Kierkegaard and Belief James Joseph Dagenais Loyola University Chicago

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Kierkegaard and Belief James Joseph Dagenais Loyola University Chicago Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1957 Kierkegaard and Belief James Joseph Dagenais Loyola University Chicago Recommended Citation Dagenais, James Joseph, "Kierkegaard and Belief " (1957). Master's Theses. Paper 1380. http://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/1380 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1957 James Joseph Dagenais lCIERIEGAA.RD AND BRLIEF by Jame8 Joeeph Dagena18~ S.J. A. Thesis Submitted to the Faculty at the Graduate School at Loyola University in Partial Fultillment of the Requ:1rements tor the Degree at Muter at Arts February 19S7 LIFE JaJIles Joseph Dagenais was bom in Blue Island, illinois, June 12, 1928. He was graduated from St. Ignatius High School, Chicago, Illinois, June, 1946, and entered the Society of Jesus at. Milf'ord, Ohio, in September of the aame year. Atter two ,..arst Iovitiate and two ,..ars spent. in the studT of the Human.­ ities at Milford, Ohio, he was transferred, in August, 19SO, to West Baden College, West Baden Springs, Indiana, where he studied Philosophy ter three ",ars. He reee1Ted his Bachelor ot Arts Degree trom Loyo~ UniTersitr, Chicago, D.linois, in June, 1951, and began his graduate studies in Loyola University in September, 1952. Fran 1953 to 19S6 the author taught English am Latin at the University of of Detroit High School, Detroit, Michigan, where he also assisted in the De- partment of Speech. At present, the writer 18 pursuing the stud1' of theology at West Baden College in preparation tor the priesthood. ill PREFA.CE Several years of association with the subjoct-matter of the thesis has taught the author that he is presenting only a brief introduction to ICiarke­ gaardts Phi1080Ph;y or Religion. In spite of this llrd.tation, however, the th sis may ~pear to the reader to be too 1en.gtb.y'. It was thought best, therefor to omit an expanded treatment of Kierlcegaard's.llf'e and the background of the times in which be l1yed. The interested reader I'IIIA7 find this information in the following works. E. L. Allen, Existentialism From Within, (London, 1953), pp. 3-7; Walter Lowrie, !. Short ~ £'!. K1erkegaard (Princeton, New Jcosey, 1944), pp. 1-16J H. V. Martin, Kierkegaard, !h!. Melanchol;r l?!!!! (London, 1950), pp. 24-33. Denail Patrick, Pascal !!!.2 Kicokegaard (London, 1941), pp. 1-40; Reidar Thomte, Kierkegaard.'s Philosophy .2! Religion (Princeton, New Jersey, 1948), pp. 3-1. The word "Bellef" is used in the title to signify that the prima.ry occu­ patlon of the thesis is with the psychological and ontological character of human belief', and not wi til Supernatural Fa!th. Very special thanks are due to the ReY'erend Robert F. HarV'cu, S.J., ot West Baden College and to the ReYermd Robert W. Mulligan, S.J., of 1o)"Ola University for their ldn&Iness and helptulnes8, and to Mrs. C. P. Culhane, of Detroit, Michigan. t«> undertaking the task ot typing the final copies. iv TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter Page I. INTRODtXTION A. Kierkegaard'. Lite. 1. The elder K1erkegaard • • • • • • • • • • • 1 2. Relationship between father and BOn, a. Inheritance or imag1na tion .. • • .. • • .. 2 b. Inheritance of dialectic • • • .. .. • • 3 i c. Inheritance of convictions • • • .. .. .. • 3 3. Karkegeard's University Lite. a. From 1830 to the moral regeneration of 1837 .. • • .. .. .. • .. .. .. .. • • .. • • • 4 b. From 1837 to the lPiritual· regeneration or 1838 • • • • • • • .. • .. .. • • .. .. .. 4 4. Eng~nt to Regine Olsen • • • • • • .. • , ,.. The Corsair Incident .. .. • .. • .. ·.. • • • • .. 6 6. Att&dC upon the Established Church • .. • • .. 