On the Connections Between Set Theory and Group Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

On the Connections Between Set Theory and Group Theory ON THE CONNECTIONS BETWEEN SET THEORY AND GROUP THEORY DINGDING DONG Abstract. This paper is an introduction to the connections between set the- ory and group theory. After introducing the notion of cardinal arithmetic, we prove the Schroeder-Bernstein Theorem about cardinal equivalence. We then discuss how sets and groups exhibit the properties of each other, specifically, the cardinal relations between groups and the group structures within sets of different cardinalities. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Cardinal Arithmetic 1 3. Schroeder-Bernstein Theorem 4 4. Lagrange's Theorem 6 5. Cyclic Groups 7 6. Understanding Sets within Group Structures 8 Acknowledgments 10 References 10 1. Introduction The exploration of uncountable sets dates back to the nineteenth century, when Georg Cantor proved the existence of infinite sets that cannot be put into one- to-one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Through the diagonal argument, Cantor showed that there is no bijection between the sets of real and natural numbers. Stemmed from this discovery, the notion of cardinality helped mathematicians understand more about sets that seem not as approachable. Groups are a particular kind of sets equipped with a binary operation, which satisfies the four group axioms of closure, associativity, identity and invertibility. Since groups are still sets, anything about sets still holds true in groups. However, due to their specific properties, there is more accessible information about groups themselves. 2. Cardinal Arithmetic Cardinal numbers measure the cardinality, or size of sets. In terms of bijective functions, it defines an equivalence relation between sets. Definition 2.1. Two sets A and B are of the same cardinality if there exists a bijection f : A ! B between A and B. 1 2 DINGDING DONG Definition 2.2. A cardinal number is thought of as an equivalence class of cardi- nality, i.e. card(A) = card(B) if A and B are of the same cardinality. Definition 2.3. Let a; b be cardinal numbers. If there exist sets A; B with card(A) = a, card(B) = b and A ⊆ B, then a ≤ b. Definition 2.4. Let a; b be cardinal numbers. If A; B are sets with card(A) = a, card(B) = b and A \ B = ?, then a + b = card(A [ B). Definition 2.5. Let a; b be cardinal numbers. If A; B are sets with card(A) = a and card(B) = b, then a · b = card(A × B). Definition 2.6. @0 = card(N). Theorem 2.7. For any infinite cardinal number a, @0 ≤ a. Proof. Let A be an infinite set with card(A) = a, and F0 ⊂ F1 ⊂ F2 ⊂ ::: be a sequence of subsets of A with jFij = i. Let xi 2 Fi n Fi−1. Then x1; x2; ::: 2 A with xi 6= xj for any i 6= j, fxi j i 2 Ng ⊆ A, card(fxi j i 2 Ng) ≤ card(A), @0 ≤ a. An important lemma in set theory is Zorn's Lemma, which identifies the existence of a maximal element within any partially ordered set that is bounded above. Definition 2.8. A partially ordered set is a set P with a binary relation ≤ such that, for all a; b; c 2 P : (1) (Reflexivity) a ≤ a. (2) (Antisymmetry) If a ≤ b and b ≤ a, then a = b. (3) (Transitivity) If a ≤ b and b ≤ c, then a ≤ c. Lemma 2.9. (Zorn's Lemma) Suppose a partially ordered set P has the property that every chain in P has an upper bound in P. Then the set P contains at least one maximal element. Theorem 2.10. Let a be an infinite cardinal