Very Informal Fallacies Elivian.Nl (High Quality - Poorly Written) 06-06-2018

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Very Informal Fallacies Elivian.Nl (High Quality - Poorly Written) 06-06-2018 Very informal fallacies elivian.nl (high quality - poorly written) 06-06-2018 1. Introduction Formal fallacies, or logical fallacies, are patterns of reasoning which can be concluded to be false without further need of context. For example: “Humans are mammals, Peter isn’t human, therefore Peter is not a mammal” (Denying the Antecedent). Or one of my favorites: Proof: booze brings top grades HARRY SHUKMAN A clear correlation has been found between the amount of money colleges spend on alcohol and the percentage of firsts they receive. A genius Cambridge grad has found a link between the money colleges spend on booze and the number of firsts their students achieve. Churchill grad Grayden Reece-Smith has made a chart that appears to show a relationship between the amount of wine supplied by colleges and academic performance. Students have widely accepted that this chart is the best excuse for bad behaviour since telling your mum you only read Playboy for the articles. 1 elivian.nl (correlation does not imply causation, cum hoc ergo propter hoc, or more specific: ignoring common cause. In this case -> the wealth of a college). Formal fallacies, due to their objective nature, are usually easy enough to spot and I find that after attending for example University people are quite adapt at spotting and avoiding these. But humans being humans, we still find plenty of ways to fuck things up without being formally wrong. Plenty of ways to be correct, but hurting the cause. These are called informal fallacies. This article will be about those. The idea of informal fallacies existing is far from new. For example, a list of 129 informal fallacies can be found here [1]. I find the list a boring read, I guess you’d too. So in this article I will focus on fallacies based on three criteria (in order of importance): i. are they new? (e.g. not in the list of 129) ii. do you actually encounter these in practice? iii. are they hard to spot in practice? The third criteria explain the title: very informal fallacies, fallacies which require a lot of context to distinguish and therefore might be actually somewhere between fallacies and errors of thought (/biases). In order to make it easier to spot them in practice I’ve tried to use as many examples as possible. I’ll always sort the examples from what I consider high-importance to low-importance, so if you’re bored you can easily skip the rest of the examples. Examples will be mostly from my own experience as this might give the best representation of what you might encounter in practice. Also, these happen to be the ones I know. Examples will most often feature me as the wise one. This might give the impression that I consider myself to be an (above average) wise person. This however is not the case. I do a lot of stupid things quite frequently. I just don’t always notice and therefore they might not have made it into an example. Informal fallacies which will not be covered in this article because I didn’t have anything to add but which I do consider important are: appeal to authority, ad hominem (personal attacks), circular reasoning, sunk costs, false dilemma, fallacy of the single cause, Occam’s razor. Goal of this article isn’t to help you win an argument with informally irrational people. I’ve never find a good strategy for dealing with irrational people (I still consider running away the best option in these cases). Neither is the goal to make you a more rational person. The goal is to make you adapt at spotting mistakes of reasoning and become more adapt at spotting quality of reasoning in others. Especially when conducting science, being in a meeting and/or being in a discussion. A rule of thumb you might like: as long as you don’t understand the opposing opinion, as long as you cannot pinpoint where/why they went wrong you might want to look harder at what they are saying. Disclaimers: * I try to point out similarities to well-known fallacies. If I don’t the name (or the fallacy) is one I just made up. I think it makes it easier to remember things. If you’ve got better names (or notice something I mention is already described somewhere) please let me know! * This is a first version. There will be many mistakes/inaccuracies/boring parts/parts missing sufficient refferences. Let me know if you find any: [email protected]. The very informal fallacies are sorted in 4 categories: relevance, abstraction, generalization and social. 