7 7.. Death ani Burial • • .. • • • • • • • .. • • 8 B. Kierkegaard t s Workst 1. The pseudonymous works • • .. .. • • .. .. • .. • 9 2. The polemical works • • .. • .. • .. • • .. .. • • 10 3. The devotional works .. • .. .. .. • • • .. • .. 10 4.. The pseudonJlRlls • .. .. • • .. • 11 • • • • • • • of C. The object or the thesis .. • • .. .. .. .. .. • • • .. 13 II. SOURCES OF KIERK'EG.URDtS OONCEPT OF BELIEF A. Introduction ............... • • • • • • 14 B. Catholic Doctrine or Supernatural Faith • • • • .. 14 C. The Theological scuree. of Kierkegaard t s concept or belief, Martin Luther ............... .. 16 1. Sources or Luther's doctrines ......... .. 17 2. Luther's teachings on man and Faith • .. .. • .. 18 3. Luther t s voluntarism md emotionalism • .. • • 19 D. The Philosophical sources or K1erkegaard's concept of beliefs Locke, Hunte, and Kant ........... .. 20 1. I.oek:. • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • 21 2. HUIle ••• • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • 22 3. Karl' •• • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • 2, vi III. KIERKEOAARDtS ATTACK UPON DETERMINISM AND RJMA.NTICISM A. Introduction •••••••••••• • • • • • • 29 B. Kierkegaardts attack upon Hegelian Determinismt 1. Introduction: a. K1erkegaani's relationship to Hegel •• 30 b. K1erkegaard.'s 1n.teUectllal and religious motivation • ••••••••••••• 31 c. Kierkegaard's interest in the individual 32 d. K1erkegaard' s Rom.antic outlook • • • • • 33 2. Three anti-Hegelian theses: a. The first thesis I i. Hegel's world-historical outlook ls . damaging to Eth1 cs •••••••• 3S .\ li. Kierkegaardts thesis of man's tree relationship with God • • • • • • • 37 r- b. The second thesis: , i. "A logical .,stem. is possible: an existential system. is impossible." 37 ii. Kierkegaard on the contingency of existence ••••••••••••• 41 c. The third the Ii•• 1. Hegel cannot justifY change •••• 43 ii. K1erkegaard on "becoming n s' Three proofs • • • • • • • • • 44 Belief as correlative to existential "beeoming" •••• 47 3. S\l1'!PI8.r1' • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • .. • • • 48 C. 1Cierkegaard t s attack upon Romantic aestheticism: 1. Introduction, The dialectics a. Hegelian dialectic • • • • • • • • • • • 50 b. Kierkegaard's dialectic •••••••• Sl 2. Doctrine of the Three Stages. a. Characteristics of the Stages ••••• 52 b. The Stages theselvesa i. The aesthetic Stage • • • • • • • • 53 ii. The Ethical Stage •••••••• iii. Transition to Religious Stage • • • ~~ D. S'IllIImB.ry' • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • 60 IV. THE ~ OF BELIEP' A. Introduction ................". 62 B. The Third Stage of Exist.ence, the Religious. 1. Kierkegaard' $ problem. I becollling a Christian 64 a. Mants relationship to Christianity cannot be "objective" ...".... 66 b. Mants relationship to Christianity l1lUSt be -subjective". The Subjectivity of Truth. • 68 i. The nature of the Subjective thinker 71 Passion • • • • • • • • • • • 72 Three Expressions • • • • • • 72 ii. The need for a subjective relation­ ship: Repetition • • • • • • • • • 76 iii. The object of the relationship: An Absolute telos which is also a contin­ gent, historical fact • • • • • • • 18 iv. The means of relating: Religiousness A, Religiousness B • • • • • • • • • • • 80 v. The difficulty of rela1dng c Paradoxes ••••••••• • • • • • 82 vi. The aot of relating: The Freedom of Faith • • • • • • • • • • •• • • • • 86 vii. The resul.t s of the relatdonab1.p • • • 89 c. Summary . .. .. 90 V. SUMMARY AND EVALUATION A. Summary of the Thesis • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • 93 B. Evaluation of Kierkegaards 1. Intelligibility of b1.s doctrines in the light of the history of Philosopny • • • • • • • • • 96 a. Subjectivity before Aquinas • • ~ • • • • 97 b. Subjectivi tT after Aquinas ••••••• 98 c. The subj ectivity of belief in Thom1S1'1l • • 98 d. The subjectivity of belief in Modern Philosophy • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • 101 2. Conclusions concerning the subjectivity of belief • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • ... 