number. Then a + a = a. Proof. Following the proof of Z. Nagy, let A be an infinite set with card(A) = a. Let S(A) be the set of families fAi j i 2 Ig of subsets of A with (a) card(Ai) = @0 for all i 2 I; (b) Ai \ Aj = ? for all i; j 2 I. S(A) with set inclusion is a partially ordered set. For any S 2 S(A), S ⊆ S. If S1;S2 2 S(A), S1 ⊆ S2 and S2 ⊆ S1, then S1 = S2. If S1;S2;S3 2 S(A), S1 ⊆ S2 and S2 ⊆ S3, then S1 ⊆ S3. Since S(A) with set inclusion is a partially ordered set and every chain in S(A) is bounded above by fAi j Ai ⊆ A; card(Ai) = @0g, S(A) contains a maximal element fAi j i 2 I0g. Let B = An(S A ). Since fA g is maximal, B is finite, card(A) = card(S A ). i2I0 i i i2I0 i Then a = card(A) = card(N × I0). Suppose card(I0) = c. Then a = @0 · c. Let C0 = fn 2 N j n eveng, C1 = fn 2 N j n oddg. Since there are bijections f(x) = 2x between N and C0, g(x) = 2x − 1 between N and C1, card(C0) = card(C1) = @0. Since (C0 × I0) [ (C1 × I0) = N × I0,(C0 × I0) \ (C1 × I0) = ?, ON THE CONNECTIONS BETWEEN SET THEORY AND GROUP THEORY 3 a = card(N × I0) = card(C0 × I0) + card(C1 × I0) = @0 · card(I0) + @0 · card(I0) = @0 · c + @0 · c = a + a: Theorem 2.11. If a; b are cardinal numbers with 1 ≤ b ≤ a and a infinite, then a · b = a. Proof. Since a ≤ a · b ≤ a · a, it is sufficient to prove that a = a · a. Define χ = f(D; f): D ⊂ A; f : D ! D × D bijectiveg; and equip χ with the order ( 0 0 0 D ⊂ D (D; f) ≺ (D ; f ) () 0 : f = f jD S Let τ = f(Di; fi): i 2 Ig be a totally ordered subset of χ, D0 = i2I Di, f : D0 ! D0 × D0 be the unique function with fjDi = fi. Then f is injective with [ [ [ f(D0) = f(Di) = fi(Di) = (Di × Di) = D0 × D0: i2I i2I i2I (D; f) is an upper bound of τ. According to Zorn's Lemma, since 8τ ⊆ χ is bounded above, there exists a maximal element (D; f) 2 χ. Let card(D) = d. Since (D; f) 2 χ, d · d = d. If d = a, then a · a = a. By contradiction, assume that d 6= a. Since d ≤ a as D ⊂ A, d < a. Let G = A n D. Then d + card(G) = a. Since d < a, card(G) = a by Theorem 2.10, and there exists a subset E ⊂ G with card(E) = d. Consider the set P = (E × E) [ (E × D) [ (D × E): Since E \D = ?,(E ×E); (E ×D); (D×E) are disjoint from each other. According to Theorem 2.10, card(P ) = card(E × E) + card(E × D) + card(D × E) = d · d + d · d + d · d = d = card(E): There exists a bijection g : E ! P . Since E \ D = P \ (D × D) = ?, there exists a bijection h : D [ E ! P [ (D × D) such that hjD = f and hjE = g. Since P [(D ×D) = (D [E)×(D [E), (D [E; h) 2 χ,(D; f) is not the maximal element in χ. )( Hence d = a, a · a = a. 4 DINGDING DONG 3. Schroeder-Bernstein Theorem Schroeder-Bernstein Theorem states that if there exists an injection from set A to set B and an injection from set B to set A, then there exists a bijection between A and B. In terms of cardinality, it means that if jAj ≤ jBj and jBj ≤ jAj, then jAj = jBj, which completes the ordering of cardinal numbers. Proposition 3.1. If B ⊆ A and there exists an injective function f : A ! B, then there exists a bijective function h : A ! B between A and B. Proof. If X ⊆ Y , then ff(k) j k 2 Xg ⊆ ff(k) j k 2 Y g, f(X) ⊆ f(Y ). Since in the base case, we have A ⊇ B, B ⊇ f(A), A ⊇ B ⊇ f(A) ⊇ f(B) ⊇ f 2(A) ⊇ f 2(B) ⊇ ::: by induction. Consider the sequence of sets X0 = A n B; X1 = B n f(A);X2 = f(A) n f(B); ::: Since for any n, Xn+2 = f(P ) n f(Q) while Xn = P n Q, for any x 2 Xn+2, x 2 f(P ), there exists p 2 P such that f(p) = x. Since p2 = Q (or x = f(p) 2 f(Q)), p 2 P n Q = Xn