EPISTEMOLOGY Two Kinds of Truth NECESSARY TRUTHS

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

EPISTEMOLOGY Two Kinds of Truth NECESSARY TRUTHS EPISTEMOLOGY Theory of knowledge and Truth 1 EPISTEMOLOGY: The theory of knowledge (1) What does it mean for a set of beliefs to be true? What kinds of truth are there? (2) How will we know when our beliefs are true? What are the criteria for having knowledge? 2 Two Kinds of Truth Traditionally, there are two kinds of truth (1) NECESSARY (2) EMPIRICAL (or Contingent) 3 NECESSARY TRUTHS A statement expressing a necessary truth cannot possibly be false. Examples: All triangles have three sides. All bachelors are unmarried. No one who believes that God exists is an atheist. 4 Necessary Truths The truth of a necessary truth does not depend on what the facts are like; necessary truths are always true no matter what. Examples: Can you ever find a bachelor who is married? Can you ever find a triangle that does not have 3 sides? Is it possible to find an atheist who believes in God? 5 Necessary Falsehoods We can say similar things about necessary falsehoods. Impossible to be true Their falsity does not depend on what the facts are like; necessary falsehoods are always false no matter what 6 Necessary Truths and the A Priori (ā prē or ē) A Priori = prior to experience or independent of any experience of facts or states of affairs in the world. Necessary truths are often said to be true a priori, true independent of any particular facts. 7 Necessary Truths and A Priori Truths It is also said that their poof (or justification) does not depend on any particular facts of the world. 8 Necessary Truths and Analytic Truths Necessary truths are sometimes called analytic truths Analytic truths are necessarily true because (1) The predicate is contained in the concept of the subject. (2) Denying the truth of the statement leads to a contradiction. (3) Contradictions are impossible and go against reason. 9 Analytic Truths “All sisters are female” is an analytic truth because the predicate “female” is contained in the subject “sister.” Why? A sister is defined as being a female sibling. So “All sisters are female” says the same thing as “All female siblings are female.” The predicate is contained in the subject. It is easy to see that it would be a contradiction to say that not all female siblings are female. So “All sisters are female” is necessarily true and couldn’t possibly be false. 10 Analytic Truths Example: Fathers are males. The concept “male” is in the concept of “father” (male parent). 11 Analytic Truths Example: All electrons are subatomic particles. An electron is by definition a certain type of subatomic particle. So the concept of a subatomic particle is contained in the concept of an electron. 12 Empirical (or Contingent) Truths Empirical = having to do with experience Contingent = depending on experience A statement expressing an empirical truth is true in virtue of the facts. An empirical statement is empirical because its truth value (whether it is true or false) depends on what the world is like. 13 Empirical (or Contingent) Truths They can be known to be true only after actually looking at (or knowing about) the facts of the world. It is possible for an empirical truth to be false because of the facts. We can say similar things about empirical falsehoods. 14 Empirical (or Contingent) Truths Empirical Statement: Microorganisms live on Mars. Empirical truth: Over 5 billion people live on Earth. Empirical falsehood: Germany won WWII. 15 Empirical Truths and A Posteriori Truths A posteriori = with experience or depending on experience of the facts Empirical truths are sometimes called “a posteriori” because empirical truths depend on the facts. 16 Test: A Priori and A Posteriori: Are these statements true or false? I can know a priori that all bachelors are unmarried. It is impossible to know a priori whether New York has more inhabitants than Mexico City. I can know a priori that there is life on other planets. All of mathematics is based on a priori reasoning. 17 Test: A Priori and A Posteriori: Are these statements true or false? Nobody can know through a priori reasoning that the Empire State building is the tallest building in the world. I can know a priori that is someone is shot to death, then somebody must have been a shooter. I can know a priori that a cube must have 12 edges. I can know a priori that all swans are white. 