104 3. lUerkegaard and the subjectivitY' of beliet • • lOS 4. Practical assent in belief. a. According to Cardinal Newman ••• • • • 106 b. According to St. Ignatius Loyola • • • • 107 C. CriticieM of Xlerkegaard I 1. Positive contributions of Klerkegaard •••• 108 2. Vitiating elements of Kierkegaard's contribu­ tions a. His denial or the value or reason for faith • . • . • . • • • • • • • 109 b. His denial of the validity or objective tl'Uth ••••••••••••••••• 110 c. His denial of objective certitude ••• ll2 D. conclusion • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • 113 BIBLIOGRAPHY • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • 122 CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION Sor~ Aabye Kierkegaard was bom in Copenhagen. Denmark. on May 5. 181.3. the seventh and last child of Michael Pedersen Kierkegaard and Ana ~rensdatter Lund Kurkegaard. Ane was Michael Kierkegaard's second wite (his first wife having died childless atter two years of married. life), and had been a maid- servant in his home. The father, Michael K1erkegaard, bad risen .from the sta­ tus of a hungry shepherd boT on the West Jutland heaths to a position of wealth as a hoaier in the city of Copenhagen. At the age of fortT, thirteen years We1"ore the birth of ~ren, he decided that he had 'earned enough money to live the rest or his lite in retirement. He spent his time thereatter reading and pondering religious and phUosophica.l questions.l Michael Kierkegaard was a man of deep and brooding dLsposition,.. given to cea8eles8 introspection. As a boy, he had cursed God for allowing him, a poor and hungry shepherd to suffer so much without coming to his aid. ae looked upon his later prosperitT as God' 8 answer to his
Recommended publications
  • |||GET||| Analytical Thomism 1St Edition
    ANALYTICAL THOMISM 1ST EDITION DOWNLOAD FREE Matthew S Pugh | 9781351958554 | | | | | Taking Aquinas Seriously Get A Copy. The Dominican order, to which Aquinas had belonged, defended his thought, and by a number of young teachers were among his strongest advocates. The extensive commentary on the Summa theologiae by Cardinal Cajetan remains unsurpassed for its detailed analysis. Through the influence of traditional Augustinian theologians, some theses of Aquinas were condemned in by the ecclesiastical authorities of Paris and Oxford the most important theological schools in the Middle Ages. Next Article. The rest of what you need we teach at VIU. In philosophy, Aquinas ' disputed questions and commentaries on Aristotle are perhaps his best-known Analytical Thomism 1st edition. Aristotle's De anima On the Soul divides the mind into three parts: sensationimagination and intellection. I also recommend that you read all of C. Consequently, God's causality is never in competition with the causality of creatures; rather, God even causes some things through the causality of creatures. It illuminates the Analytical Thomism 1st edition of Aquinas's work for contemporary problems by drawing on the resources of contemporary Anglo- Saxon analytical philosophy, the work of Frege, Wittgenstein, and Kripke proving particularly significant. See also: God. Mazdakism Mithraism Zoroastrianism Zurvanism. Lists with This Book. Get A Copy. The dominant theme was metaphysics Analytical Thomism 1st edition the study of being reality. But I am a knowing and moral being which is undeniable. The cover caught my attention. Repeated legislation of the General Chapters, beginning after the death of St. Aristotle categorized causality into four Analytical Thomism 1st edition in the Metaphysicswhich is an integral part of Thomism:.
