Contemporary Perspectives on Natural Law

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Contemporary Perspectives on Natural Law 1 CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES ON NATURAL LAW 2 [Dedication/series information/blank page] 3 CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES ON NATURAL LAW NATURAL LAW AS A LIMITING CONCEPT 4 [Copyright information supplied by Ashgate] 5 CONTENTS Note on the sources and key to abbreviations and translations Introduction Part One The Concept of Natural Law 1. Ana Marta González. Natural Law as a Limiting Concept. A Reading of Thomas Aquinas Part Two Historical Studies 2. Russell Hittinger. Natural Law and the Human City 3. Juan Cruz. The Formal Foundation of Natural Law in the Golden Age. Vázquez and Suárez’s case 4. Knud Haakonssen. Natural Law without Metaphysics. A Protestant Tradition 5. Jeffrey Edwards. Natural Law and Obligation in Hutcheson and Kant 6. María Jesús Soto–Bruna. Spontaneity and the Law of Nature. Leibniz and the Precritical Kant 7. Alejandro Vigo. Kant’s Conception of Natural Right 8. Montserrat Herrero. The Right of Freedom Regarding Nature in G. W. F. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right 6 Part Three Controversial Issues about Natural Law 9. Alfredo Cruz. Natural Law and Practical Philosophy. The Presence of a Theological Concept in Moral Knowledge 10. Alejandro Llano. First Principles and Practical Philosophy 11. Christopher Martin. The Relativity of Goodness: a Prolegomenon to a Rapprochement between Virtue Ethics and Natural Law Theory 12. Urbano Ferrer. Does the Naturalistic Fallacy Reach Natural Law? 13. Carmelo Vigna. Human Universality and Natural Law Part Four Natural Law and Science 14. Richard Hassing. Difficulties for Natural Law Based on Modern Conceptions of Nature 15. John Deely. Evolution, Semiosis, and Ethics: Rethinking the Context of Natural Law 16. David S. Oderberg. Teleology: Inorganic and Organic 17. Robert Spaemann. The Unrelinquishability of Teleology 7 Key to Abbreviations Aristotle EE = Eudemian Ethics De An. = De anima Metaph. = Metaphysics NE = Nichomachean Ethics Phys. = Physics Thomas Aquinas De malo = Quaestiones disputatae de malo. Opera omnia, vol. 23 (Rome/Louvain: Leonine Commission/Editori de San Tommaso, 1976. De pot. = De potentia, in Quaestiones disputatae, vol. 2 ed. P. Pession (Rome and Turin: Marietti, 1953). De princ. Nat. = De principiis naturae ad Fratrem Sylvestrum. Opera omnia, vol. 43 (Rome: Leonine Commission/Editori di San Tommaso, 1976), pp. 1– 47. De ver. = Quaestiones disputatae de veritate. Opera omnia, vol. 22 (Rome: Leonine Commission/Editori di San Tommaso, 1970–1975). In Ethic = Sentenia libri Ethicorum. Opera omnia, vol. 47 (Rome: Leonine Commission, 1969). 8 In Phys. = In octos libros Physicorum Aristotelis expositio, ed. P.M. Maggiòlo (Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1965) [contains Leonine Commission text of 1884]. In Pol. = Sententia libri Politicorum. Opera omnia, vol. 48 (Rome: Leonine Commission, 1971). In Sent. = Commentum in quatuor libros Sententiarum Magistri Petri Lombardi. Opera omnia, vols. 6–7 (Parma: Typis Petri Fiaccadori, 1856–1858). In Trin. = Super Boetium De Trinitate. Opera omnia, vol. 50 (Rome and Paris: Leonine Commission and Les Éditions du Cerf, 1992), pp. 1–230. SCG = Summa contra gentiles sive De Veritate Catholicae Fidei contra errores Infidelium. Opera omnia, vols. 13–14 (Rome: Leonine Commission, 1926). ST = Summa theologiae. Opera omnia, vols. 4–7 (Rome: Leonine Commission, 1888–1892). Super II Cor. = Super Epistolas S. Pauli lectura, t. 1: Super secundam Epistolam ad Corinthios lectura, 8th edn. (Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1953), pp. 437–561. Ioannes Duns Scotus 9 Ox = Opus Oxoniense. Opera omnia, ed. Editio nova iuxta editionem Waddingi... recognita (26 vols. Paris: apud Ludovicum Vivés, 1893). Ord = Ordinatio. Opera omnia, ed. Commissionis Scotisticae ad fidem codicum edita (Civitas Vaticana: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, 1950 ff). William of Ockham Op. Theol. / Op. Philos. = Opera philosophica et theologica ad fidem codicum manuscriptorum edita, ed. Instituti Franciscani (10 vols., New York: St. Bonaventure University, 1980). Sum. Nat. Philos. = Summa Philosophiae Naturalis, in Opera philosophica et theologica ad fidem codicum manuscriptorum edita, ed. Instituti Franciscani (10 vols., New York: St. Bonaventure University, 1980), vol VI, ed. Stephanus Brown (New York: St. Bonaventure University, 1984), pp. 137–396. Francisco Suárez De legibus = Commentaria ac disputationes in primam secundae D. Thomae, de legibus seu legislatore Deo. Tractatus de legibus, utriusque form hominibus utilis, in decem libros dividitur quorum quinque ultimos in hoc tomo reperie, in R.P. Francisci Suarez e Societate Jesu opera omnia, ed. Nova a D. M. André (28 vols., Paris, Ludovicum Vivés, 1856–1878), vols. V and VI, ed. Carolo Berton (Paris, Ludovicum Vivés, 1856). 