Downloaded on 19Th June 2013))

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Downloaded on 19Th June 2013)) The Structured Uses of Concepts as Tools Comparing fMRI Experiments that Investigate either Mental Imagery or Hallucinations Eden Tariq Smith ORCID iD: 0000-0003-4058-6619 Doctor of Philosophy September 2018 History and Philosophy of Science School of Historical and Philosophical Studies The University of Melbourne Submitted in total fulfilment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Abstract Sensations can occur in the absence of perception and yet be experienced ‘as if’ seen, heard, tasted, or otherwise perceived. Two concepts used to investigate types of these sensory-like mental phenomena (SLMP) are mental imagery and hallucinations. Mental imagery is used as a concept for investigating those SLMP that merely resemble perception in some way. Meanwhile, the concept of hallucinations is used to investigate those SLMP that are, in some sense, compellingly like perception. This may be a difference of degree. Attempts to reliably differentiate between instances of each type of SLMP remain unresolved. Despite this, the concepts of mental imagery and hallucinations are each routinely used independently of the other. These uses are especially interesting in those published accounts of experiments where equivalent findings about the neuroanatomical correlates of SLMP are reported in support of diverging knowledge-claims about the role of SLMP in neurocognitive processes. This practice presents a puzzle. To examine one aspect of this puzzle, I compare the uses of these two scientific concepts in three ways: examining their roles in differentiating between types of SLMP; exploring how their respective historical developments intersect; and analysing their contributions in neuroimaging experiments. In presenting this series of comparative analyses, I will draw on three themes from historical, philosophical, and social studies of scientific practices: interest in material contributions to knowledge; accounts of how concepts are used in experiments; and explorations of the historical conditions within which current practices emerge. Building on this literature, my comparative analyses supports five related claims. My first claim is that the concepts of mental imagery and hallucinations are each used as independent tools in neuroimaging experiments. My second claim is that, as experimental i tools, the concepts of mental imagery and hallucinations are each used for investigating discrete epistemic goals. My third claim is that there are implicit interdependent associations that structure the uses of these two concepts as tools for independently investigating these discrete epistemic goals in neuroimaging experiments. This third claim rests on my analyses of both past and present uses of each concept. Firstly, as seen in their intersecting histories, there are disciplined performances of using the concepts of mental imagery and hallucinations that carry-along shared associations about the mediating role of SLMP in thought. Secondly, these interdependent ‘mediator-view’ associations continue to structure the independent uses of each concept as a tool for investigating SLMP in pursuit of specific goals. Taking this further, my fourth claim is that recognising the structured uses of the concepts of mental imagery and hallucinations can help to account for how equivalent SLMP-neuro- correlates are generated in support of diverging knowledge-claims. Finally, my fifth claim is that the structured uses of these concepts as tools can contribute to experiments in ways analogous to, yet not equivalent with, the active contributions of material instruments. Bringing these claims together, I argue that the concepts of mental imagery and hallucinations operate as structured tools that can actively contribute to the knowledge generated by neuroimaging experiments. In presenting this argument I seek to demonstrate that examining the structured uses of concepts as tools can complement existing approaches to studying how the heterogeneous dynamics of experimental practices can come to contribute to scientific knowledge in unintended ways. ii Declaration This is to certify that: i. the thesis comprises only my original work towards the PhD ii. due acknowledgement has been made in the text to all other material used; and iii. the thesis is fewer than 100,000 words in length, exclusive of tables, maps, bibliographies, and appendices. Signed, Eden Tariq Smith, 18 September 2018 iii Preface This following is my own work. None of the chapters are published, or in the process of publication. At the time of submission, the only related publication is drawn from just one of the five claims developed further here in Chapter Eight; a claim supported by research detailed more extensively here in chapters Chapter Two, Three, and Four: Smith, Eden T. 2018. ‘Interdependent Concepts and Their Independent Uses: Mental Imagery and Hallucinations’. Perspectives on Science 26 (3): 360–99. https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_a_00278 The research for this thesis was undertaken during my PhD candidature, and has been funded through an Australian Government Research Training Program Scholarship (Australian Postgraduate Award, 2014 Round 1). In addition to this, I received faculty and school grants that allowed me to travel to international conferences and receive feedback from acclaimed scholars in my field. I am also grateful to academics in the History and Philosophy of Science program who provided teaching and research assistant opportunities throughout my candidature. In relation to this, I would also like to recognise the support shown by professional staff – notably, Sarah Gloger and June McBeth – who went beyond their expected roles in helping me find accessibility solutions. Finally, I wish to acknowledge the history of colonial practices I am