2 elivian.nl 2. Relevance (necessity) Alice: “I think we should invest more in nuclear energy because it doesn’t contribute to global warming.” Bob: “Have you seen the new Star Wars movie? I think it’s epic!” Although Bob is correct, it doesn’t contribute to the discussion. Fallacies of relevance are relatively easy to spot and understand. But somehow this is still one of the most common types of fallacies I encounter. If you’ve ever been taking minutes at a meeting you might have found that reality actually isn’t far from the Alice and Bob example above. Fallacies of relevance is already a an existing term which include the red herring, irrelevant conclusion (Ignoratio Elenchi). I find the fallacies listed there to be slightly on the formal side (i.e. focused on an incorrect conclusions rather than just hindering progress), so here are a couple of additions. 1.1 Complete irrelevance Irrelevant details. People tend to be really in fond of details. But sometimes you don’t need all the details in order to see the bigger picture. And sometimes the bigger picture is all you need to make a decision. Incorrect assumptions. Something I note in applied sciences is that people are usually really good at taking assumptions and turning them into corresponding correct conclusions. A lot of effort is put into this and there seems to be an unspoken agreement among peers to focus critique solely on someone’s work from assumptions to conclusions, not the assumptions itself. For theoretical research this seems good to me, but in applied sciences the assumptions do matter a lot. Incorrect important assumptions lead to a research which has no practical implications (completely irrelevant). One might think that the research will contribute to other research. In theory this sounds great, but I haven’t seen this happen in practice, probably because it is too applied (not general) to be used by other research. So to sum it up, I see a lot of research which is too practical for theoretical use and too theoretical for practical use. (warning: speculation paragraph!) I think the cause of this is that following rules and combining assumptions is relatively easy, but finding the right assumptions is hard. Perhaps also because we’re never taught to find the correct assumptions in school, but we are usually given the assumptions and asked for the conclusion. Perhaps because finding the right conclusion actually much easier than finding the right assumptions. This comic exactly describes my experience during my master thesis [2]. I was studying the field of the economics of law in which the goal is to find optimal laws with respect to 3 elivian.nl happiness (or utility). I found a field with so many different (strong) assumptions, and corresponding very different conclusions. To some firm believers in a specific theory the field might have felt relevant. But when looking at a distance the field feels completely irrelevant as there is no research in which the assumptions come close to reality. In my thesis I go in great length about the literature and tried to find the most realistic approach. As an illustration of my perceived culture of disregarding the impact of assumptions. In a book comparing many different strategies for CO2 reduction [3] they state: “Assumption 1: Future infrastructure required to sufficiently manufacture and scale each solution globally is in place in the year of adoption, and is included in the cost to the agent (the individual or household, company, community, city, utility, etc.). Because we have made this assumption, we have eliminated the need for analysis of capital spending to enable or augment manufacturing.” This is fundamentally wrong, just because you assume something doesn’t exist, doesn’t eliminate the need to look at it. The need is still there, you just fail to address it. Although this is only a small and in this case rather insignificant example, I see this as a perfect example of the culture in applied sciences. If something is too difficult to incorporate you just assume something, hide the assumption somewhere (like in this case, in the back of the book in the methodology section, or refer people to the internet like in this case) and pretend it isn’t that relevant. In your abstract and conclusions you can still expect people to believe your numbers and there is no need to discuss the important assumptions. If you really cannot hide it you can always suggest it for further research. An example of research where one (seemingly innocuous) assumption makes the research irrelevant. Some background is needed. (warning: this a boring example!). Traffic jams are self-sustaining. A normal highway can handle up to 1500 vehicles per hour per lane, anymore and it will result in a traffic jam. In a traffic jam the speeds are lower so now the highway can now handle only 800 vehicles per hour per lane, any number above that and people will just join the queue.