18 Empirical Truths and Synthetic Truths Empirical truths are sometimes called synthetic truths because the predicate of the statement is not contained in the subject but is connected to it through experience. Example: My car has more than 1 gallon of gas in it. Example: The door to this room is shut. 19 Test: Analytic or Synthetic Claims? All pencils and pens are writing utensils. Electrons are the smallest physical particles in the universe. More than 20 million people died of AIDS last year. There are more heterosexual humans than homosexual humans. Earthquakes are natural disasters. 20 Test: Analytic or Synthetic Claims? Dogs and cows are both animals. Texas is larger than Oklahoma. The average lawyer makes more than $70,000 a year. All solid spheres have one surface. 21 Test: Necessary or Empirical Claim? If one multiplies any natural number by 2, the resulting number is even. The income of the average worker in the US is higher than the income of the average worker in Europe. Every state must have some form of government. Every event has a cause. If any nation should ever use nuclear weapons again, then millions of people will die. 22 Test: Necessary or Empirical Claim? Every recession in the economy is eventually followed by an economic recovery. If a person freely performs an action, then the person can be held responsible for the action. Sugar is sweet. All human beings have the same fundamental rights. All cats are animals. 23 Test: Necessary or Empirical Claim? The moon moves around the earth. All US presidents are male. The US withdrew from Vietnam in 1975. If Frank has more than 2 sisters, then he has at least three siblings. There are infinitely many prime numbers. In order to graduate from Northwestern University, one has to take at least 3 English classes. 24 Necessary and Empirical Truths Necessary Truths Analytic A priori Empirical (or contingent) Truths Synthetic A posteriori 25 Knowledge: Three Kinds (1) Knowing how (2) Knowledge by acquaintance (3) Knowing that In philosophy, we are almost always concerned with (3), the knowing-that kind of knowledge. 26 Knowing How (1) Knowing how (competence knowledge, skill knowledge): This has to do with knowing how to do something. For example, I know how to ride a bike. 27 Knowledge by Acquaintance (2) Knowledge by acquaintance: This is knowledge that one has when one knows something or someone directly. For example, I know my friend Jack by having been in direct contact with him. 28 Knowing That (3) Knowing that (propositional knowledge, descriptive knowledge): This is knowledge that something is the case. For example, I know that the earth has one moon. In philosophy, we are almost always concerned with (3), the knowing-that kind of knowledge. 29 Test: Knowledge: (1) how, (2) by acquaintance, or (3) propositional? I know exactly how you feel about her death. “2+2=4,” I know that for a fact. I used to know Peter very well but in recent times we have grown apart. I’m not afraid to cheat on my exams because I know how to cheat without getting caught. 30 Test: Knowledge: (1) how, (2) by acquaintance, or (3) propositional? If only I knew more about the Vietnam war. My father used to be the smartest man. Now, he has Alzheimer’s, and he doesn’t know anything anymore. You might know something that is in your accounting book, but this doesn’t mean that you know anything about how to run an accounting firm. 31 Knowledge: Does Believing Strongly Give Us Knowledge? • Can believing strongly that something is true, make it true? 32 Knowledge • Simply believing strongly that something is true in no way establishes that it is true. Strong belief is not the key to having knowledge. Do you agree? 33 Knowledge: Does Having a True Belief Give One Knowledge? Suppose you have a true belief. Do you have knowledge? Do you know that this belief is true? 34 Knowledge: True Belief Is Not Enough for Knowledge Suppose Mike is on the quiz show Who Wants To Be a Millionaire? He is asked the name of the Greek city- state that defeated the Persians in the battle of Marathon. Mike doesn’t know ancient Greek history or the battle of Marathon. But he believes that “Athens” is the answer and selects it. It turns out that “Athens” is the correct answer. But does Mike know that it is the correct answer? No, he is merely guessing. 35 Knowledge: What is needed for it? • When a belief is appropriately linked to truth, then the belief counts as knowledge. But what exactly is this link, and what is knowledge? Can you think of some beliefs that you have that count as examples of knowledge? 36 Knowledge: Classical Definition Someone S knows that P if and only if: (1) S believes that P is true (2) P is true (3) S is justified in believing that P is true We have to add justification. One has to have reasons or evidence of some kind to establish that the belief is 37 Can you KNOW any of the following? (Can you justify any?) I know that I have two hands.