a product of. While far from adequate, I offer my respects to the Wurundjeri people on whose land I lived and worked while conducting this research. iv Acknowledgements This thesis would not exist without the support of wonderful individuals and collectives. Most directly, I was fortunate to be supervised by Mike Arnold and James Bradley who both showed an unflappable belief in my abilities. I am also sincerely grateful to Kristian Camilleri, Fiona Fidler, and Gerhard Wiesenfeldt for generous advice and guidance over many years. In addition, my department was filled with so many wonderful people researching fascinatingly diverse topics. I would especially like to thank Tessa Leach, Katia Wilson, Fallon Mody, Kate Mannell, Hannah Fraser, and Martin Bush for the many conversations exploring connections within historical, philosophical, and social studies of science and technology. I also want to take this opportunity to publicly recognise the wide range of support I relied upon to reach this once-inconceivable milestone, and in maintaining an interest in what adventures might follow. Specific thanks are also due: to my parent Gray, for teaching me to question everything; to Fi, for celebrating divergent thinking; to Althea and Brooke, for continuing conversations after our contexts diverged; to Jo, for cultivating my interest in public policy; to Glen, for recognising the beauty of being in the moment and sharing that with me; to Mich, for teaching me to ask for more than I thought possible, and for steadfastly expecting to share whatever the future brings; to Tamlyn, for sharing intentions and enthusiastically investing in me time and time again; to Hän, for teaching me to hope, and repeatedly re-committing to the new puzzles of shared futures; to Wens, for effortless- connections regardless of how time passes; to Nicole, for adapting to my particularities; to Sony, for never taking me too seriously; to Max, for meeting me wherever I am; to Bek, for being such a resilient force of delightful whimsy periodically lighting up my solar system; to Kate, for generously sharing struggles and solidarity; to Frances, for co-creating a space of trust within which we can live alongside each other, regardless of what else may change; to Christopher, for expressing joy in momentary connections of mutual recognition; to Cam, for the unexpected chance to discover our uncanny similarities and valuable differences; to Anna, for demonstrating the power of defying norms, and sharing the challenges and value of resilience; to Naomi, for constantly questioning assumptions; to Bonnie, for such inspiringly nerdy excitement about brains; to Craig, for timely distractions and orbiting in ways that so reliably return to the spaces we create together; to maia, for thinking out-loud and letting me listen; to L, for helping to reframe uncertainties as possibilities; and to Tracey, for helping to build a future where dyslexia is no obstacle to academia – or anything else. v Table of Contents Abstract .................................................................................................................................... i List of Tables ........................................................................................................................ viii Introduction ............................................................................................................................ 1 Studying Scientific Practices ........................................................................................................................ 3 Using the Concepts of Mental Imagery and Hallucinations in Experiments ...................................... 8 1 Material and Conceptual Contributions to Scientific Practice .....................................
Recommended publications
  • Articles Revisiting the Logical Empiricist Criticisms of Vitalism Bohang Chen1 Abstract
    Revisiting the Logical Empiricist Criticisms of Vitalism Bohang Chen Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science 2019 (7): 1-17 ISSN 2526-2270 www.historiographyofscience.org Belo Horizonte – MG / Brazil © The Author 2019 – This is an open access article Articles Revisiting the Logical Empiricist Criticisms of Vitalism Bohang Chen1 Abstract: Vitalism claims that biological organisms are governed by nonmaterial agents like entelechies. The received view today rejects vitalism by presupposing metaphysical materialism (or physicalism). Metaphysical materialism maintains that the world is ultimately material (or physical), and it, therefore, repudiates the existence of nonmaterial entelechies. However, this marks a shift compared with the arguments against vitalism developed by logical empiricists, who were indifferent to metaphysical issues and were only concerned with logical and empirical matters in the sciences. Logical empiricists rejected the concept of the entelechy (vitalism), because vital laws confirmed by biological phenomena were unavailable; in contrast, they accepted the concept of the atom (materialism), since it constituted physical laws and was therefore associated with verifiable results in modern physics. 1 Keywords: Vitalism; Materialism (or Physicalism); Logical Empiricism; Entelechy; Atom Received: 27 June 2019. Reviewed: 13 October 2019. Accepted: 17 October 2019. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.24117/2526-2270.2019.i7.03 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. _______________________________________________________________________ Introduction: The Metaphysical Refutation of Vitalism Today most biologists and philosophers understand vitalism as a heretical doctrine in the history of biology, originally proposed by Hans Driesch in the early twentieth century. 2 According to Driesch’s doctrine of vitalism, biological organisms are governed by nonmaterial vital agents termed entelechies (Driesch 1929; Churchill 1969; Allen 2008).