Recommended publications
  • False Dilemma Wikipedia Contents
    False dilemma Wikipedia Contents 1 False dilemma 1 1.1 Examples ............................................... 1 1.1.1 Morton's fork ......................................... 1 1.1.2 False choice .......................................... 2 1.1.3 Black-and-white thinking ................................... 2 1.2 See also ................................................ 2 1.3 References ............................................... 3 1.4 External links ............................................. 3 2 Affirmative action 4 2.1 Origins ................................................. 4 2.2 Women ................................................ 4 2.3 Quotas ................................................. 5 2.4 National approaches .......................................... 5 2.4.1 Africa ............................................ 5 2.4.2 Asia .............................................. 7 2.4.3 Europe ............................................ 8 2.4.4 North America ........................................ 10 2.4.5 Oceania ............................................ 11 2.4.6 South America ........................................ 11 2.5 International organizations ...................................... 11 2.5.1 United Nations ........................................ 12 2.6 Support ................................................ 12 2.6.1 Polls .............................................. 12 2.7 Criticism ............................................... 12 2.7.1 Mismatching ......................................... 13 2.8 See also
    [Show full text]
  • Remittance Economy Migration-Underdevelopment in Sri Lanka
    REMITTANCE ECONOMY MIGRATION-UNDERDEVELOPMENT IN SRI LANKA Matt Withers A thesis submitted in fulfilment of requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences Department of Political Economy The University of Sydney 2017 “Ceylon ate the fruit before growing the tree” - Joan Robinson (Wilson 1977) (Parren as 2005) (Eelens and Speckmann 1992) (Aneez 2016b) (International Monetary Fund (IMF) 1993; International Monetary Fund (IMF) 2009) (Central Bank of Sri Lanka (CBSL) 2004) (United Nations Population Division 2009) Acknowledgements Thanks are due to a great number of people who have offered support and lent guidance throughout the course of my research. I would like to extend my appreciation foremost to my wonderful supervisors, Elizabeth Hill and Stuart Rosewarne, whose encouragement and criticism have been (in equal measure) invaluable in shaping this thesis. I must similarly offer heartfelt thanks to my academic mentors, Nicola Piper and Janaka Biyanwila, both of whom have unfailingly offered their time, interest and wisdom as my work has progressed. Gratitude is also reserved for my colleagues Magdalena Cubas and Rosie Hancock, who have readily guided me through the more challenging stages of thesis writing with insights and lessons from their own research. A special mention must be made for the Centre for Poverty Analysis in Colombo, without whose assistance my research would simply not have been possible. I would like to thank Priyanthi Fernando for her willingness to accommodate me, Mohamed Munas for helping to make fieldwork arrangements, and to Vagisha Gunasekara for her friendship and willingness to answer my incessant questions about Sri Lanka.
    [Show full text]
  • ANTONY ANTONIOU (OSINT Security Analyst)
    EUROPEAN INTELLIGENCE ACADEMY (EIA) E-BOOK No. 1, MAY 2013 ANTONY ANTONIOU (OSINT Security Analyst) OPEN SOURCE INFORMATION, THE FUTURE OF INTELLIGENCE Copyright: Research Institute for European and American Studies (RIEAS) EUROPEAN INTELLIGENCE ACADEMY E-BOOK No. 1 MAY 2013 OPEN SOURCE INFORMATION, THE FUTURE OF INTELLIGENCE ANTONY ANTONIOU (OSINT Security Analyst) Preface. People from ancient times to our days had understood the importance of information and the significant role that valid information can play in all fields of human activities (politics, economy, during wars etc). References to spies, and their methods – techniques and means that they used can be found in historical texts from antiquity until today, also known theorists of war have addressed and reported (in their writings), the importance of information and the necessity of an enemy misinformation (we will mention two of them of Carl Von Clausewitz1 and Sun - Tzu2). The intelligence services began to take shape during the Second World War. Pioneers at the “intelligence field” were the Germans (in espionage, cryptography - cryptology, propaganda and generally speaking at the development of the appropriate techniques – methods and instruments – means), followed by British. Americans because of their non-participation in the war had left behind in the development of techniques and means for collecting and processing information. This changed after the Japanese attack on Pearl Harbor3 and the American entry into the war4. The USA intelligence 1 Carl Philipp Gottfried von Clausewitz (1 July 1780 – 16 November 1831): was a German-Prussian soldier and military theorist who stressed the "moral" (in modern terms, psychological) and political aspects of war.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Reasoning in Constructing a Persuasive Argument
    The Role of Reasoning in Constructing a Persuasive Argument <http://www.orsinger.com/PDFFiles/constructing-a-persuasive-argument.pdf> [The pdf version of this document is web-enabled with linking endnotes] Richard R. Orsinger [email protected] http://www.orsinger.com McCurley, Orsinger, McCurley, Nelson & Downing, L.L.P. San Antonio Office: 1717 Tower Life Building San Antonio, Texas 78205 (210) 225-5567 http://www.orsinger.com and Dallas Office: 5950 Sherry Lane, Suite 800 Dallas, Texas 75225 (214) 273-2400 http://www.momnd.com State Bar of Texas 37th ANNUAL ADVANCED FAMILY LAW COURSE August 1-4, 2011 San Antonio CHAPTER 11 © 2011 Richard R. Orsinger All Rights Reserved The Role of Reasoning in Constructing a Persuasive Argument Chapter 11 Table of Contents I. THE IMPORTANCE OF PERSUASION.. 1 II. PERSUASION IN ARGUMENTATION.. 1 III. BACKGROUND.. 2 IV. USER’S GUIDE FOR THIS ARTICLE.. 2 V. ARISTOTLE’S THREE COMPONENTS OF A PERSUASIVE SPEECH.. 3 A. ETHOS.. 3 B. PATHOS.. 4 C. LOGOS.. 4 1. Syllogism.. 4 2. Implication.. 4 3. Enthymeme.. 4 (a) Advantages and Disadvantages of Commonplaces... 5 (b) Selection of Commonplaces.. 5 VI. ARGUMENT MODELS (OVERVIEW)... 5 A. LOGIC-BASED ARGUMENTS. 5 1. Deductive Logic.. 5 2. Inductive Logic.. 6 3. Reasoning by Analogy.. 7 B. DEFEASIBLE ARGUMENTS... 7 C. THE TOULMIN ARGUMENTATION MODEL... 7 D. FALLACIOUS ARGUMENTS.. 8 E. ARGUMENTATION SCHEMES.. 8 VII. LOGICAL REASONING (DETAILED ANALYSIS).. 8 A. DEDUCTIVE REASONING.. 8 1. The Categorical Syllogism... 8 a. Graphically Depicting the Simple Categorical Syllogism... 9 b. A Legal Dispute as a Simple Syllogism.. 9 c.
    [Show full text]
  • Loss of Memory As a Cause of Failure of Foresight in Safety
    Chapter 4 Loss of Memory as a Cause of Failure of Foresight in Safety Miloš Ferjenčík Nicolas Dechy Table of contents 4.7.4 Learning acts against the loss of memory . 96 4.7.5 Role of safety management system functions . 98 4.7.6 Safety management against the loss of memory. 99 4.1 Executive Summary ............................................ 84 4.8 Conclusions ................................................... 100 4.2 Key Messages .................................................. 84 4.9 Acknowledgments.............................................. 100 4.3 Introduction ................................................... 84 4.10 References ................................................... 100 4.4 Loss of Memory Relates to Learning and Knowledge . 86 4.4.1 Failures of foresight in safety due to a loss of memory . 86 4.4.2 Early warning signs and foresight in safety . 87 4.4.3 Four aspects of memory useful for foresight in safety . 87 4.4.4 Applied example: the kitchen dangers . 88 4.4.5 Other examples from industry . 88 4.4.6 The four aspects of LoM: description related to hazards . 88 4.5 The Process of Loss of Memory.................................. 89 4.5.1 Memory and forgetting . 89 4.5.2 The process of memorising: three key faculties. 90 4.5.3 The process of loss of memory useful for foresight in safety . 90 4.5.4 Twelve categories of loss of memory . 90 4.5.5 Applied example: loss of memory in the kitchen. 91 4.6 Loss of Memory and Organisational Memory .................... 91 4.6.1 Extension from human to organisational memory . 91 4.6.2 Nature of organisational memory . 92 4.6.3 Extension accords with nature of organisational memory .
