www.orsinger.com McCurley, Orsinger, McCurley, Nelson & Downing, L.L.P. San Antonio Office: 1717 Tower Life Building San Antonio, Texas 78205 (210) 225-5567 http://www.orsinger.com and Dallas Office: 5950 Sherry Lane, Suite 800 Dallas, Texas 75225 (214) 273-2400 http://www.momnd.com State Bar of Texas 37TH ANNUAL ADVANCED FAMILY LAW COURSE August 1-4, 2011 San Antonio CHAPTER 11 The Role of Reasoning in Constructing a Persuasive Argument Chapter 11 Table of Contents I. THE IMPORTANCE OF PERSUASION.. 1 II. PERSUASION IN ARGUMENTATION.. 1 III. BACKGROUND.. 2 IV. USER’S GUIDE FOR THIS ARTICLE.. 2 V. ARISTOTLE’S THREE COMPONENTS OF A PERSUASIVE SPEECH.. 3 A. ETHOS.. 3 B. PATHOS.. 4 C. LOGOS.. 4 1. Syllogism.. 4 2. Implication.. 4 3. Enthymeme.. 4 (a) Advantages and Disadvantages of Commonplaces... 5 (b) Selection of Commonplaces.. 5 VI. ARGUMENT MODELS (OVERVIEW)... 5 A. LOGIC-BASED ARGUMENTS. 5 1. Deductive Logic.. 5 2. Inductive Logic.. 6 3. Reasoning by Analogy.. 7 B. DEFEASIBLE ARGUMENTS... 7 C. THE TOULMIN ARGUMENTATION MODEL... 7 D. FALLACIOUS ARGUMENTS.. 8 E. ARGUMENTATION SCHEMES.. 8 VII. LOGICAL REASONING (DETAILED ANALYSIS).. 8 A. DEDUCTIVE REASONING.. 8 1. The Categorical Syllogism... 8 a. Graphically Depicting the Simple Categorical Syllogism... 9 b. A Legal Dispute as a Simple Syllogism.. 9 c. Disputed Facts; Disputed Law.. 9 2. The Hypothetical Syllogism... 10 a. The Conditional Syllogism.. 10 b. The Conjunctive Syllogism... 10 c. The Disjunctive Syllogism.. 10 3. The Dilemma.. 10 4.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 UNIT 4 VALIDITY, INVALIDITY and LIST of VALID SYLLOGISMS Contents 4.0 Objectives 4.1 Introduction 4.2 the Rules of Categorical
    UNIT 4 VALIDITY, INVALIDITY AND LIST OF VALID SYLLOGISMS Contents 4.0 Objectives 4.1 Introduction 4.2 The Rules of Categorical Syllogisms 4.3 Special Applications of General Rules 4.4 Reduction of Arguments to I Figure 4.5 Antilogism or Inconsistent Triad 4.6 Venn Diagram Technique 4.7 Boolean Analysis 4.8 Let us Sum up 4.9 Key Words 4.10 Further Readings and References 4.0 OBJECTIVES This unit brings out the most important part of your study of categorical syllogism. You will be introduced to the rules which determine the validity of arguments. While this is the most important objective, the icing on the cake is the variety of the methods of determining the validity of arguments. Both traditional and modern methods of testing the validity receive due recognition in this unit. Therefore contribution of both John Venn and George Boole find place in this unit. This particular study enables you to grasp the relation between logic and set theory which is brought to the fore in this unit. 4.1 INTRODUCTION In the second and third units we learnt two important aspects of categorical syllogism, viz., figures and moods. However, we did not develop the technique of distinguishing valid from invalid arguments. Consequently, we could not know under what conditions a mood becomes valid and what is still worse, we could not understand why a certain arrangement or configuration of propositions in one figure is legitimate (only a legitimate combination of propositions yields valid mood) and in some other figure illegitimate yielding only invalid moods, and conversely, why a certain configuration of propositions is illegitimate in some figures and legitimate in some other figure or figures.
    [Show full text]
  • List of Fallacies
    List of fallacies For specific popular misconceptions, see List of common if>). The following fallacies involve inferences whose misconceptions. correctness is not guaranteed by the behavior of those log- ical connectives, and hence, which are not logically guar- A fallacy is an incorrect argument in logic and rhetoric anteed to yield true conclusions. Types of propositional fallacies: which undermines an argument’s logical validity or more generally an argument’s logical soundness. Fallacies are either formal fallacies or informal fallacies. • Affirming a disjunct – concluding that one disjunct of a logical disjunction must be false because the These are commonly used styles of argument in convinc- other disjunct is true; A or B; A, therefore not B.[8] ing people, where the focus is on communication and re- sults rather than the correctness of the logic, and may be • Affirming the consequent – the antecedent in an in- used whether the point being advanced is correct or not. dicative conditional is claimed to be true because the consequent is true; if A, then B; B, therefore A.[8] 1 Formal fallacies • Denying the antecedent – the consequent in an indicative conditional is claimed to be false because the antecedent is false; if A, then B; not A, therefore Main article: Formal fallacy not B.[8] A formal fallacy is an error in logic that can be seen in the argument’s form.[1] All formal fallacies are specific types 1.2 Quantification fallacies of non sequiturs. A quantification fallacy is an error in logic where the • Appeal to probability – is a statement that takes quantifiers of the premises are in contradiction to the something for granted because it would probably be quantifier of the conclusion.
    [Show full text]
  • CATEGORICAL INFERENCES Inference Is the Process by Which
    CHAPTER 3: CATEGORICAL INFERENCES Inference is the process by which the truth of one proposition (the conclusion) is affirmed on the basis of the truth of one or more other propositions that serve as its premise or premises. When a conclusion is drawn from only one premise, the inference is said to be immediate. Where there is more than one premise involved, the inference is said to be mediate. This chapter will study these two forms of argument in categorical logic. A. Arguments Expressing Immediate Inference We will consider three kinds of immediate inferences: 1. Immediate inferences embodied in the square of opposition 2. Obversion 3. Conversion I. Introduction to the Traditional Square of Opposition. In everyday life, we come across many complex issues. People express their opinions about them in statements or propositions. Let us take the issue of war, for example. Some are opposed to all forms of violence. And they express their position on war by defending the proposition that “All wars are unjust.” This is a pacifist position. On the other hand, others might associate themselves more closely with Social Darwinism, believing that evolution is through survival of the fittest and that “No war is unjust.” However, someone who attempted to defend both propositions would be inconsistent: “All wars are unjust and “no wars are unjust” cannot both be true. Now suppose Alicia asserts that “Some wars are unjust.” Should we take this to imply that she believes “Some wars are not unjust”? Does the truth of “Some men are fathers” 79 imply that “Some men are not fathers” is also true? It is a common fallacy to assume that the truth of a statement of the form “Some S are P” necessarily implies the truth of the statement with form “Some S are not P.” Thus, many find it difficult to accept the truth of “Some fathers are men” because they misleadingly believe this would imply that they accept “Some fathers are not men” as true.
    [Show full text]