    [Show full text]
  • Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, Spi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, Spi
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics Alexis Burgess, Herman Cappelen, and David Plunkett 1 OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © the several contributors 2020 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition published in 2020 Impression: 1 Some rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, for commercial purposes, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. This is an open access publication, available online and distributed under the terms of a Creative Commons Attribution – Non Commercial – No Derivatives 4.0 International licence (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0), a copy of which is available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of this licence should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: 2019946746 ISBN 978–0–19–880185–6 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198801856.003.0001 Printed and bound in Great Britain by Clays Ltd, Elcograf S.p.A.
    [Show full text]
  • Reductionism in Biology
    pdf version of the entry Reductionism in Biology http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/reduction-biology/ Reductionism in Biology from the Summer 2012 Edition of the First published Tue May 27, 2008; substantive revision Mon Apr 30, 2012 Stanford Encyclopedia Reductionism encompasses a set of ontological, epistemological, and methodological claims about the relations between different scientific of Philosophy domains. The basic question of reduction is whether the properties, concepts, explanations, or methods from one scientific domain (typically at higher levels of organization) can be deduced from or explained by the properties, concepts, explanations, or methods from another domain of science (typically one about lower levels of organization). Reduction is Edward N. Zalta Uri Nodelman Colin Allen John Perry germane to a variety of issues in philosophy of science, including the Principal Editor Senior Editor Associate Editor Faculty Sponsor structure of scientific theories, the relations between different scientific Editorial Board disciplines, the nature of explanation, the diversity of methodology, and http://plato.stanford.edu/board.html the very idea of theoretical progress, as well as to numerous topics in Library of Congress Catalog Data metaphysics and philosophy of mind, such as emergence, mereology, and ISSN: 1095-5054 supervenience. Notice: This PDF version was distributed by request to mem- In recent philosophy of biology (1970s to the 1990s), the primary debate bers of the Friends of the SEP Society and by courtesy to SEP content contributors. It is solely for their fair use. Unauthorized about reduction has focused on the question of whether and in what sense distribution is prohibited. To learn how to join the Friends of the classical genetics can be reduced to molecular biology.
    [Show full text]
  • What Can the Philosophy of Biology Learn from the History of Biology?