with f(p) = x. Hence f is both surjective and injective, there exists a bijection f : Xn ! Xn+2 between Xn and Xn+2. For any n; m 2 N such that n > m, since Xm \ Xm+1 = ? and Xm+1 ⊇ Xn, Xm \ Xn = ?. Hence for sets 1 1 [ [ V = Xn;W = Xn; n=0 n=1 there exists a bijection F : V ! W between V and W with ( x if x 2 X ; n odd F (x) = n : f(x) if x 2 Xn; n even Since B ⊆ A, V ⊆ A, W ⊆ V , W ⊆ B, A = (A n (B [ V )) [ (B n V ) [ (V n B) [ ((B \ V ) n W ) [ W B = (B n V ) [ ((B \ V ) n W ) [ W V = (V n B) [ ((B \ V ) n W ) [ W with (A n (B [ V )); (B n V ); (V n B); ((B \ V ) n W );W disjoint from each other. Since A n B = X0 = V n W , (A n (B [ V )) [ (V n B) = A n B = V n W = (V n B) [ ((B \ V ) n W ) (A n (B [ V )) = ((B \ V ) n W ) A n V = (A n (B [ V )) [ (B n V ) = (B n V ) [ ((B \ V ) n W ) = B n W Let Z = A n V = B n W .
Recommended publications
  • Set Theory, by Thomas Jech, Academic Press, New York, 1978, Xii + 621 Pp., '$53.00
    BOOK REVIEWS 775 BULLETIN (New Series) OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 3, Number 1, July 1980 © 1980 American Mathematical Society 0002-9904/80/0000-0 319/$01.75 Set theory, by Thomas Jech, Academic Press, New York, 1978, xii + 621 pp., '$53.00. "General set theory is pretty trivial stuff really" (Halmos; see [H, p. vi]). At least, with the hindsight afforded by Cantor, Zermelo, and others, it is pretty trivial to do the following. First, write down a list of axioms about sets and membership, enunciating some "obviously true" set-theoretic principles; the most popular Hst today is called ZFC (the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms with the axiom of Choice). Next, explain how, from ZFC, one may derive all of conventional mathematics, including the general theory of transfinite cardi­ nals and ordinals. This "trivial" part of set theory is well covered in standard texts, such as [E] or [H]. Jech's book is an introduction to the "nontrivial" part. Now, nontrivial set theory may be roughly divided into two general areas. The first area, classical set theory, is a direct outgrowth of Cantor's work. Cantor set down the basic properties of cardinal numbers. In particular, he showed that if K is a cardinal number, then 2", or exp(/c), is a cardinal strictly larger than K (if A is a set of size K, 2* is the cardinality of the family of all subsets of A). Now starting with a cardinal K, we may form larger cardinals exp(ic), exp2(ic) = exp(exp(fc)), exp3(ic) = exp(exp2(ic)), and in fact this may be continued through the transfinite to form expa(»c) for every ordinal number a.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematics 144 Set Theory Fall 2012 Version
    MATHEMATICS 144 SET THEORY FALL 2012 VERSION Table of Contents I. General considerations.……………………………………………………………………………………………………….1 1. Overview of the course…………………………………………………………………………………………………1 2. Historical background and motivation………………………………………………………….………………4 3. Selected problems………………………………………………………………………………………………………13 I I. Basic concepts. ………………………………………………………………………………………………………………….15 1. Topics from logic…………………………………………………………………………………………………………16 2. Notation and first steps………………………………………………………………………………………………26 3. Simple examples…………………………………………………………………………………………………………30 I I I. Constructions in set theory.………………………………………………………………………………..……….34 1. Boolean algebra operations.……………………………………………………………………………………….34 2. Ordered pairs and Cartesian products……………………………………………………………………… ….40 3. Larger constructions………………………………………………………………………………………………..