    [Show full text]
  • TOOLKIT Exchanges of Practices
    “Exchange of learning and teaching strategies: media literacy in adult education” Erasmus+ Strategic Partnerships for adult education (2016-2018) Project number: 2016-1-FR01-KA204-024220 TOOLKIT Exchanges of Practices This project has been funded with support from the European Commission. This publication reflects the views only of the author and the Commission cannot be held responsible for any use, which may be made of the information contained therein. Content Introduction……………………………………………………………………………………….3 “Media bias, fallacies and social representations definitions” workshop…………….4 Social representation……………………………………………………………………………7 “Recognizing Fallacies” workshop…………………………………………………………..9 “Recognizing Appeals to Emotion” workshop……………………………………………21 ”Text analysis” workshop………………………………………………………………….....25 Text for analysis………………………………………………………………………………...30 Critical Thinking workshop "The Logical Fallacies of Nationalism"………………….33 Workshop on writing: “Traditional and inverted pyramids”……………………………36 Deconstructing image………………………………………………………………………....40 Project poster…………………………………………………………………………………...44 Introduction "Exchange of learning and teaching strategies: media literacy in adult education" is an Erasmus+ Strategic Partnerships project for six partners from France, Estonia, Italy, Malta, Spain and Sweden. The coordinator of this project is MITRA FRANCE non-governmental organization from France. The project is funded by the Erasmus+ Programme of the European Commission. It seeks to develop initiatives addressing spheres of adult education, gathering and exchanges of experience and best practices in media literacy. This initiative contributes to strengthening media literacy as a mean of countering online and ordinary radicalisation and stigmatisation. As one of the results of this partnership the consortium has compiled a Toolkit with several good practices exchanged and tested during this project. This Toolkit is designed for adult educators, trainers and support staff who are interested in using media literacy in their daily work.
    [Show full text]
  • Appendix 1 a Great Big List of Fallacies
    Why Brilliant People Believe Nonsense Appendix 1 A Great Big List of Fallacies To avoid falling for the "Intrinsic Value of Senseless Hard Work Fallacy" (see also "Reinventing the Wheel"), I began with Wikipedia's helpful divisions, list, and descriptions as a base (since Wikipedia articles aren't subject to copyright restrictions), but felt free to add new fallacies, and tweak a bit here and there if I felt further explanation was needed. If you don't understand a fallacy from the brief description below, consider Googling the name of the fallacy, or finding an article dedicated to the fallacy in Wikipedia. Consider the list representative rather than exhaustive. Informal fallacies These arguments are fallacious for reasons other than their structure or form (formal = the "form" of the argument). Thus, informal fallacies typically require an examination of the argument's content. • Argument from (personal) incredulity (aka - divine fallacy, appeal to common sense) – I cannot imagine how this could be true, therefore it must be false. • Argument from repetition (argumentum ad nauseam) – signifies that it has been discussed so extensively that nobody cares to discuss it anymore. • Argument from silence (argumentum e silentio) – the conclusion is based on the absence of evidence, rather than the existence of evidence. • Argument to moderation (false compromise, middle ground, fallacy of the mean, argumentum ad temperantiam) – assuming that the compromise between two positions is always correct. • Argumentum verbosium – See proof by verbosity, below. • (Shifting the) burden of proof (see – onus probandi) – I need not prove my claim, you must prove it is false. • Circular reasoning (circulus in demonstrando) – when the reasoner begins with (or assumes) what he or she is trying to end up with; sometimes called assuming the conclusion.
    [Show full text]
  • A Hierarchy of Limitations in Machine Learning
    A Hierarchy of Limitations in Machine Learning Momin M. Malik Berkman Klein Center for Internet & Society at Harvard University momin [email protected] 29 February 2020∗ Abstract \All models are wrong, but some are useful," wrote George E. P. Box(1979). Machine learning has focused on the usefulness of probability models for prediction in social systems, but is only now coming to grips with the ways in which these models are wrong|and the consequences of those shortcomings. This paper attempts a comprehensive, structured overview of the specific conceptual, procedural, and statistical limitations of models in machine learning when applied to society. Machine learning modelers themselves can use the described hierarchy to identify possible failure points and think through how to address them, and consumers of machine learning models can know what to question when confronted with the decision about if, where, and how to apply machine learning. The limitations go from commitments inherent in quantification itself, through to showing how unmodeled dependencies can lead to cross-validation being overly optimistic as a way of assessing model performance. Introduction There is little argument about whether or not machine learning models are useful for applying to social systems. But if we take seriously George Box's dictum, or indeed the even older one that \the map is not the territory' (Korzybski, 1933), then there has been comparatively less systematic attention paid within the field to how machine learning models are wrong (Selbst et al., 2019) and seeing possible harms in that light. By \wrong" I do not mean in terms of making misclassifications, or even fitting over the `wrong' class of functions, but more fundamental mathematical/statistical assumptions, philosophical (in the sense used by Abbott, 1988) commitments about how we represent the world, and sociological processes of how models interact with target phenomena.