    What can the Philosophy of Biology learn from the History of Biology? 19‐20 March 2016, Utrecht University (Sweelinckzaal, Drift 21), The Netherlands Questions about the interrelation between the history of science and the philosophy of science have received renewed attention in recent years. This workshop focuses on the life sciences and asks how we might employ historical findings and approaches in order to shed light on questions in the philosophy of biology. The workshop aims to take stock of previous work in this domain, to highlight current lines of research, and to identify challenges and opportunities for the future. This is the first Utrecht Workshop in Philosophy of the Life Sciences. It is hosted by the Descartes Centre for the History and Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities. 19 March 9.30‐10.30 Sabina Leonelli (Exeter) The Epistemology of Data‐Intensive Science: Integrating History, Philosophy and Social Studies of Data Practices 10.30‐11.30 Bert Theunissen (Utrecht) The role of genetics theory in animal breeding 11.30‐12.00 Coffee 12.00‐13.00 William Bechtel (San Diego) What can the history of biology teach philosophy about representing biological knowledge? 13.00‐14.00 Lunch 14.00‐15.00 Ingo Brigandt (Alberta) Research on developmental constraints in the 1980s, and its relevance to current work on evolvability 15.00‐16.00 Raphael Scholl (Cambridge) Rethinking the relationship between history and philosophy of biology 16.00‐17.00 Plenary Discussion 17.00 End 20 March 9.30‐10.30 Joeri Witteveen (Utrecht) Rethinking ‘population thinking’ 10.30‐11.30 Kärin Nickelsen (Munich) Research fields and research collectives: The case of photosynthesis studies, 1930s‐1950s 11.30‐12.00 Coffee 12.00‐13.00 Sahotra Sarkar (Austin) Reductionism in the Philosophy of Biology: What a Little History Does to the Debates 13.00‐14.00 Lunch 14.00‐15.00 Plenary Discussion 15.00 End of Workshop The event is free and open to all.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae of Ingo Brigandt
    Curriculum Vitae Ingo Brigandt Department of Philosophy Email: [email protected] University of Alberta Phone: +1 780-492-9030 2-40 Assiniboia Hall Webpage: http://www.ualberta.ca/~brigandt Edmonton, AB T6G 2E7 Canada Citizenship: Canadian and German citizen AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION Philosophy of Biology, Feminist Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Mind AREAS OF COMPETENCE Philosophy of Science, Socially Relevant Philosophy of Science, Bioethics, Philosophy of Language, Epistemology, History of Biology, Science Education ACADEMIC POSITIONS 07/2017 – Professor of Philosophy, University of Alberta 07/2015 – 06/2021 Associate Chair (Graduate Studies), Department of Philosophy, University of Alberta (on leave from July to December 2019) 04/2014 – 03/2024 Canada Research Chair in Philosophy of Biology, University of Alberta 08/2019 – 12/2019 Visiting Fellow, Centre for Advanced Study at the Norwegian Academy of Science and Letters, Oslo 2012 – 2017 Associate Professor of Philosophy (with tenure), University of Alberta 03/2015 – 05/2015 Visiting Scholar, Sydney Centre for the Foundations of Science, University of Sydney 09/2014 – 12/2014 Visiting Fellow, Center for Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh 2008 – 2012 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Alberta (hired in 2006, appointment deferred for 2 years to take up a postdoctoral fellowship) 2006 – 2008 Izaak Walton Killam Memorial Postdoctoral Fellow, University of Alberta EDUCATION 2000 – 2006 Ph.D. in History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh
    [Show full text]
  • Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change
    Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change Ingo Brigandt Department of History and Philosophy of Science 1017 Cathedral of Learning University of Pittsburgh Pittsburgh, PA 15260 E-mail: [email protected] To be presented at the 4th Congress of the Spanish Society for Analytic Philosophy Murcia (Spain), 16-18 December 2004 paper: 2997 words abstract: 150 words Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change Abstract The paper discusses concept individuation in the context of scientific concepts and conceptual change in science. It is argued that some concepts can be individuated in different ways. A particular term may be viewed as corresponding to a single concept (which is ascribed to every person from a whole scientific field). But at the same time, we can legitimately individuate in a more fine grained manner, i.e., this term can also be considered as corresponding to two or several concepts (so that each of these concepts is attributed to a smaller group of persons only). The reason is that there are different philosophical and explanatory interests that underlie a particular study of the change of a scientific term. These interests determine how a concept is to be individuated; and as the same term can be subject to different philosophical studies and interests, its content can be individuated in different ways. HOLISM, CONCEPT INDIVIDUATION, AND CONCEPTUAL CHANGE 1 The topic of the present discussion is the individuation of concepts. I am primarily interested in scientific concepts and the phenomenon of conceptual change. My account will be based on a moderate holism about concept, using a conceptual role semantics—an approach that I view as fruitful for studying and explaining conceptual change in science, at least in biology.1 In order to motivate my position, I will briefly look at some recent debates about conceptual role semantics.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Levels of Organization in the Biological Sciences
    The Concept of Levels of Organization in the Biological Sciences PhD Thesis Submitted August 2014 Revised June 2015 Daniel Stephen Brooks Department of Philosophy Bielefeld University Reviewers: Martin Carrier, Maria Kronfeldner Dedicated in friendship to Jan and Magga “He who has suffer'd you to impose on him knows you.” Table of Contents Table of Contents........................................................................................................................1 Chapter One: The Intuitive Appeal and Ubiquity of 'Levels of Organization'............................5 1.1 Introduction ................................................................................................................5 1.2 Analyzing 'Levels of Organization' in Biological Science..........................................7 1.2.1 Level Claims.....................................................................................................10 1.2.2 Wimsatt’s Characterization of Levels ..............................................................14 1.3 Initial Distinctions.....................................................................................................16 1.3.1 Erroneous Concepts of Levels...........................................................................18 1.4 Depictions of Levels in Biological Textbooks...........................................................20 1.4.1 The Character of 'Levels' in Biological Science................................................24 1.4.2 The Significance of 'Levels' in Biological Science...........................................30
