{TEXTBOOK} the Philosophical Vision of John Duns Scotus

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

{TEXTBOOK} the Philosophical Vision of John Duns Scotus THE PHILOSOPHICAL VISION OF JOHN DUNS SCOTUS: AN INTRODUCTION PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Mary Elizabeth Ingham,Mechthild Dreyer | 256 pages | 31 Jul 2004 | The Catholic University of America Press | 9780813213705 | English | Washington, United States The Philosophical Vision of John Duns Scotus: An Introduction PDF Book When Scotus rejects the idea that will is merely intellectual appetite, he is saying that there is something fundamentally wrong with eudaimonistic ethics. They would be true no matter what God willed. He just did. Retrieved 18 January Franciscan Friars of the Immaculate. II , the Quaestiones super libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis vols. Allan Hillman Edited by Edward Craig. Scotus argues that if Henry is right about the limitations of our natural powers, even divine illumination is not enough to save us from pervasive uncertainty. Duns Scotus online. Fourth, certain propositions about present sense experience are also known with certainty if they are properly vetted by the intellect in light of the causal judgments derived from experience. For some today, Scotus is one of the most important Franciscan theologians and the founder of Scotism , a special form of Scholasticism. Wolter , p. Wikimedia Commons has media related to John Duns Scotus. Sign in with your library card Please enter your library card number. See also Renaissance philosophy. The First Being is intellectual and volitional, and the intellect and will are identical with the essence of this supreme nature. Wolter, OFM, — Search by title, catalog stock , author, isbn, etc. Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world- wide funding initiative. The conjecture, plausible but by no means certain, is that Scotus would have been ordained as early as canonically permitted. God has one volition ad intra , but this one volition can be related to many opposite things ad extra. Different versions of the proof are given at Lectura 1, d. Unlike the proper attributes of being and the disjunctive transcendentals, however, they are not coextensive with being. And since we cannot look to the uncreated exemplar by our natural powers, certainty is impossible apart from some special divine illumination. France taught me. Williams, Thomas, ed. God could have brought it about 1 that she was never in original sin, 2 she was in sin only for an instant, 3 she was in sin for a period of time, being purged at the last instant. The Philosophical Vision of John Duns Scotus: An Introduction Writer On Being and Cognition: Ordinatio 1. New ideas were included pseudographically in later editions of his work, such as the principle of explosion , now attributed to Pseudo-Scotus. Duns Scotus died unexpectedly in Cologne in November ; the date of his death is traditionally given as 8 November. Scotism flourished well into the seventeenth century, and its influence can be seen in such writers as Descartes and Bramhall. Scotus holds just as Aquinas had held that the human intellect never understands anything without turning towards phantasms Lectura 2, d. Scotus rejected the distinction. Hoffmann, Tobias, The only issue he argues against is the proposition that God cannot have determinate knowledge of the future. He died there in ; the date of his death is traditionally given as 8 November. Prime matter, though entirely without form, could be actual; and a purely immaterial being is not automatically bereft of potentiality. The study of being qua being includes, first of all, the study of the transcendentals, so called because they transcend the division of being into finite and infinite, and the further division of finite being into the ten Aristotelian categories. Different versions of the proof are given at Lectura 1, d. Secondary literature Borland, Tully, and T. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The first covers our obligations to God and consists of the first three commandments: You shall have no other gods before me , You shall not take the name of the Lord your God in vain , and Remember the Sabbath day to keep it holy. For Scotus the natural law in the strict sense contains only those moral propositions that are per se notae ex terminis along with whatever propositions can be derived from them deductively Ordinatio 3, d. An Exposition of the on the Hebdomads of Boethius. Scotus follows Aristotle in identifying matter as what persists through substantial change and substantial form as what makes a given parcel of matter the definite, unique, individual substance that it is. The Decalogue has often been thought of as involving two tablets. Scotus agrees with Thomas Aquinas that all our knowledge of God starts from creatures, and that as a result we can only prove the existence and nature of God by what the medievals call an argument quia reasoning from effect to cause , not by an argument propter quid reasoning from essence to characteristic. Retrieved 18 