10 Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz GP = Die philosophischen Schriften, ed. C. I. Gerhardt (7 vols, Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1965). Grua= Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Textes inédits, d’àpres les manuscrits de la Bibliothèque provinciales de Hanovre, ed. Gaston Grua (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1948). Francis Hutcheson IBV = An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue, ed. Wolfgang Leidhold (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1725, 2004). Richard Cumberland DLN = De legibus naturae disquisitio philosophica (London: 1672). Immanuel Kant1 GMS = Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten (1785, 2nd ed. 1786), in Kant’s gesammelte Schriften, ed. Akademie der Wissenschaften (24 vols., Berlin, 1902– ), vol. IV, ed. Paul Menzer (Berlin, 1911), pp. 386–463. 1 Apart from the the Kritik der reinen Vernunft all references to Kant are to page number and volume of Kant’s gesammelte Schriften, edited by the Akademie der Wissenschaften: Immanuel Kant, Kant’s gesammelte Schriften, ed. Akademie der Wissenschaften (24 vols, Berlin, 1902 ff.). References to the Kritik der reinen Vernunft are to the A and B pagination of the first and second editions. 11 KpV = Kritik der praktischen Vernunft (1788), in Kant’s gesammelte Schriften, ed. Akademie der Wissenschaften (24 vols, Berlin, 1902– ), vol. V, ed. ed. Paul Natorp (Berlin, 1913), pp. 1–163. KrV = Kritik der reinen Vernunft (1781, 2nd edn 1787), ed. Jens Timmerman (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1998). MdS = Metaphysik der Sitten (1797) in Kant’s gesammelte Schriften, ed. Akademie der Wissenschaften (24 vols, Berlin, 1902– ), vol. VI, ed. Paul Natorp (Berlin, 1914), pp. 203–491. Rechtslehre = Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Rechtslehre (1797), Metaphysik der Sitten, Erster Teil, ed. Bernd Ludwig, 2nd rev. edn (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1998). Religion= Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der bloßen Vernunft (1793), ), in Kant’s gesammelte Schriften, ed. Akademie der Wissenschaften (24 vols, Berlin, 1902– ), vol. VI, ed. Georg Wobbermin (Berlin, 1914), pp. 1–202. Tugendlehre = Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Tugendlehre (1797), ed. Bernd Ludwig (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1990). Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel Enzyklopädie = Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830), Gesammelte Werke XX, (Hamburg: Meiner, 1992). Grundlinien = Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, (Hamburg: Meiner, 1995). For English quotes from this work by 12 Hegel, we have used the translation by H. B. Nisbet for Cambridge University Press, 1991. Philosophische Propädeutik = Philosophische Propädeutik, Gymnasialreden und Gutachten über den Philosophie–Unterricht, in Sämtliche Werke III, (Stuttgart: Frommann–Holzboog, 1961). Geschichte der Philosophie = Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie, in Sämtliche Werke XVIII (Stuttgart–Bad Cannstatt: Frommann, 1965) Glöckner–Ausg. System der Philosophie I = System der Philosophie I, in Sämtliche Werke VIII (Stuttgart–Bad Cannstatt: Frommann, 1964) Glöckner–Ausg. Other abreviations Other abreviations used (some already mentioned) are the following a. = article c. = corpus (body of an article or solution) cap. = capitulum (chapter) col. = column d. = distinction ll. = lines 13 INTRODUCTION In recent years, we have witnessed a new revival of the theory of natural law, together with increasing scholarship on modern natural law. It is true that, as Rommen put it, the theory of natural law is bound to come up again and again at the core of moral theory1, particularly in times of cultural crisis2. Among the factors explaining its periodic revival is that it seems to promise a clear moral criterion in a world affected by moral ambiguities and disagreement. That such promise is not a vain illusion of our reason, or a moral appeal without legal or political consequence, is part of the challenges natural law theorists should