    [Show full text]
  • Reductionism in Biology - Philosophy - Oxford Bibliographies
    Reductionism in Biology - Philosophy - Oxford Bibliographies Reductionism in Biology Sahotra Sarkar, Alan Love, William Wimsatt LAST MODIFIED: 11 JANUARY 2018 DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780195396577-0359 Introduction Reductionism concerns a set of ontological and epistemological claims, and methodological strictures based on them, about the relationship between two different scientific domains. The critical assumption is that one of these domains is privileged over the other in the sense that the concepts, rules, laws, and other elements of the privileged domain can be used to specify, constitute, or account for those of the other “reduced” domain. This specification often consists of explanation, such that the “reducing” domain is epistemically privileged over the reduced one. Explanations of this type are “reductionist” (or, are “reductions”) and reductionism is then the thesis that such explanations will always be forthcoming or at least are possible in principle. Reductionism is most plausible if the entities of the reduced domain can be interpreted as arising from (e.g., as aggregates of) entities of the reduced domain. This ontological claim is controversial but motivates many reductionist theses and associated scientific research programs. Thus, epistemological and ontological claims about reductionism have the methodological implication that they should govern and guide scientific research. When such research proves to be fruitless over a period of time, the associated reductionist claims themselves become suspect. Although issues connected with reductionism arise in the physical and social sciences, most attention to reductionism in philosophy of science over the last few decades has focused on the biological sciences, especially after the advent of molecular biology made it plausible to believe that biological phenomena can be uniformly explained (in detail) from their physical basis.
    [Show full text]
  • A Theory of Conceptual Advance
    A THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL ADVANCE : EXPLAINING CONCEPTUAL CHANGE IN EVOLUTIONARY, MOLECULAR, AND EVOLUTIONARY DEVELOPMENTAL BIOLOGY by Ingo Brigandt M.Sc. in Mathematics, University of Konstanz, 1999 M.A. in Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2005 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Faculty of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2006 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH FACULTY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Ingo Brigandt It was defended on August 2, 2006 and approved by Robert B. Brandom Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh James G. Lennox Professor of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh Sandra D. Mitchell Professor of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh G¨unter P. Wagner Alison Richard Professor of Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, Yale University Dissertation Directors: Anil Gupta Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh Paul E. Griffiths ARC Federation Fellow, Professor of Philosophy, University of Queensland ii Copyright c by Ingo Brigandt 2006 iii A THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL ADVANCE : EXPLAINING CONCEPTUAL CHANGE IN EVOLUTIONARY, MOLECULAR, AND EVOLUTIONARY DEVELOPMENTAL BIOLOGY Ingo Brigandt, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2006 Abstract The theory of concepts advanced in the dissertation aims at accounting for a) how a concept makes successful practice possible, and b) how a scientific concept can be subject to rational change in the course of history. Traditional accounts in the philosophy of science have usually studied concepts in terms only of their reference; their concern is to establish a stability of reference in order to address the incommensurability problem.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Thirty Years of Biology & Philosophy: Philosophy of Which
    Thirty years of Biology & Philosophy: Philosophy of which biology? Final draft. To appear in Biology and Philosophy. Thomas Pradeu - ImmunoConcept, CNRS & University of Bordeaux, 146 rue Léo Saignat 33076 Bordeaux, France - Institut d’histoire et de philosophie des sciences et des techniques, CNRS & Panthéon-Sorbonne University, 11 rue du Four 75006, France Email: [email protected] Phone: +33-5-5757-9547 Fax: +33-5-5757-1472 Abstract Which domains of biology do philosophers of biology primarily study? The fact that philosophy of biology has been dominated by an interest for evolutionary biology is widely admitted, but it has not been strictly demonstrated. Here I analyse the topics of all the papers published in Biology & Philosophy, just as the journal celebrates its thirtieth anniversary. I then compare the distribution of biological topics in Biology & Philosophy with that of the scientific journal Proceedings of the National Academy of Science of the USA, focusing on the recent period 2003-2015. This comparison reveals a significant mismatch between the distributions of these topics. I examine plausible explanations for that mismatch. Finally, I argue that many biological topics underrepresented in philosophy of biology raise important philosophical issues and should therefore play a more central role in future philosophy of biology. Keywords Biology & Philosophy; Philosophy of biology; History of philosophy of biology. Acknowledgments I would like to thank Jean Gayon for his inspiring work. In addition, I would like to thank Lynn Chiu, Jean Gayon, Peter Godfrey-Smith, Matt Haber, Philippe Huneman, Maureen O’Malley, Sahotra Sarkar, and two anonymous referees for their comments on previous drafts.