January Metaphysics , theology , logic , epistemology , ethics. There was nothing constraining him or forcing him to create one thing rather than another. Hence, those entities which are called contingent with respect to their factual existence are necessary with respect to their possible existence — for instance, although "There exists a man" is contingent, nevertheless "It is possible that he exists" is necessary, because his existence does not include any contradiction. Username Please enter your Username. Such a quotation seems to refer to epistemology, with abstracted concepts, rather than with ontology, which Scotus admits can be diverse. DOI: His school was probably at the height of its popularity at the beginning of the seventeenth century; during the sixteenth and the seventeenth centuries there were special Scotist chairs, e. Therefore, it is possible that it is from something else. Henry therefore concludes that if we are to have certainty, we must look to the uncreated exemplar. Franciscan Church , Cologne, Germany. According to tradition, Duns Scotus was educated at a Franciscan studium generale a medieval university , a house behind St Ebbe's Church, Oxford , in a triangular area enclosed by Pennyfarthing Street and running from St Aldate's to the Castle, the Baley and the old wall, [15] where the Friars Minor had moved when the University of Paris was dispersed in — History of Catholic theology. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. The Philosophical Vision of John Duns Scotus: An Introduction Reviews Therefore, it is possible that some item possesses C without dependence on some prior item. A History of Merton College. Duns Scotus was back in Paris before the end of , probably returning in May. Scotus rejected the distinction. II , the Quaestiones super libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis vols. Whitehead Bertrand Russell G. But as Scotus elaborates his views on form and matter, he espouses three important theses that mark him off from some other philosophers of his day: he holds that matter can exist without any form whatsoever, that not all created substances are composites of form and matter, and that one and the same substance can have more than one substantial form. Scotus elaborates a distinct view on hylomorphism , with three important strong theses that differentiate him. The proof for the conclusion that "some efficient cause is simply first such that neither can it be an effect nor can it, by virtue of something other than itself, cause an effect" Ordinatio I. See also Renaissance philosophy. Wishlist Wishlist. But clearly not all changes are accidental changes. The humanity-of-Socrates is individual and non-repeatable, as is the humanity- of-Plato; yet humanity itself is common and repeatable, and it is ontologically prior to any particular exemplification of it Ordinatio 2, d. Third, Scotus says that many of our own acts are as certain as first principles. Ask a Question What would you like to know about this product? But only God is pure actuality. Archived from the original on 27 September John Duns Scotus b. The basic difference comes down to this. In The Catholic Encyclopedia. Scottish Franciscan friar, philosopher and Catholic blessed. Moreover, given that matter is a thing distinct from form, God creates matter directly and immediately; and what God creates immediately, he can conserve immediately. Fairly comprehensive volume, with chapters written by some of the best specialists on Duns Scotus, with strong emphasis on analytic accuracy and less on historical context. Briefly, Scotus begins his proof by explaining that there are two angles we must take in arguing for the existence of an actually infinite being. In an essentially ordered series, by contrast, the causal activity of later members of the series depends essentially on the causal activity of earlier members. Welcome to Christianbook. On Being and Cognition: Ordinatio 1. Aquinas had argued that in all finite being i. Augustinianism Scholasticism Thomism Scotism Occamism. My arms are capable of moving the golf club only because they are being moved by my shoulders. And even that point is not quite as general as my unqualified statement suggests. Etzkorn, Girard J. Have a question about this product? Given that there is some extra-mental reality common to Socrates and Plato, we also need to know what it is in each of them that makes them distinct exemplifications of that extra-mental reality. Gerard Manley Hopkins was able to reconcile his religious calling and his vocation as a poet thanks to his reading of Duns Scotus. By the time of Scotus, these 'commentaries' on the Sentences were no longer literal commentaries. But he takes this a step further than Anselm. He therefore opposes both skepticism, which denies the possibility of certain knowledge, and illuminationism, which insists that we need special divine illumination in order to attain certainty. Plato Kant Nietzsche. A pure perfection is any predicate that does not imply limitation. Therefore, God is not finite. Scotus counters that we can show that skepticism is false.