    [Show full text]
  • Heinrich Rommen, the Natural Law: a Study in Legal and Social History and Philosophy (1936)
    Rommen_0017 09/15/2005 09:46 AM THE ONLINE LIBRARY OF LIBERTY © Liberty Fund, Inc. 2005 http://oll.libertyfund.org/Home3/index.php HEINRICH ROMMEN, THE NATURAL LAW: A STUDY IN LEGAL AND SOCIAL HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY (1936) URL of this E-Book: http://oll.libertyfund.org/EBooks/Rommen_0017.pdf URL of original HTML file: http://oll.libertyfund.org/Home3/HTML.php?recordID=0017 ABOUT THE AUTHOR Heinrich Rommen was a Catholic German lawyer who practised in Germany during the Weimar Republic before fleeing to the United States in 1938. He taught in Germany and England before concluding his distinguished scholarly career at Georgetown University. ABOUT THE BOOK Originally published in German in 1936, The Natural Law is the first work to clarify the differences between traditional natural law as represented in the writings of Cicero, Aquinas, and Hooker and the revolutionary doctrines of natural rights espoused by Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau. Beginning with the legacies of Greek and Roman life and thought, Rommen traces the natural law tradition to its displacement by legal positivism and concludes with what the author calls "the reappearance" of natural law thought in more recent times. In seven chapters each Rommen explores "The History of the Idea of Natural Law" and "The Philosophy and Content of the Natural Law." In his introduction, Russell Hittinger places Rommen’s work in the context of contemporary debate on the relevance of natural law to philosophical inquiry and constitutional interpretation. THE EDITION USED The Natural Law: A Study in Legal and Social History and Philosophy, trans. Thomas R.
    [Show full text]
  • Friars' Bookshelf 353
    The Silence of Saint Thoma1: Three Eswys. By Josef Pieper. New York, Pantheon Boo ks, 1957. pp. 122. $2 .75. Silence of Saint Thonws: a compelling title! We who know so well the vigor and clarity of Thomas's voice, is it not somewhat sur­ prising that we should be invited to think on his silence! And yet, as Josef Pieper points out in these three masterful essays, it is one of the most significant traits of the Angelic Doctor. For his silence is nothing more than Thomas's deep reverence for mystery. Easily said, and easily agreed to; but do we, as our minds dwell on the articulate rationality of his every argument, do we really grasp the full meaning of this reverence? To grasp it would be to share, to make our own, the silence of Saint Thomas. Silence to listen, to hear in peace and purity the secret whisper­ ings of God and of reality. And silence, a certain reticence, in speak­ ing: " ... it is as straw." Thomas was silent, ultimately, because he knew that human words could not give full expression to the meaning of reality, could never give full answer to the age-old metaphysical question. For the very ontological truth of things, their conformity to plan, their constant "nature" which alone makes them knowable, is not itself fully known except in the inscrutable depths of the Divine Intellect creatively thinking it. This is the thesis of Josef P ieper: Human knowledge is at the same time true and not fully sufficient. True, because it attains to nature; inadequate, because nature is sunk deep in Divinity.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Law in the Renaissance Period, We Must Look Elsewhere
    THE NATURAL LAW IN THE RENAISSANCE PERIOD* Heinrich A. Rommen I T HE Renaissance period is usually associated with the Arts and with Literature; it is considered as a new birth of the Greek and Roman classics but also as the discovery of a new sense of life, as a period in which the autonomous individual, as the person in a pronounced meaning, escapes from the pre-eminence of the clergy and a morality determined by the Church. Nourished by the rediscovered philosophy of life of the classics, an emancipation takes place of the man of the world, of the man of secular learning, and of the artist and the poet, who set themselves up as of their own right beside, not against, the secular clergy and the learned monk. In politics this means the dissolution of the medieval union of Church and Empire in favor of the now fully devel- oped nation-states and city-republics which stress their autonomy against the Church as against the Empire. While the Renaissance, thus conceived, was of tremen- dous significance, it is nevertheless true that as such it con- tributed little for the development of the theory of Nat- ural Law. The reason for this is that the Humanists were admirers of the stoic philosophy and of the great orator, Cicero, the elegant popularizer of the stoic philosophy and of the philosophical ideas of the Roman Law, which, * Also printed in the Summer, 1949, issue of the Notre Dame Lawyer. 89 NATURAtL LAW INSTITUTE PROCEEDINGS at that time, freed from the Canon Law, conquered the world again.