….42 4. A convenient assumption………………………………………………………………………………………… ….45 I V. Relations and functions ……………………………………………………………………………………………….49 1.Binary relations………………………………………………………………………………………………………… ….49 2. Partial and linear orderings……………………………..………………………………………………… ………… 56 3. Functions…………………………………………………………………………………………………………… ….…….. 61 4. Composite and inverse function.…………………………………………………………………………… …….. 70 5. Constructions involving functions ………………………………………………………………………… ……… 77 6. Order types……………………………………………………………………………………………………… …………… 80 i V. Number systems and set theory …………………………………………………………………………………. 84 1. The Natural Numbers and Integers…………………………………………………………………………….83 2. Finite induction
    [Show full text]
  • 641 1. P. Erdös and A. H. Stone, Some Remarks on Almost Periodic
    1946] DENSITY CHARACTERS 641 BIBLIOGRAPHY 1. P. Erdös and A. H. Stone, Some remarks on almost periodic transformations, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. vol. 51 (1945) pp. 126-130. 2. W. H. Gottschalk, Powers of homeomorphisms with almost periodic propertiesf Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. vol. 50 (1944) pp. 222-227. UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA AND UNIVERSITY OF VIRGINIA A REMARK ON DENSITY CHARACTERS EDWIN HEWITT1 Let X be an arbitrary topological space satisfying the TVseparation axiom [l, Chap. 1, §4, p. 58].2 We recall the following definition [3, p. 329]. DEFINITION 1. The least cardinal number of a dense subset of the space X is said to be the density character of X. It is denoted by the symbol %{X). We denote the cardinal number of a set A by | A |. Pospisil has pointed out [4] that if X is a Hausdorff space, then (1) |X| g 22SW. This inequality is easily established. Let D be a dense subset of the Hausdorff space X such that \D\ =S(-X'). For an arbitrary point pÇ^X and an arbitrary complete neighborhood system Vp at p, let Vp be the family of all sets UC\D, where U^VP. Thus to every point of X, a certain family of subsets of D is assigned. Since X is a Haus­ dorff space, VpT^Vq whenever p j*£q, and the correspondence assigning each point p to the family <DP is one-to-one. Since X is in one-to-one correspondence with a sub-hierarchy of the hierarchy of all families of subsets of D, the inequality (1) follows.
    [Show full text]
  • 17 Axiom of Choice
    Math 361 Axiom of Choice 17 Axiom of Choice De¯nition 17.1. Let be a nonempty set of nonempty sets. Then a choice function for is a function f sucFh that f(S) S for all S . F 2 2 F Example 17.2. Let = (N)r . Then we can de¯ne a choice function f by F P f;g f(S) = the least element of S: Example 17.3. Let = (Z)r . Then we can de¯ne a choice function f by F P f;g f(S) = ²n where n = min z z S and, if n = 0, ² = min z= z z = n; z S . fj j j 2 g 6 f j j j j j 2 g Example 17.4. Let = (Q)r . Then we can de¯ne a choice function f as follows. F P f;g Let g : Q N be an injection. Then ! f(S) = q where g(q) = min g(r) r S . f j 2 g Example 17.5. Let = (R)r . Then it is impossible to explicitly de¯ne a choice function for . F P f;g F Axiom 17.6 (Axiom of Choice (AC)). For every set of nonempty sets, there exists a function f such that f(S) S for all S . F 2 2 F We say that f is a choice function for . F Theorem 17.7 (AC). If A; B are non-empty sets, then the following are equivalent: (a) A B ¹ (b) There exists a surjection g : B A. ! Proof. (a) (b) Suppose that A B.