confront. As we know, natural law was first invoked by the Stoics as a means of providing people with a moral reference, at a moment marked by deep political transformation: the emergence of Alexander‘s Empire involved the decadence of the polis as a moral context for individual action, without providing an adequate political replacement; this meant that the relevance of individual actions had to be sought elsewhere. While Aristotle had still approached eudaimonia from the perspective of the citizen of the polis, Stoicism introduced a new, more universalistic approach, in which the moral relevant factor was not common citizenship but common human nature3. Of course, this 1 See Rommen, H., Die ewige wiederkehr des Naturrechts, Leipzig, Hegner, 1936. 2 ‗In moments of crisis, it is true, natural law flowers briefly. John Locke summoned natural law in defence of Whig interests against the claims of monarchy. So also did the American revolutionaries in their struggle against the crown. After World War II natural law emerged as
Recommended publications
  • El Aporte Antropológico De Leonardo Polo a La Universidad Y a La Teoría
    UNIVERSIDAD DE NAVARRA INSTITUTO EMPRESA Y HUMANISMO EL APORTE ANTROPOLOGICO DE LEONARDO POLO A LA UNIVERSIDAD Y A LA TEORIA DE LA EMPRESA TESIS DOCTORAL Silvia Carolina Martino Director Prof. Dr. Juan Fernando Sellés Dauder Co-Directora Prof. Dra. Concepción Naval Durán PAMPLONA – ABRIL, 2017. ÍNDICE ÍNDICE .............................................................................................................................. 3 INTRODUCCIÓN ............................................................................................................. 9 Agradecimientos ........................................................................................................ 28 PRIMERA PARTE .......................................................................................................... 30 Capítulo 1. El Planteamiento Antropológico de Leonardo Polo. ............................. 30 Introducción ...................................................................................................... 30 1.1. Semblanza y trayectoria intelectual. El autor ............................................. 33 1.1.1. Recorrido intelectual y biográfico ........................................................ 34 1.2. Propuesta antropológica de Leonardo Polo ............................................... 45 1.2.1 El método filosófico poliano ................................................................ 46 1.2.2. La ampliación trascendental ................................................................. 51 1.2.3. La distinción real de
    [Show full text]
  • Presentation Slides
    Conceptions of Environment & Coexistence According to the Spanish Philosopher Leonardo Polo: Implications for Sustainability Education ALIZA D. RACELIS Cesar E.A. Virata School of Business University of the Philippines, Diliman BACKGROUND The Spanish philosopher Leonardo Polo (February 1, 1926 - February 9, 2013) engaged with both Classical and Medieval thinkers such as Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas, and William of Ockham, as well as Modern and Contemporary philosophers such as Descartes, Kant, Hegel, Husserl, Heidegger, and Nietzsche. Polo scholars have come to call his philosophical proposal “transcendental anthropology”, given that ―using the method of abandonment of the mental limit― he made available 4 great themes in relation to man: • on the one hand, the (1) act of being and (2) essence that lie outside the mind, and • on the other hand, the (3) act of being and (4) essence of the human being. BACKGROUND Having distinguished act of being in metaphysics vs. act of being in anthropology, Polo’s works then proposes 4 “anthropological transcendentals”, namely: 1) Personal Co-existence 2) Personal Freedom 3) Personal Intellect/Knowing 4) Transcendental Love (Self-Gift ) [Rich and Poor. Equality and Inequality.] Conceptions of Environment & Coexistence According to the Spanish Philosopher Leonardo Polo: Implications for Sustainability Education “Rich and Poor. Equality and Inequality.” Say's Law “supply constitutes demand” George Gilder “True wealth is not found in the acquisitive capacity of a country, but rather in the capacity to invest in and produce consumable goods in the future. It is rooted, in effect, in: initiative, creativity, and the human work of the businessmen and workers, who are, in the end, the generators of wealth.” Man is an ethical being because he is free.