    [Show full text]
  • The Question of Modernity in the Political Thought of Heinrich Rommen
    3 The Question of Modernity in the Political Thought of Heinrich Rommen William Haggerty Introduction or every thoughtful student of Catholic political theory, modernity must Fremain a problem, a question. Given its close association with the history and traditions of the pre-modern world, the Church has never had an easy or uncomplicated relation with the political ideas and movements of the modern era. And insofar as most of the intellectual architects of the modern horizon established their teaching in response (if not in direct opposition) to the theological and philosophical positions embodied in orthodox Christianity, it seems an essential task for the Catholic theorist to attempt, in some manner or form, to come to terms with their claims. The German political thinker, Professor Heinrich A. Rommen, is no exception to this rule. In his magisterial study, The State in Catholic Thought, he presents an exhaustive account of the Catholic tradition in political and social philosophy. Though he does not ignore the history of modern practice, he is more interested in examining the response of Catholic thought to modern political philosophy and its intellectual challenges. Along with other theorists in the mid-century Neo-scholastic revival, he would maintain that the orthodox Christian teaching provides a helpful corrective to possible excesses in modern theory partly because it places or locates "politics" within a certain designated sphere. But what are the grounds of his criticism of modernity? What does he consider to be the characteristic excesses or abuses in modern political philosophy? And what remedy, in his estimation, can Catholic political thought offer to cure the ills of modernity? In responding to a criticism in The State in Catholic Thought, Rommen refers to an idea that helps answer these questions.
    [Show full text]
  • Indicative Conditionals: Truth Functional Or Non - Truth Functional? an Analysis of the Or - If Inference Jack Waites the University of Sheffield
    PhilonoUS Issue 1, Vol 2 | Autumn 2016 | Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy Indicative Conditionals: Truth Functional or Non - Truth Functional? An Analysis of the Or - If Inference Jack Waites The University of Sheffield pp. 15 - 26 Visit our website at: www.uosphilosophyjournal.wordpress.com © 2016 The University of Sheffield All works contained within are the property of their respective owners. Indicative Conditionals: Truth Functional or Non- Truth Functional? An Analysis of the Or-If Inference Jack Waites The University of Sheffield Introduction In this paper, I will argue that Stalnaker’s non-truth-functional account of indicative conditionals is preferable to Grice and Jackson’s truth-functional account. For the most part, this paper will be concerned with providing an exposition of the truth-functional account of indicative conditionals and demonstrating that the or-if inference can be accounted for without the need to subscribe to the truth-functional equivalence thesis. I will then argue that since the equivalence thesis is not required in accounting for the or- if inference being a good inference to make, we should prefer Stalnaker’s non-truth-functional account for two reasons. Firstly, Stalnaker’s account is preferable on the grounds of semantic Occamism, as it can account for the or-if inference without footing the semantic cost of the truth-functional equivalence thesis. Secondly, it offers us the attractive prospect of a unified account of both indicative and subjunctive conditionals due to its utilisation of possible worlds. 1.0: Indicative Conditionals and the Truth-functional Account Consider the following two statements; “If Edmund is in Manchester, then he is happy” and “if Oswald hadn’t killed Kennedy, someone else would have”.