    [Show full text]
  • Cardinal Invariants Concerning Functions Whose Sum Is Almost Continuous Krzysztof Ciesielski West Virginia University, [email protected]
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by The Research Repository @ WVU (West Virginia University) Faculty Scholarship 1995 Cardinal Invariants Concerning Functions Whose Sum Is Almost Continuous Krzysztof Ciesielski West Virginia University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://researchrepository.wvu.edu/faculty_publications Part of the Mathematics Commons Digital Commons Citation Ciesielski, Krzysztof, "Cardinal Invariants Concerning Functions Whose Sum Is Almost Continuous" (1995). Faculty Scholarship. 822. https://researchrepository.wvu.edu/faculty_publications/822 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Research Repository @ WVU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of The Research Repository @ WVU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Cardinal invariants concerning functions whose sum is almost continuous. Krzysztof Ciesielski1, Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University, Mor- gantown, WV 26506-6310 ([email protected]) Arnold W. Miller1, York University, Department of Mathematics, North York, Ontario M3J 1P3, Canada, Permanent address: University of Wisconsin-Madison, Department of Mathematics, Van Vleck Hall, 480 Lincoln Drive, Madison, Wis- consin 53706-1388, USA ([email protected]) Abstract Let A stand for the class of all almost continuous functions from R to R and let A(A) be the smallest cardinality of a family F ⊆ RR for which there is no g: R → R with the property that f + g ∈ A for all f ∈ F . We define cardinal number A(D) for the class D of all real functions with the Darboux property similarly.
    [Show full text]
  • Elements of Set Theory
    Elements of set theory April 1, 2014 ii Contents 1 Zermelo{Fraenkel axiomatization 1 1.1 Historical context . 1 1.2 The language of the theory . 3 1.3 The most basic axioms . 4 1.4 Axiom of Infinity . 4 1.5 Axiom schema of Comprehension . 5 1.6 Functions . 6 1.7 Axiom of Choice . 7 1.8 Axiom schema of Replacement . 9 1.9 Axiom of Regularity . 9 2 Basic notions 11 2.1 Transitive sets . 11 2.2 Von Neumann's natural numbers . 11 2.3 Finite and infinite sets . 15 2.4 Cardinality . 17 2.5 Countable and uncountable sets . 19 3 Ordinals 21 3.1 Basic definitions . 21 3.2 Transfinite induction and recursion . 25 3.3 Applications with choice . 26 3.4 Applications without choice . 29 3.5 Cardinal numbers . 31 4 Descriptive set theory 35 4.1 Rational and real numbers . 35 4.2 Topological spaces . 37 4.3 Polish spaces . 39 4.4 Borel sets . 43 4.5 Analytic sets . 46 4.6 Lebesgue's mistake . 48 iii iv CONTENTS 5 Formal logic 51 5.1 Propositional logic . 51 5.1.1 Propositional logic: syntax . 51 5.1.2 Propositional logic: semantics . 52 5.1.3 Propositional logic: completeness . 53 5.2 First order logic . 56 5.2.1 First order logic: syntax . 56 5.2.2 First order logic: semantics . 59 5.2.3 Completeness theorem . 60 6 Model theory 67 6.1 Basic notions . 67 6.2 Ultraproducts and nonstandard analysis . 68 6.3 Quantifier elimination and the real closed fields .