    [Show full text]
  • The Underlying Assumptions of Germain Grisez's Critique of The
    The underlying assumptions of Germain Grisez’s critique of the perverted faculty argument Los presupuestos subyacentes de la crítica de Germain Grisez al argumento de la facultad pervertida Carlos A. Casanova Universidad Santo Tomás, Chile [email protected] proyecto fondecyt 1180720 Abstract: This paper demonstrates the underlying assumptions of Germain Grisez’s critique of the perverted faculty argument. In the first place, it establishes what formula- tions of the principle Grisez considered in his criticism (those of Father Henry Davis) and what his arguments are. Afterward it establishes his assumptions: (a) a latent ethical logicism; (b) a pragmatist conception of choice and the good; (c) a mistaken metaphysics of being, the good and the theoretical and practical principles. It underlines John Dewey’s influence. Lastly, it defends the classical formulation of the perverted faculty argument and even its rendition by Father Davis. Key words: Perverted faculty argument, Germain Grisez, choice, good as source of ethical rules. Resumen: Este artículo presenta los presupuestos subyacentes a la crítica de Gri- sez al argumento de la facultad pervertida. Muestra, en primer lugar, qué formula- ciones tenía Grisez en mente cuando criticó el argumento (las del p. Henry Davis) y cuáles son sus críticas. Después investiga y determina cuáles son esos presupuestos: un cierto logicismo ético; una concepción pragmatista de la elección y del bien; una metafísica errada del ser, del bien y de los principios teóricos y prácticos. Se subraya la influencia de John Dewey. Se defienden la formulación clásica del principio e -in cluso la del p. Davis. Palabras clave: Argumento de la facultad pervertida, Germain Grisez, elección, bien como fuente de las reglas éticas.
    [Show full text]
  • Dignitatis Humanae and the Development of Moral Doctrine: Assessing Change in Catholic Social Teaching on Religious Liberty
    THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA Dignitatis humanae and the Development of Moral Doctrine: Assessing Change in Catholic Social Teaching on Religious Liberty A DISSERTATION Submitted to the Faculty of the School of Theology and Religious Studies Of The Catholic University of America In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree Doctor of Philosophy By Barrett Hamilton Turner Washington, D.C 2015 Dignitatis humanae and the Development of Moral Doctrine: Assessing Change in Catholic Social Teaching on Religious Liberty Barrett Hamilton Turner, Ph.D. Director: Joseph E. Capizzi, Ph.D. Vatican II’s Declaration on Religious Liberty, Dignitatis humanae (DH), poses the problem of development in Catholic moral and social doctrine. This problem is threefold, consisting in properly understanding the meaning of pre-conciliar magisterial teaching on religious liberty, the meaning of DH itself, and the Declaration’s implications for how social doctrine develops. A survey of recent scholarship reveals that scholars attend to the first two elements in contradictory ways, and that their accounts of doctrinal development are vague. The dissertation then proceeds to the threefold problematic. Chapter two outlines the general parameters of doctrinal development. The third chapter gives an interpretation of the pre- conciliar teaching from Pius IX to John XXIII. To better determine the meaning of DH, the fourth chapter examines the Declaration’s drafts and the official explanatory speeches (relationes) contained in Vatican II’s Acta synodalia. The fifth chapter discusses how experience may contribute to doctrinal development and proposes an explanation for how the doctrine on religious liberty changed, drawing upon the work of Jacques Maritain and Basile Valuet.