Recommended publications
  • Demystifying the Saint
    DEMYSTIFYING THE SAINT: JAY L. GARFIELDʼS RATIONAL RECONSTRUCTION OF NĀGĀRJUNAʼS MĀDHYAMAKA AS THE EPITOME OF CONTEMPORARY CROSS-CULTURAL PHILOSOPHY TIINA ROSENQVIST Tampereen yliopisto Yhteiskunta- ja kulttuuritieteiden yksikkö Filosofian pro gradu -tutkielma Tammikuu 2011 ABSTRACT Cross-cultural philosophy approaches philosophical problems by setting into dialogue systems and perspectives from across cultures. I use the term more specifically to refer to the current stage in the history of comparative philosophy marked by the ethos of scholarly self-reflection and the production of rational reconstructions of foreign philosophies. These reconstructions lend a new kind of relevance to cross-cultural perspectives in mainstream philosophical discourses. I view Jay L. Garfieldʼs work as an example of this. I examine Garfieldʼs approach in the context of Nāgārjuna scholarship and cross-cultural hermeneutics. By situating it historically and discussing its background and implications, I wish to highlight its distinctive features. Even though Garfield has worked with Buddhist philosophy, I believe he has a lot to offer to the meta-level discussion of cross-cultural philosophy in general. I argue that the clarity of Garfieldʼs vision of the nature and function of cross-cultural philosophy can help alleviate the identity crisis that has plagued the enterprise: Garfield brings it closer to (mainstream) philosophy and helps it stand apart from Indology, Buddhology, area studies philosophy (etc). I side with Garfield in arguing that cross- cultural philosophy not only brings us better understanding of other philosophical traditions, but may enhance our self-understanding as well. I furthermore hold that his employment of Western conceptual frameworks (post-Wittgensteinian language philosophy, skepticism) and theoretical tools (paraconsistent logic, Wittgensteinian epistemology) together with the influence of Buddhist interpretative lineages creates a coherent, cogent, holistic and analytically precise reading of Nāgārjunaʼs Mādhyamaka philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Questions for Phil 251.501, Spring 2012 (Daniel)
    Reading Questions for Phil 251.501, Spring 2012 (Daniel) Class One: What is Philosophy? (Jan. 17) • How is philosophy different from mythology? • How is philosophy different from religion? • How is philosophy different from science? • What does it mean to say that the “love of wisdom” is concerned with the justification of opinions? • Why is giving reasons for your beliefs important regarding the main areas of philosophy (e.g., metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, aesthetics, and logic)? Class Two: Philosophical Tools (Jan. 19) • What is “logical consistency”? Give some examples. • What is the difference between logical possibility and causal possibility? • What is the difference between lexical and real definitions? • What is the difference between necessary and sufficient conditions? • What are thought experiments? • In philosophy, what is an argument? • What is the difference between a deductive vs. and inductive argument? Class Three: Knowledge and Skepticism (Jan. 24) • What distinguishes propositional knowledge, “knowing how,” and “knowledge by acquaintance”? • How does Clifford’s insistence on having evidence highlight the moral significance of distinguishing belief and knowledge? • What are the three necessary conditions for knowledge? Give an example of a Gettier- case exception—that is, a case of meeting these conditions that is still not knowledge. • How are skepticism, empiricism, and rationalism different? • What is the difference between global and local skepticism? • What is Descartes’ method of doubt, and why does he adopt it? • For Descartes, why can’t we trust knowledge based on sense experience? • For Descartes, how are doubts raised by dreaming more profound than doubts about sensations? • How are the thought experiments of the evil demon, the brain in the vat, or the matrix even more profound than doubts about sense experience or dreaming? • How are skepticism, solipsism, and fallibilism possible responses to Descartes’ doubts? Class Four: Huemer on Skepticism (Jan.
    [Show full text]
  • Forthcoming In: Episteme Why Disagreement-Based Skepticism
    Forthcoming in: Episteme Why Disagreement-Based Skepticism Cannot Escape the Challenge of Self-Defeat Thomas Grundmann, University of Cologne penultimate version Abstract. Global meta-philosophical skepticism (i.e. completely unrestricted skepticism about philosophy) based upon disagreement faces the problem of self-defeat since it undercuts its motivating conciliatory principle. However, the skeptic may easily escape this threat by adopting a more modest kind of skepticism, that will be called “extensive meta-philosophical skepticism”, i.e., the view that most of our philosophical beliefs are unjustified, except our beliefs in epistemically fundamental principles. As I will argue in this paper, this kind of skepticism is well-motivated, does not undercut the conciliatory principle, but still poses a radical challenge to philosophy as a cognitive discipline. Moreover, I will argue that non-global skepticism that is still extensive undermines itself as well. The deeper reason for this is that this more modest kind of skepticism can only be motivated by the assumption that disagreement with philosophical peers is abundant and that we can identify peers only by relying on track-record arguments. But then one can argue for extensive meta-philosophical skepticism only if one presupposes that those philosophical beliefs that form the basis of track-record evaluations are justified. Here, the threat of self-defeat looms again. I will proceed by first defending the premises of this new anti- skeptical argument against standard objections from the literature. Second, I will show in more detail where the epistemic inconsistency arises in the argument for extensive meta-philosophical skepticism. I conclude with an assessment of the scope and the limits of my argument.