Recommended publications
  • |||GET||| Analytical Thomism 1St Edition
    ANALYTICAL THOMISM 1ST EDITION DOWNLOAD FREE Matthew S Pugh | 9781351958554 | | | | | Taking Aquinas Seriously Get A Copy. The Dominican order, to which Aquinas had belonged, defended his thought, and by a number of young teachers were among his strongest advocates. The extensive commentary on the Summa theologiae by Cardinal Cajetan remains unsurpassed for its detailed analysis. Through the influence of traditional Augustinian theologians, some theses of Aquinas were condemned in by the ecclesiastical authorities of Paris and Oxford the most important theological schools in the Middle Ages. Next Article. The rest of what you need we teach at VIU. In philosophy, Aquinas ' disputed questions and commentaries on Aristotle are perhaps his best-known Analytical Thomism 1st edition. Aristotle's De anima On the Soul divides the mind into three parts: sensationimagination and intellection. I also recommend that you read all of C. Consequently, God's causality is never in competition with the causality of creatures; rather, God even causes some things through the causality of creatures. It illuminates the Analytical Thomism 1st edition of Aquinas's work for contemporary problems by drawing on the resources of contemporary Anglo- Saxon analytical philosophy, the work of Frege, Wittgenstein, and Kripke proving particularly significant. See also: God. Mazdakism Mithraism Zoroastrianism Zurvanism. Lists with This Book. Get A Copy. The dominant theme was metaphysics Analytical Thomism 1st edition the study of being reality. But I am a knowing and moral being which is undeniable. The cover caught my attention. Repeated legislation of the General Chapters, beginning after the death of St. Aristotle categorized causality into four Analytical Thomism 1st edition in the Metaphysicswhich is an integral part of Thomism:.
    [Show full text]
  • Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations Spring 2010 Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Jason Skirry University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Skirry, Jason, "Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection" (2010). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 179. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Abstract This dissertation presents a unified interpretation of Malebranche’s philosophical system that is based on his Augustinian theory of the mind’s perfection, which consists in maximizing the mind’s ability to successfully access, comprehend, and follow God’s Order through practices that purify and cognitively enhance the mind’s attention. I argue that the mind’s perfection figures centrally in Malebranche’s philosophy and is the main hub that connects and reconciles the three fundamental principles of his system, namely, his occasionalism, divine illumination, and freedom. To demonstrate this, I first present, in chapter one, Malebranche’s philosophy within the historical and intellectual context of his membership in the French Oratory, arguing that the Oratory’s particular brand of Augustinianism, initiated by Cardinal Bérulle and propagated by Oratorians such as Andre Martin, is at the core of his philosophy and informs his theory of perfection. Next, in chapter two, I explicate Augustine’s own theory of perfection in order to provide an outline, and a basis of comparison, for Malebranche’s own theory of perfection.
    [Show full text]
  • Heinrich Rommen, the Natural Law: a Study in Legal and Social History and Philosophy (1936)
    Rommen_0017 09/15/2005 09:46 AM THE ONLINE LIBRARY OF LIBERTY © Liberty Fund, Inc. 2005 http://oll.libertyfund.org/Home3/index.php HEINRICH ROMMEN, THE NATURAL LAW: A STUDY IN LEGAL AND SOCIAL HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY (1936) URL of this E-Book: http://oll.libertyfund.org/EBooks/Rommen_0017.pdf URL of original HTML file: http://oll.libertyfund.org/Home3/HTML.php?recordID=0017 ABOUT THE AUTHOR Heinrich Rommen was a Catholic German lawyer who practised in Germany during the Weimar Republic before fleeing to the United States in 1938. He taught in Germany and England before concluding his distinguished scholarly career at Georgetown University. ABOUT THE BOOK Originally published in German in 1936, The Natural Law is the first work to clarify the differences between traditional natural law as represented in the writings of Cicero, Aquinas, and Hooker and the revolutionary doctrines of natural rights espoused by Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau. Beginning with the legacies of Greek and Roman life and thought, Rommen traces the natural law tradition to its displacement by legal positivism and concludes with what the author calls "the reappearance" of natural law thought in more recent times. In seven chapters each Rommen explores "The History of the Idea of Natural Law" and "The Philosophy and Content of the Natural Law." In his introduction, Russell Hittinger places Rommen’s work in the context of contemporary debate on the relevance of natural law to philosophical inquiry and constitutional interpretation. THE EDITION USED The Natural Law: A Study in Legal and Social History and Philosophy, trans. Thomas R.