    [Show full text]
  • Concou()Ia Theological Montbly
    Concou()ia Theological Montbly JUNE 1957 Was Luther a Nominalist? 1 By BENGT HAEGGLUND t-rHE problem of the relation between Luther and the tradition 1 which derives its name from William of Occam 2 has in our time acquired a new interest. Certain Roman Catholic critics are inclined to ascribe the Reformer's heretical ideas to nominalist influences. According to them nominalism bears within itself a ferment of dissolution; it rejects in a radical manner the funda­ mental presuppositions of the whole scholastic theology. Is such a view based on an accurate representation of nominalism? This is a question which we cannot answer within the limits of the present article. Much can be said in favour of the contention; but it must not be forgotten that the theologians who may be regarded as Luther's masters were not in any marked degree innovators. In addition to William of Occam himself, there were Cardinal Pierre d' Ailly and above all Gabriel Biel, professor at Tiibingen, whom his contemporaries regarded as a great theologian. They all kept rigorously within the framework fixed by the Church; though their school met with some opposition at the outset, it ended by becoming dominant in a whole chain of universities that were among the most influential of the period. There are other reasons as well that make a study of the relations of Luther with occamism highly interesting. In spite of the exten­ sive work that has been done on Luther's theology during recent decades, this particular topic has received hardly any attention. No doubt that is partly owing to practical difficulties in the way of all research into nominalist theology.
    [Show full text]
  • Luther's Moral Synthesis: Occamism, Christian Mysticism and the Idea Of
    Luther’s moral synthesis: occamism, Christian mysticism and the idea of being A. Raath Department of Constitutional Law & Philosophy of Law University of the Free State BLOEMFONTEIN E-mail: [email protected] Abstract Luther’s moral synthesis: occamism, Christian mysticism and the idea of being To Luther human beings can only come to true redemptive knowledge through the Word and through faith. Although philosophical knowledge in the domain of man’s earthly exis- tence cannot provide him with true knowledge in matters of faith, such knowledge is of much importance for man’s earthly existence from a moral point of view. By submitting to universal being even unbelievers can gain valuable insights into moral matters. Such moral insights are important for making human co-existence possible in society. Within the broad context of Luther’s Occamist views on knowledge, both German mysticism and the Stoic-Ciceronian idea of being contribute towards a synthesis from which Luther’s views on morals in matters of faith and philosophy respectively emanate. Opsomming Luther se morele sintese: okkamisme, Christelike mistiek en die idee van syn Vir Luther kan die mens slegs tot ware verlossende kennis kom deur die Woord en geloof. Alhoewel filosofiese kennis op die terrein van die mens se aardse bestaan hom nie in staat stel om tot ware kennis in aangeleenthede betreffende die geloof te kom nie, is sodanige kennis vanuit ’n morele oogpunt beskou van groot belang. Deur die agting vir universele syn kan selfs ongelowiges waardevolle insigte in morele aangeleenthede verwerf. Sodanige morele insigte is belangrik vir die menslike saambestaan in die samelewing.
    [Show full text]
  • Popper's Philosophy of Science: Looking Ahead
    Popper's Philosophy of Science: Looking Ahead Peter Godfrey-Smith Philosophy Department Harvard University 2007 Forthcoming in J. Shearmur and G. Stokes (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Popper. 1. Popper's Peculiar Standing 2. Eliminative Inference 3. Skeptical Realism 4. Tests, Risks, and Pseudo-Contact 5. The Diachronic Perspective on Evidence 6. Conclusion 1. Popper's Peculiar Standing Is Popper's philosophy alive or dead? If we make a judgment based on recent discussion in academic philosophy of science, he definitely seems to be fading. Popper is still seen as an important historical figure, a key part of the grand drama of 20th century thinking about science. He is associated with an outlook, a mindset, and a general picture of scientific work. His name has bequeathed us an adjective, "Popperian," that is well established. But the adjective is used for very general ideas that, according to most current philosophers, Popper did not develop convincingly. His detailed account is often seen as attractive on first impression, but full of holes that become bigger rather than smaller as discussion continues. The picture and the name remain, which is more than 1 most philosophers can hope for. But the name attaches more and more to a set of instincts and intuitions, less and less to views that are seeing ongoing philosophical development. Inside science itself, Popper's standing is quite different. He continues to be just about the only philosopher who can seize the imagination and command the loyalty of successful professional scientists. And he is popular within science not only for purposes of general commentary and public relations.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Theology and Natural Philosophy in the Late Renaissance