    [Show full text]
  • Escaping the Mcnamara Fallacy: Towards More Impactful Recommender Systems Research
    Escaping the McNamara Fallacy: Towards more Impactful Recommender Systems Research Dietmar Jannach1 and Christine Bauer2 1University of Klagenfurt, [email protected] 2Utrecht University, [email protected] This is the accepted version of the paper appearing in the AI Magazine. The final publication is available at: https://ojs.aaai.org/index.php/aimagazine/article/view/5312 Jannach, Dietmar & Bauer, Christine (2020). Escaping the McNamara Fallacy: Toward More Impactful Recommender Systems Research. AI Magazine, 41(4), pp 79–95. DOI: 10.1609/aimag.v41i4.5312 Abstract Recommender systems are among today’s most successful application areas of AI. However, in the recommender systems research community, we have fallen prey of a McNamara fallacy to a worrying extent: In the majority of our research efforts, we rely almost exclusively on computational measures such as prediction accuracy, which are easier to make than applying other evaluation methods. However, it remains unclear whether small improvements in terms of such computational measures actually matter a lot and whether they lead us to better systems in practice. A paradigm shift in terms of our research culture and goals is therefore needed. We cannot focus exclusively on abstract computational measures any longer, but must direct our attention to research questions that are more relevant and have more impact in the real world. In this work, we review the various ways of how recommender systems may create value; how they, positively or negatively, impact consumers, businesses, and the society; and how we can measure the resulting effects. Through our analyses, we identify a number of research gaps and propose ways of broadening and improving our methodology in a way that leads us to more impactful research in our field.
    [Show full text]
  • Current Developments in Language Testing. Anthology Series 25
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 365 144 FL 021 757 AUTHOR Anivan, Sarinee, Ed. TITLE Current Developments in Language Testing. Anthology Series 25. INSTITUTION Southeast Asian Ministers of Education Organization (Singapore). Regional Language Centre. REPORT NO ISBN-9971-74-037-0; ISSN-0129-8895; RELCP383-91 PUB DATE 91 NOTE 271p.; Selected papers presented at the Regional Language Centre Seminar on Language Testing and Language Programme Evaluation (April 9-12, 1990). For selected individual papers, see also ED 328 072; ED 350 819, ED 322 725, ED 342 211, ED 317 073, ED 322 729. PUB TYPE Collected Works General (020) Collected Works Serials (022) EDRS PRICE MF01/PC11 Plus Postage. DESCRIPTORS Communicative Competence (Languages); Comparative Analysis; Computer Assisted Testing; Cues; English (Second Language); Evaluation CriterCa; Instructional Materials; International Programs; Interviews; Item Response Theory; Language Aptitude; *Language Proficiency; Language Research; *Language Tests; *Second Languages; Simulation; Sociocultural Patterns; Speech Skills; Teacher Developed Materials; *Test Format; *Testing; Testing Programs; Test Validity; Trend Analysis; Writing Evaluation; Writing Exercise IDENTIFIERS *Oral Proficiency Testing ABSTRACT The selection of papers on language testing includes: "Language Testing in the 1990s: How Far Have We Come? How Much Further Have We To Go?" (J. Charles Alderson); "Current Research/Development in Language Testing" (John W. 011er, Jr.); "The Difficulties of Difficulty: Prompts in Writing Assessment" (Liz Hamp-Lyons, Sheila Prochnow); "The Validity of Writing Test Tasks" (John Read); "Affective Factors in the Assessment of Oral Interaction: Gender and Status" (Don Porter); "Authenticity in Foreign Language Testing" (Peter Doye); "Evaluating Communicative Tests" (Keith Morrow); "Materials-Based Tests: How Well Do They Work?" (Michael Milanovic); "Defining Language Ability: The Criteria for Criteria" (Geoff Brindley); "The Role of Item Response Theory in Language Test Validation" (T.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Reasoning in Constructing a Persuasive Argument