    [Show full text]
  • Friars' Bookshelf 353
    The Silence of Saint Thoma1: Three Eswys. By Josef Pieper. New York, Pantheon Boo ks, 1957. pp. 122. $2 .75. Silence of Saint Thonws: a compelling title! We who know so well the vigor and clarity of Thomas's voice, is it not somewhat sur­ prising that we should be invited to think on his silence! And yet, as Josef Pieper points out in these three masterful essays, it is one of the most significant traits of the Angelic Doctor. For his silence is nothing more than Thomas's deep reverence for mystery. Easily said, and easily agreed to; but do we, as our minds dwell on the articulate rationality of his every argument, do we really grasp the full meaning of this reverence? To grasp it would be to share, to make our own, the silence of Saint Thomas. Silence to listen, to hear in peace and purity the secret whisper­ ings of God and of reality. And silence, a certain reticence, in speak­ ing: " ... it is as straw." Thomas was silent, ultimately, because he knew that human words could not give full expression to the meaning of reality, could never give full answer to the age-old metaphysical question. For the very ontological truth of things, their conformity to plan, their constant "nature" which alone makes them knowable, is not itself fully known except in the inscrutable depths of the Divine Intellect creatively thinking it. This is the thesis of Josef P ieper: Human knowledge is at the same time true and not fully sufficient. True, because it attains to nature; inadequate, because nature is sunk deep in Divinity.
    [Show full text]
  • Sauterdivineansamplepages (Pdf)
    The Decline of Space: Euclid between the Ancient and Medieval Worlds Michael J. Sauter División de Historia Centro de Investigación y Docencia Económicas, A.C. Carretera México-Toluca 3655 Colonia Lomas de Santa Fe 01210 México, Distrito Federal Tel: (+52) 55-5727-9800 x2150 Table of Contents List of Illustrations ............................................................................................................. iv Acknowledgments .............................................................................................................. v Preface ............................................................................................................................... vi Introduction: The divine and the decline of space .............................................................. 1 Chapter 1: Divinus absconditus .......................................................................................... 2 Chapter 2: The problem of continuity ............................................................................... 19 Chapter 3: The space of hierarchy .................................................................................... 21 Chapter 4: Euclid in Purgatory ......................................................................................... 40 Chapter 5: The ladder of reason ........................................................................................ 63 Chapter 6: The harvest of homogeneity ............................................................................ 98 Conclusion: The
    [Show full text]
  • Predication and the Problem of Universals Catherine Legg
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Research Commons@Waikato Philosophical Papers Vol. 30, No. 2 (July 2001): 117-143 Predication and the Problem of Universals Catherine Legg Abstract: This paper contrasts the scholastic realists of David Armstrong and Charles Peirce. It is argued that the so-called 'problem of universals' is not a problem in pure ontology (concerning whether universals exist) as Armstrong construes it to be. Rather, it extends to issues concerning which predicates should be applied where, issues which Armstrong sets aside under the label of 'semantics', and which from a Peircean perspective encompass even the fundamentals of scientific methodology. It is argued that Peir ce's scholastic realism not only presents a more nuanced ontology (distinguishing the existent front the real) but also provides more of a sense of why realism should be a position worth fighting for. ... a realist is simply one who knows no more recondite reality than that which is represented in a true representation. C.S. Peirce Like many other philosophical problems, the grandly-named 'Problem of Universals' is difficult to define without begging the question that it raises. Laurence Goldstein, however, provides a helpful hands-off denotation of the problem by noting that it proceeds from what he calls The Trivial Obseruation:2 The observation is the seemingly incontrovertible claim that, 'sometimes some things have something in common'. The 1 Philosophical Writings of Peirce, ed. Justus Buehler (New York: Dover Publications, 1955), 248. 2 Laurence Goldstein, 'Scientific Scotism – The Emperor's New Trousers or Has Armstrong Made Some Real Strides?', Australasian Journal of Philosophy, vol 61, No.