    Natural theology and natural philosophy in the late Renaissance Thomas Woolford Trinity College This dissertation is submitted to the University of Cambridge for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy November 2011 Declaration This dissertation is the result of my own work and includes nothing which is the outcome of work done in collaboration except where specifically indicated in the text. This dissertation is also not substantially the same as any that I have submitted for a degree or diploma or other qualification at any other University. The length of this dissertation is under 80,000 words. Thomas A. Woolford November 2011 i Acknowledgements Many thanks to the Arts and Humanities Research Council for providing a studentship bursary to enable me to undertake research and to Cambridge University, Trinity College and the School of Humanities for providing an outstanding work environment. I am most grateful for the support, guidance, encouragement and friendship of my supervisor Richard Serjeantson. I’d also like to mention here friends and family who have cared for and supported me: my wonderful wife Julie, Dad, sister Kim, brother-in-law Doug, brother Sam, parents-in-law Margaret and James, friends Tim, Alex, Jon and Chrissy, and our hospitable neighbours Christine and David. To fulfil a twenty-year-old promise, this is dedicated to my cousins Alison and David, but they have to share the dedication with my late mother, Mary. SDG ii Natural theology and natural philosophy in the late Renaissance T. A. Woolford Despite some great strides in relating certain areas of Christian doctrine to the study of the natural world, the category ‘natural theology’ has often been subject to anachronism and misunderstanding.
    [Show full text]
  • Martin Luther – the Problem of Faith and Reason
    Luther’s critics have consistently charged him as an irrationalist and pessimist concer- ning reason’s capabilities, and even by his followers as a fideist who sees little or no David Andersen relationship between faith and reason. In this book, David Andersen offers a fresh and timely re-evaluation of Luther and his understanding of the relationship between faith and reason based upon a thorough en- gagement with Luther’s mature writings. Dr. Andersen persuasively argues that, far from being either an irrationalist or a fideist, Luther stands within an empiricist tradition and Martin Luther – that his pronouncements on fallen human reason can be understood only from that phi- losophical perspective. Based upon recent research into the writings of William of Ock- ham, who positively influenced Luther in this area, Dr. Andersen also shows that Luther can no longer be charged as a pessimist concerning human knowledge. The Problem of Reason has an important role to play for Luther in bringing one to faith, and the objec- tivity of Christ’s resurrection serves as that focal point that validates all Christian dis- Faith and Reason course. In subordinating itself to the facts of the death and resurrection of Christ for the forgiveness of sins, reason’s created function is restored to some extent as it receives A Reexamination in Light of the that forgiveness in the words of Holy Scripture and the visible means of Baptism and the Lord’s Supper. Epistemological and Christological Issues “Luther has long been regarded, both by secular philosophers and by misguided be- lievers, as an irrationalist....A careful reading of Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    On the Law of Nature in the Three States of Life E. J. Hutchinson and Korey D. Maas Introduction Niels Hemmingsen (1513–1600) and the Development of Lutheran Natural-Law Teaching Because the Danish Protestant theologian and philosopher Niels Hemmingsen (1513–1600) is today little known outside his homeland, some of the claims made for his initial importance and continuing impact can appear rather extravagant. He is described, for example, not only as having “dominated” the theology of his own country for half a century1 but more broadly as having been “the greatest builder of systems in his generation.”2 In the light of this indefatigable system building, he has further been credited with (or blamed for) initiating modern trends in critical biblical scholarship,3 as well as for being “one of the founders 1 Lief Grane, “Teaching the People—The Education of the Clergy and the Instruction of the People in the Danish Reformation Church,” in The Danish Reformation against Its International Background, ed. Leif Grane and Kai Hørby (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1990), 167. 2 F. J. Billeskov Janson, “From the Reformation to the Baroque,” in A History of Danish Literature, ed. Sven Hakon Rossel (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1993), 79. 3 Kenneth Hagen, “De Exegetica Methodo: Niels Hemmingsen’s De Methodis (1555),” in The Bible in the Sixteenth Century, ed. David C. Steinmetz (Durham: Duke University Press, 1990), 196. iii 595 Scholia iv Introduction of modern jurisprudence.”4 Illuminating this last claim especially are the more
    [Show full text]