    [Show full text]
  • 21 Cardinal and Ordinal Numbers. by W. Sierpióski. Monografie Mate
    BOOK REVIEWS 21 Cardinal and ordinal numbers. By W. Sierpióski. Monografie Mate- matyczne, vol. 34. Warszawa, Panstwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe, 1958. 487 pp. Not since the publication in 1928 of his Leçons sur les nombres transfinis has Sierpióski written a book on transfinite numbers. The present book, embodying the fruits of a lifetime of research and ex­ perience in teaching the subject, is therefore most welcome. Although generally similar in outline to the earlier work, it is an entirely new book, and more than twice as long. The exposition is leisurely and thickly interspersed with illuminating discussion and examples. The result is a book which is highly instructive and eminently readable. Whether one takes the chapters in order or dips in at random he is almost sure to find something interesting. Many examples and ap­ plications are included in the form of exercises, nearly all accom­ panied by solutions. The exposition is from the standpoint of naive set theory. No axioms, other than the axiom of choice, are ever stated explicitly, although Zermelo's system is occasionally referred to. But the role of the axiom of choice is a central theme throughout the book. For a student who wishes to learn just when and how this axiom is needed this is the best book yet written. There is an excellent chapter de­ voted to theorems equivalent to the axiom of choice. These include not only well-ordering, trichotomy, and Zorn's principle, but also several less familiar propositions: Lindenbaum's theorem that of any two nonempty sets one is equivalent to a partition of the other; Vaught's theorem that every family of nonempty sets contains a maximal disjoint family; Tarski's theorem that every cardinal has a successor, and other propositions of cardinal arithmetic; Kurepa's theorem that the proposition that every partially ordered set con­ tains a maximal family of incomparable elements is an equivalent when joined with the ordering principle, i.e., the proposition that every set can be ordered.
    [Show full text]
  • Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses A
    EQUIVALENTS TO THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND THEIR USES A Thesis Presented to The Faculty of the Department of Mathematics California State University, Los Angeles In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Science in Mathematics By James Szufu Yang c 2015 James Szufu Yang ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii The thesis of James Szufu Yang is approved. Mike Krebs, Ph.D. Kristin Webster, Ph.D. Michael Hoffman, Ph.D., Committee Chair Grant Fraser, Ph.D., Department Chair California State University, Los Angeles June 2015 iii ABSTRACT Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses By James Szufu Yang In set theory, the Axiom of Choice (AC) was formulated in 1904 by Ernst Zermelo. It is an addition to the older Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) set theory. We call it Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice and abbreviate it as ZFC. This paper starts with an introduction to the foundations of ZFC set the- ory, which includes the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms, partially ordered sets (posets), the Cartesian product, the Axiom of Choice, and their related proofs. It then intro- duces several equivalent forms of the Axiom of Choice and proves that they are all equivalent. In the end, equivalents to the Axiom of Choice are used to prove a few fundamental theorems in set theory, linear analysis, and abstract algebra. This paper is concluded by a brief review of the work in it, followed by a few points of interest for further study in mathematics and/or set theory. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Between the two department requirements to complete a master's degree in mathematics − the comprehensive exams and a thesis, I really wanted to experience doing a research and writing a serious academic paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Bijections and Infinities 1 Key Ideas
    INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL REASONING Worksheet 6 Bijections and Infinities 1 Key Ideas This week we are going to focus on the notion of bijection. This is a way we have to compare two different sets, and say that they have \the same number of elements". Of course, when sets are finite everything goes smoothly, but when they are not... things get spiced up! But let us start, as usual, with some definitions. Definition 1. A bijection between a set X and a set Y consists of matching elements of X with elements of Y in such a way that every element of X has a unique match, and every element of Y has a unique match. Example 1. Let X = f1; 2; 3g and Y = fa; b; cg. An example of a bijection between X and Y consists of matching 1 with a, 2 with b and 3 with c. A NOT example would match 1 and 2 with a and 3 with c. In this case, two things fail: a has two partners, and b has no partner. Note: if you are familiar with these concepts, you may have recognized a bijection as a function between X and Y which is both injective (1:1) and surjective (onto). We will revisit the notion of bijection in this language in a few weeks. For now, we content ourselves of a slightly lower level approach. However, you may be a little unhappy with the use of the word \matching" in a mathematical definition. Here is a more formal definition for the same concept.