    [Show full text]
  • Contemporary Perspectives on Natural Law
    1 CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES ON NATURAL LAW 2 [Dedication/series information/blank page] 3 CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES ON NATURAL LAW NATURAL LAW AS A LIMITING CONCEPT 4 [Copyright information supplied by Ashgate] 5 CONTENTS Note on the sources and key to abbreviations and translations Introduction Part One The Concept of Natural Law 1. Ana Marta González. Natural Law as a Limiting Concept. A Reading of Thomas Aquinas Part Two Historical Studies 2. Russell Hittinger. Natural Law and the Human City 3. Juan Cruz. The Formal Foundation of Natural Law in the Golden Age. Vázquez and Suárez’s case 4. Knud Haakonssen. Natural Law without Metaphysics. A Protestant Tradition 5. Jeffrey Edwards. Natural Law and Obligation in Hutcheson and Kant 6. María Jesús Soto–Bruna. Spontaneity and the Law of Nature. Leibniz and the Precritical Kant 7. Alejandro Vigo. Kant’s Conception of Natural Right 8. Montserrat Herrero. The Right of Freedom Regarding Nature in G. W. F. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right 6 Part Three Controversial Issues about Natural Law 9. Alfredo Cruz. Natural Law and Practical Philosophy. The Presence of a Theological Concept in Moral Knowledge 10. Alejandro Llano. First Principles and Practical Philosophy 11. Christopher Martin. The Relativity of Goodness: a Prolegomenon to a Rapprochement between Virtue Ethics and Natural Law Theory 12. Urbano Ferrer. Does the Naturalistic Fallacy Reach Natural Law? 13. Carmelo Vigna. Human Universality and Natural Law Part Four Natural Law and Science 14. Richard Hassing. Difficulties for Natural Law Based on Modern Conceptions of Nature 15. John Deely. Evolution, Semiosis, and Ethics: Rethinking the Context of Natural Law 16.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Issues in the Long Scotist Tradition
    Online Conference 11-13 February 2021 Cognitive Issues in the Long Scotist Tradition Thursday 11/2 Cognitive Issues in Early Scotism Chair: Daniel Heider 12:45–13:00 CET Introduction Daniel Heider and Claus A. Andersen 13:00–13:50 CET Giorgio Pini (Fordham University, New York): In God’s Mind: Divine Cognition in Duns Scotus and Some Scotists 14:00–14:50 CET Richard Cross (Notre Dame University): The Ontological Status of esse intelligibile in William of Alnwick Coffee Break 15:10–16:00 CET Francesco Fiorentino (Q. Orazio Flacco High School, Bari): Cognitive Being and the Divine Ideas in the First Two Centuries of Scotism 16:10–17:00 CET Marina Fedeli (University of Macerata): The Species Intelligibilis in the Cognitive Process in Early Scotism, especially in Alnwick Coffee Break 17:20–18:10 CET Damian Park (Boston College): The Non-Beatific Vision of God according to Franciscus de Mayronis (c. 1285–1328) Friday 12/2 Cognitive Issues in Scotism and Reformed Protestant Thought Chair: Ueli Zahnd 11:00–11:50 CET Ueli Zahnd (University of Geneva): The Epistemological Limits of Religious Images: On the Scotist Sources of a Reformed Theological Tenet 12:00–12:50 CET Arthur Huiban (University of Geneva): Melanchthon and the Will: An Early Protestant Reception of Scotist Epistemology? Coffee Break 13:10–13:50 CET Giovanni Gellera (University of Geneva): Univocity of Being, the Cogito and “Proto-Idealism in Johannes Clauberg (16221665) Lunch break Cognitive Issues in Baroque Scotism I Chair: Claus A. Andersen 15:00–15:50 CET Daniel Heider (University
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Law in the Renaissance Period, We Must Look Elsewhere
    THE NATURAL LAW IN THE RENAISSANCE PERIOD* Heinrich A. Rommen I T HE Renaissance period is usually associated with the Arts and with Literature; it is considered as a new birth of the Greek and Roman classics but also as the discovery of a new sense of life, as a period in which the autonomous individual, as the person in a pronounced meaning, escapes from the pre-eminence of the clergy and a morality determined by the Church. Nourished by the rediscovered philosophy of life of the classics, an emancipation takes place of the man of the world, of the man of secular learning, and of the artist and the poet, who set themselves up as of their own right beside, not against, the secular clergy and the learned monk. In politics this means the dissolution of the medieval union of Church and Empire in favor of the now fully devel- oped nation-states and city-republics which stress their autonomy against the Church as against the Empire. While the Renaissance, thus conceived, was of tremen- dous significance, it is nevertheless true that as such it con- tributed little for the development of the theory of Nat- ural Law. The reason for this is that the Humanists were admirers of the stoic philosophy and of the great orator, Cicero, the elegant popularizer of the stoic philosophy and of the philosophical ideas of the Roman Law, which, * Also printed in the Summer, 1949, issue of the Notre Dame Lawyer. 89 NATURAtL LAW INSTITUTE PROCEEDINGS at that time, freed from the Canon Law, conquered the world again.