    THE ROLE OF REASONING IN CONSTRUCTING A PERSUASIVE ARGUMENT RICHARD R. ORSINGER [email protected] http://www.orsinger.com McCurley, Orsinger, McCurley, Nelson & Downing, L.L.P. San Antonio Office: 1717 Tower Life Building San Antonio, Texas 78205 (210) 225-5567 http://www.orsinger.com and Dallas Office: 5950 Sherry Lane, Suite 800 Dallas, Texas 75225 (214) 273-2400 http://www.momnd.com State Bar of Texas 37TH ANNUAL ADVANCED FAMILY LAW COURSE August 1-4, 2011 San Antonio CHAPTER 11 The Role of Reasoning in Constructing a Persuasive Argument Chapter 11 Table of Contents I. THE IMPORTANCE OF PERSUASION.. 1 II. PERSUASION IN ARGUMENTATION.. 1 III. BACKGROUND.. 2 IV. USER’S GUIDE FOR THIS ARTICLE.. 2 V. ARISTOTLE’S THREE COMPONENTS OF A PERSUASIVE SPEECH.. 3 A. ETHOS.. 3 B. PATHOS.. 4 C. LOGOS.. 4 1. Syllogism.. 4 2. Implication.. 4 3. Enthymeme.. 4 (a) Advantages and Disadvantages of Commonplaces... 5 (b) Selection of Commonplaces.. 5 VI. ARGUMENT MODELS (OVERVIEW)... 5 A. LOGIC-BASED ARGUMENTS. 5 1. Deductive Logic.. 5 2. Inductive Logic.. 6 3. Reasoning by Analogy.. 7 B. DEFEASIBLE ARGUMENTS... 7 C. THE TOULMIN ARGUMENTATION MODEL... 7 D. FALLACIOUS ARGUMENTS.. 8 E. ARGUMENTATION SCHEMES.. 8 VII. LOGICAL REASONING (DETAILED ANALYSIS).. 8 A. DEDUCTIVE REASONING.. 8 1. The Categorical Syllogism... 8 a. Graphically Depicting the Simple Categorical Syllogism... 9 b. A Legal Dispute as a Simple Syllogism.. 9 c. Disputed Facts; Disputed Law.. 9 2. The Hypothetical Syllogism... 10 a. The Conditional Syllogism.. 10 b. The Conjunctive Syllogism... 10 c. The Disjunctive Syllogism.. 10 3. The Dilemma.. 10 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Splitting a Difference of Opinion: the Shift to Negotiation
    University of Groningen Splitting a Difference of Opinion van Laar, Jan Albert; Krabbe, Erik C. W. Published in: Argumentation DOI: 10.1007/s10503-017-9445-7 IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult the publisher's version (publisher's PDF) if you wish to cite from it. Please check the document version below. Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Publication date: 2018 Link to publication in University of Groningen/UMCG research database Citation for published version (APA): van Laar, J. A., & Krabbe, E. C. W. (2018). Splitting a Difference of Opinion: The Shift to Negotiation. Argumentation, 32(3), 329-350. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-017-9445-7 Copyright Other than for strictly personal use, it is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). The publication may also be distributed here under the terms of Article 25fa of the Dutch Copyright Act, indicated by the “Taverne” license. More information can be found on the University of Groningen website: https://www.rug.nl/library/open-access/self-archiving-pure/taverne- amendment. Take-down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Downloaded from the University of Groningen/UMCG research database (Pure): http://www.rug.nl/research/portal. For technical reasons the number of authors shown on this cover page is limited to 10 maximum.
    [Show full text]