    [Show full text]
  • Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Boise State University, [email protected]
    Boise State University ScholarWorks Mathematics Undergraduate Theses Department of Mathematics 5-2014 Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Boise State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.boisestate.edu/ math_undergraduate_theses Part of the Set Theory Commons Recommended Citation Rahim, Farighon Abdul, "Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice" (2014). Mathematics Undergraduate Theses. Paper 1. Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Advisor: Samuel Coskey Boise State University May 2014 1 Introduction Sets are all around us. A bag of potato chips, for instance, is a set containing certain number of individual chip’s that are its elements. University is another example of a set with students as its elements. By elements, we mean members. But sets should not be confused as to what they really are. A daughter of a blacksmith is an element of a set that contains her mother, father, and her siblings. Then this set is an element of a set that contains all the other families that live in the nearby town. So a set itself can be an element of a bigger set. In mathematics, axiom is defined to be a rule or a statement that is accepted to be true regardless of having to prove it. In a sense, axioms are self evident. In set theory, we deal with sets. Each time we state an axiom, we will do so by considering sets. Example of the set containing the blacksmith family might make it seem as if sets are finite.
    [Show full text]
  • DISCONTINUITY SETS of SOME INTERVAL BIJECTIONS E. De
    International Journal of Pure and Applied Mathematics Volume 79 No. 1 2012, 47-55 AP ISSN: 1311-8080 (printed version) url: http://www.ijpam.eu ijpam.eu DISCONTINUITY SETS OF SOME INTERVAL BIJECTIONS E. de Amo1 §, M. D´ıaz Carrillo2, J. Fern´andez S´anchez3 1,3Departamento de Algebra´ y An´alisis Matem´atico Universidad de Almer´ıa 04120, Almer´ıa, SPAIN 2Departamento de An´alisis Matem´atico Universidad de Granada 18071, Granada, SPAIN Abstract: In this paper we prove that the discontinuity set of any bijective function from [a, b[ to [c, d] is infinite. We then proceed to give a gallery of examples which shows that this is the best we can expect, and that it is possible that any intermediate case exists. We conclude with an example of a (nowhere continuous) bijective function which exhibits a dense graph in the rectangle [a, b[ × [c, d] . AMS Subject Classification: 26A06, 26A09 Key Words: discontinuity set, fixed point 1. Introduction During our investigations [1] concerning on the application of Ergodic Theory of Numbers to generate singular functions (i.e., their derivatives vanish almost everywhere), we came across a bijection from a closed interval to another that it is not closed: c : [0, 1] −→ [0, 1[, given by (segments on some intervals): (n − 1)! n! − 1 1 c (x) := x − + n n2 n + 1 1 1 1 1 which maps 1 − n! , 1 − (n+1)! onto n+1 , n and c(1) = 0. h h h h c 2012 Academic Publications, Ltd. Received: April 19, 2012 url: www.acadpubl.eu §Correspondence author 48 E.
    [Show full text]
  • Cardinality and the Nature of Infinity
    Cardinality and The Nature of Infinity Recap from Last Time Functions ● A function f is a mapping such that every value in A is associated with a single value in B. ● For every a ∈ A, there exists some b ∈ B with f(a) = b. ● If f(a) = b0 and f(a) = b1, then b0 = b1. ● If f is a function from A to B, we call A the domain of f andl B the codomain of f. ● We denote that f is a function from A to B by writing f : A → B Injective Functions ● A function f : A → B is called injective (or one-to-one) iff each element of the codomain has at most one element of the domain associated with it. ● A function with this property is called an injection. ● Formally: If f(x0) = f(x1), then x0 = x1 ● An intuition: injective functions label the objects from A using names from B. Surjective Functions ● A function f : A → B is called surjective (or onto) iff each element of the codomain has at least one element of the domain associated with it. ● A function with this property is called a surjection. ● Formally: For any b ∈ B, there exists at least one a ∈ A such that f(a) = b. ● An intuition: surjective functions cover every element of B with at least one element of A. Bijections ● A function that associates each element of the codomain with a unique element of the domain is called bijective. ● Such a function is a bijection. ● Formally, a bijection is a function that is both injective and surjective.
    [Show full text]