    [Show full text]
  • The Question of Modernity in the Political Thought of Heinrich Rommen
    3 The Question of Modernity in the Political Thought of Heinrich Rommen William Haggerty Introduction or every thoughtful student of Catholic political theory, modernity must Fremain a problem, a question. Given its close association with the history and traditions of the pre-modern world, the Church has never had an easy or uncomplicated relation with the political ideas and movements of the modern era. And insofar as most of the intellectual architects of the modern horizon established their teaching in response (if not in direct opposition) to the theological and philosophical positions embodied in orthodox Christianity, it seems an essential task for the Catholic theorist to attempt, in some manner or form, to come to terms with their claims. The German political thinker, Professor Heinrich A. Rommen, is no exception to this rule. In his magisterial study, The State in Catholic Thought, he presents an exhaustive account of the Catholic tradition in political and social philosophy. Though he does not ignore the history of modern practice, he is more interested in examining the response of Catholic thought to modern political philosophy and its intellectual challenges. Along with other theorists in the mid-century Neo-scholastic revival, he would maintain that the orthodox Christian teaching provides a helpful corrective to possible excesses in modern theory partly because it places or locates "politics" within a certain designated sphere. But what are the grounds of his criticism of modernity? What does he consider to be the characteristic excesses or abuses in modern political philosophy? And what remedy, in his estimation, can Catholic political thought offer to cure the ills of modernity? In responding to a criticism in The State in Catholic Thought, Rommen refers to an idea that helps answer these questions.
    [Show full text]
  • Kierkegaard and Belief James Joseph Dagenais Loyola University Chicago
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1957 Kierkegaard and Belief James Joseph Dagenais Loyola University Chicago Recommended Citation Dagenais, James Joseph, "Kierkegaard and Belief " (1957). Master's Theses. Paper 1380. http://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/1380 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1957 James Joseph Dagenais lCIERIEGAA.RD AND BRLIEF by Jame8 Joeeph Dagena18~ S.J. A. Thesis Submitted to the Faculty at the Graduate School at Loyola University in Partial Fultillment of the Requ:1rements tor the Degree at Muter at Arts February 19S7 LIFE JaJIles Joseph Dagenais was bom in Blue Island, illinois, June 12, 1928. He was graduated from St. Ignatius High School, Chicago, Illinois, June, 1946, and entered the Society of Jesus at. Milf'ord, Ohio, in September of the aame year. Atter two ,..arst Iovitiate and two ,..ars spent. in the studT of the Human.­ ities at Milford, Ohio, he was transferred, in August, 19SO, to West Baden College, West Baden Springs, Indiana, where he studied Philosophy ter three ",ars. He reee1Ted his Bachelor ot Arts Degree trom Loyo~ UniTersitr, Chicago, D.linois, in June, 1951, and began his graduate studies in Loyola University in September, 1952. Fran 1953 to 19S6 the author taught English am Latin at the University of of Detroit High School, Detroit, Michigan, where he also assisted in the De- partment of Speech.
    [Show full text]
  • The Virtue of Faith in Theology, Natural Science, and Philosophy
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 15 Issue 4 Article 3 10-1-1998 The Virtue of Faith in Theology, Natural Science, and Philosophy Kenneth W. Kemp Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Kemp, Kenneth W. (1998) "The Virtue of Faith in Theology, Natural Science, and Philosophy," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 15 : Iss. 4 , Article 3. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil199815443 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol15/iss4/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. THE VIRTUE OF FAITH IN THEOLOGY, NATURAL SCIENCE, AND PHILOSOPHY Kenneth W. Kemp In this paper, I attempt to develop the account of intellectual virtues offered by Aristotle and St. Thomas in a way which recognizes faith as a good intellectual habit. I go on to argue that, as a practical matter, this virtue is needed not only in theology, where it provides the basis of further intellectual work, but also in the natural sciences, where it is required given the complexity of the subject matter and the cooperative nature of the enterprise. There are various ways in which a comparison and contrast between theology, natural science, and philosophy can be made. It is instructive, for example, to raise the question of whether, and if so to what extent, they have a common object.
    [Show full text]