    [Show full text]
  • Summary %E History of Skepticism
    Summary %e History of Skepticism. In Search of Consistency e book is devoted to the reconstruction of the history of the idea of philosophical skepticism from ancient to present time. It is also an attempt to present the recent state of research in the 'eld of both history of philosophical skepticism (recent interpretations) and epistemology of skepticism (recent discussions and opinions). e thesis of the book is that the basic problem for the skeptical position throughout history is the problem of inconsistency (self-refutation). Since antiquity skeptics were forced to answer to this charge, they invented many ways to avoid it. But the result was either not e0ective or too costly. Sextus Empiricus took his own words as the description of his feelings without any assertion. However, his skepticism is not a thesis at all and it cannot be accepted as true. Hume weakened the assertion for all beliefs and for his skeptical thesis. Such view in contemporary vocabulary is fallibilism rather than skepticism. In contemporary philosophy the skeptical thesis No one ever knows anything about anything or No one is ever justi(ed in believing anything is treated as a clear paradox. e main result of the book is the thesis that skeptical inconsistency is a pragmatic inconsistency. It is not a logical inconsistency, because there is no clear contradiction here. Pragmatic inconsistency is also a contradiction between two propositions, but only one of them is overtly stated; the second is tacitly presupposed in the act of assertion of the skeptical thesis. When skeptics assert No one ever knows anything about anything they presuppose that they have some reasonable ground for such assertion.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Questions for Phil 251.200, Fall 2012 (Daniel)
    Reading Questions for Phil 251.200, Fall 2012 (Daniel) Class One: What is Philosophy? (Aug. 28) How is philosophy different from mythology? How is philosophy different from religion? How is philosophy different from science? What does it mean to say that the “love of wisdom” is concerned with the justification of opinions? Why is giving reasons for your beliefs important regarding the main areas of philosophy (e.g., metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, aesthetics, and logic)? Class Two: The Activity of Philosophy and The Life of Reason [two readings] (Aug. 30) How is the appeal to reason different from an appeal to authority, emotion, and self- interest? What are the criteria for determining whether your reasons for doing or believing something are justified (i.e., “good” reasons)? According to Socrates, “the unexamined life is not worth living”: why?—especially since it is obvious that human beings are not essentially or inherently rational. How can reason be used to resolve conflicts in feelings and among different people? Why is appealing to reason preferable to relying on authority or allowing people to believe whatever they want about the world? Class Three: Knowledge and Skepticism (Sept. 4) What distinguishes propositional knowledge, “knowing how,” and “knowledge by acquaintance”? How does Clifford’s insistence on having evidence highlight the moral significance of distinguishing belief and knowledge? What are the three necessary conditions for knowledge? Give an example of a Gettier- case exception—that is, a case of
    [Show full text]
  • HISTORIA SCEPTYCYZMU Monografie Fundacji Na Rzecz Nauki Polskiej
    HISTORIA SCEPTYCYZMU monografie fundacji na rzecz nauki polskiej rada wydawnicza prof. Tomasz Kizwalter, prof. Janusz Sławiński, prof. Antoni Ziemba, prof. Marek Ziółkowski, prof. Szymon Wróbel fundacja na rzecz nauki polskiej Renata Ziemińska HISTORIA SCEPTYCYZMU W POSZUKIWANIU SPÓJNOŚCI toruń 2013 Wydanie książki subwencjonowane przez Fundację na rzecz Nauki Polskiej w ramach programu Monografie FNP Redaktor tomu Anna Mądry Korekty Ewelina Gajewska Projekt okładki i obwoluty Barbara Kaczmarek Printed in Poland © Copyright by Renata Ziemińska and Wydawnictwo Naukowe Uniwersytetu Mikołaja Kopernika Toruń 2013 ISBN 978-83-231-2949-3 WYDAWNICTWO NAUKOWE UNIWERSYTETU MIKOŁAJA KOPERNIKA Redakcja: ul. Gagarina 5, 87-100 Toruń tel. +48 56 611 42 95, fax +48 56 611 47 05 e-mail: [email protected] Dystrybucja: ul. Reja 25, 87-100 Toruń tel./fax: +48 56 611 42 38, e-mail: [email protected] www.wydawnictwoumk.pl Wydanie pierwsze Druk i oprawa: Abedik Sp. z o.o. ul. Glinki 84, 85-861 Bydgoszcz Spis treści wstęp ......................................................................................................... 9 część i. pojęcie i rodzaje sceptycyzmu rozdział 1. genealogia terminu „sceptycyzm” ........................... 15 rozdział 2. ewolucja pojęcia sceptycyzmu .................................. 21 Starożytny sceptycyzm jako zawieszenie sądów pretendujących do prawdy .......................................................................................... 21 Średniowieczny sceptycyzm jako uznanie słabości ludzkich sądów wobec Bożej wszechmocy
    [Show full text]
  • A Non-Contextual Rule for Epistemic Contextualism.1