    [Show full text]
  • Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations Spring 2010 Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Jason Skirry University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Skirry, Jason, "Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection" (2010). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 179. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Abstract This dissertation presents a unified interpretation of Malebranche’s philosophical system that is based on his Augustinian theory of the mind’s perfection, which consists in maximizing the mind’s ability to successfully access, comprehend, and follow God’s Order through practices that purify and cognitively enhance the mind’s attention. I argue that the mind’s perfection figures centrally in Malebranche’s philosophy and is the main hub that connects and reconciles the three fundamental principles of his system, namely, his occasionalism, divine illumination, and freedom. To demonstrate this, I first present, in chapter one, Malebranche’s philosophy within the historical and intellectual context of his membership in the French Oratory, arguing that the Oratory’s particular brand of Augustinianism, initiated by Cardinal Bérulle and propagated by Oratorians such as Andre Martin, is at the core of his philosophy and informs his theory of perfection. Next, in chapter two, I explicate Augustine’s own theory of perfection in order to provide an outline, and a basis of comparison, for Malebranche’s own theory of perfection.
    [Show full text]
  • Acta 15 Pass
    00_Prima Parte_Acta 15:Prima Parte-Acta9 17/02/10 08:35 Pagina 1 CATHOLIC SOCIAL DOCTRINE AND HUMAN RIGHTS 00_Prima Parte_Acta 15:Prima Parte-Acta9 17/02/10 08:35 Pagina 2 Address The Pontifical Academy of Social Sciences Casina Pio IV, 00120 Vatican City Tel.: +39 0669881441 – Fax: +39 0669885218 E-mail: [email protected] 00_Prima Parte_Acta 15:Prima Parte-Acta9 17/02/10 08:35 Pagina 3 THE PONTIFICAL ACADEMY OF SOCIAL SCIENCES Acta 15 CATHOLIC SOCIAL DOCTRINE AND HUMAN RIGHTS the PROCEEDINGS of the 15th Plenary Session 1-5 May 2009 • Casina Pio IV Edited by Roland Minnerath Ombretta Fumagalli Carulli Vittorio Possenti IA SCIEN M T E IA D R A V C M A S A O I C C I I A F I L T I V N M O P VATICAN CITY 2010 00_Prima Parte_Acta 15:Prima Parte-Acta9 17/02/10 08:35 Pagina 4 The opinions expressed with absolute freedom during the presentation of the papers of this plenary session, although published by the Academy, represent only the points of view of the participants and not those of the Academy. 978-88-86726-25-2 © Copyright 2010 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form, or by any means, electronic, mechanical, recording, photocopying or otherwise without the expressed written permission of the publisher. THE PONTIFICAL ACADEMY OF SOCIAL SCIENCES VATICAN CITY 00_Prima Parte_Acta 15:Prima Parte-Acta9 17/02/10 08:35 Pagina 5 His Holiness Pope Benedict XVI 00_Prima Parte_Acta 15:Prima Parte-Acta9 17/02/10 08:35 Pagina 6 Participants in the conference hall of the Casina Pio IV 00_Prima Parte_Acta 15:Prima Parte-Acta9 17/02/10 08:35 Pagina 7 Participants of the 15th Plenary Session 00_Prima Parte_Acta15:PrimaParte-Acta917/02/1008:35Pagina8 His Holiness Benedict XVI with the Participants of the 15th Plenary Session 00_Prima Parte_Acta 15:Prima Parte-Acta9 17/02/10 08:35 Pagina 9 CONTENTS Address of the Holy Father to the Participants.........................................
    [Show full text]
  • Response to Germain Grisez's
    GRISEZ ON ARISTOTLE AND HUMAN GOODS Response to “Natural Law, God, Religion, and Human Fulfilment” In his essay ‘Natural Law, God, Religion, and Human Fulfillment’ Professor Grisez has given us, in his usual stimulating and provocative way, a good many ideas to chew on and react to. Reading him is always a challenge. In this particular piece he has covered a lot of ground in moral philosophy, theology, and the history of thought. Happily it is not my task to comment on everything. My focus is to be Grisez’s discussion and criticism of Aristotle. However, this focus, while narrow enough for the purposes of this paper, will also give me the opportunity to discuss some of the other things he says. As regards Aristotle, Grisez finds in the Stagirite certain ideas that, as he says, are “disastrous for religion and moral life” (p.13). Well, perhaps they are, but I think we ought to register a certain initial surprise that they could be. After all Aristotle’s philosophy has had such an effect on the theological and moral thinking of the past two millennia, whether Christian or not, that if we are to judge his philosophy disastrous we will probably find ourselves having to judge the thinking it affected disastrous too. Grisez does seem to think that, at least if his remarks on St. Thomas Aquinas later in his paper are anything to go by. But that would suggest that Grisez’s “renewal of Christian ethics” (p. 27) is less like a renewal and more like a revolution. Still it might be a needed revolution.