    [Show full text]
  • The APA Guide to Graduate Programs in Philosophy
    2013 The APA GUide To GraduatE ProGrAms in PhilosoPhy University of Delaware Newark, DE 19716 www.apaonline.org All data collected by the American Philosophical Association. The data in this publication have been provided by the departments and programs listed; in the cases where no response was received to repeated requests for information, the most recent data provided, if any, can be found in the previous edition. The APA cannot guarantee the accuracy of this report; because all information has been self- reported, there may be errors or inconsistencies in these data. Readers should therefore examine the available data closely to ensure that any comparisons are made in a fair and reasonable manner. Errors or inconsistencies should be brought to the attention of the American Philosophical Association by email to [email protected]. For clarification, correction, updating, or supplementation of the information provided, contact the department(s) in question. © 2012 The American Philosophical Association This publication of the American Philosophical Association may not be reproduced for sale or future distribution without the express written consent of the executive director. Inquiries should be directed as follows: The American Philosophical Association University of Delaware, 31 Amstel Avenue, Newark, DE 19716 Phone (302) 831-1112 • Fax (302) 831-8690 [email protected] Last updated February 3, 2013 About the Grad Guide The Guide to Graduate Programs in Philosophy, originally published biennially until the early 2000s, was relaunched in 2012 as an annual online resource. The guide compiles data on both doctoral and master’s degree programs in philosophy at institutions throughout the US and Canada, offering prospective students, job candidates, and other members of the profession a rich resource on post- graduate education and employment in philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Reduction and Pluralism: Toward an Epistemology of Explanatory Integration in Biology
    Beyond Reduction and Pluralism: Toward an Epistemology of Explanatory Integration in Biology Ingo Brigandt Department of Philosophy University of Alberta 2-40 Assiniboia Hall Edmonton, AB T6G 2E7 Canada Tel: +1 780-492-0623 Fax: +1 780-492-9160 Email: [email protected] Abstract The paper works towards an account of explanatory integration in biology, using as a case study explanations of the evolutionary origin of novelties—a problem requiring the integration of several biological fields and approaches. In contrast to the idea that fields studying lower level phenomena are always more fundamental in explanations, I argue that the particular combination of disciplines and theoretical approaches needed to address a complex biological problem and which among them is explanatorily more fundamental varies with the problem pursued. Solving a complex problem need not require theoretical unification or the stable synthesis of different biological fields, as items of knowledge from traditional disciplines can be related solely for the purposes of a specific problem. Apart from the development of genuine interfield theories, successful integration can be effected by smaller epistemic units (concepts, methods, explanations) being linked. Unification or integration is not an aim in itself, but needed for the aim of solving a particular scientific problem, where the problem’s nature determines the kind of intellectual integration required. TOWARD AN EPISTEMOLOGY OF EXPLANATORY INTEGRATION IN BIOLOGY 2 1 Introduction Explanatory integration as a philosophical issue can be motivated by looking back at recent debates about reductionism in biology—often taking place in a dialectic between reductionism and pluralism. The traditional model about the relation of different scientific disciplines or domains of knowledge was ‘theory reduction’, which construed reduction as a deductive relation between theories conceived of as axiomatic systems including laws.
    [Show full text]