    SKÉPSIS, ISSN 1981-4194, ANO VIII, Nº 15, 2017, p. 52-61. A Non-contextual Rule for Epistemic Contextualism.1 Gustavo Almeida de Azevedo (Universidade Estadual de Campinas) E-mail: [email protected] Abstract: Our idea here is to offer a version of epistemic contextualism that can respond to skeptical doubts. More precisely, we believe we can combine the theories of DeRose (1992) and Feldman (1988, 2004) in order to invert the burden of proof for the skeptical side. That is, what we call rule of reasonableness requires that the skeptic has to provide reasons why we should take their doubt into account, what I am calling here 'relevant alternative'. Thus, we claim that two clauses need to be reached, in order to such doubt be taken into account, namely, (i) S has evidence to believe R; and (ii) given the contextual standards of justification to which S is submitted, it is required that the possibility of R occurs remains excluded. Key words: Contextualism; Evidence; Skeptical Doubt. 1 - Introduction The following lines over this paper intend to discuss the possibility of an epistemic contextualism based on a non-contextual rule. Such strategy is not a new one and it was developed, for example, by Blome-Tillman (2014). However, I disagree with his development. In order to state the foundations for this disagreement and consequently state my proposal, I should have to establish the framework problem I am considering here, namely, the general skeptic argument (SA), which any epistemologist must dare to. SA, since Descartes (1641) at least, can be represented by the below formulation: If one subject S knows P, then S knows that R is not the case (sKp → sK~r) because R implies not-P.
    [Show full text]
  • Sextus Was No Eudaimonist
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 7-14-2008 Sextus was no Eudaimonist Joseph B. Bullock Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Bullock, Joseph B., "Sextus was no Eudaimonist." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2008. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/40 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. SEXTUS WAS NO EUDAIMONIST by JOSEPH B. BULLOCK Under the Direction of Dr. Tim O’Keefe ABSTRACT Ancient Greek philosophical schools are said to share a common structure in their ethical theories which is characterized by a eudaimonistic teleology based in an understanding of human nature. At first glance, the skepticism of Sextus Empiricus as described in the Outlines of Pyrrhonism seems to fit into this model insofar as he describes the end of the skeptic as ataraxia, a common account of the expression of human happiness. I argue that this is a misunderstanding of Sextus’s philosophy for several reasons. “The end of skepticism” cannot be eudaimonistic or teleological in the way that other ancient ethical theories are typically understood; moreover, ataraxia is not an end derived from a theory about human nature. For these reasons, the skeptical way of life is radically different than the ethical theories proposed by other schools. I argue that this difference is a result of the character of the skeptical enterprise which involves the implicit rejection of norms in both the epistemological and the ethical spheres.
    [Show full text]
  • Bridging the Secular-Religious Divide with Assistance from the Buddha
    861 WILSON SWLR PROOF - PAGINATED (DO NOT DELETE) 12/1/2016 6:40 PM BRIDGING THE SECULAR-RELIGIOUS DIVIDE WITH ASSISTANCE FROM THE BUDDHA James G. Wilson* I. INTRODUCTION The Seventh ClassCrit Conference contemplated emerging coalitions that could effectively combat unjust structural inequalities. To determine the appropriate size, nature, and durability of any humane electoral/cultural coalition, one must first estimate the severity of our species’ current problems. The next step is to build a conceptual framework that might create and maintain an adequate alliance. Tragically, most prior political ideologies have been primarily animated by our instinct to optimize power, not just over each other but also the rest of Nature. As a result, our legal and philosophical systems laid the intellectual foundation for humanity’s deepest structural inequality, one that is exponentially accelerating: mankind’s temporary dominance of the biosphere, a relationship that may not outlast this millennium. To employ the enduringly useful political terminology of the ancient Greeks, humans are the “few” and all other beings and landscapes constitute the “many.”1 The most troubling prophecy is that nine billion people will soon seek some form of satisfaction on this diminutive planet. Strain is evident everywhere: filthy sewage ruining the sacred waters of India, drought in California and Australia, melting and collapsing ice caps at both poles and Greenland, annihilation of rain forests, acidic oceans, dwindling fish populations, earthquakes caused by fracking, and so forth. We recklessly abuse the four elements: voraciously burning limited fossil fuels and producing innumerable chemicals that toxify the earth, air, sky, and water.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemology.Pdf