    [Show full text]
  • Suárez, Natural Law and Contemporary Criticism
    Suárez, Natural Law and Contemporary Criticism Sebastián Contreras Universidad de los Andes, Chile [email protected] Abstract This paper deals with Suárez’s doctrine of natural law. Contemporary scholars often refer to Suárez as responsible of a turning to a physicalist understanding of right, where practical reason is confined to discover the group of commands that nat- ural inclinations imply. Against that interpretation, this paper intends to show that Suárez sustains a practical and rational un- derstanding of natural law in consonance with the Medieval and Thomist tradition. Keywords: Francisco Suárez, natural law, philosophy of law, natural justice. Received: 29 - 06 - 2016. Accepted: 05 - 10 - 2016. Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía 53 (2017), 255-272. 256 Sebastián Contreras Suárez, el derecho natural y la crítica contemporánea* Sebastián Contreras Universidad de los Andes, Chile [email protected] Resumen Este artículo trata sobre la doctrina suareciana de la ley natural. Los estudiosos contemporáneos suelen presentar a Suárez como el responsable del vuelco hacia una comprensión fisicalista del derecho en donde la razón práctica se limita a descubrir el conjunto de mandatos que envuelven las inclinaciones naturales. En contra de esa interpretación, el presente trabajo intenta mostrar que Suárez defiende una comprensión racional-práctica del derecho natural en línea con la tradición medieval y tomista de la ley natural. Palabras clave: Francisco Suárez, ley natural, filosofía del derecho, derecho natural. Recibido: 29 - 06 - 2016. Aceptado: 05 - 10 - 2016. * El autor agradece el patrocinio de Fondecyt-Chile, proyecto 11150649. Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía 53 (2017) Suárez, el derecho natural y la crítica contemporánea 257 Entre los estudiosos de la teoría del derecho natural, actualmente existe una importante discusión acerca del papel que toca a la naturaleza en la fundación de las normas.
    [Show full text]
  • Francisco Suárez
    (ED.) SIMONE GUIDI MANUEL LÁZARO PULIDO MÁRIO SANTIAGO DE CARVALHO Mário Santiago de Carvalho é Professor Catedrático (2002) da Faculdade de Letras da O presente volume publica as Atas do Iº Encontro Internacional “Pensar o Barroco Universidade de Coimbra. Licenciado em Filosofia e Mestre em Filosofia Medieval em Portugal” (26-28 de Junho de 2017), que se ocupou do pensamento metafísico, pela Universidade do Porto, doutorou-se em Letras, pela Universidade de Coimbra, ético e político de Francisco Suárez. Contando com a colaboração de alguns dos após estudos realizados na Bélgica (Hoger Instituut voor Wijsbegeerte - Katholieke maiores especialistas internacionais na obra e no pensamento deste famoso profes- Universiteit Leuven), como bolseiro da Fundação Calouste Gulbenkian. FRANCISCO sor da Universidade de Coimbra no século XVII, este volume celebra os 400 anos da sua morte e assinala a produtividade do seu legado filosófico-teológico. Manuel Lázaro Pulido é Professor (2017) do Departamento de Filosofia da UNED (Madrid), Investigador Integrado do CEFi da Universidade Católica Portuguesa e Investigador Associado do Departamento de Ciências do Direito da Universidade SUÁREZ Bernardo O’Higgins (Santiago do Chile). Doutor em Filosofia pela Universidade Pontifícia de Salamanca, Mestre em Teologia, Teologia Fundamental (UCP e Pontificia Università Antonianum respetivamente) e Humanidades (Universidade de Múrcia), METAPHYSICS, POLITICS AND ETHICS e DEA em Filosofia Medieval pela Universidade de Paris 1 (Panthéon-Sorbonne). FRANCISCO SUÁREZ FRANCISCO Simone Guidi é Professor Auxiliar da Faculdade de Letras da Universidade de Coimbra (2019) e membro efetivo da U.I.&D. “Instituto de Estudos Filosóficos”. Doutor em Filosofia pela Universidade de Roma “La Sapienza”, onde também se licenciou.