    Epistemology An overview Contents 1 Main article 1 1.1 Epistemology ............................................. 1 1.1.1 Background and meaning ................................... 1 1.1.2 Knowledge .......................................... 1 1.1.3 Acquiring knowledge ..................................... 5 1.1.4 Skepticism .......................................... 7 1.1.5 See also ............................................ 7 1.1.6 References .......................................... 8 1.1.7 Works cited .......................................... 9 1.1.8 External links ......................................... 10 2 Knowledge 11 2.1 Knowledge ............................................... 11 2.1.1 Theories of knowledge .................................... 11 2.1.2 Communicating knowledge ................................. 12 2.1.3 Situated knowledge ...................................... 13 2.1.4 Partial knowledge ...................................... 13 2.1.5 Scientific knowledge ..................................... 13 2.1.6 Religious meaning of knowledge ............................... 14 2.1.7 See also ............................................ 15 2.1.8 References .......................................... 15 2.1.9 External links ......................................... 16 2.2 Belief ................................................. 16 2.2.1 Knowledge and epistemology ................................. 17 2.2.2 As a psychological phenomenon ............................... 17 2.2.3 Epistemological belief compared to religious belief
    [Show full text]
  • Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, Second Edition
    Chapter Five Can Skepticism Be Refuted? A standard form of skepticism rests on the premise that the choice between our ordinary beliefs and skeptical hypotheses is evidentially underdetermined. To make a case against this premise, Jonathan Vogel invokes inference-to-the-best-explanation and considers what he calls the “isomorphic hypothesis,” which matches the cause and effect relationships of the real world hypothesis, according to which things are by and large what we take them to be. The isomorphic hypothesis’s explanatory power seems to be no less than that of the real world hypothesis. On what grounds, then, can we prefer the latter over the former? Vogel argues that the isomorphic skeptical hypothesis does not deepen our understanding of our perceptual experiences. The isomorphic hypothesis is more complex than the real world hypothesis because it replaces genuine shapes with pseudo-shapes and genuine locations with pseudo- locations. This increased complexity is not offset by a commensurate increase in explanatory scope and depth. Hence, Vogel suggests, we may prefer the real world hypothesis over the skeptical isomorphic hypothesis and thus reject the evidential underdetermination premise on which skepticism relies. In his response essay, Richard Fumerton explores the challenge of refuting skepti- cism within the traditional framework of inferential internalism, according to which knowing propositions about the external world requires (a) that we have evidence E making such propositions probable and (b) that we know E makes such propositions probable. For inferential internalists to avoid skepticism, they must meet two serious challenges. First, to avoid an infinite regress, they must show that we can have direct knowledge of what makes what probable.
    [Show full text]
  • 7. Inferential Abilities and Common Epistemic Goods Abrol Fairweather
    7. Inferential Abilities And Common Epistemic Goods Abrol Fairweather & Carlos Montemayor While the situationist challenge has been prominent in philosophical literature in ethics for over a decade, only recently has it been extended to virtue epistemology1. Alfano argues that virtue epistemology is shown to be empirically inadequate in light of a wide range of results in social psychology, essentially succumbing to the same argument as virtue ethics. We argue that this meeting of the twain between virtue epistemology and social psychology in no way signals the end of virtue epistemology, but is rather a boon to naturalized virtue epistemology. We use Gird Gigerenzer’s models for bounded rationality (2011) to present a persuasive line of defense for virtue epistemology, and consider prospects for a naturalized virtue epistemology that is supported by current research in psychology. Keywords: inference, reliabilism, bounded rationality, naturalized virtue epistemology, situationism 1. From Moral to Epistemic Situationism A wide range of psychological research on trait attribution and rationality has chipped away at what appeared to be a solid empirical footing for virtue ethics, thereby challenging the adequacy of virtue ethics on the very point that appeared to be a primary strength2. Philosophers such as Gilbert Harman (2000) have been led to question the very existence of character traits, and others like John Doris (2003) have denied their robustness and explanatory value. Character trait attributions enjoin predictive and explanatory commitments that simply fail too often to meet norms of epistemic success that require the manifestation of epistemic virtues. Doris(2002) argues that traditional forms of virtue ethics cannot be empirically adequate and normatively adequate at the same time.
    [Show full text]