    [Show full text]
  • Practical Principles, Moral Truth, and Ultimate Ends John M
    Notre Dame Law School NDLScholarship Journal Articles Publications 1987 Practical Principles, Moral Truth, and Ultimate Ends John M. Finnis Notre Dame Law School, [email protected] Germain Grisez Joseph Boyle Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.nd.edu/law_faculty_scholarship Part of the Legal History Commons, and the Natural Law Commons Recommended Citation John M. Finnis, Germain Grisez & Joseph Boyle, Practical Principles, Moral Truth, and Ultimate Ends, 32 Am. J. Juris. 99 (1987). Available at: https://scholarship.law.nd.edu/law_faculty_scholarship/846 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Publications at NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. PRACTICAL PRINCIPLES, MORAL TRUTH, AND ULTIMATE ENDS GERMAIN GRISEZ, JOSEPH BOYLE, AND JOHN FINNIS The natural-law theory on which we have been working during the past twenty-five years has stimulated many critical responses. We have restated the theory in various works, not always calling attention to developments. This paper reformulates some parts of the theory, taking into account the criticisms of which we are aware. We append an annotated, select bibliography. I. INTRODUCTION A. PLEASE NOTE WELL WHILE THIS PAPER PROPOSES PHILOSOPHICAL clarifications and arguments rather than textual interpretations, it uses some language common in the (broadly speaking, Thomistic) natural-law tradition from which we developed the theory. But what we say here differs in various ways from the theories articulated by Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas, and others. In previous works covering more or less the same ground as this paper, we have expressed key concepts in various ways.
    [Show full text]
  • Sauterdivineansamplepages (Pdf)
    The Decline of Space: Euclid between the Ancient and Medieval Worlds Michael J. Sauter División de Historia Centro de Investigación y Docencia Económicas, A.C. Carretera México-Toluca 3655 Colonia Lomas de Santa Fe 01210 México, Distrito Federal Tel: (+52) 55-5727-9800 x2150 Table of Contents List of Illustrations ............................................................................................................. iv Acknowledgments .............................................................................................................. v Preface ............................................................................................................................... vi Introduction: The divine and the decline of space .............................................................. 1 Chapter 1: Divinus absconditus .......................................................................................... 2 Chapter 2: The problem of continuity ............................................................................... 19 Chapter 3: The space of hierarchy .................................................................................... 21 Chapter 4: Euclid in Purgatory ......................................................................................... 40 Chapter 5: The ladder of reason ........................................................................................ 63 Chapter 6: The harvest of homogeneity ............................................................................ 98 Conclusion: The
    [Show full text]
  • Predication and the Problem of Universals Catherine Legg
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Research Commons@Waikato Philosophical Papers Vol. 30, No. 2 (July 2001): 117-143 Predication and the Problem of Universals Catherine Legg Abstract: This paper contrasts the scholastic realists of David Armstrong and Charles Peirce. It is argued that the so-called 'problem of universals' is not a problem in pure ontology (concerning whether universals exist) as Armstrong construes it to be. Rather, it extends to issues concerning which predicates should be applied where, issues which Armstrong sets aside under the label of 'semantics', and which from a Peircean perspective encompass even the fundamentals of scientific methodology. It is argued that Peir ce's scholastic realism not only presents a more nuanced ontology (distinguishing the existent front the real) but also provides more of a sense of why realism should be a position worth fighting for. ... a realist is simply one who knows no more recondite reality than that which is represented in a true representation. C.S. Peirce Like many other philosophical problems, the grandly-named 'Problem of Universals' is difficult to define without begging the question that it raises. Laurence Goldstein, however, provides a helpful hands-off denotation of the problem by noting that it proceeds from what he calls The Trivial Obseruation:2 The observation is the seemingly incontrovertible claim that, 'sometimes some things have something in common'. The 1 Philosophical Writings of Peirce, ed. Justus Buehler (New York: Dover Publications, 1955), 248. 2 Laurence Goldstein, 'Scientific Scotism – The Emperor's New Trousers or Has Armstrong Made Some Real Strides?', Australasian Journal of Philosophy, vol 61, No.
    [Show full text]